The Social Institution of Discursive Norms最新文献

筛选
英文 中文
Discursive Injustice and the Speech of Indigenous Communities 话语不公正与原住民社群的言论
The Social Institution of Discursive Norms Pub Date : 2021-05-05 DOI: 10.4324/9781003047483-14
Leo Townsend
{"title":"Discursive Injustice and the Speech of Indigenous Communities","authors":"Leo Townsend","doi":"10.4324/9781003047483-14","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003047483-14","url":null,"abstract":"An important strand in recent feminist philosophy of language has been guided by the thought that speech is social action, and more specifically that the performance of speech acts requires not only a contribution from a suitably competent and entitled speaker but also that the speaker’s contribution be given a suitable reception or social uptake. Put somewhat crudely, the idea is that, in order to perform a speech act of, say, promising, or telling, or warning, a speaker must be taken by others as doing so. In this way, speakers are thought to depend profoundly on the competence, goodwill, and receptiveness of others—their audiences and other relevant parties—in order to exercise their linguistic agency. The idea that speakers are profoundly dependent in this way on others has prompted a lot of discussion about what could be called the politics of uptake. In particular, feminist philosophers of language working within this tradition have highlighted various kinds of injustice that occur in speech situations. Certain speakers from are said to be “silenced,” or to be the victims of “discursive injustice,” on account of the social reception their acts routinely receive.1 Though the philosophers working in this field acknowledge the broad significance and applicability of this theoretical framework, the overwhelming focus of the extant literature is on the ways in which the speech of women, in particular, is unjustly disempowered. In this chapter, my aim is to explore how unjust uptake impedes the speech of a different kind of speaker—Indigenous communities. This involves looking focusing on Indigeneity rather than gender as the salient social identity, and looking at the ways that group speech, rather than only individual speech, can be unjustly impeded. I argue that, just as the speech of women is often heard in ways that tend to reinforce their disempowerment, so too is the speech of Indigenous communities routinely taken in ways that contribute toward their ongoing marginalization and disenfranchisement. In order to make this argument, I adopt a “social normativist” approach to speech acts. After briefly outlining the framework (Section 2), 11 Discursive Injustice and the Speech of Indigenous Communities","PeriodicalId":343943,"journal":{"name":"The Social Institution of Discursive Norms","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-05-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130315442","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Assertion 断言
The Social Institution of Discursive Norms Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.4135/9781412972024.n154
Ladislav Koreň
{"title":"Assertion","authors":"Ladislav Koreň","doi":"10.4135/9781412972024.n154","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4135/9781412972024.n154","url":null,"abstract":"In every assertion we may distinguish a speaker and a listener. The latter, it is true, need have only a problematical existence, as when during a shipwreck an account of the accident is sealed in a bottle and thrown upon the water. The problematical “listener” may be within the same person as the “speaker”; as when we mentally register a judgment, to be remembered later. If there be any act of judgment independent of any registry, and if it have any logical significance (which is disputable), we may say that in that case the listener becomes identical with the speaker.","PeriodicalId":343943,"journal":{"name":"The Social Institution of Discursive Norms","volume":"33 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115278179","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1114
Normative Attitudes 规范的态度
The Social Institution of Discursive Norms Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.4324/9781003047483-8
J. Peregrin
{"title":"Normative Attitudes","authors":"J. Peregrin","doi":"10.4324/9781003047483-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003047483-8","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":343943,"journal":{"name":"The Social Institution of Discursive Norms","volume":"219 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131315449","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
相关产品
×
本文献相关产品
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信