Notre Dame Law Review最新文献

筛选
英文 中文
The Meanings of the 'Privileges and Immunities of Citizens' on the Eve of the Civil War 内战前夕“公民特权与豁免”的意义
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-03-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2107460
David R. Upham
{"title":"The Meanings of the 'Privileges and Immunities of Citizens' on the Eve of the Civil War","authors":"David R. Upham","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2107460","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2107460","url":null,"abstract":"This article presents important, largely-overlooked evidence concerning the antebellum understanding of the Privileges and Immunities Clause of Article IV, with an eye toward illuminating the Privileges or Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.This article explains that from 1857 to 1861, in the course of prominent national political debates, three contrasting interpretations of the Privileges and Immunities Clause arose: (1) a pro-slavery absolute-rights reading adopted by southern Democrats and some northern Democrats; (2) an anti-slavery absolute-rights reading adopted by Republicans; and (3) a strictly interstate-equality reading held by some northern and border-state Democrats. The prominence, if not dominance, of the first two readings represented, in some respects, radical developments relative to the interpretations that had prevailed in the courts and political debates before 1857. These first two readings, at the same time, effectively marginalized the interstate-equality reading that still largely prevailed in the courts.This article concludes by noting the ways in which this evidence illuminates both the original understanding of the “privileges and immunities of citizens of the United States” secured by the Fourteenth Amendment, and the reason why the Fourteenth Amendment proved so vulnerable to judicial misconstruction.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"152 1","pages":"1117"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76741126","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Exceptional Role of Courts in the Constitutional Order 法院在宪制秩序中的特殊作用
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-02-18 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2734218
N. Barber, Adrian Vermeule
{"title":"The Exceptional Role of Courts in the Constitutional Order","authors":"N. Barber, Adrian Vermeule","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2734218","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2734218","url":null,"abstract":"We examine exceptional cases in which judges are called upon to pass judgment on the constitution itself. There are three groups of cases. First, in exceptional cases the validity of the constitution and the legal order is thrown into dispute. The court is asked to rule on the legitimacy of the constitution and, by derivation, on the standing of the court and the legal authority of the judge. Second, on some occasions the judge is asked to rule on the transition from one constitutional order to another. This can occur in the aftermath of a revolution, or when the state is acceding to a new constitutional order. Third, there are some cases in which the health of the constitutional order requires the judge to act not merely beyond the law, as it were, but actually contrary to the law. The judge must act contrary to the rules of the legal order, precisely in order to preserve the health of the legal order. We claim that \"constitutional decisionism\" is inevitable in all three groups of cases. Courts sometimes have no option but to take it upon themselves to rule upon, and indeed to participate in constituting, the validity of the very constitutional order that gives them their authority, in a kind of bootstrapping.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"19 1","pages":"817"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-02-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73934303","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Penn Central Take Two 宾州中央2路
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-02-05 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2728417
C. Serkin
{"title":"Penn Central Take Two","authors":"C. Serkin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2728417","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2728417","url":null,"abstract":"Penn Central v. New York is the most important regulatory takings case of all time. There, the Supreme Court upheld the historic preservation of Grand Central Terminal in part because the City offset the burden of the landmarking with a valuable new property interest — a transferable development right (TDR) — that could be sold to neighboring property. Extraordinarily, 1.2 million square feet of those very same TDRs, still unused for over 40 years, are the subject of new takings litigation. According to a newly filed complaint, the TDRs that saved Grand Central have themselves been taken by the government, which allegedly wiped out their value by permissively upzoning the neighboring property. The litigation is not only a captivating postscript to Penn Central, but also a compelling context for examining the category of regulatory property more generally. Regulatory property — like TDRs and pollution credits, for example — is increasingly important and valuable, but raises complicated trade-offs between the need for stability in property-based entitlements and policy flexibility in governance. This Essay ultimately argues that the creation of regulatory property should not prevent policy changes far into the future.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"18 1","pages":"913"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-02-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86986181","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Prosecutorial Accountability 2.0 检控问责2.0
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-01-26 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2722791
B. Green, Ellen Yaroshefsky
{"title":"Prosecutorial Accountability 2.0","authors":"B. Green, Ellen Yaroshefsky","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2722791","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2722791","url":null,"abstract":"This article examines prosecutors’ accountability for professional misconduct. It begins by identifying a significant evolution since the Warren Court era both in the rhetoric regarding prosecutorial misconduct and in how prosecutors are regulated. Prior to the information age, the public and the judiciary largely accepted prosecutors’ contention that prosecutorial misconduct should be narrowly conceived as intentional lawbreaking, and that isolated and aberrational instances of misconduct could be addressed by disciplining rogue prosecutors. In contrast, in the shift to “Prosecutorial Accountability 2.0,” increasing segments of the public and judiciary now accept that prosecutorial misconduct is systemic; it calls for systemic remedies; and it includes negligent wrongdoing, abuses of discretion, and failures of supervision. The article rejects suggestions that the rhetorical and regulatory changes occurred because prosecutorial misconduct has become more prevalent. It identifies other social causes: a public awakening to criminal justice problems for which prosecutors bear responsibility; revelations, in particular, regarding the role of prosecutorial misconduct in wrongful conviction cases; new social science understandings about social and psychological predicates for prosecutorial wrongdoing; and reform organizations’ inclusion of systemic prosecutorial reform on their agenda. The article shows how the internet has served as the essential catalyst for shifting public and judicial attitudes. The article concludes by predicting that the old and new approaches to prosecutorial accountability will coexist into the foreseeable future, and that the implications will include both a more active judicial role in critiquing and overseeing prosecutors and increased self-regulation by prosecutors’ offices.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"30 1","pages":"51"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-01-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80951122","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
DNA and Distrust DNA和不信任
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-01-20 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2473728
Kerry Abrams, Brandon L. Garrett
{"title":"DNA and Distrust","authors":"Kerry Abrams, Brandon L. Garrett","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2473728","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2473728","url":null,"abstract":"Over the past three decades, government regulation and funding of DNA testing has reshaped the use of genetic evidence across various fields, including criminal law, family law, and employment law. Courts have struggled with questions of when and whether to treat genetic evidence as implicating individual rights, policy trade-offs, or federalism problems. We identify two modes of genetic testing: identification testing, used to establish a person’s identity, and predictive testing, which seeks to predict outcomes for a person. Judges and lawmakers have often drawn a bright line at predictive testing, while allowing uninhibited identity testing. The U.S. Supreme Court in Maryland v. King, for example, held that entering arrestee DNA in databanks does not implicate substantial Fourth Amendment concerns, since police do not test for genetic predispositions “not relevant to identity.” We argue that policy implications of genetic testing laws cannot be so neatly demarked. For example, federal welfare laws require states to use DNA to establish paternity to collect child support from “deadbeat dads,” which may be relevant to identity, but also creates potentially destabilizing effects on families. We explore how genetic testing has been legally regulated across a variety of fields. We identify two dominant modes of regulatory action dealing with genetics: data-driven and ethics-based. Data-driven legislation is ostensibly focused on short-term benefits of gathering a population’s genetic information. Ethics-based legislation, in contrast, is concerned with long-term consequences, such as effects on privacy. We particularly critique data-driven legislation, and we argue that judges, legislators and scholars should focus squarely on the individual and government interests at stake. We set out a list of five factors that legal actors should consider when considering genetics regulation: (1) equality, (2) accuracy, (3) privacy, (4) finality, and (5) federalism. In particular, equality concerns permeate the short history of DNA regulation. In each of the areas explored, comparatively disadvantaged groups such as arrestees, convicts, juveniles, noncitizens, and welfare recipients, have received the most intrusive regulation and collection of their genetic evidence, while comparatively privileged persons benefit from enhanced genetic privacy. We conclude that the regulation of genetic evidence deserves far more careful legal scrutiny, since the ways that genetic evidence is deployed can profoundly affect constitutional rights and the structure of legal and social institutions.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"12 1","pages":"757"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-01-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82914275","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16
Why the Right to Elective Abortion Fails Casey's Own Interest-Balancing Methodology -- And Why It Matters 为什么选择性堕胎的权利不符合凯西自己的利益平衡方法——为什么它很重要
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-01-18 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2489652
Stephen G. Gilles
{"title":"Why the Right to Elective Abortion Fails Casey's Own Interest-Balancing Methodology -- And Why It Matters","authors":"Stephen G. Gilles","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2489652","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2489652","url":null,"abstract":"In Planned Parenthood v. Casey, the Supreme Court reaffirmed the right to elective abortion before viability, but abandoned Roe v. Wade’s characterization of it as a fundamental right that can be overcome only by a compelling state interest. Instead, Casey treats the right to elective abortion as grounded in an interest-balancing judgment that the woman’s liberty interest in terminating her pregnancy outweighs the state’s interest in protecting pre-viable fetal life. Remarkably, however, the Casey Court did not defend that interest-balancing judgment on the merits: indeed, three of the five Justices in the majority expressly declined to explain how they would have decided the interest-balancing question as an original matter. As a result, the majority was forced to rely on stare decisis and related considerations of \"institutional integrity.\" In this Article, I engage in the interest-balancing analysis Casey omitted, and argue that the right to elective abortion is unsound in Casey’s own terms. I assume the validity of Casey’s \"reasoned judgment\" approach to identifying unenumerated rights, including the interest-balancing methodology Casey used to reshape the right to elective abortion. I also assume that Casey (like Roe before it) is correct in characterizing the pre-viable fetus as \"potential human life\" rather than as an actual, normatively human being. These are obviously unfavorable premises on which to argue against a right to elective abortion. But that is precisely the point. My thesis is that even when an interest-balancing analysis is conducted on terms generally favorable to recognizing a constitutional right to elective abortion, the state’s interest in protecting the life of the pre-viable fetus prevails.I make that case through a close reading of Casey, careful descriptions and comparisons of the competing state and individual interests, and a concise analysis of the treatment of abortion – and of fetal life generally – in the Anglo-American legal tradition. As to precedent, I argue that a majority of the Justices in Casey believed that the state’s interest in protecting fetal life outweighs the woman’s interest in an elective abortion, and that their judgments should carry appreciable weight because they dictated Casey’s reliance on stare decisis. As to the competing interests, I acknowledge that the woman’s interest is entitled to great weight, but argue that the fetus’s inherent, self-directing \"potential\" to develop into a normatively human being should lead us to assign even greater weight to protecting its life – and its future. As for history, building on the scholarship of Joseph Dellapenna and others, I argue that the Anglo-American legal tradition has always protected the lives of fetuses once they could be known to be alive – initially at quickening, and throughout pregnancy once the basic facts of embryology were discovered in the 19th century. Precedent, reasoned evaluation of the competing interests, and tradition all","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"38 1","pages":"5"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-01-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76712168","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Religion and Social Coherentism 宗教与社会一致性
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2016-01-06 DOI: 10.31228/osf.io/5qgak
N. Tebbe
{"title":"Religion and Social Coherentism","authors":"N. Tebbe","doi":"10.31228/osf.io/5qgak","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/5qgak","url":null,"abstract":"Today, prominent academics are questioning the very possibility of a theory of free exercise or non-establishment. They argue that judgments in the area can only be conclusory or irrational. In contrast to such skeptics, this Essay argues that decisionmaking on questions of religious freedom can be morally justified. Two arguments constitute the Essay. Part I begins by acknowledging that skepticism has power. The skeptics rightly identify some inevitable indeterminacy, but they mistakenly argue that it necessarily signals decisionmaking that is irrational or unjustified. Their critique is especially striking because the skeptics’ prudential way of working on concrete problems actually shares much with the methods of others. Part II then argues that the best defense of religious freedom jurisprudence begins with an approach known as coherentism. In political philosophy, coherentism refers to the way legal actors compare new problems to existing principles and paradigms in order to identify solutions that are justified. The Essay then extracts and emphasizes the social aspects of this basic account. It contends that arguments about the meaning of the Constitution appropriately reflect social and political dynamics. The resulting approach, social coherentism, describes a powerful method for generating interpretations of the First Amendment that are justified, not conclusory. This matters at a moment when some defenders of religious traditionalism are suggesting that principled decisionmaking on questions of religious freedom is impossible, and therefore that such issues should be largely surrendered to political processes.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"1 1","pages":"363"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2016-01-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78425058","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Supreme Court's Quiet Revolution in Induced Patent Infringement 最高法院对诱导专利侵权的悄无声息的改革
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2015-08-29 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2653077
T. Holbrook
{"title":"The Supreme Court's Quiet Revolution in Induced Patent Infringement","authors":"T. Holbrook","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2653077","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2653077","url":null,"abstract":"The Supreme Court over the last decade or so has reengaged with patent law. While much attention has been paid to the Court’s reworking of what constitutes patent eligible subject matter and enhancing tools to combat “patent trolls,” what many have missed is the Court’s reworking of the contours of active inducement of patent infringement under 35 U.S.C. § 271(b). The Court has taken the same number of § 271(b) cases as subject matter eligibility cases – four. Yet this reworking has not garnered much attention in the literature. This article offers the first comprehensive assessment of the Court’s efforts to define active inducement. In so doing, it identifies the surprising significance of the Court’s most recent case, Commil USA, LLC v. Cisco Systems, Inc., where the Court held that a good faith belief on the part of the accused inducer cannot negate the mental state required for inducement – the intent to induce acts of infringement. In so doing, the Court moved away from its policy of encouraging challenges to patent validity as articulated in Lear, Inc. v. Adkins and its progeny. This step away from Lear is significant and surprising, particularly where critiques of the patent system suggest there are too many invalid patents creating issues for competition. This article critiques these aspects of Commil and then addresses lingering, unanswered questions. In particular, this article suggests that a good faith belief that the induced acts are not infringing, which remains as a defense, should only act as a shield against past damages and not against prospective relief such as injunctions or ongoing royalties. The courts so far have failed to appreciate this important temporal dynamic.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"27 1","pages":"1007"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2015-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84361680","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The Fixation Thesis: The Role of Historical Fact in Original Meaning 固定命题:历史事实在原意中的作用
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2015-08-05 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2559701
Lawrence B. Solum
{"title":"The Fixation Thesis: The Role of Historical Fact in Original Meaning","authors":"Lawrence B. Solum","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2559701","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2559701","url":null,"abstract":"The central debate in contemporary constitutional theory is the clash between originalists and living constitutionalists. Originalism is the view that the original meaning of the constitutional text should constrain or bind constitutional practice — paradigmatically, the decision of constitutional cases by the United States Supreme Court. Living constitutionalists contend that the content of constitutional law should evolve over time in response to changing values and circumstances. One of the central questions in this debate is over the question whether the meaning of the constitutional text is fixed or changeable. This essay makes the case for the Fixation Thesis — the claim that the linguistic meaning (or communicative content) of the constitutional text was fixed when each provision was framed and ratified. Although the Fixation Thesis is a basic assumption of almost every version of originalism or textualism, it has never been the explicit focus of an extended examination and defense. This essay remedies that lacuna by providing a precise formulation of the fixation thesis, making the affirmative case for fixation, and answering potential objections. The most important claim made by the essay is that the Fixation Thesis is entailed by our common sense understanding of how communication works. Communicative content is created by using conventional semantic meanings (fixed by linguistic practices at the time words are used) and context (which is fixed by the understanding of author and reader at the time a writing is created).The essay proceeds in five steps. Part One clarifies the Fixation Thesis by situating it in the content of contemporary debates about originalism. Part Two states the affirmative case for the fixation thesis and articulates several versions of the argument corresponding to different members of the originalist family of constitutional theories. Part Three provides additional clarification and answers objections. Part Four examines rival theories of constitutional meaning that deny fixation. Part Five explores two examples, “cruel and unusual punishment” and “privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States.”This is the final published version of the \"The Fixation Thesis\" and it replaces the earlier versions previously available at this location.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"10 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2015-08-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87317260","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 25
Assessing the Role of History in the Federal Courts Canon: A Word of Caution 评估历史在联邦法院经典中的作用:一个警告
IF 0.9 3区 社会学
Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2015-07-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2652585
A. Tyler
{"title":"Assessing the Role of History in the Federal Courts Canon: A Word of Caution","authors":"A. Tyler","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2652585","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2652585","url":null,"abstract":"One of the most pervasive and important debates in federal courts jurisprudence is over the role that history should play in interpreting Article III of the United States Constitution. To that end, federal courts jurisprudence is not altogether different from constitutional law jurisprudence more generally. But in the federal courts arena — more so than in the broader domain of constitutional law — originalism has always wielded tremendous influence over much of the judicial and scholarly thinking. It is for this reason that a distinct conversation about its role in the federal courts canon is appropriate.There is little question that in the field of federal courts, historical study has a great deal to contribute to modern debates. Indeed, historical study holds enormous potential to illuminate the founding purpose behind constitutional provisions, to unearth contemporary meanings associated with terms of art that were included in the document, and to uncover important evidence relating to historical practices and context, which in turn can shed light on the background understandings and assumptions that underlie constitutional text. But sometimes — if not often — the historical record on important questions of federal courts jurisprudence is absent, incomplete, or more complex than jurists and scholars tend to acknowledge. In keeping with this idea, one should never forget that certain aspects of the Constitution — including Article III and the structural framework within which it is situated — represented major innovations in their time. At the Founding, the concept of federalism — and with it the idea of two sets of courts, state and federal — was entirely new. Moreover, the separation of powers framework was, at the least, a transformation of the British model, if not a dramatic departure from it. Against this backdrop, it would be curious indeed if the details of the Article III power were fully settled from the outset. More likely, as Madison recognized early on, there would need to be a “liquidat[ion]” of meaning over time.Accordingly, I wish to offer a word of caution about making historical arguments in federal courts jurisprudence. Specifically, in undertaking historical inquiry in the field of federal courts, one must be careful about assigning certain data points from the Founding period determinative weight, rather than treating them as part of a larger conversation about the role of the judicial power in our constitutional framework. This is because in studying the early years following ratification of the Constitution, one tends to find both examples of major principles that remained the subject of disagreement as well as examples of early legislation and practices that today we would reject as plainly inconsistent with the constitutional separation of powers. As historian Jack Rakove has observed, the Founding period documents are the product of collective decisionmaking “whose outcomes necessarily reflected a bewildering array of","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":"19 1","pages":"1739-1752"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2015-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77160261","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
相关产品
×
本文献相关产品
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信