共振教育

IF 1 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH
Stanton Wortham
{"title":"共振教育","authors":"Stanton Wortham","doi":"10.1111/edth.12683","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>The articles in this symposium make two important contributions: they introduce and explain the powerful but opaque philosophy of Jean-Luc Nancy; and they show how his philosophy illuminates central issues in education. Their accounts also diverge in interesting ways, raising provocative questions for the philosophy of education.</p><p>The contributors describe how <i>being with</i> captures Nancy's core ontological claim. The basic level of human being is in relation to others. As David Hansen articulates, we exist only “in common,” through activities with others.<sup>1</sup> This does not mean that we are subsumed into a group, however. We are simultaneously <i>singular-plural</i>. “Being with” captures individual distinctiveness as well as connectedness, without reducing one to the other.</p><p>The contributors argue that for Nancy the paradigmatic human activity is not individual cognition about the world, but is instead <i>listening</i>. As Eduardo Duarte Bono says, we must replace “the [Cartesian] philosophical subject” with “the listening subject,” and we must replace the predominant visual metaphor with a musical one.<sup>2</sup> Instead of standing apart from the world and observing it, we “resonate” with something in the world and are taken out of ourselves by it. As Sophie Haroutunian-Gordon and Megan Laverty say, “the listener's search for meaning … is a search guided by felt resonance rather than intellectual cognizing, at least initially.”<sup>3</sup> The traditional philosophical focus on internal self-reflection, according to Nancy, impedes genuine listening and distorts our relations with others and the world.</p><p>Nancy does not eliminate the subject, but he focuses on <i>resonant subjectivity</i>. Our basic mode of experiencing the world involves resonating with aspects of it. Duarte Bono explores this musical metaphor, describing how listening to music involves a “letting go” of oneself and an openness to experience. Together with Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty, Duarte Bono shows how music evokes meaning, how it can be transformative even though it does not contain analytic messages. Hansen describes this as a “pre-cognitive” responsiveness to the world.</p><p><i>Touch</i> is another important metaphor for Nancy. Unlike vision, touch involves contact with others and a distinctive immediacy. It is a second-person experience, in contact with something next to me. This contrasts with the third-person experience of analytic abstraction associated with vision and the Cartesian subject. René Arcilla explains how this emphasis on resonance and touch demands a different attitude toward experience — an “opening” or an “expansion of being.” According to Arcilla, Nancy calls for “bearing witness and lyrically summoning other witnesses.” We should not strive for “conclusive epiphany,” but for “perpetual intimation.”<sup>4</sup></p><p>This is a process-based philosophy, emphasizing <i>becoming</i>. Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty describe how meaning emerges gradually in listening, through resonance that connects to prior experience but remains open to the world. This process does not end with a final judgment. Hansen shows that, for Nancy, human life involves an unending series of “co-appearances.” There are no stable individuals or stable groups that are ontologically prior. We exist only as we are with others, across a series of spontaneous, contingent, unique events. Arcilla uses the metaphor of “dance” to capture this — we are all involved in this dance, with ongoing responsiveness to and interconnections with others.</p><p>Each time we encounter and resonate with others it changes us, and it changes them. This means that individuals travel <i>unique pathways</i>. Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty describe how an individual potentially becomes a new person in each experience, across the series of events that make up a life. Hansen summarizes Nancy's account of an individual “as a being who embodies a lived, dynamic history of responses to experience, and who is influenced by others who are responding in their distinctive ways.” Individuals are distinctive and deserve respect not because they possess a moral core, but because of their unique pathway across experience and their ability to take distinctive stances and engage others.</p><p>Listening and “being with” thus have an <i>ethical</i> dimension. Individuals have dignity, based in their unique histories and their capacity to engage with and draw out resonance in others. We owe others true “listening,” which Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty characterize as being open to more challenging meanings, as opposed to simply “hearing” others by employing familiar categories. We owe others openness and respect. Hansen describes this moral obligation in the context of teaching, arguing that teachers must attend to the distinctiveness of individual students and unique moments. Instead of imposing abstract categories, or dealing in exchange value and instrumental rationality, we must be open to and engage with others — acknowledging their unique history of engagement in “the dance” and their capacity to evoke resonance in us.</p><p>Arcilla connects Nancy's ontology to politics, describing the kind of “<i>we</i>” implied by our “being with.” The Cartesian subject presupposes autonomous individuals who pursue self-determination, fundamentally separate from others. In contrast, Nancy argues that people are always already with others. This presupposes some kind of collective. But Arcilla argues that two kinds of collectives on offer at this historical moment do not suffice. On one hand, we have universalizing visions that presuppose we are all the same, typically taking the norms of one ethnic or economic group as allegedly universal. On the other hand, we have essentializing identity politics that claims some ethnic or economic characteristic binds together supposedly homogeneous groups. Both of these erase the uniqueness of individuals and close off spontaneous, unexpected experience. Nancy wants a sense of community that is not based on fixed, shared characteristics. Instead, he imagines a community based in our mutual participation in the ongoing dance of engagement with others.</p>","PeriodicalId":47134,"journal":{"name":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","volume":"74 6","pages":"963-967"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2025-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/edth.12683","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Resonant Education\",\"authors\":\"Stanton Wortham\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/edth.12683\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>The articles in this symposium make two important contributions: they introduce and explain the powerful but opaque philosophy of Jean-Luc Nancy; and they show how his philosophy illuminates central issues in education. Their accounts also diverge in interesting ways, raising provocative questions for the philosophy of education.</p><p>The contributors describe how <i>being with</i> captures Nancy's core ontological claim. The basic level of human being is in relation to others. As David Hansen articulates, we exist only “in common,” through activities with others.<sup>1</sup> This does not mean that we are subsumed into a group, however. We are simultaneously <i>singular-plural</i>. “Being with” captures individual distinctiveness as well as connectedness, without reducing one to the other.</p><p>The contributors argue that for Nancy the paradigmatic human activity is not individual cognition about the world, but is instead <i>listening</i>. As Eduardo Duarte Bono says, we must replace “the [Cartesian] philosophical subject” with “the listening subject,” and we must replace the predominant visual metaphor with a musical one.<sup>2</sup> Instead of standing apart from the world and observing it, we “resonate” with something in the world and are taken out of ourselves by it. As Sophie Haroutunian-Gordon and Megan Laverty say, “the listener's search for meaning … is a search guided by felt resonance rather than intellectual cognizing, at least initially.”<sup>3</sup> The traditional philosophical focus on internal self-reflection, according to Nancy, impedes genuine listening and distorts our relations with others and the world.</p><p>Nancy does not eliminate the subject, but he focuses on <i>resonant subjectivity</i>. Our basic mode of experiencing the world involves resonating with aspects of it. Duarte Bono explores this musical metaphor, describing how listening to music involves a “letting go” of oneself and an openness to experience. Together with Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty, Duarte Bono shows how music evokes meaning, how it can be transformative even though it does not contain analytic messages. Hansen describes this as a “pre-cognitive” responsiveness to the world.</p><p><i>Touch</i> is another important metaphor for Nancy. Unlike vision, touch involves contact with others and a distinctive immediacy. It is a second-person experience, in contact with something next to me. This contrasts with the third-person experience of analytic abstraction associated with vision and the Cartesian subject. René Arcilla explains how this emphasis on resonance and touch demands a different attitude toward experience — an “opening” or an “expansion of being.” According to Arcilla, Nancy calls for “bearing witness and lyrically summoning other witnesses.” We should not strive for “conclusive epiphany,” but for “perpetual intimation.”<sup>4</sup></p><p>This is a process-based philosophy, emphasizing <i>becoming</i>. Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty describe how meaning emerges gradually in listening, through resonance that connects to prior experience but remains open to the world. This process does not end with a final judgment. Hansen shows that, for Nancy, human life involves an unending series of “co-appearances.” There are no stable individuals or stable groups that are ontologically prior. We exist only as we are with others, across a series of spontaneous, contingent, unique events. Arcilla uses the metaphor of “dance” to capture this — we are all involved in this dance, with ongoing responsiveness to and interconnections with others.</p><p>Each time we encounter and resonate with others it changes us, and it changes them. This means that individuals travel <i>unique pathways</i>. Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty describe how an individual potentially becomes a new person in each experience, across the series of events that make up a life. Hansen summarizes Nancy's account of an individual “as a being who embodies a lived, dynamic history of responses to experience, and who is influenced by others who are responding in their distinctive ways.” Individuals are distinctive and deserve respect not because they possess a moral core, but because of their unique pathway across experience and their ability to take distinctive stances and engage others.</p><p>Listening and “being with” thus have an <i>ethical</i> dimension. Individuals have dignity, based in their unique histories and their capacity to engage with and draw out resonance in others. We owe others true “listening,” which Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty characterize as being open to more challenging meanings, as opposed to simply “hearing” others by employing familiar categories. We owe others openness and respect. Hansen describes this moral obligation in the context of teaching, arguing that teachers must attend to the distinctiveness of individual students and unique moments. Instead of imposing abstract categories, or dealing in exchange value and instrumental rationality, we must be open to and engage with others — acknowledging their unique history of engagement in “the dance” and their capacity to evoke resonance in us.</p><p>Arcilla connects Nancy's ontology to politics, describing the kind of “<i>we</i>” implied by our “being with.” The Cartesian subject presupposes autonomous individuals who pursue self-determination, fundamentally separate from others. In contrast, Nancy argues that people are always already with others. This presupposes some kind of collective. But Arcilla argues that two kinds of collectives on offer at this historical moment do not suffice. On one hand, we have universalizing visions that presuppose we are all the same, typically taking the norms of one ethnic or economic group as allegedly universal. On the other hand, we have essentializing identity politics that claims some ethnic or economic characteristic binds together supposedly homogeneous groups. Both of these erase the uniqueness of individuals and close off spontaneous, unexpected experience. Nancy wants a sense of community that is not based on fixed, shared characteristics. Instead, he imagines a community based in our mutual participation in the ongoing dance of engagement with others.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":47134,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"EDUCATIONAL THEORY\",\"volume\":\"74 6\",\"pages\":\"963-967\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2025-01-09\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/edth.12683\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"EDUCATIONAL THEORY\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/edth.12683\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/edth.12683","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

这个研讨会的文章让两个重要贡献:他们介绍和解释jean - luc南希的强大但不透明的哲学;他们还展示了他的哲学如何阐释了教育中的核心问题。他们的叙述也以有趣的方式出现分歧,为教育哲学提出了一些具有挑衅性的问题。作者描述了“与”是如何抓住南希的核心本体论主张的。人的基本层次是与其他人的关系。正如大卫·汉森所阐明的那样,通过与他人的活动,我们只存在于“共同”之中然而,这并不意味着我们被归入一个群体。我们同时是单复数。“在一起”既抓住了个体的独特性,也抓住了连通性,而不是将其中一个简化为另一个。作者认为,对南希来说,典型的人类活动不是个体对世界的认知,而是倾听。正如爱德华多·杜阿尔特·波诺所说,我们必须用“倾听的主体”取代“(笛卡尔式的)哲学主体”,我们必须用音乐的隐喻取代占主导地位的视觉隐喻我们不是站在世界之外观察它,而是与世界上的某些东西“产生共鸣”,并被它从我们自己身上带走。正如Sophie Haroutunian-Gordon和Megan Laverty所说,“听众对意义的寻找……是一种由感觉共鸣引导的搜索,而不是智力认知,至少在最初是这样。”南希认为,传统的哲学关注于内在的自我反省,阻碍了真诚的倾听,扭曲了我们与他人和世界的关系。南希并没有消除这个主题,但他关注的是共鸣的主体性。我们体验世界的基本模式包括与世界的各个方面产生共鸣。杜阿尔特·波诺(Duarte Bono)探索了这个音乐隐喻,描述了听音乐如何涉及到对自己的“放手”和对体验的开放。与Haroutunian-Gordon和Laverty一起,Duarte Bono展示了音乐是如何唤起意义的,即使它不包含分析信息,它也是如何具有变动性的。汉森将其描述为对世界的“前认知”反应。触摸是南希的另一个重要隐喻。与视觉不同,触觉涉及与他人的接触和独特的即时性。这是一种第二人称的体验,与我身边的事物接触。这与与视觉和笛卡尔主体相关的分析抽象的第三人称经验形成对比。ren<s:1>·阿西拉解释了这种对共鸣和触摸的强调如何要求一种不同的体验态度——一种“开放”或“存在的扩展”。根据阿西拉的说法,南希要求“作证并抒情地传唤其他证人”。我们不应该追求“决定性的顿悟”,而应该追求“永恒的暗示”。这是一种基于过程的哲学,强调成为。Haroutunian-Gordon和Laverty描述了意义是如何在倾听中逐渐出现的,通过与先前经验联系在一起的共鸣,但仍然对世界开放。这一过程不会以最终判决结束。汉森表明,对南希来说,人类的生活包含了一系列无休止的“共同出现”。没有稳定的个体或稳定的群体在本体论上是优先的。我们之所以存在,是因为我们与他人在一起,经历了一系列自发的、偶然的、独特的事件。阿西拉用“舞蹈”的比喻来捕捉这一点——我们都参与了这场舞蹈,与他人保持着持续的反应和相互联系。每次我们与他人相遇并产生共鸣,都会改变我们,也会改变他们。这意味着每个人都走着独特的道路。Haroutunian-Gordon和Laverty描述了一个人如何在每一次经历中潜在地成为一个新的人,跨越构成生活的一系列事件。汉森总结了南希对个人的描述:“一个人体现了对经验的生动的、动态的反应历史,并受到以自己独特方式作出反应的其他人的影响。”每个人都是与众不同的,值得尊重,不是因为他们拥有道德核心,而是因为他们独特的经历,以及他们采取独特立场和吸引他人的能力。因此,倾听和“与”有一个伦理的维度。每个人都有尊严,这是基于他们独特的历史,以及他们与他人接触并引起他人共鸣的能力。我们应该真正的“倾听”他人,Haroutunian-Gordon和Laverty将其描述为对更具挑战性的意义持开放态度,而不是简单地通过使用熟悉的类别来“倾听”他人。我们应该对他人开放和尊重。汉森在教学的背景下描述了这种道德义务,他认为教师必须关注个别学生的独特性和独特的时刻。 我们不应该强加抽象的分类,也不应该处理交换价值和工具理性,我们必须对他人开放并与之交往——承认他们参与“舞蹈”的独特历史,以及他们在我们心中唤起共鸣的能力。阿西拉将南希的本体论与政治联系起来,描述了我们“与”所隐含的那种“我们”。笛卡尔主体预设了追求自我决定的自主个体,从根本上与他人分离。相反,南希认为人们总是已经和别人在一起了。这是以某种集体为前提的。但阿西拉认为,在这个历史时刻,两种类型的集体是不够的。一方面,我们有普遍化的愿景,假设我们都是一样的,通常认为一个种族或经济群体的规范是普遍的。另一方面,我们有本质化的身份政治,声称一些种族或经济特征将本应同质的群体联系在一起。这两者都抹去了个体的独特性,关闭了自发的、意想不到的体验。南希想要的是一种社区意识,而不是基于固定的、共有的特征。相反,他想象了一个基于我们相互参与与他人交往的持续舞蹈的社区。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Resonant Education

The articles in this symposium make two important contributions: they introduce and explain the powerful but opaque philosophy of Jean-Luc Nancy; and they show how his philosophy illuminates central issues in education. Their accounts also diverge in interesting ways, raising provocative questions for the philosophy of education.

The contributors describe how being with captures Nancy's core ontological claim. The basic level of human being is in relation to others. As David Hansen articulates, we exist only “in common,” through activities with others.1 This does not mean that we are subsumed into a group, however. We are simultaneously singular-plural. “Being with” captures individual distinctiveness as well as connectedness, without reducing one to the other.

The contributors argue that for Nancy the paradigmatic human activity is not individual cognition about the world, but is instead listening. As Eduardo Duarte Bono says, we must replace “the [Cartesian] philosophical subject” with “the listening subject,” and we must replace the predominant visual metaphor with a musical one.2 Instead of standing apart from the world and observing it, we “resonate” with something in the world and are taken out of ourselves by it. As Sophie Haroutunian-Gordon and Megan Laverty say, “the listener's search for meaning … is a search guided by felt resonance rather than intellectual cognizing, at least initially.”3 The traditional philosophical focus on internal self-reflection, according to Nancy, impedes genuine listening and distorts our relations with others and the world.

Nancy does not eliminate the subject, but he focuses on resonant subjectivity. Our basic mode of experiencing the world involves resonating with aspects of it. Duarte Bono explores this musical metaphor, describing how listening to music involves a “letting go” of oneself and an openness to experience. Together with Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty, Duarte Bono shows how music evokes meaning, how it can be transformative even though it does not contain analytic messages. Hansen describes this as a “pre-cognitive” responsiveness to the world.

Touch is another important metaphor for Nancy. Unlike vision, touch involves contact with others and a distinctive immediacy. It is a second-person experience, in contact with something next to me. This contrasts with the third-person experience of analytic abstraction associated with vision and the Cartesian subject. René Arcilla explains how this emphasis on resonance and touch demands a different attitude toward experience — an “opening” or an “expansion of being.” According to Arcilla, Nancy calls for “bearing witness and lyrically summoning other witnesses.” We should not strive for “conclusive epiphany,” but for “perpetual intimation.”4

This is a process-based philosophy, emphasizing becoming. Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty describe how meaning emerges gradually in listening, through resonance that connects to prior experience but remains open to the world. This process does not end with a final judgment. Hansen shows that, for Nancy, human life involves an unending series of “co-appearances.” There are no stable individuals or stable groups that are ontologically prior. We exist only as we are with others, across a series of spontaneous, contingent, unique events. Arcilla uses the metaphor of “dance” to capture this — we are all involved in this dance, with ongoing responsiveness to and interconnections with others.

Each time we encounter and resonate with others it changes us, and it changes them. This means that individuals travel unique pathways. Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty describe how an individual potentially becomes a new person in each experience, across the series of events that make up a life. Hansen summarizes Nancy's account of an individual “as a being who embodies a lived, dynamic history of responses to experience, and who is influenced by others who are responding in their distinctive ways.” Individuals are distinctive and deserve respect not because they possess a moral core, but because of their unique pathway across experience and their ability to take distinctive stances and engage others.

Listening and “being with” thus have an ethical dimension. Individuals have dignity, based in their unique histories and their capacity to engage with and draw out resonance in others. We owe others true “listening,” which Haroutunian-Gordon and Laverty characterize as being open to more challenging meanings, as opposed to simply “hearing” others by employing familiar categories. We owe others openness and respect. Hansen describes this moral obligation in the context of teaching, arguing that teachers must attend to the distinctiveness of individual students and unique moments. Instead of imposing abstract categories, or dealing in exchange value and instrumental rationality, we must be open to and engage with others — acknowledging their unique history of engagement in “the dance” and their capacity to evoke resonance in us.

Arcilla connects Nancy's ontology to politics, describing the kind of “we” implied by our “being with.” The Cartesian subject presupposes autonomous individuals who pursue self-determination, fundamentally separate from others. In contrast, Nancy argues that people are always already with others. This presupposes some kind of collective. But Arcilla argues that two kinds of collectives on offer at this historical moment do not suffice. On one hand, we have universalizing visions that presuppose we are all the same, typically taking the norms of one ethnic or economic group as allegedly universal. On the other hand, we have essentializing identity politics that claims some ethnic or economic characteristic binds together supposedly homogeneous groups. Both of these erase the uniqueness of individuals and close off spontaneous, unexpected experience. Nancy wants a sense of community that is not based on fixed, shared characteristics. Instead, he imagines a community based in our mutual participation in the ongoing dance of engagement with others.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
EDUCATIONAL THEORY
EDUCATIONAL THEORY EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH-
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
19
期刊介绍: The general purposes of Educational Theory are to foster the continuing development of educational theory and to encourage wide and effective discussion of theoretical problems within the educational profession. In order to achieve these purposes, the journal is devoted to publishing scholarly articles and studies in the foundations of education, and in related disciplines outside the field of education, which contribute to the advancement of educational theory. It is the policy of the sponsoring organizations to maintain the journal as an open channel of communication and as an open forum for discussion.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信