Symposium Introduction: Educating Responsible Believers

IF 1 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH
Michael Hand, Nicholas C. Burbules
{"title":"Symposium Introduction: Educating Responsible Believers","authors":"Michael Hand,&nbsp;Nicholas C. Burbules","doi":"10.1111/edth.70011","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>A central aim of education, at the primary, secondary, and postsecondary levels, is to bring it about that students believe responsibly. We want students to form new beliefs, and revise existing beliefs, on the basis of the best available evidence, argument, and testimony. We do not want them to cling dogmatically to beliefs acquired in childhood, nor to be warily skeptical of new information, nor to lurch haphazardly from one set of beliefs to another. Responsible believers are willing to subject their beliefs to critical scrutiny, to give new candidates for belief a fair hearing, and to amend their convictions when there is reason to do so.</p><p>Where the truth is known, our aim as educators is to impart knowledge: to bring it about that students hold true beliefs and understand what justifies them. Sometimes this will be achieved by presenting the evidence or rehearsing the argument that provides the warrant for a belief. At other times it will be achieved by testifying to the existence of evidence or argument that cannot, for one reason or another, be presented or rehearsed in the classroom. The goal in those cases is to share with students such knowledge as is available in the various theoretical and practical domains for which we are preparing them.</p><p>Where the truth is not known, our aim is to assist students in thinking clearly and independently about what to believe. There are controversies and dilemmas in all domains of action and inquiry that students must learn to navigate with due regard for relevant epistemic and normative considerations. They must work out for themselves when to take a stand on an unsettled question — and what stand to take — and when to remain agnostic. As educators we cannot do this work for our students: our role is to guide and support them on the road to becoming responsible believers and decision-makers.</p><p>How might these educational aims be realized? What types of pedagogical intervention promote responsible belief and what types of intervention impede it? What skills and techniques, what habits and norms, what intellectual traits and virtues, do responsible believers need? What forms of psychological resistance and cognitive bias stand in the way of clear and independent thinking, and what can be done to overcome these? What are the external forces that militate against responsible belief, that push students in the direction of dogmatism and gullibility, that cloud their judgment and undermine their confidence, that reinforce their prejudices and trap them in echo chambers? And are there educational measures by which we can realistically hope to counter these forces?</p><p>These are the questions that animated the Educating Responsible Believers project, a collaboration between faculty and graduate researchers at the University of Birmingham (UK) and the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign (US). Generously funded by the Birmingham-Illinois Partnership for Discovery, Engagement and Education (BRIDGE), the project ran from September 2023 to August 2024. The project team — comprising Nicholas C. Burbules, Danielle Diver, Laura D'Olimpio, Michael Hand, Ben Kotzee, Seunghyun Lee, Martha Perez-Mugg, Jeff Standley, Nicolas Tanchuk, Rebecca Taylor, and Ruth Wareham — met first in Champaign in autumn 2023, then in Birmingham in spring 2024, to exchange ideas, explore common ground, and develop lines of argument. No attempt was made to force a single position shared by all: our intention was to create a community of critical friends with whom to think through and test out our individual responses to the problem of educating for responsible belief. It was a rich and rewarding collaboration for all involved. The ten papers collected here are the fruit of our endeavors.</p><p>The first article in the collection is by Nicholas C. Burbules, “The Communicative Dimensions of Social Epistemologies.”<sup>1</sup> Beginning with the idea of communicative practices, Burbules asks what virtues are needed to sustain such practices and how we might cultivate them. He emphasizes that these communicative virtues overlap and interact in various ways, but he singles out five virtues that strike him as particularly important: <i>fallibilism</i>, <i>questioning group-think</i>, <i>open-mindedness</i>, <i>(self)disciplined thinking</i>, and <i>truthfulness</i>.</p><p>Jeff Standley's “On the Special Epistemic Obligations of the Educator” raises the question of whether educators should be held to higher epistemic standards than others.<sup>2</sup> Standley identifies a number of features of the work of teachers that make special demands on their epistemic character. He concludes that, when one decides to become a teacher, one does indeed take on special epistemic responsibilities and should therefore be held to higher epistemic standards than the layperson.</p><p>The next two articles focus in on specific contemporary impediments to responsible belief: the phenomenon of vaccine refusal and the popular practice of “manifesting.” In “Should Teachers Promote Vaccination?,” Ruth Wareham asks whether, and how, we should try to persuade students (1) that vaccines are safe and effective, and (2) that there is a civic duty to be vaccinated.<sup>3</sup> She examines the debate about directive and nondirective teaching and argues that, whichever criterion of controversiality one favors, the case for promoting both the safety of vaccines and the duty to be vaccinated is compelling. In “What's Wrong with Wishful Thinking? Manifesting as an Epistemic Vice,” Laura D'Olimpio diagnoses the problem with manifesting — “a form of wishful thinking that confuses thought with reality” — and proposes some educational remedies for it.<sup>4</sup> She recommends drawing on the methods of Philosophy for Children (P4C) to teach students about epistemic virtues and vices and, in particular, about the difference between positive thinking and wishful thinking.</p><p>Next is Michael Hand's “Does Indoctrination Still Matter?”<sup>5</sup> Hand begins by outlining what he calls the standard view of indoctrination, according to which (1) to indoctrinate someone is to impart beliefs to her in such a way that she comes to hold them non-rationally, and (2) indoctrination is a pernicious form of miseducation. He proceeds to defend the standard view against four objections found in the recent literature on indoctrination: the <i>impossibility</i>, <i>unavoidability</i>, <i>desirability</i>, and <i>third-party</i> objections.</p><p>There follow two articles on teaching the virtue of open-mindedness. “Teaching Open-Mindedness for Challenging Classrooms,” by Seunghyun Lee, explores the difficulty of cultivating epistemic virtues in inhospitable environments. Lee takes seriously the possibility that open-mindedness might actually be disadvantageous when an epistemic environment is “permeated by falsehoods, deception, or misdirection.”<sup>6</sup> But he contends that open-mindedness is, at least, a <i>student role virtue</i> and considers ways of cultivating it in the classroom. “Educating Open-Mindedness through Philosophy in Schools,” by Danielle Diver, highlights the distinctive capacity of philosophy to foster open-mindedness in its practitioners.<sup>7</sup> In part because of the close attention philosophers pay to arguments, reasons, logic, and validity, and in part because of the focus in P4C on listening, dialogue, and constructive criticism, Diver argues that teaching philosophy in schools would make a significant contribution to the enterprise of educating responsible believers.</p><p>The eighth article in the collection is Nicolas Tanchuk and Rebecca Taylor's “Personalized Learning with AI Tutors: Assessing and Advancing Epistemic Trustworthiness.” Tanchuk and Taylor raise the thorny issue of the trustworthiness of artificially intelligent (AI) tutors. They argue that, when presented with AI-generated information, students on their own cannot reasonably be expected to distinguish what is reliable from what is not. Instead, teachers, administrators, technologists, and policymakers must take on shared responsibility for ensuring that students can have confidence in their AI tutors — with policymakers having “an especially important role to play in incentivizing the creation of AI tutoring platforms aligned to the conditions of epistemic trust.”<sup>8</sup></p><p>Martha Perez-Mugg's “Instruction in the Age of Misinformation: Pedagogical Implications for Educating Responsible Knowers” probes the connections between civic reasoning, digital literacy, and epistemic responsibility.<sup>9</sup> Perez-Mugg shows how education in democracy and digital media depends in various ways on education for responsible belief. She goes on to identify four pedagogical principles for promoting epistemic responsibility in the context of civic education.</p><p>The final article is Ben Kotzee's “The Ethics of Belief Debate and the Norm of Teaching.” Kotzee's question is whether there is a <i>norm of teaching</i> that “will settle what teachers ought to teach the students in their classes in their role as professional educators.”<sup>10</sup> He first surveys the philosophical literatures on norms of belief and norms of assertion, then considers four possible norms of teaching, which he terms <i>pragmatic</i>, <i>truth</i>, <i>evidential</i>, and <i>knowledge</i>. He concludes that the knowledge norm — “teach only what is known” — is the most defensible.</p><p>Given the scope of the questions that animated our project, our discussions of them are hardly exhaustive. But we are optimistic about having identified some promising avenues of inquiry, and hopeful that we have vindicated some significant preliminary claims, in an area of the first importance for educational theory and practice. The damage wrought by irresponsible belief — to our lives, our health, our relationships, and our democracies — is palpable and, arguably, worsening: attention to the task of educating responsible believers is as necessary now as it has ever been.</p>","PeriodicalId":47134,"journal":{"name":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","volume":"75 2","pages":"188-191"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2025-03-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/edth.70011","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/edth.70011","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

A central aim of education, at the primary, secondary, and postsecondary levels, is to bring it about that students believe responsibly. We want students to form new beliefs, and revise existing beliefs, on the basis of the best available evidence, argument, and testimony. We do not want them to cling dogmatically to beliefs acquired in childhood, nor to be warily skeptical of new information, nor to lurch haphazardly from one set of beliefs to another. Responsible believers are willing to subject their beliefs to critical scrutiny, to give new candidates for belief a fair hearing, and to amend their convictions when there is reason to do so.

Where the truth is known, our aim as educators is to impart knowledge: to bring it about that students hold true beliefs and understand what justifies them. Sometimes this will be achieved by presenting the evidence or rehearsing the argument that provides the warrant for a belief. At other times it will be achieved by testifying to the existence of evidence or argument that cannot, for one reason or another, be presented or rehearsed in the classroom. The goal in those cases is to share with students such knowledge as is available in the various theoretical and practical domains for which we are preparing them.

Where the truth is not known, our aim is to assist students in thinking clearly and independently about what to believe. There are controversies and dilemmas in all domains of action and inquiry that students must learn to navigate with due regard for relevant epistemic and normative considerations. They must work out for themselves when to take a stand on an unsettled question — and what stand to take — and when to remain agnostic. As educators we cannot do this work for our students: our role is to guide and support them on the road to becoming responsible believers and decision-makers.

How might these educational aims be realized? What types of pedagogical intervention promote responsible belief and what types of intervention impede it? What skills and techniques, what habits and norms, what intellectual traits and virtues, do responsible believers need? What forms of psychological resistance and cognitive bias stand in the way of clear and independent thinking, and what can be done to overcome these? What are the external forces that militate against responsible belief, that push students in the direction of dogmatism and gullibility, that cloud their judgment and undermine their confidence, that reinforce their prejudices and trap them in echo chambers? And are there educational measures by which we can realistically hope to counter these forces?

These are the questions that animated the Educating Responsible Believers project, a collaboration between faculty and graduate researchers at the University of Birmingham (UK) and the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign (US). Generously funded by the Birmingham-Illinois Partnership for Discovery, Engagement and Education (BRIDGE), the project ran from September 2023 to August 2024. The project team — comprising Nicholas C. Burbules, Danielle Diver, Laura D'Olimpio, Michael Hand, Ben Kotzee, Seunghyun Lee, Martha Perez-Mugg, Jeff Standley, Nicolas Tanchuk, Rebecca Taylor, and Ruth Wareham — met first in Champaign in autumn 2023, then in Birmingham in spring 2024, to exchange ideas, explore common ground, and develop lines of argument. No attempt was made to force a single position shared by all: our intention was to create a community of critical friends with whom to think through and test out our individual responses to the problem of educating for responsible belief. It was a rich and rewarding collaboration for all involved. The ten papers collected here are the fruit of our endeavors.

The first article in the collection is by Nicholas C. Burbules, “The Communicative Dimensions of Social Epistemologies.”1 Beginning with the idea of communicative practices, Burbules asks what virtues are needed to sustain such practices and how we might cultivate them. He emphasizes that these communicative virtues overlap and interact in various ways, but he singles out five virtues that strike him as particularly important: fallibilism, questioning group-think, open-mindedness, (self)disciplined thinking, and truthfulness.

Jeff Standley's “On the Special Epistemic Obligations of the Educator” raises the question of whether educators should be held to higher epistemic standards than others.2 Standley identifies a number of features of the work of teachers that make special demands on their epistemic character. He concludes that, when one decides to become a teacher, one does indeed take on special epistemic responsibilities and should therefore be held to higher epistemic standards than the layperson.

The next two articles focus in on specific contemporary impediments to responsible belief: the phenomenon of vaccine refusal and the popular practice of “manifesting.” In “Should Teachers Promote Vaccination?,” Ruth Wareham asks whether, and how, we should try to persuade students (1) that vaccines are safe and effective, and (2) that there is a civic duty to be vaccinated.3 She examines the debate about directive and nondirective teaching and argues that, whichever criterion of controversiality one favors, the case for promoting both the safety of vaccines and the duty to be vaccinated is compelling. In “What's Wrong with Wishful Thinking? Manifesting as an Epistemic Vice,” Laura D'Olimpio diagnoses the problem with manifesting — “a form of wishful thinking that confuses thought with reality” — and proposes some educational remedies for it.4 She recommends drawing on the methods of Philosophy for Children (P4C) to teach students about epistemic virtues and vices and, in particular, about the difference between positive thinking and wishful thinking.

Next is Michael Hand's “Does Indoctrination Still Matter?”5 Hand begins by outlining what he calls the standard view of indoctrination, according to which (1) to indoctrinate someone is to impart beliefs to her in such a way that she comes to hold them non-rationally, and (2) indoctrination is a pernicious form of miseducation. He proceeds to defend the standard view against four objections found in the recent literature on indoctrination: the impossibility, unavoidability, desirability, and third-party objections.

There follow two articles on teaching the virtue of open-mindedness. “Teaching Open-Mindedness for Challenging Classrooms,” by Seunghyun Lee, explores the difficulty of cultivating epistemic virtues in inhospitable environments. Lee takes seriously the possibility that open-mindedness might actually be disadvantageous when an epistemic environment is “permeated by falsehoods, deception, or misdirection.”6 But he contends that open-mindedness is, at least, a student role virtue and considers ways of cultivating it in the classroom. “Educating Open-Mindedness through Philosophy in Schools,” by Danielle Diver, highlights the distinctive capacity of philosophy to foster open-mindedness in its practitioners.7 In part because of the close attention philosophers pay to arguments, reasons, logic, and validity, and in part because of the focus in P4C on listening, dialogue, and constructive criticism, Diver argues that teaching philosophy in schools would make a significant contribution to the enterprise of educating responsible believers.

The eighth article in the collection is Nicolas Tanchuk and Rebecca Taylor's “Personalized Learning with AI Tutors: Assessing and Advancing Epistemic Trustworthiness.” Tanchuk and Taylor raise the thorny issue of the trustworthiness of artificially intelligent (AI) tutors. They argue that, when presented with AI-generated information, students on their own cannot reasonably be expected to distinguish what is reliable from what is not. Instead, teachers, administrators, technologists, and policymakers must take on shared responsibility for ensuring that students can have confidence in their AI tutors — with policymakers having “an especially important role to play in incentivizing the creation of AI tutoring platforms aligned to the conditions of epistemic trust.”8

Martha Perez-Mugg's “Instruction in the Age of Misinformation: Pedagogical Implications for Educating Responsible Knowers” probes the connections between civic reasoning, digital literacy, and epistemic responsibility.9 Perez-Mugg shows how education in democracy and digital media depends in various ways on education for responsible belief. She goes on to identify four pedagogical principles for promoting epistemic responsibility in the context of civic education.

The final article is Ben Kotzee's “The Ethics of Belief Debate and the Norm of Teaching.” Kotzee's question is whether there is a norm of teaching that “will settle what teachers ought to teach the students in their classes in their role as professional educators.”10 He first surveys the philosophical literatures on norms of belief and norms of assertion, then considers four possible norms of teaching, which he terms pragmatic, truth, evidential, and knowledge. He concludes that the knowledge norm — “teach only what is known” — is the most defensible.

Given the scope of the questions that animated our project, our discussions of them are hardly exhaustive. But we are optimistic about having identified some promising avenues of inquiry, and hopeful that we have vindicated some significant preliminary claims, in an area of the first importance for educational theory and practice. The damage wrought by irresponsible belief — to our lives, our health, our relationships, and our democracies — is palpable and, arguably, worsening: attention to the task of educating responsible believers is as necessary now as it has ever been.

研讨会简介:培养负责任的信徒
在小学、中学和高等教育阶段,教育的一个中心目标是使学生相信自己是负责任的。我们希望学生形成新的信念,并修改现有的信念,在最好的证据,论点和证词的基础上。我们不希望他们教条地坚持童年时期获得的信仰,也不希望他们对新信息持谨慎的怀疑态度,也不希望他们随意地从一套信仰转向另一套信仰。负责任的信徒愿意让自己的信仰接受严格的审查,给新的信仰候选人一个公平的听证机会,并在有理由的情况下修改自己的信念。在了解真理的地方,作为教育者,我们的目标是传授知识:让学生拥有真正的信念,并理解是什么证明了这些信念。有时,这将通过提出证据或排练为信念提供保证的论点来实现。在其他时候,它将通过证明证据或论点的存在来实现,因为这样或那样的原因,不能在课堂上展示或排练。在这些情况下,目标是与学生分享我们正在为他们准备的各种理论和实践领域的知识。在不知道真相的地方,我们的目标是帮助学生清晰而独立地思考应该相信什么。在行动和探究的所有领域都存在争议和困境,学生必须学会在适当考虑相关认知和规范因素的情况下进行导航。他们必须自己决定什么时候对一个悬而未决的问题采取立场——以及采取什么样的立场——什么时候保持不可知论。作为教育工作者,我们不能为学生做这些工作:我们的角色是引导和支持他们走上成为负责任的信徒和决策者的道路。如何才能实现这些教育目标?哪些类型的教学干预促进负责任信念,哪些类型的干预阻碍负责任信念?负责任的信徒需要什么样的技能和技巧,什么样的习惯和规范,什么样的智力特征和美德?哪些形式的心理阻力和认知偏见阻碍了清晰和独立的思考,如何克服这些?是什么外部力量阻碍了负责任的信念,把学生推向教条主义和轻信的方向,蒙蔽了他们的判断,破坏了他们的信心,强化了他们的偏见,把他们困在回音室里?我们是否有切实可行的教育措施来对抗这些力量?这些问题激发了教育负责任的信徒项目,这是伯明翰大学(英国)和伊利诺伊大学厄巴纳-香槟分校(美国)的教师和研究生研究人员合作的项目。该项目由伯明翰-伊利诺伊州发现、参与和教育合作伙伴关系(BRIDGE)慷慨资助,从2023年9月持续到2024年8月。项目团队由Nicholas C. Burbules、Danielle Diver、Laura D’olimpio、Michael Hand、Ben Kotzee、Seunghyun Lee、Martha Perez-Mugg、Jeff Standley、Nicolas Tanchuk、Rebecca Taylor和Ruth Wareham组成,他们于2023年秋季在香槟市首次会面,然后于2024年春季在伯明翰会面,交换意见,探索共同点,并发展论点。我们并没有试图强迫所有人都有一个共同的立场:我们的目的是建立一个由具有批判性的朋友组成的社区,与他们一起思考和测试我们对负责任的信仰教育问题的个人反应。对所有参与者来说,这是一次丰富而有益的合作。这里收集的十篇论文是我们努力的成果。文集中的第一篇文章是尼古拉斯·c·伯布尔斯的《社会认识论的交际维度》。1从交际实践的概念开始,波布尔斯提出了维持这种实践需要什么样的美德以及我们如何培养它们的问题。他强调,这些沟通美德以各种方式重叠和相互作用,但他挑出了五种对他来说特别重要的美德:易错性、质疑群体思维、思想开放、(自我)自律思维和诚实。杰夫·斯坦德利的《教育工作者的特殊认识义务》提出了一个问题,即教育工作者是否应该比其他人有更高的认识标准斯坦德利指出了教师工作的一些特征,这些特征对教师的认识论特征提出了特殊要求。他的结论是,当一个人决定成为一名教师时,他确实承担了特殊的认识责任,因此应该比外行有更高的认识标准。接下来的两篇文章将集中讨论当代阻碍负责任信仰的具体障碍:拒绝接种疫苗的现象和流行的“表现”做法。 在“教师应该提倡接种疫苗吗?”Ruth Wareham问道,我们是否应该以及如何说服学生(1)疫苗是安全有效的,(2)接种疫苗是公民的义务她研究了关于指导性和非指导性教学的争论,并认为,无论人们倾向于哪种争议标准,促进疫苗安全性和接种疫苗义务的案例都是令人信服的。在《一厢情愿有什么错?》劳拉·德·奥林皮奥(Laura D’olimpio)将“显化”问题诊断为“一种混淆思想与现实的一厢情愿的想法”,并提出了一些教育方面的补救措施她建议借鉴《儿童哲学》(P4C)的方法,教学生认识上的美德和罪恶,特别是积极思考和一厢情愿的想法之间的区别。接下来是迈克尔·汉德的《灌输还重要吗?》汉德首先概述了他所谓的灌输的标准观点,根据这种观点:(1)灌输某人就是以一种方式向她灌输信仰,使她非理性地持有这些信仰;(2)灌输是一种有害的错误教育形式。他继续为标准观点辩护,反对在最近关于灌输的文献中发现的四种反对意见:不可能、不可避免、可取性和第三方反对意见。接下来有两篇文章是关于教导开放思想的美德。李承铉(Seunghyun Lee)的《为具有挑战性的教室教授开放思想》(Teaching open - minded for Challenging classroom)探讨了在恶劣环境中培养认知美德的难度。李开复严肃地认为,当一个认知环境“充斥着谎言、欺骗或误导”时,思想开放实际上可能是不利的。但他认为,思想开放至少是学生的一种美德,并考虑了在课堂上培养这种美德的方法。丹妮尔·戴弗(Danielle Diver)的《通过学校哲学教育开放思想》(education open- dedness in Schools)强调了哲学在培养实践者开放思想方面的独特能力部分原因是哲学家对论证、推理、逻辑和有效性的密切关注,部分原因是P4C对倾听、对话和建设性批评的关注,戴弗认为,在学校教授哲学将对培养负责任的信徒做出重大贡献。该系列的第八篇文章是尼古拉斯·坦丘克和丽贝卡·泰勒的《与人工智能导师进行个性化学习:评估和提高认知可信度》。坦丘克和泰勒提出了人工智能(AI)导师的可信度这一棘手问题。他们认为,当呈现人工智能生成的信息时,学生自己无法合理地区分哪些是可靠的,哪些是不可靠的。相反,教师、管理人员、技术专家和政策制定者必须共同承担责任,确保学生对他们的人工智能导师有信心——政策制定者“在激励创建符合认知信任条件的人工智能辅导平台方面发挥着特别重要的作用”。玛莎·佩雷斯-马格的《错误信息时代的教学:培养负责任的知识分子的教学意义》探讨了公民推理、数字素养和认知责任之间的联系佩雷斯-穆格展示了民主教育和数字媒体如何以各种方式依赖于负责任信念的教育。她接着指出了在公民教育的背景下促进认知责任的四个教学原则。最后一篇文章是Ben Kotzee的《信仰辩论的伦理与教学规范》。Kotzee的问题是,是否存在一种教学规范,“将决定教师作为专业教育者在课堂上应该教学生什么。”他首先调查了关于信仰规范和断言规范的哲学文献,然后考虑了四种可能的教学规范,他称之为实用主义、真理、证据和知识。他的结论是,知识规范——“只教已知的东西”——是最站得住脚的。考虑到使我们的项目充满活力的问题的范围,我们对它们的讨论很难详尽无遗。但我们乐观地认为,我们已经确定了一些有希望的研究途径,并希望我们已经在一个对教育理论和实践至关重要的领域证明了一些重要的初步主张是正确的。不负责任的信仰对我们的生活、我们的健康、我们的人际关系和我们的民主所造成的损害是显而易见的,而且可以说正在恶化:教育负责任的信徒的任务,现在和以往一样有必要。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
EDUCATIONAL THEORY
EDUCATIONAL THEORY EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH-
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
19
期刊介绍: The general purposes of Educational Theory are to foster the continuing development of educational theory and to encourage wide and effective discussion of theoretical problems within the educational profession. In order to achieve these purposes, the journal is devoted to publishing scholarly articles and studies in the foundations of education, and in related disciplines outside the field of education, which contribute to the advancement of educational theory. It is the policy of the sponsoring organizations to maintain the journal as an open channel of communication and as an open forum for discussion.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信