Symposium Introduction: Discourse Ethical Perspectives on Education in Polarized Political Cultures

IF 1 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH
Christopher Martin
{"title":"Symposium Introduction: Discourse Ethical Perspectives on Education in Polarized Political Cultures","authors":"Christopher Martin","doi":"10.1111/edth.12572","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>When the game of reason-giving and reason-taking is supported by broadly shared norms of civic morality, trust in public deliberation tends to follow. It is far more difficult to practice (and defend) deliberation when these norms, including deliberative norms themselves, are in dispute.</p><p>Is the contemporary situation of liberal democracies more akin to the former or the latter? The jury is still out on the nature, causes, and seriousness of what is sometimes called “political,” “affective,” or “civic” polarization. What does seem clear is that polarization has had an effect on the deliberative dimension of liberal democratic life. One worrisome development is the increasing pressure put on the Supreme Courts of liberal states, such as Canada and the United States, to resolve contentious policy differences as opposed to working them out through deliberative legislatures and informal public spheres.<sup>1</sup> (As many Canadian and UK readers might point out, the word “parliament” means “speak” or “dialogue.”) But education systems also seem to be pulled into the vortex. Many schools and universities have found themselves in the unenviable position of weathering a number of controversial public and political events, be those events real or manufactured by social media actors. And while partisan stirring of the civic pot is by no means new, a polarized political environment has clearly changed public perception of these controversies and the institution's response to them. What was once a “tough call” is now reframed as “picking a side.” But not picking a side is <i>also</i> “picking a side.” The upshot is that schools and universities are shouldering a lot of civic stress (not always well, one might add), and one consequence is a troubling decline in public trust in them. Polarization also has pedagogical costs, especially in terms of classroom deliberation. Consider teaching “controversial issues” as an approach to civic education aimed at fostering better public reasoning and civic tolerance. The framing of some issues as “controversial,” and not others, now seems to risk accusations of partisanship, or even professional misconduct.<sup>2</sup></p><p>Polarization seems to fit the very practical situation that the discourse ethical project aims to address: when basic interpersonal norms and norms of political morality are in fundamental dispute and epistemically uncertain. As Jürgen Habermas puts it, discourse ethics “provides an answer to the predicament in which members of any moral community find themselves when … though they still argue with reasons about moral judgments and beliefs, their substantive background consensus on the underlying moral norms has been shattered.”<sup>3</sup></p><p>Yet, the civic appetite for reason-giving, perspective-taking, tolerance, and intellectual charity seems to ebb exactly when it is most needed. How, then, can discourse ethics guide citizens in dealing with problems of educational policy and practice under polarizing conditions? Are certain accounts, emphasizing some aspects of a discourse ethic over others, better able to capture the philosophical dimensions of these problems? To what extent can/should a discourse ethic provide practical guidance for individual educators and schools working in a polarized culture? Can it motivate deliberation? And what if the institutions themselves are similarly divided? The papers in this symposium take up these practical and conceptual challenges, assessing the educational merits of inclusive deliberation under conditions of moral, epistemic, and educational polarization.</p><p>As mentioned above, polarization seems to undermine civic trust in liberal civic norms and its basic institutions. The first two papers undertake a discourse-theoretical analysis of this phenomenon and how it bears on liberal democratic educational goals.</p><p>Julian Culp offers a comprehensive description of the broader epistemic environment of what he calls “digitized societies” and the challenges that this environment poses to civic education. On his account, a civic education that targets specific pathologies such as “fake news” downplays the economic and technological backdrop that makes productive deliberation (im)possible. Consequently, an education for deliberative democracy should equip future citizens to understand the extent to which, and ways in which, media that we might have once assumed would be conducive to public reasoning and argumentation (social media, for example) in actual fact thwart reasoned agreement and increase hostile, polarizing feelings about our fellow citizens.</p><p>Christopher Martin undertakes an analysis of “indoctrination,” attempting to separate the concept from its increasingly partisan usage as a term indiscriminately applied to entire educational institutions. He claims that “institutional” indoctrination must refer to an alleged failure by that institution to responsibly promote deliberative norms. One characteristic failure is institutional tolerance for “closed” deliberative norms, such as the norm that a demand for reasons in support of some belief P, just because P, is sufficient to justify the discursive exclusion of those making such a demand. Being clear on the concept of indoctrination, Martin argues, can help citizens distinguish legitimate worries about indoctrination from partisan rhetoric.</p><p>Polarization seems to have both a moral and an epistemic dimension. Conflating the two dimensions may further compound the polarization problem. Anniina Leiviskä adopts Habermas's distinction between the justification of “rightness” and “truth” claims in order to better understand recent debates over the nature, scope, and justification of “decolonizing” university curriculum. For Habermas, the validity of “rightness” claims is constructed in the sense that arguments in support of those claims must be publicly available, contestable, and acceptable by all. But truth-claims — claims about what <i>is</i> — are not constructed in this way. Leiviskä argues that a discourse ethical perspective warrants “decolonizing” the university in the sense that its institutional norms and pedagogical practices would greatly benefit from a more inclusive justification. However, epistemic standards are not <i>themselves</i> “de-colonizable” in the sense that such standards are fundamentally incommensurable with, and rival to, different cultural traditions. Universities therefore ought to pursue decolonizing policies on moral grounds while maintaining epistemic standards, such as impartiality and fallibility, that are constitutive of knowledge and understanding.</p><p>Krassimir Stojanov focuses on a constituency often neglected in discourse ethical accounts: children. Stojanov defends a demanding conception of epistemic respect for children in the sense that even very young students should be treated as credible and independent sources of reasons about justice and fairness. This especially matters since, as he puts it, “[p]recisely because of their otherness and strangeness, these perspectives and beliefs, if adults treat them seriously and with epistemic respect, could transcend established norms, and so they could contribute to their further development, revision, or modification as well as to the articulation of new norms and new reasons supporting them.”<sup>4</sup> While children may be in some ways uninformed and naïve about various normative issues, they are also liberated from the prejudices and assumptions that are often carried along with them. Stojanov's analysis suggests that young students have the potential to articulate claims about justice and fairness that put the civic acrimony of adults into childish relief.</p><p>I opened with the idea of trust in public deliberation. We can include here pessimism about the <i>effectiveness</i> of ethical deliberation. The last two papers aim to demonstrate how the philosophical project of discourse ethics motivates empirical insights that have real benefits for educational policy and practice.</p><p>None of the contributions in this symposium frame their argument as a panacea for the conflicts and tensions that currently occupy our public sphere(s). However, they demonstrate the extent to which, and ways in which, reaffirming an educational commitment to deliberative inclusion and tolerance is necessary if we are to have a public sphere, and public reason, at all.</p>","PeriodicalId":47134,"journal":{"name":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-06-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/edth.12572","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/edth.12572","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

When the game of reason-giving and reason-taking is supported by broadly shared norms of civic morality, trust in public deliberation tends to follow. It is far more difficult to practice (and defend) deliberation when these norms, including deliberative norms themselves, are in dispute.

Is the contemporary situation of liberal democracies more akin to the former or the latter? The jury is still out on the nature, causes, and seriousness of what is sometimes called “political,” “affective,” or “civic” polarization. What does seem clear is that polarization has had an effect on the deliberative dimension of liberal democratic life. One worrisome development is the increasing pressure put on the Supreme Courts of liberal states, such as Canada and the United States, to resolve contentious policy differences as opposed to working them out through deliberative legislatures and informal public spheres.1 (As many Canadian and UK readers might point out, the word “parliament” means “speak” or “dialogue.”) But education systems also seem to be pulled into the vortex. Many schools and universities have found themselves in the unenviable position of weathering a number of controversial public and political events, be those events real or manufactured by social media actors. And while partisan stirring of the civic pot is by no means new, a polarized political environment has clearly changed public perception of these controversies and the institution's response to them. What was once a “tough call” is now reframed as “picking a side.” But not picking a side is also “picking a side.” The upshot is that schools and universities are shouldering a lot of civic stress (not always well, one might add), and one consequence is a troubling decline in public trust in them. Polarization also has pedagogical costs, especially in terms of classroom deliberation. Consider teaching “controversial issues” as an approach to civic education aimed at fostering better public reasoning and civic tolerance. The framing of some issues as “controversial,” and not others, now seems to risk accusations of partisanship, or even professional misconduct.2

Polarization seems to fit the very practical situation that the discourse ethical project aims to address: when basic interpersonal norms and norms of political morality are in fundamental dispute and epistemically uncertain. As Jürgen Habermas puts it, discourse ethics “provides an answer to the predicament in which members of any moral community find themselves when … though they still argue with reasons about moral judgments and beliefs, their substantive background consensus on the underlying moral norms has been shattered.”3

Yet, the civic appetite for reason-giving, perspective-taking, tolerance, and intellectual charity seems to ebb exactly when it is most needed. How, then, can discourse ethics guide citizens in dealing with problems of educational policy and practice under polarizing conditions? Are certain accounts, emphasizing some aspects of a discourse ethic over others, better able to capture the philosophical dimensions of these problems? To what extent can/should a discourse ethic provide practical guidance for individual educators and schools working in a polarized culture? Can it motivate deliberation? And what if the institutions themselves are similarly divided? The papers in this symposium take up these practical and conceptual challenges, assessing the educational merits of inclusive deliberation under conditions of moral, epistemic, and educational polarization.

As mentioned above, polarization seems to undermine civic trust in liberal civic norms and its basic institutions. The first two papers undertake a discourse-theoretical analysis of this phenomenon and how it bears on liberal democratic educational goals.

Julian Culp offers a comprehensive description of the broader epistemic environment of what he calls “digitized societies” and the challenges that this environment poses to civic education. On his account, a civic education that targets specific pathologies such as “fake news” downplays the economic and technological backdrop that makes productive deliberation (im)possible. Consequently, an education for deliberative democracy should equip future citizens to understand the extent to which, and ways in which, media that we might have once assumed would be conducive to public reasoning and argumentation (social media, for example) in actual fact thwart reasoned agreement and increase hostile, polarizing feelings about our fellow citizens.

Christopher Martin undertakes an analysis of “indoctrination,” attempting to separate the concept from its increasingly partisan usage as a term indiscriminately applied to entire educational institutions. He claims that “institutional” indoctrination must refer to an alleged failure by that institution to responsibly promote deliberative norms. One characteristic failure is institutional tolerance for “closed” deliberative norms, such as the norm that a demand for reasons in support of some belief P, just because P, is sufficient to justify the discursive exclusion of those making such a demand. Being clear on the concept of indoctrination, Martin argues, can help citizens distinguish legitimate worries about indoctrination from partisan rhetoric.

Polarization seems to have both a moral and an epistemic dimension. Conflating the two dimensions may further compound the polarization problem. Anniina Leiviskä adopts Habermas's distinction between the justification of “rightness” and “truth” claims in order to better understand recent debates over the nature, scope, and justification of “decolonizing” university curriculum. For Habermas, the validity of “rightness” claims is constructed in the sense that arguments in support of those claims must be publicly available, contestable, and acceptable by all. But truth-claims — claims about what is — are not constructed in this way. Leiviskä argues that a discourse ethical perspective warrants “decolonizing” the university in the sense that its institutional norms and pedagogical practices would greatly benefit from a more inclusive justification. However, epistemic standards are not themselves “de-colonizable” in the sense that such standards are fundamentally incommensurable with, and rival to, different cultural traditions. Universities therefore ought to pursue decolonizing policies on moral grounds while maintaining epistemic standards, such as impartiality and fallibility, that are constitutive of knowledge and understanding.

Krassimir Stojanov focuses on a constituency often neglected in discourse ethical accounts: children. Stojanov defends a demanding conception of epistemic respect for children in the sense that even very young students should be treated as credible and independent sources of reasons about justice and fairness. This especially matters since, as he puts it, “[p]recisely because of their otherness and strangeness, these perspectives and beliefs, if adults treat them seriously and with epistemic respect, could transcend established norms, and so they could contribute to their further development, revision, or modification as well as to the articulation of new norms and new reasons supporting them.”4 While children may be in some ways uninformed and naïve about various normative issues, they are also liberated from the prejudices and assumptions that are often carried along with them. Stojanov's analysis suggests that young students have the potential to articulate claims about justice and fairness that put the civic acrimony of adults into childish relief.

I opened with the idea of trust in public deliberation. We can include here pessimism about the effectiveness of ethical deliberation. The last two papers aim to demonstrate how the philosophical project of discourse ethics motivates empirical insights that have real benefits for educational policy and practice.

None of the contributions in this symposium frame their argument as a panacea for the conflicts and tensions that currently occupy our public sphere(s). However, they demonstrate the extent to which, and ways in which, reaffirming an educational commitment to deliberative inclusion and tolerance is necessary if we are to have a public sphere, and public reason, at all.

研讨会简介:两极政治文化下教育的话语伦理视角
当给予和接受理由的游戏得到广泛共享的公民道德规范的支持时,对公共审议的信任就会随之而来。当这些规范(包括审议规范本身)存在争议时,实践(和捍卫)审议要困难得多。自由民主国家的现状是更接近前者还是后者?有时被称为“政治的”、“情感的”或“公民的”两极分化的性质、原因和严重性仍然没有定论。似乎很清楚的是,两极分化对自由民主生活的审议层面产生了影响。一个令人担忧的事态发展是,加拿大和美国等自由主义国家的最高法院面临越来越大的压力,要求它们解决有争议的政策分歧,而不是通过审议立法机构和非正式的公共领域来解决这些分歧(正如许多加拿大和英国读者可能指出的那样,“议会”这个词的意思是“发言”或“对话”。)但教育系统似乎也被卷入了漩涡。许多学校和大学发现自己处于一个不令人羡慕的位置,在一些有争议的公共和政治事件中安然度过,不管这些事件是真实的还是社交媒体演员制造的。虽然公民锅中的党派骚动绝不是什么新鲜事,但两极分化的政治环境显然改变了公众对这些争议的看法以及该机构对这些争议的回应。曾经的“艰难抉择”现在被重新定义为“选边站队”。但不选边站也是“选边站”。其结果是,中小学和大学承担了大量的公民压力(有人可能会补充说,并不总是很好),其中一个后果是公众对它们的信任出现了令人不安的下降。两极分化也有教学成本,尤其是在课堂审议方面。考虑将教授“有争议的问题”作为公民教育的一种方法,旨在培养更好的公共推理和公民宽容。把一些问题定义为“有争议的”,而把另一些问题定义为“有争议的”,现在似乎有可能被指责为党派之争,甚至是职业上的不端行为。2极化似乎符合话语伦理项目旨在解决的非常实际的情况:当基本的人际规范和政治道德规范处于根本的争议和认识论上的不确定性时。正如j<s:1>根·哈贝马斯(jrgen Habermas)所说,话语伦理学“为任何道德共同体的成员发现自己处于这样的困境提供了答案……尽管他们仍在就道德判断和信仰进行理性辩论,但他们对潜在道德规范的实质性背景共识已被打破。”然而,在最需要的时候,公民对给予理由、换位思考、宽容和智识慈善的兴趣却似乎消退了。那么,话语伦理如何引导公民在两极分化的条件下处理教育政策和实践问题呢?强调话语伦理的某些方面而不是其他方面的某些描述,是否能够更好地捕捉这些问题的哲学维度?话语伦理在多大程度上可以/应该为在两极分化的文化中工作的个人教育者和学校提供实践指导?它能激发深思吗?如果这些机构本身也存在类似的分歧呢?本次研讨会的论文接受了这些实践和概念上的挑战,在道德、认知和教育两极分化的条件下评估包容性审议的教育价值。如上所述,两极分化似乎削弱了公民对自由主义公民规范及其基本制度的信任。前两篇论文对这一现象及其对自由民主教育目标的影响进行了话语理论分析。朱利安·卡尔普(Julian Culp)全面描述了他所谓的“数字化社会”的更广泛的认知环境,以及这种环境对公民教育构成的挑战。在他看来,以“假新闻”等特定病态为目标的公民教育,低估了使富有成效的审议成为可能的经济和技术背景。因此,对协商民主的教育应该使未来的公民能够理解,我们曾经认为有助于公共推理和辩论的媒体(例如社交媒体),在多大程度上以及以何种方式,实际上阻碍了理性的协议,并增加了对我们同胞的敌意和两极分化情绪。克里斯托弗·马丁(Christopher Martin)对“教化”(indoctrination)一词进行了分析,试图将这个概念与它日益带有党派色彩的用法区分开来,因为它是一个不加区分地适用于整个教育机构的术语。他声称,“体制”灌输必须是指该机构据称未能负责任地促进审议规范。 一个典型的失败是制度上对“封闭的”审议规范的容忍,例如,仅仅因为P而要求理由来支持某些信念P的规范,就足以证明对提出这种要求的人的话语排斥是正当的。马丁认为,明确灌输的概念可以帮助公民区分对灌输的合理担忧和党派言论。两极分化似乎既有道德层面,也有认知层面。将两个维度合并可能会进一步加剧极化问题。Anniina Leiviskä采用了哈贝马斯对“正确”和“真理”主张的区分,以便更好地理解最近关于“非殖民化”大学课程的性质、范围和理由的辩论。对于哈贝马斯来说,“正确”主张的有效性是在支持这些主张的论据必须是公开的、可争议的和被所有人接受的意义上构建的。但是真理的主张——关于“是什么”的主张——并不是以这种方式构建的。Leiviskä认为,话语伦理观点保证了大学的“去殖民化”,因为它的制度规范和教学实践将从更具包容性的理由中受益匪浅。然而,认知标准本身并不是“去殖民化”的,因为这些标准从根本上说与不同的文化传统不可通约,并与之竞争。因此,大学应该在道德基础上推行非殖民化政策,同时保持构成知识和理解的知识标准,例如不偏不倚和易犯错误。Krassimir Stojanov关注的是一个在话语伦理叙述中经常被忽视的群体:儿童。Stojanov捍卫了一种对儿童的认知尊重的苛刻概念,即即使是非常年轻的学生也应该被视为关于正义和公平的可信和独立的理由来源。这一点尤其重要,因为正如他所说,“正是因为它们的差异性和陌生性,这些观点和信仰,如果成年人认真对待它们,并以认知上的尊重对待它们,就可以超越既定的规范,因此它们可以促进它们的进一步发展、修订或修改,以及阐明支持它们的新规范和新理由。”虽然儿童在某些方面可能对各种规范问题不了解和naïve,但他们也从经常伴随他们的偏见和假设中解放出来。斯托亚诺夫的分析表明,年轻的学生有可能表达出关于正义和公平的主张,这让成年人的公民尖刻变成了幼稚的解脱。我以信任公众审议作为开场白。我们可以在这里包括对伦理审议有效性的悲观主义。最后两篇论文旨在证明话语伦理的哲学项目如何激发对教育政策和实践有真正好处的经验见解。本次研讨会上的任何一篇文章都没有把他们的论点作为解决目前占据我们公共领域的冲突和紧张局势的灵丹妙药。然而,它们表明,如果我们要有一个公共领域和公共理性,那么重申教育对审慎包容和宽容的承诺是必要的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
EDUCATIONAL THEORY
EDUCATIONAL THEORY EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH-
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
19
期刊介绍: The general purposes of Educational Theory are to foster the continuing development of educational theory and to encourage wide and effective discussion of theoretical problems within the educational profession. In order to achieve these purposes, the journal is devoted to publishing scholarly articles and studies in the foundations of education, and in related disciplines outside the field of education, which contribute to the advancement of educational theory. It is the policy of the sponsoring organizations to maintain the journal as an open channel of communication and as an open forum for discussion.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信