Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy最新文献

筛选
英文 中文
Regulation of Franchisor Opportunism and Production of the Institutional Framework: Federal Monopoly or Competition Between the States? 特许人机会主义的规制与制度框架的产生:联邦垄断还是州间竞争?
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 2000-03-21 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.186049
Alan J. Meese
{"title":"Regulation of Franchisor Opportunism and Production of the Institutional Framework: Federal Monopoly or Competition Between the States?","authors":"Alan J. Meese","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.186049","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.186049","url":null,"abstract":"The Sherman Act forbids contracts that restrain interstate commerce, and proof of significant market power is usually necessary to establish the existence of such a restraint. Recently, however, some have argued that courts should employ the Sherman Act to regulate opportunistic behavior by franchisors that do not possess the sort of market power ordinarily necessary to establish antitrust liability. Inspired by the Supreme Court's decision in Eastman Kodak v. Image Technical Services, these advocates find \"market power\" in the presence of relationship-specific investments and would impose antitrust liability on franchisors that abuse such power to the detriment of their franchisees. Informational asymmetries and bargaining costs, it is said, prevent franchisees from protecting themselves in the bargaining process from unduly onerous contractual terms. This essay argues that reliance upon the Sherman Act to combat franchisor opportunism would constitute an unjustified expansion of federal regulatory authority and upset the traditional division of labor between states and the national government. To be sure, scholars have provided a plausible story of opportunism in the franchising context, where bargaining and information costs can be significant. Still, these advocates have not explained why federal regulation of such behavior is warranted. As Professor Coase has recognized, bargaining and information costs do not exist in a vacuum, but are instead a function of the institutional framework, a framework constructed by background rules of (state) contract law that lower the costs of entering and maintaining relational contracts. Any argument for federal intervention to combat opportunism, then, must explain why the background rules of contract law are not adequate to minimize information and bargaining costs and thus deter opportunistic behavior. More precisely, those who advocate Sherman Act regulation of franchiser opportunism must demonstrate that competition between the states to produce the institutional framework governing the franchisor-franchisee relationship is characterized by a \"race to the bottom\" that warrants federal intervention. Preliminary analysis suggests that such a race to the bottom is unlikely. No state can become a \"haven\" for opportunistic franchisors without the cooperation of other states, who must enforce the franchisor's choice of law clauses. Moreover, states that adopt institutional frameworks that raise the cost of transacting and thus facilitate franchisor opportunism will raise the costs of intrastate transactions and make their own citizens vulnerable to opportunism. Federalizing this body of law, then, would unnecessarily deprive businesses and consumers of the benefits of interjurisdictional competition.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2000-03-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.186049","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67763471","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Toward a Principled Interpretation of the Commerce Clause 商事条款的原则性解释
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1998-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D86H4H17
T. Merrill
{"title":"Toward a Principled Interpretation of the Commerce Clause","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D86H4H17","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D86H4H17","url":null,"abstract":"Formalism is the jurisprudence of rules.1 Functionalism is the jurisprudence of balancing tests.2 If forced to choose between formalism and functionalism, I would probably corne down on the side of formalism. I would not do so, however, because there is some meta-rule that prescribes formalism. Rather, it would be because formalism, on balance, has better consequences than functionalism-in other words, because there are good functionalist reasons to be a formalist.3 Where I part company with many constitutional formalists is not so much over the desirability of rules as opposed to ad hoc balancing,4 but rather over the generality and the source of the","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"22 1","pages":"31-43"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1998-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71364962","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Judicial Review and Federalism 司法审查与联邦制
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1998-01-01 DOI: 10.2307/j.ctv56fggn.12
J. Yoo
{"title":"Judicial Review and Federalism","authors":"J. Yoo","doi":"10.2307/j.ctv56fggn.12","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv56fggn.12","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"22 1","pages":"197"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1998-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68813459","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Does Public Choice Theory Justify Judicial Activism After All 公共选择理论是否为司法能动主义辩护
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1997-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D8Z037S2
T. Merrill
{"title":"Does Public Choice Theory Justify Judicial Activism After All","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D8Z037S2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8Z037S2","url":null,"abstract":"Some legal scholars have argued that public choice theory justifies certain kinds of judicial activism.! Others have said it does not. 2 Given the present state of the debate, it would appear that those finding no necessary support for judicial activism have the stronger argument. I will suggest, however, that if we tweak the analysis a little further, it may turn out that public choice theory provides limited support for judicial activism after all. From an economic perspective-which is to say, the public choice perspective-it may be useful to think of judicial activism as part of a larger market in which a product called \"law change\" is bought and sold.3 This market has many potential buyers, in the form of the interest groups to which the previous panelists have already referred. Virtually every group has some change in law it would like to see adopted, whether it be producer groups that would like to see new limitations on entry by potential competitors, or environmental groups that would like to see new limitations on the development of natural resources. On the seller side, we can simplifY the analysis by assuming that there are only two firms in the market for law change-the legislature and the courts. We can then reformulate the inquiry as follows: what sorts of factors will determine the demand for","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"21 1","pages":"219-230"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1997-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71368437","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 14
Bork V. Burke 伯克V.伯克
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1996-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D8S46RKJ
T. Merrill
{"title":"Bork V. Burke","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D8S46RKJ","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8S46RKJ","url":null,"abstract":"I would like to make the case for a conservative alternative to originalism. Much of the discussion that has taken place over the last two days has proceeded on the assumption that there are two choices. One is Robert Bork's originalism,1 justified by various values near and dear to conservative hearts, such as the rule of law, continuity with the past, the principle of democratic accountability, and so forth. The other is to flee into the hands of the so-called nonoriginalists, and embrace, to quote Judge Easterbrook quotingJustice Brennan, the judge's \"personal confrontation with the well-springs 6f our society.\"2 My thesis is that there is a third option, which I will call conventionalism.' Conventionalism draws much of its inspiration from the writings of a British politician and man of letters, Edmund Burke.4 I will argue that there is a Burkean or conventionalist approach to interpretation that is distinct from both Borkean originalism and from the various types of nonoriginalism favored in the legal academy, which I will lump together under the label normativism. I will also argue that the conventionalist approach can be justified by the same conservative values-the rule of law, promotion of democracy, and so on-that","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"19 1","pages":"509-523"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1996-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71368001","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
A Modest Proposal for a Political Court 一个关于政治法庭的温和建议
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1994-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D80P0ZMK
T. Merrill
{"title":"A Modest Proposal for a Political Court","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D80P0ZMK","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D80P0ZMK","url":null,"abstract":"I offer a modest proposal. You can decide for yourself whether it is offered in the spirit of Jonathan Swift,1 or whether I mean it to be taken seriously. The legitimacy of the Supreme Court is widely assumed to depend on the perception that its decisions are dictated by law. This is the central thesis of the extraordinary joint opinion in Planned Parenthood v. Casey,' decided by the Supreme Court at the end of the 1991 Term. The joint opinion observes that the Court's power lies in its legitimacy, and that its legitimacy is \"a product of the substance and perception\" that it is a court of law.3 Thus, frequent overrulings are to be avoided, because this would \"overtax the country's belief' that the Court's rulings are grounded in law.4 Especially when a controversial ruling like Roe v. Wad is involved, a decision to overrule should be avoided at all costs, because this would give rise to the perception that the Court is \"surrender[ing] to political pressure\" or \"over-nul[ing] under fire.\"6 Such a perception, in turn, would lead to \"loss of confidence in the judiciary.\"7 Translated, the thesis of the joint opinion is that the further a decision deviates from the Constitution, the more important it is for the Court to adhere to that decision, or else the public may conclude that the emperor is wearing no clothes.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"17 1","pages":"137-147"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1994-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71363329","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
An International Rule of Law. By Eberhard P. Deutsch. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1977. Pp. xxix, 389. Appendixes. Index. $20. 国际法治。埃伯哈德·p·多伊奇著。夏洛茨维尔:弗吉尼亚大学出版社,1977年。第29页,389页。附录。索引。20美元。
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1980-04-01 DOI: 10.2307/2201524
Peter D. Trooboff
{"title":"An International Rule of Law. By Eberhard P. Deutsch. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1977. Pp. xxix, 389. Appendixes. Index. $20.","authors":"Peter D. Trooboff","doi":"10.2307/2201524","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/2201524","url":null,"abstract":"ments (pp. 145, 296, 338,353,355, 359, 390, and 391), some actually adopted, others merely proposed and left to perish from indifference (pp. 300, 373, and 379). In consequence, the author repeatedly finds himself involved in discussion of points that lead nowhere and of distinctions that, in the end, prove to be without differences. For example, following elaborate discussion, he is led to admit that in respect of succession as applied to African regional organizations, political interests have voided of juridical content the otherwise significant distinction between real and movable property (pp. 380, 387). One must question the author's assertion that there has been no problem in recognizing succession of international organizations in the case of the takeover of the properties of the East African Common Services Organization (EACSO) by the East African Community. The latter organization was the creation of three independent states (Kenya, Tanzania, and Uganda), whereas the former was a structure created unilaterally by the British Government. The emphasis is on \"succession\" as applied to the Afro-Malagasy Union (UAM), the Afro-Malagasy Organization of Economic Cooperation (OAMCE), the Afro-Malagasy Union of Economic Cooperation (UAMCE), and the Afro-Malagasy Common Organization (OCAM). Contributions from French authors are extensively cited and quoted, including unpublished lectures (repetitions ecrites), to the almost total exclusion of works in English. Little use has been made of the jurisprudence of the International Court of Justice in the South West Africa, the AngloIranian, and the Aerial Incident cases, and the theoretical underpinnings of the problem are completely ignored. Nor can one share Professor Bastid's enthusiasm for the \"meticulous treatment of materials and discussion\" and \"the care in assembling documentation\" (pp. x, xi). A generous indifference to accuracy infuses both the text and quotations from official documents (pp. 32, 71, 77, 173, 195, 337, 375, and 389).","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"74 1","pages":"463 - 464"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1980-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/2201524","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"69271060","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 68
Understanding “ The Loop ” : Autonomy , System Decision-Making , and the Next Generation of War Machines 理解“循环”:自主性、系统决策和下一代战争机器
IF 0.6 4区 社会学
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2043131
{"title":"Understanding “ The Loop ” : Autonomy , System Decision-Making , and the Next Generation of War Machines","authors":"","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2043131","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2043131","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/ssrn.2043131","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67877112","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
相关产品
×
本文献相关产品
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信