{"title":"“Pure” or “useful”: the cultural status of science and the prospects for its change","authors":"S. Pirozhkova","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2021-26-2-52-67","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2021-26-2-52-67","url":null,"abstract":"The article analyzes the evolution of the cultural status of science by considering its history through the prism of the opposition to the ideal of pure and useful science. The purpose of the study is not to propose a new periodization of the development of the scientific tradition, but to identify the dynamics of its relationship with the cultural whole and to correct on this basis the previously obtained scenarios of the development of science as a cultural phenomenon. It is shown that science arises as a separate social practice, opposed to another type of normalized activity. The way out from under such rationing is fixed by the idea of scientific leisure as a necessary condition for scientific and philosophical knowledge. This is a model of pure science, the practical usefulness of which is not questioned. However, the very fact of the appearance of a new type of activity entails its socialization, transformation into a profession and the gradual emergence of the principle of the social utility of science. The accumulated historical experience leads to the formation in modern times of a strategy for justifying science as both existentially and ideologically valuable (through its integration into religious discourse) and practically useful. Secularization, scientific and technological progress and economic development lead to a non-religious interpretation of human history. This interpretation is characterized by the dominance of two socio-cultural myths – technological and economic. The future of science depends on whether it will be absorbed by these myths (largely generated by itself) or will be able to offer, primarily through the efforts of socio-humanitarian disciplines, an alternative project for the development of culture.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127049181","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Some consequences of Kant’s Copernican turn","authors":"T. Rockmore","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-46-60","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-46-60","url":null,"abstract":"Kant turns from an early representational view of cognition to a later anti-representational, epistemic constructivist view, often simply referred to as the Copernican revolution or the Copernican turn. Kant’s Copernican turn belongs to the modern, non-standard interest in epistemic constructivism. At least since Parmenides the standard approach to cognition requires knowledge of the real, reality or the world. In modern philosophy this approach is countered by the emergence of epistemic constructivism as a non-standard solution for the cognitive problem in Francis Bacon, Hobbes, Vico, and others, and independently in Kant. This paper briefly describes consequences of Kant’s Copernican turn concerning at least five themes: (i) cognition, (ii) German idealism, (iii) the subject, (iv) the historical character of knowledge and (v) the success or failure of the philosophical tradition.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"49 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125452576","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Comments on the Tom Rockmore’s article “Some consequences of Kant’s Copernican turn”","authors":"V. Przhilenskiy","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-69-71","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-69-71","url":null,"abstract":"The “remarks” assess the consistency of T. Rockmore’s assertion that Kant’s philosophy creates the possibility of further development of anti-representationalist and constructivist ideas. They criticize the reduction of the turn to the statement that phenomena are only representations, not things-in-themselves. Rockmore’s interpretation of the turn is opposed to a more traditional position whereby I. Kant changed a ratio of theoretical and practical in the hierarchy of knowledge, which caused a “revolutionary” and “turnable” revision of the whole idea of mind, its structure and content.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"118 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"117339812","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Philosophy as a scientific discipline: subject, functions and tasks in modern context","authors":"S. Pirozhkova","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2022-27-1-84-98","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2022-27-1-84-98","url":null,"abstract":"The article describes philosophy as a part of the modern system of scientific knowledge in Russia, reconstructs basic arguments against the recognizing philosophy as a scientific discipline, distinguishes between philosophers and non-philosophers criticism of philosophy scientificity, shows that while the former consider philosophy as an intellectual activity which is superior to science in its functionality, the latter, by contrast, regard it as unable to meet the basic criteria of scientific knowledge. Based on the reconstruction of the evolution of theoretical knowledge, it is shown that if the core and model of modern science is theoretical natural science, which allows to obtain universal theoretical knowledge, providing it with empirical content through procedures of empirical interpretation and testing, then philosophy is a form of theoretical knowledge, that cannot be subjected to the same rigorous procedures of establishing empirical content. However, this fact only proves to be a problem if philosophy claims to study the same objects that empirical disciplines study. Such a claim was proclaimed by the program of Soviet scientific philosophy, and it was questioned in Soviet philosophy as well. It is argued that the subject of philosophy as a scientific discipline is thinking and its forms, tools, and results – not cognitive activity, but human activity, objectified in language, conceptual and figurative representations, cultural and social practices, and institutions, including science. Thus, science incorporating philosophy into its structure acquires the possibility to make not just itself (it is also possible within, for example, the framework of science studies), but its own boundaries and foundations the object of cognition. This opens the prospect for science to design its own development more effectively, while understanding science as a human enterprise and ensuring its humanistic orientation.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"77 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115583474","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Philosophy, activity, life","authors":"D. Bakhurst","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2022-27-2-31-45","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2022-27-2-31-45","url":null,"abstract":"This paper, written to honor Prof. Vladislav Lektorsky on the occasion of his 90th birthday, addresses a subject to which Lektorsky has returned many times in the course of his long and distinguished career: the concept of activity. I begin with the distinction between activity and action, arguing against the view, associated with Leontiev, that actions are components of activities. In my view, the distinction between activity and action is an aspectual rather than ontological or mereological one. I then draw on the analysis of intentional action offered by G.E.M. Anscombe to argue that her understanding of action, intention and practical knowledge, when supplemented by insights from MacIntyre, McDowell and others, provides grounds to endorse three theses central to the activity approach (theses I find in Prof. Lektorsky’s recent summation of the tradition): that (i) consciousness, the inner plane of our mental lives, can be understood only in relation to the forms of our activity as embodied beings; (ii) human agency and behavior cannot be described or explained without essential reference to the social, cultural and historical context; and (iii) selves or persons are constituted in and through their activity. I then consider the objection that my analysis is too focused on the intentional activities of the individual, at the expense of the collective. I reply that the unit of analysis is neither the individual nor the collective, but the human life form. There is plenty of room, as there must be, for countenancing joint, shared and collective intentionality, and for recognizing that individuals and collectives do many things unintentionally. But no sense can be made of any of that without a robust account of intentional action. I believe my findings are congenial to three themes that characterize the legacy of Vladislav Lektorsky: (i) respect for the phenomenology of everyday thought and experience; (ii) humanism; and (iii) the belief that much is to be gained by bringing Russian philosophy into constructive dialogue with fruitful trends in Anglo-American philosophy.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"184 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114753310","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Scientific activity of the State Optical Institute during the war years (Yoshkar-Ola period): from the history of physics science","authors":"I. V. Krechetova, L. V. Tselishcheva","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2022-27-1-149-162","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2022-27-1-149-162","url":null,"abstract":"The main idea of the article is to use the method of historical reconstruction in the study of physics at a modern university as a basis for the formation of an interest in understanding the events of the Great Patriotic War, which took place in 1941–1945 in the city of Yoshkar – Ola during the scientific activity of the State Optical Institute (GOI). The scientific discoveries of the Institute’s staff and academician S.I. Vavilov (head of the GOI) are particularly emphasized. Research attention is paid to the creation by the teacher of conditions for the formation of patriotic consciousness, feelings and beliefs among students through the study of certain historical material while organizing independent work through traditional and online learning from the point of view of the history of science. The implementation of research tasks was achieved on the basis of the use of historical documents from the archive of the Museum of the Volga State Technological University and the library fund of the S.G. Chavain National Library of the Republic of Mari El.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"15 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125732291","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Beyond the coincidental fine-tuning of the universe: The ontology of Essential Time","authors":"Ahmed Siddiqui Naseeb","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-145-158","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-145-158","url":null,"abstract":"The first part of this research discussed a theoretical framework of a new theory of time which was systematically proposed, developed and defended. Time was exposed to a natural categorization that calls forth two different real times; Existential and Essential. The current paper which is the conclusion of the research deals with the ontological dimension of Essential time. Contrary to the fine-tuning of physical constants of the universe by coincidence, this article tries to establish that “coincidence” in itself depends on time. The Essential time provides a timeline of creation which starts from absolute uniformity to dis-uniform universe and coincidence is planned. Hence, essential time is uniform, formless and powerful to facilitate the creation of the universe by forming dis-uniformity to everything that was uniform. The question that why essential time is able to do that and what is the source to trigger dis-uniformity brings the discussion to the ontology of essential time. This ontological being in essential time will be proved by two premises. The article argues that why the interpretation based on essential time must be considered instead of “coincidences” of modern science, “Demiurge” of Plato and “unmoved mover” of Aristotle to explain the final cause of the universe. By doing so the fundamental flaw in the anthropic principle is revealed and argued that it does not present a convincing answer to the “why” question of the universe. The combinations of scientific, philosophical and metaphysical arguments establish a conclusive interpretation about the ontological being in essential time without any deviation from the universal facts of the universe. This might end the creation dilemma which is, why did the universe come into existence.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"29 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123222758","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Nikolay N. Semyonov: a prophet and a tamer of fire and atom energy","authors":"K. Dolgov","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2021-25-2-151-158","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2021-25-2-151-158","url":null,"abstract":"The paper is a memoirs of the Honoured scientist of the Russian Federation Konstantin M. Dolgov of his communication with Soviet Academy of Science member Nikolay N. Semyonov – one of the founders of the physical chemistry and the only Soviet Nobel Prize winner in chemistry. The paper provides the analysis of the personality of this prominent scientist, his achievements and his views upon the development of science and interactions between different branches of science.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"38 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123335316","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"The collective subject in complex human-dimensional systems: intelligence or the sum of technologies?","authors":"E. Nikitina","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2021-26-1-122-130","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2021-26-1-122-130","url":null,"abstract":"The relevance of addressing the problem of the collective subject is due to the need to study the laws of complex self-developing human-dimensional systems. In these systems, the subjects of knowledge and activity are organically connected with the means of knowledge and activity and objects. Self-development is realized in these systems through the information and communication technology environment. Self-development is carried out with the help of the reflexive activity of the collective subject. The purpose of the article is to identify the features of the collective subject in complex human-dimensional systems. It is shown that the characteristics of the collective subject are influenced by such trends as the intellectualization of the technosphere and the technologization of human cognition and activity. The functions of a collective subject in the information society are beginning to be performed by information management systems. The collective subject under the conditions of the co-evolution of man and technology evolves in the direction of a hybrid collective subject.","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"65 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126296742","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
{"title":"Page from the history of philosophical problems of physics in the USSR: Eduard Fritsevich Lepin (1893‒1937)","authors":"S. Korsakov","doi":"10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-76-89","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2413-9084-2019-24-1-76-89","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":227944,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy of Science and Technology","volume":"2012 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129907236","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}