联邦制作为一种制度理论

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS
Michael Da Silva
{"title":"联邦制作为一种制度理论","authors":"Michael Da Silva","doi":"10.1111/josp.12540","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Federalism is, minimally, a method of allocating final decision-making authority over subjects (e.g., crime, healthcare, and immigration) in a governance unit (e.g., country). Faced with questions of the form “who can decide what when,” federal bodies, like the United States., Canada, Australia, and Germany, provide at least two entities (federal governments, provinces, cities, etc.) with final decision-making “powers” over at least one subject. No other entity is morally permitted to directly interfere (substitute decisions, fine, etc.) with the authority's decision-making regarding those subject(s). This is distinct from the unitary or centralized governance of, for example, France and Israel whereby one central entity possesses all final decision-making authority.<sup>1</sup> Beyond these basics, the meaning of and criteria for evaluating claims about federalism remain contested in law and political science.<sup>2</sup> The broader debates are then oft-ignored in mainstream political philosophy, resulting in conceptual confusion with important practical results discussed below.<sup>3</sup></p><p>The following argues for adopting an “institutional” approach to federalism, rather than more common “ideological” approaches.<sup>4</sup> A long tradition equates federalism with the US Founding Fathers' institutional proposals (Publius, <span>1788/1987</span>). Yet, partly due to empirical developments, the dominant account outside philosophy now holds that federalism is a normative doctrine promoting a secure political organization combining “shared[-]rule and self-rule” and separates this federal “idea” from institutional forms that may realize it (Elazar, <span>1987</span>; Watts, <span>2008</span>). Philosophers often begin by accepting this ideological approach (as I discuss further in Da Silva, <span>2022</span>).<sup>5</sup> Popelier (<span>2021</span>, p. 33) even suggests “all” scholars view this combination as federalism's “normative core.” But philosophical strictures and practical realities demand a more circumscribed approach. The dominant ideological approach is too broad to be a distinct normative doctrine or cannot even apply to many paradigmatic federal bodies. Institutional approaches defining federalism by advocacy for the adoption of federations (defined below) for authority allocation are preferable.</p><p>To establish this, I first detail and defend criteria for evaluating philosophical accounts of federalism. I then elaborate the distinction between ideological and institutional approaches and apply the criteria to the dominant ideological approach and a new specification of an institutional approach inspired by Wheare (<span>1946/1953</span>, p. 11)'s classic, oft-critiqued account. I thereby demonstrate that ideological accounts fail to fulfill many normative adequacy criteria for a philosophical account of federalism and one can articulate a more action-guiding institutional account that avoids common critiques. I finally explain how this exemplary application grounds a broader case for institutional approaches to federalism and address pressing objections. The result is deceptively radical as it weakens a decades-old stark contrast between “federalism” and “federation.” The broader arguments challenge several orthodox positions in the study of federalism. However, the balance of reasons supports an institutional approach to federalism.</p><p>My arguments are conceptual and normative. I aim to clarify the concept of federalism in a way that maintains it as a distinct, action-guiding contribution to moral ontology. Rather than offer an alternative to leading accounts of why one <i>should</i> adopt federalism (e.g., Bellamy, <span>1996</span>; Levy, <span>2007</span>; Norman, <span>2006</span>), I identify and specify the institutional normative concept they may support. I do not seek to defend all federations over other forms of governance. I instead demonstrate that advocacy for that institutional form is a normative doctrine one can justifiably adopt, albeit one with fewer necessary conceptual commitments than many claim. The concept is sufficiently distinct and compelling to warrant closer scrutiny if it does not best fit the “federalism” description. The concept matters, not the word. But findings below explain why one would adopt the institutional concept, why it deserves the label “federalism,” and other commitments a federalist should make. They thereby provide ample guidance for ongoing debates about the merits of <i>federalism</i> vis-à-vis other systems. The argument for institutionalism succeeds even if my specification is problematic. If, in turn, the general argument for institutionalism (rather than my neo-Whearean specification) fails, my analysis at least identifies burdens ideological accounts must meet and demonstrates that the dominant example does not meet them.</p><p>Existing practices and scholarship provide criteria for judging theories of federalism. A complete theory should be descriptively adequate. It should also serve federalism's professed normative functions, including guiding authority allocation within countries and judicial interpretation. It should do so in a way that is distinct, normatively compelling and explains its relationship to adjacent concepts. It should thereby assist the development of comparative law and politics and philosophical analysis of related concepts, like democracy. These are plausible conceptual desiderata even if no theory fulfills them all and can be evaluative criteria for comparing views.</p><p>Federalism is, in short, a normative ideal with numerous institutional forms. Federations are just one type of federal system that instantiate the combination of shared- and self-rule characteristics of the concept. Elazar developed this definition for the purposes of comparative political science and offers much more detail on which institutional forms plausibly qualify as “federal.” As discussed below, some institutional design features guide Elazar's own view. But Elazar is explicit in stating that all “federalist rather than monist or centralist” approaches to political life are connected by “some conception of the federal <i>idea</i>, some persuasive or ideology that endorsed federal solutions, some particular application of the federal <i>principle</i>, or some particular federal <i>framework</i>” (12–13). The basic idea that “federalism” does not simply refer to advocacy for particular institutional forms proved highly influential not only in political science but also in law and philosophy. Subsequent work in each builds on Elazar's framework and explicitly distinguishes the federal “idea” characteristic of federalism and particular federal institutional forms. Even the institutionalist Wheare's followers, like Watts (<span>2008</span>), use the federal idea—as contrasted with a particular federal form (e.g., federation)—as a framing device. It remains the starting point for most philosophical analyses. I accordingly present and then evaluate stylized versions of leading institutional and ideological approaches to federalism.</p><p>Applying the conceptual desiderata above suggests ideological approaches are less plausible and institutional ones less problematic than many suggest. Both face issues along some evaluative dimensions. But the strongest case for ideological federalism is weaker than many suppose; the balance of reasons supports a form of institutionalism. At a minimum, this application suggests the dominant ideological view is problematic and sets burdens for developing stronger examples.</p><p>I argue for this conclusion first by outlining the case for and limits of ideological federalism and then by explaining how institutional views fulfill the desiderata above better than many suppose. This section analyzes ideological federalism. However, I spend considerable time contrasting ideological approaches with their institutionalist rivals when specifying ideological federalism's strengths and weaknesses. This helps streamline presentation of institutional views below.</p><p>Using “federalism” to describe governance characterized by a combination of “rule” in the form of a set list of formal final decision-making powers for central powers and “rule” in distinct formal final decision-making powers for non-central units could save the term in a manner consistent with use post-1788. It also avoids many challenges with past approaches. I thus propose a thin institutional account of federalism inspired by, but distinct from, Wheare's classic. If it proves undesirable all things considered, it still helps motivate institutionalism generally.</p><p>In this proposal, federalism is advocacy for adopting the federation. Consistent with the institutional Wheare and rival ideological Elazar (along with most of their followers, like Watts, <span>2008</span>), federations here require at least two levels of government, each of which has distinct domains of final decision-making authority, does not rely on the other to implement its authority, and is accountable to a public not completely overlapping with that of another level of government. There must be a constitutional division of powers and at least two entities must be able to wield powers independent of each other while being accountable to distinct entities.<sup>30</sup></p><p>The United States, Canada, and Australia are paradigmatic. Federal and provincial (though not municipal) governments in those countries each have distinct constitutional authority over particular subjects. While powers may overlap in particular cases, each level of government can only validly act in a domain to the extent it is within their defined area of constitutional jurisdiction. It is, for example, possible that insurance promotion within banks can be considered part of a federal banking power and a provincial insurance power. However, federal and provincial governments can each only regulate aspects of insurance promotion within their defined powers. If a law fundamentally concerns banking, only the federal government can pass it. If conflicts between valid federal and provincial laws arise, country-specific rules resolve the conflicts.<sup>31</sup></p><p>Each government should also be accountable to distinct constituencies. Elections for members of each should be (at least largely) distinct. The federal government should have members from each province (viz., United States.- or Australia-style constituent state, Swiss canton, German lander), but members should not only be members of provincial legislatures. Provinces, for example, should have representatives in the federal government. Some representatives could also serve in the provincial one. But personnel should be non-identical and roles should not collapse. This is necessary to safeguard distinct decision-making and accountability loci. If the same persons fulfill most roles at both levels, the possibility of distinctiveness minimizes. There should also be means for a province to make decisions alone. Provincial “rule” should not rely only on representation within a body that also maintains members from other constituent units.</p><p>The view on offer is still firmly institutional: It takes institutional form as conceptually prior to any ideas that may follow from it and accepts the concomitant narrower range of genuinely federal phenomena. Yet it has fewer institutional requirements than many predecessor views. Its less demanding definition of a federation permits a thinner concept of federalism. The proposal does not require negotiations to resolve issues, as Elazar (<span>1987</span>) suggests, or that federations result from pre-existing groups contracting in ways that maintain their status in new constitutional arrangements (contra <i>id</i>.; Tierney, <span>2022</span>). This already suggests without proving that federalism itself does not entail a loyalty requirement. Multiple entities must have distinct domains of authority. The concept of federalism itself is agnostic on whether they must work together to do so or when. If a requirement exists, it must follow from the nature of the constitutive institutional form: Loyalty requirement proponents must explain how it is necessary for federations to exist. The same is true of subsidiarity. Likewise, the concept of federalism does not require many features frequently correlating with it, be they commitments to democracy or judicial review. The federal form may entail each. However, <i>the concept</i> does not include them.</p><p>This view shares Wheare's commitments to federations as the defining form of federal governance and federalism as a normative doctrine promoting adoption of that form. It adopts Whearean understandings of the federal form as requiring multiple decision-makers with final authority and the independence of their decision-making bodies such that, for example, the federal government is not just a collection of representatives of provincial governments and provincial governments do not rely on representation in a centralized body for much of their authority. Following Wheare, it further commits to distinct domains of authority in which governments are free to make decisions absent direct interference and views the United States as a paradigm case.</p><p>The proposal is nonetheless distinct from and helps avoid common criticisms of Wheare and thicker institutional models. Popelier (<span>2021</span>), for example, critiques federation-focused institutional views for their undermotivated commitments to democracy and the superiority of American-style federations, failing to account for non-democratic federations like the U.S.S.R or the normative desirability of German or Swiss governance.<sup>32</sup> Tierney (<span>2022</span>), in turn, criticizes institutional theorists for taking the United States as exemplary and thereby failing to account for federalism's distinct constitutional commitments to cultural diversity. Wheare himself admittedly only counts the United States, Switzerland, Australia, and Canada as clear cases of federal governance (<span>1946/1953</span>, p. 22). While some of his limitations were the result of historical circumstance, like the then-nascent status of the Indian constitution (47), discussing Germany as quasi-federal (26–27) appears curious. Yet descriptive issues in Wheare do not undermine his broader institutionalist project. Closer attention to cases he dismisses suggests nuances in the basic federal form, not a need to go beyond institutionalism. India has the basic federal form characterizing the proposal on offer. And complications with the German division of powers can be accommodated within the view. For example, Germany's recognition of concurrent powers is unproblematic where exclusive federal and exclusive lander powers each remain. For another, lander delegate representatives in the upper house are acceptable where the lower, legislative house is distinct.<sup>33</sup></p><p>Popelier and Tierney's concerns are not, in turn, inherent to institutional federalism and do not apply here. The proposed view does not, for example, consider the United States alone as exemplary of federalism, suggest federations are categorically normatively superior to other forms of governance, entail strong commitments to democracy, or rely on cultural homogeneity.<sup>34</sup> The United States is merely one paradigmatic federation and I merely present advocacy for federalism as a plausibly normative view here without relying on commitments to democracy or a monoculture. The view on offer may not directly make the “cultural diversity” Tierney requires characteristic of federalism. But I respectfully see little reason to think federalism requires such diversity.</p><p>The proposed view, in other words, avoids many descriptive criticisms lodged at Wheare's original view by relaxing its institutional and ideological requirements. It may not address concerns that federalism ought to have further ideological commitments, but this is a feature, not a bug. Any ideological commitments should follow from the form or be argued for independently.</p><p>Applying our desiderata to this view demonstrates that many empirical issues with institutional views are not inherent to institutionalism and some form of institutional federalism, if not the present one, offers much stronger prospects for fulfilling other desiderata for a complete theory.</p><p>The preceding suggests one can construct a non-ad hoc institutional account of federalism that meets many desiderata of a complete theory and avoids the most common empirical challenges to other institutional approaches, including Wheare's account. Viewing federalism as a doctrine advocating the institutional form of the federation can, in short, maintain federalism as a distinct, plausibly justifiable concept that provides a unique solution to authority allocation problems, permits comparative inquiry, and explains (at least many) important historical developments. It does so in ways that can also serve other normative roles, like guiding judicial interpretation. While the idea matters regardless of its name, the concept is plausibly described as “federalism.”</p><p>Simply outlining this option for how to address important issues and contrasting it with its dominant ideological rival adds to our philosophical and political ontology and points to a more general case for institutionalism. If one does not find my particular view fully compelling, the manner in which it meets many burdens for a compelling theory of federalism supports adopting <i>some</i> institutional approach. It further supports moving away from the dominant ideological view(s). At a minimum, the forgoing demonstrates how one could construct a plausible institutional approach. There is no longer sufficient reason to assume institutional approaches must be empirically problematic or normatively inert. The quest for a distinct federal form and normatively compelling concept supporting its adoption need not be quixotic. If the distinct concept does not fit one's preferred use of the word “federalism,” scholars should still analyze it independently from other forms of decentralization. But calling it federalism now appears apt.</p><p>The forgoing identified how a thin institutional approach can avoid common empirical critiques. It first demonstrated that no form of institutionalism, including one focused on federations, must take the United States as its only paradigmatic case. If one finds the choices above too narrow, admitting further examples could provide a still stronger institutional view so long as all paradigm cases shared basic features distinct from other forms of governance. The forgoing then demonstrated that a core set of features found in the United States and other paradigms still permit great variety. The particular proposal admittedly did not account for all purportedly federal theories and practices. But it demonstrated that institutional accounts could have broader descriptive value than many expect. Where appeals to descriptive adequacy helped motivate distinguishing “the” federal idea and institutions and ideological accounts had to abandon institutional capaciousness to be action-guiding, the case for institutionalism seems strong. Where problems remain, they largely point toward details more complete views must address.</p><p>Any worries that institutionalism makes federalism a mere idealization prove too much. Institutional approaches describe an ideal type. Federal practice in most countries no longer requires <i>strict</i> divisions of powers. Overlapping areas of jurisdiction in which two entities can act under different powers are common in many federations such that a federal government can pass a public health law under a criminal law power and a provincial one can pass a public health law under a hospital regulation power. Institutional approaches committed to strict sovereignty within domains risk mere stipulation and may not account for real practices. Per Neumann (<span>2005</span>/1955, p. 207), even a “superficial” study reveals no “element common to all … [federal states] except a juristic one … [whereby citizens are] subject to two jurisdictions.” However, even the juristic conception meaningfully applies to paradigmatic federations. Such application provides benefits above even where paradigms imperfectly fit the institutionalist ideal in practice. And ideological conceptions have the same problems identifying non-trivial common features in all bodies, so idealization arguments threaten to make any form of “federalism” imaginary or trivial. If one wants to abandon the search for necessary and sufficient conditions for federalism on idealization grounds, one should recall that even conditions that do not perfectly mirror real-world challenges can serve normative functions above and ideological theories are no better here.</p><p>Further pressing objections cannot defeat this general case for institutional federalism. For instance, many forms of institutionalism permit problematic outcomes absent external commitments to other values. Philosophers traditionally avoided federalism partly due to the legacy of Jim Crow.<sup>41</sup> Federalism has admittedly been used as a screen for injustice. Absent additional normative commitments, one may understandably worry that federalism will prove unjustifiable. If human rights norms avoided Jim Crow-like outcomes, other problems could remain. Institutionalism may not, for example, preclude inequities across sub-units within a country and country-wide solidarity-undermining competition between sub-units. Yet any conception deserving the name “federalism” will permit <i>some</i> wrongs. Justifications for federalism can limit bad outcomes. State stability norms may, for example, preclude divisions of powers fostering secession. But federalism divides sovereignty. A meaningful version with broad descriptive adequacy will likely provide someone with power to decide badly. Equal opportunities across states are, for example, desirable. But potential inequalities are a cost of federalism. One should not expand concepts beyond recognition to avoid problems, like inequality, when one can address the causes head-on.</p><p>Descriptively, in turn, if institutional approaches cannot describe all purportedly federal states as “federal,” they still provide meaningful guidance on how to identify them and capture more developments, like configurations providing for municipal authority, than some suppose. Not being able to describe confederations as “federal” may be unintuitive, but the balance of reasons supports it. Commitments to exclusive spheres of jurisdiction may, for example, struggle to describe the E.U. as federal. However, this result makes sense. Members claim to maintain complete sovereignty and the E.U. operates differently than countries such one may consider E.U. law international. This raises questions about why the U.N. is not federal ideological thinkers do not answer. Moreover, even those who view the E.U. as (con)federal recognize its incomplete federalization (Hueglin &amp; Fenna, <span>2015</span>, pp. xiii–xiv). One should not <i>assume</i> the E.U. is federal. The strongest accounts of federalism that would capture it above raise several problems. Giving up on institutional approaches just to cover the E.U. thus appears undermotivated.</p><p>Finally, the need for further work to see if conceptions of federalism using other possible justificatory principles are desirable should not lead us to abandon the concept of federalism as advocacy for a unique institutional solution, federations. A concept, once again, need not explain all its possible conceptions. Problems only arise when a concept cannot coherently explain what falls underneath it. Ideological approaches either fail to set a limit or set it too narrowly to fulfill their aims. Institutional approaches at least provide clear, plausible criteria for what counts as “federal.” Where they also better serve federalism's intended functions and do not face as many empirical problems as many believe, returning to some institutional approach is warranted.</p><p>The authors declare no conflicts of interest.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"55 1","pages":"81-105"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2023-06-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12540","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Federalism as an institutional doctrine\",\"authors\":\"Michael Da Silva\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/josp.12540\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Federalism is, minimally, a method of allocating final decision-making authority over subjects (e.g., crime, healthcare, and immigration) in a governance unit (e.g., country). Faced with questions of the form “who can decide what when,” federal bodies, like the United States., Canada, Australia, and Germany, provide at least two entities (federal governments, provinces, cities, etc.) with final decision-making “powers” over at least one subject. No other entity is morally permitted to directly interfere (substitute decisions, fine, etc.) with the authority's decision-making regarding those subject(s). This is distinct from the unitary or centralized governance of, for example, France and Israel whereby one central entity possesses all final decision-making authority.<sup>1</sup> Beyond these basics, the meaning of and criteria for evaluating claims about federalism remain contested in law and political science.<sup>2</sup> The broader debates are then oft-ignored in mainstream political philosophy, resulting in conceptual confusion with important practical results discussed below.<sup>3</sup></p><p>The following argues for adopting an “institutional” approach to federalism, rather than more common “ideological” approaches.<sup>4</sup> A long tradition equates federalism with the US Founding Fathers' institutional proposals (Publius, <span>1788/1987</span>). Yet, partly due to empirical developments, the dominant account outside philosophy now holds that federalism is a normative doctrine promoting a secure political organization combining “shared[-]rule and self-rule” and separates this federal “idea” from institutional forms that may realize it (Elazar, <span>1987</span>; Watts, <span>2008</span>). Philosophers often begin by accepting this ideological approach (as I discuss further in Da Silva, <span>2022</span>).<sup>5</sup> Popelier (<span>2021</span>, p. 33) even suggests “all” scholars view this combination as federalism's “normative core.” But philosophical strictures and practical realities demand a more circumscribed approach. The dominant ideological approach is too broad to be a distinct normative doctrine or cannot even apply to many paradigmatic federal bodies. Institutional approaches defining federalism by advocacy for the adoption of federations (defined below) for authority allocation are preferable.</p><p>To establish this, I first detail and defend criteria for evaluating philosophical accounts of federalism. I then elaborate the distinction between ideological and institutional approaches and apply the criteria to the dominant ideological approach and a new specification of an institutional approach inspired by Wheare (<span>1946/1953</span>, p. 11)'s classic, oft-critiqued account. I thereby demonstrate that ideological accounts fail to fulfill many normative adequacy criteria for a philosophical account of federalism and one can articulate a more action-guiding institutional account that avoids common critiques. I finally explain how this exemplary application grounds a broader case for institutional approaches to federalism and address pressing objections. The result is deceptively radical as it weakens a decades-old stark contrast between “federalism” and “federation.” The broader arguments challenge several orthodox positions in the study of federalism. However, the balance of reasons supports an institutional approach to federalism.</p><p>My arguments are conceptual and normative. I aim to clarify the concept of federalism in a way that maintains it as a distinct, action-guiding contribution to moral ontology. Rather than offer an alternative to leading accounts of why one <i>should</i> adopt federalism (e.g., Bellamy, <span>1996</span>; Levy, <span>2007</span>; Norman, <span>2006</span>), I identify and specify the institutional normative concept they may support. I do not seek to defend all federations over other forms of governance. I instead demonstrate that advocacy for that institutional form is a normative doctrine one can justifiably adopt, albeit one with fewer necessary conceptual commitments than many claim. The concept is sufficiently distinct and compelling to warrant closer scrutiny if it does not best fit the “federalism” description. The concept matters, not the word. But findings below explain why one would adopt the institutional concept, why it deserves the label “federalism,” and other commitments a federalist should make. They thereby provide ample guidance for ongoing debates about the merits of <i>federalism</i> vis-à-vis other systems. The argument for institutionalism succeeds even if my specification is problematic. If, in turn, the general argument for institutionalism (rather than my neo-Whearean specification) fails, my analysis at least identifies burdens ideological accounts must meet and demonstrates that the dominant example does not meet them.</p><p>Existing practices and scholarship provide criteria for judging theories of federalism. A complete theory should be descriptively adequate. It should also serve federalism's professed normative functions, including guiding authority allocation within countries and judicial interpretation. It should do so in a way that is distinct, normatively compelling and explains its relationship to adjacent concepts. It should thereby assist the development of comparative law and politics and philosophical analysis of related concepts, like democracy. These are plausible conceptual desiderata even if no theory fulfills them all and can be evaluative criteria for comparing views.</p><p>Federalism is, in short, a normative ideal with numerous institutional forms. Federations are just one type of federal system that instantiate the combination of shared- and self-rule characteristics of the concept. Elazar developed this definition for the purposes of comparative political science and offers much more detail on which institutional forms plausibly qualify as “federal.” As discussed below, some institutional design features guide Elazar's own view. But Elazar is explicit in stating that all “federalist rather than monist or centralist” approaches to political life are connected by “some conception of the federal <i>idea</i>, some persuasive or ideology that endorsed federal solutions, some particular application of the federal <i>principle</i>, or some particular federal <i>framework</i>” (12–13). The basic idea that “federalism” does not simply refer to advocacy for particular institutional forms proved highly influential not only in political science but also in law and philosophy. Subsequent work in each builds on Elazar's framework and explicitly distinguishes the federal “idea” characteristic of federalism and particular federal institutional forms. Even the institutionalist Wheare's followers, like Watts (<span>2008</span>), use the federal idea—as contrasted with a particular federal form (e.g., federation)—as a framing device. It remains the starting point for most philosophical analyses. I accordingly present and then evaluate stylized versions of leading institutional and ideological approaches to federalism.</p><p>Applying the conceptual desiderata above suggests ideological approaches are less plausible and institutional ones less problematic than many suggest. Both face issues along some evaluative dimensions. But the strongest case for ideological federalism is weaker than many suppose; the balance of reasons supports a form of institutionalism. At a minimum, this application suggests the dominant ideological view is problematic and sets burdens for developing stronger examples.</p><p>I argue for this conclusion first by outlining the case for and limits of ideological federalism and then by explaining how institutional views fulfill the desiderata above better than many suppose. This section analyzes ideological federalism. However, I spend considerable time contrasting ideological approaches with their institutionalist rivals when specifying ideological federalism's strengths and weaknesses. This helps streamline presentation of institutional views below.</p><p>Using “federalism” to describe governance characterized by a combination of “rule” in the form of a set list of formal final decision-making powers for central powers and “rule” in distinct formal final decision-making powers for non-central units could save the term in a manner consistent with use post-1788. It also avoids many challenges with past approaches. I thus propose a thin institutional account of federalism inspired by, but distinct from, Wheare's classic. If it proves undesirable all things considered, it still helps motivate institutionalism generally.</p><p>In this proposal, federalism is advocacy for adopting the federation. Consistent with the institutional Wheare and rival ideological Elazar (along with most of their followers, like Watts, <span>2008</span>), federations here require at least two levels of government, each of which has distinct domains of final decision-making authority, does not rely on the other to implement its authority, and is accountable to a public not completely overlapping with that of another level of government. There must be a constitutional division of powers and at least two entities must be able to wield powers independent of each other while being accountable to distinct entities.<sup>30</sup></p><p>The United States, Canada, and Australia are paradigmatic. Federal and provincial (though not municipal) governments in those countries each have distinct constitutional authority over particular subjects. While powers may overlap in particular cases, each level of government can only validly act in a domain to the extent it is within their defined area of constitutional jurisdiction. It is, for example, possible that insurance promotion within banks can be considered part of a federal banking power and a provincial insurance power. However, federal and provincial governments can each only regulate aspects of insurance promotion within their defined powers. If a law fundamentally concerns banking, only the federal government can pass it. If conflicts between valid federal and provincial laws arise, country-specific rules resolve the conflicts.<sup>31</sup></p><p>Each government should also be accountable to distinct constituencies. Elections for members of each should be (at least largely) distinct. The federal government should have members from each province (viz., United States.- or Australia-style constituent state, Swiss canton, German lander), but members should not only be members of provincial legislatures. Provinces, for example, should have representatives in the federal government. Some representatives could also serve in the provincial one. But personnel should be non-identical and roles should not collapse. This is necessary to safeguard distinct decision-making and accountability loci. If the same persons fulfill most roles at both levels, the possibility of distinctiveness minimizes. There should also be means for a province to make decisions alone. Provincial “rule” should not rely only on representation within a body that also maintains members from other constituent units.</p><p>The view on offer is still firmly institutional: It takes institutional form as conceptually prior to any ideas that may follow from it and accepts the concomitant narrower range of genuinely federal phenomena. Yet it has fewer institutional requirements than many predecessor views. Its less demanding definition of a federation permits a thinner concept of federalism. The proposal does not require negotiations to resolve issues, as Elazar (<span>1987</span>) suggests, or that federations result from pre-existing groups contracting in ways that maintain their status in new constitutional arrangements (contra <i>id</i>.; Tierney, <span>2022</span>). This already suggests without proving that federalism itself does not entail a loyalty requirement. Multiple entities must have distinct domains of authority. The concept of federalism itself is agnostic on whether they must work together to do so or when. If a requirement exists, it must follow from the nature of the constitutive institutional form: Loyalty requirement proponents must explain how it is necessary for federations to exist. The same is true of subsidiarity. Likewise, the concept of federalism does not require many features frequently correlating with it, be they commitments to democracy or judicial review. The federal form may entail each. However, <i>the concept</i> does not include them.</p><p>This view shares Wheare's commitments to federations as the defining form of federal governance and federalism as a normative doctrine promoting adoption of that form. It adopts Whearean understandings of the federal form as requiring multiple decision-makers with final authority and the independence of their decision-making bodies such that, for example, the federal government is not just a collection of representatives of provincial governments and provincial governments do not rely on representation in a centralized body for much of their authority. Following Wheare, it further commits to distinct domains of authority in which governments are free to make decisions absent direct interference and views the United States as a paradigm case.</p><p>The proposal is nonetheless distinct from and helps avoid common criticisms of Wheare and thicker institutional models. Popelier (<span>2021</span>), for example, critiques federation-focused institutional views for their undermotivated commitments to democracy and the superiority of American-style federations, failing to account for non-democratic federations like the U.S.S.R or the normative desirability of German or Swiss governance.<sup>32</sup> Tierney (<span>2022</span>), in turn, criticizes institutional theorists for taking the United States as exemplary and thereby failing to account for federalism's distinct constitutional commitments to cultural diversity. Wheare himself admittedly only counts the United States, Switzerland, Australia, and Canada as clear cases of federal governance (<span>1946/1953</span>, p. 22). While some of his limitations were the result of historical circumstance, like the then-nascent status of the Indian constitution (47), discussing Germany as quasi-federal (26–27) appears curious. Yet descriptive issues in Wheare do not undermine his broader institutionalist project. Closer attention to cases he dismisses suggests nuances in the basic federal form, not a need to go beyond institutionalism. India has the basic federal form characterizing the proposal on offer. And complications with the German division of powers can be accommodated within the view. For example, Germany's recognition of concurrent powers is unproblematic where exclusive federal and exclusive lander powers each remain. For another, lander delegate representatives in the upper house are acceptable where the lower, legislative house is distinct.<sup>33</sup></p><p>Popelier and Tierney's concerns are not, in turn, inherent to institutional federalism and do not apply here. The proposed view does not, for example, consider the United States alone as exemplary of federalism, suggest federations are categorically normatively superior to other forms of governance, entail strong commitments to democracy, or rely on cultural homogeneity.<sup>34</sup> The United States is merely one paradigmatic federation and I merely present advocacy for federalism as a plausibly normative view here without relying on commitments to democracy or a monoculture. The view on offer may not directly make the “cultural diversity” Tierney requires characteristic of federalism. But I respectfully see little reason to think federalism requires such diversity.</p><p>The proposed view, in other words, avoids many descriptive criticisms lodged at Wheare's original view by relaxing its institutional and ideological requirements. It may not address concerns that federalism ought to have further ideological commitments, but this is a feature, not a bug. Any ideological commitments should follow from the form or be argued for independently.</p><p>Applying our desiderata to this view demonstrates that many empirical issues with institutional views are not inherent to institutionalism and some form of institutional federalism, if not the present one, offers much stronger prospects for fulfilling other desiderata for a complete theory.</p><p>The preceding suggests one can construct a non-ad hoc institutional account of federalism that meets many desiderata of a complete theory and avoids the most common empirical challenges to other institutional approaches, including Wheare's account. Viewing federalism as a doctrine advocating the institutional form of the federation can, in short, maintain federalism as a distinct, plausibly justifiable concept that provides a unique solution to authority allocation problems, permits comparative inquiry, and explains (at least many) important historical developments. It does so in ways that can also serve other normative roles, like guiding judicial interpretation. While the idea matters regardless of its name, the concept is plausibly described as “federalism.”</p><p>Simply outlining this option for how to address important issues and contrasting it with its dominant ideological rival adds to our philosophical and political ontology and points to a more general case for institutionalism. If one does not find my particular view fully compelling, the manner in which it meets many burdens for a compelling theory of federalism supports adopting <i>some</i> institutional approach. It further supports moving away from the dominant ideological view(s). At a minimum, the forgoing demonstrates how one could construct a plausible institutional approach. There is no longer sufficient reason to assume institutional approaches must be empirically problematic or normatively inert. The quest for a distinct federal form and normatively compelling concept supporting its adoption need not be quixotic. If the distinct concept does not fit one's preferred use of the word “federalism,” scholars should still analyze it independently from other forms of decentralization. But calling it federalism now appears apt.</p><p>The forgoing identified how a thin institutional approach can avoid common empirical critiques. It first demonstrated that no form of institutionalism, including one focused on federations, must take the United States as its only paradigmatic case. If one finds the choices above too narrow, admitting further examples could provide a still stronger institutional view so long as all paradigm cases shared basic features distinct from other forms of governance. The forgoing then demonstrated that a core set of features found in the United States and other paradigms still permit great variety. The particular proposal admittedly did not account for all purportedly federal theories and practices. But it demonstrated that institutional accounts could have broader descriptive value than many expect. Where appeals to descriptive adequacy helped motivate distinguishing “the” federal idea and institutions and ideological accounts had to abandon institutional capaciousness to be action-guiding, the case for institutionalism seems strong. Where problems remain, they largely point toward details more complete views must address.</p><p>Any worries that institutionalism makes federalism a mere idealization prove too much. Institutional approaches describe an ideal type. Federal practice in most countries no longer requires <i>strict</i> divisions of powers. Overlapping areas of jurisdiction in which two entities can act under different powers are common in many federations such that a federal government can pass a public health law under a criminal law power and a provincial one can pass a public health law under a hospital regulation power. Institutional approaches committed to strict sovereignty within domains risk mere stipulation and may not account for real practices. Per Neumann (<span>2005</span>/1955, p. 207), even a “superficial” study reveals no “element common to all … [federal states] except a juristic one … [whereby citizens are] subject to two jurisdictions.” However, even the juristic conception meaningfully applies to paradigmatic federations. Such application provides benefits above even where paradigms imperfectly fit the institutionalist ideal in practice. And ideological conceptions have the same problems identifying non-trivial common features in all bodies, so idealization arguments threaten to make any form of “federalism” imaginary or trivial. If one wants to abandon the search for necessary and sufficient conditions for federalism on idealization grounds, one should recall that even conditions that do not perfectly mirror real-world challenges can serve normative functions above and ideological theories are no better here.</p><p>Further pressing objections cannot defeat this general case for institutional federalism. For instance, many forms of institutionalism permit problematic outcomes absent external commitments to other values. Philosophers traditionally avoided federalism partly due to the legacy of Jim Crow.<sup>41</sup> Federalism has admittedly been used as a screen for injustice. Absent additional normative commitments, one may understandably worry that federalism will prove unjustifiable. If human rights norms avoided Jim Crow-like outcomes, other problems could remain. Institutionalism may not, for example, preclude inequities across sub-units within a country and country-wide solidarity-undermining competition between sub-units. Yet any conception deserving the name “federalism” will permit <i>some</i> wrongs. Justifications for federalism can limit bad outcomes. State stability norms may, for example, preclude divisions of powers fostering secession. But federalism divides sovereignty. A meaningful version with broad descriptive adequacy will likely provide someone with power to decide badly. Equal opportunities across states are, for example, desirable. But potential inequalities are a cost of federalism. One should not expand concepts beyond recognition to avoid problems, like inequality, when one can address the causes head-on.</p><p>Descriptively, in turn, if institutional approaches cannot describe all purportedly federal states as “federal,” they still provide meaningful guidance on how to identify them and capture more developments, like configurations providing for municipal authority, than some suppose. Not being able to describe confederations as “federal” may be unintuitive, but the balance of reasons supports it. Commitments to exclusive spheres of jurisdiction may, for example, struggle to describe the E.U. as federal. However, this result makes sense. Members claim to maintain complete sovereignty and the E.U. operates differently than countries such one may consider E.U. law international. This raises questions about why the U.N. is not federal ideological thinkers do not answer. Moreover, even those who view the E.U. as (con)federal recognize its incomplete federalization (Hueglin &amp; Fenna, <span>2015</span>, pp. xiii–xiv). One should not <i>assume</i> the E.U. is federal. The strongest accounts of federalism that would capture it above raise several problems. Giving up on institutional approaches just to cover the E.U. thus appears undermotivated.</p><p>Finally, the need for further work to see if conceptions of federalism using other possible justificatory principles are desirable should not lead us to abandon the concept of federalism as advocacy for a unique institutional solution, federations. A concept, once again, need not explain all its possible conceptions. Problems only arise when a concept cannot coherently explain what falls underneath it. Ideological approaches either fail to set a limit or set it too narrowly to fulfill their aims. Institutional approaches at least provide clear, plausible criteria for what counts as “federal.” Where they also better serve federalism's intended functions and do not face as many empirical problems as many believe, returning to some institutional approach is warranted.</p><p>The authors declare no conflicts of interest.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46756,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"volume\":\"55 1\",\"pages\":\"81-105\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-06-19\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12540\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12540\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12540","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

31 每个政府还应向不同的选区负责。每届政府成员的选举应(至少在很大程度上)是不同的。联邦政府的成员应来自各省(即美国或澳大利亚式的组成州、瑞士州、德国州),但成员不应仅仅是省立法机构的成员。例如,各省在联邦政府中应有代表。一些代表也可以在省政府中任职。但人员不应相同,角色不应重叠。这对于保障不同的决策和问责地点是必要的。如果两级政府中的大多数角色都由同一人担任,那么独特性的可能性就会降到最低。一个省也应有单独决策的手段。省一级的 "统治 "不应仅仅依赖于在一个同时拥有其他组成单位成员的机构中的代表权。我们提出的观点仍然是坚定的制度性观点:它认为制度形式在概念上先于其可能产生的任何想法,并接受随之而来的范围较窄的真正的联邦现象。然而,与许多前人的观点相比,它对制度的要求较低。它对联邦的定义要求较低,允许联邦制的概念更加细化。该建议并不像 Elazar(1987 年)所说的那样要求通过谈判来解决问题,也不要求联邦是由先前存在的团体以在新的宪法安排中保持其地位的方式缔结契约而产生的(同上;Tierney,2022 年)。这已经表明,联邦制本身并不包含忠诚要求,但这并不能证明这一点。多个实体必须拥有不同的权力领域。联邦制的概念本身对它们是否必须合作或何时合作并无定论。如果存在这样的要求,那么它必须源于构成性制度形式的性质:忠诚要求的支持者必须解释联邦是如何存在的。辅助性也是如此。同样,联邦制的概念并不要求许多经常与之相关的特征,无论是对民主的承诺还是司法审查。联邦形式可能包含每一种特征。这种观点与惠尔的观点一致,即联邦是联邦治理的定义形式,联邦制是促进采用这种形式的规范理论。这种观点采纳了惠尔对联邦形式的理解,即联邦形式需要多个具有最终权力的决策者及其决策机构的独立性,例如,联邦政府不仅仅是省级政府代表的集合,省级政府的大部分权力也不依赖于在中央机构中的代表权。尽管如此,该建议仍有别于并有助于避免对惠尔和厚重制度模式的常见批评。例如,Popelier (2021)批评以联邦为中心的制度观点对民主和美国式联邦优越性的承诺动机不足,没有考虑到像苏联这样的非民主联邦,也没有考虑到德国或瑞士治理的规范可取性。惠尔本人承认,他只将美国、瑞士、澳大利亚和加拿大作为联邦治理的明确案例(1946/1953,第22页)。虽然他的一些局限性是历史环境造成的,比如当时印度宪法的萌芽状态(47),将德国作为准联邦制国家来讨论(26-27)似乎也很奇怪。然而,惠尔的描述性问题并没有破坏他更广泛的制度主义项目。密切关注他所否定的案例表明基本联邦形式存在细微差别,而不是需要超越制度主义。印度的提案具有基本联邦形式的特征。而德国权力划分的复杂性也可以在这一观点中得到解决。例如,德国承认并行权力,这在联邦专有权力和州专有权力各自存在的情况下是没有问题的。另一个例子是,在下院和立法院各不相同的情况下,上院的州代表也是可以接受的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Federalism as an institutional doctrine

Federalism is, minimally, a method of allocating final decision-making authority over subjects (e.g., crime, healthcare, and immigration) in a governance unit (e.g., country). Faced with questions of the form “who can decide what when,” federal bodies, like the United States., Canada, Australia, and Germany, provide at least two entities (federal governments, provinces, cities, etc.) with final decision-making “powers” over at least one subject. No other entity is morally permitted to directly interfere (substitute decisions, fine, etc.) with the authority's decision-making regarding those subject(s). This is distinct from the unitary or centralized governance of, for example, France and Israel whereby one central entity possesses all final decision-making authority.1 Beyond these basics, the meaning of and criteria for evaluating claims about federalism remain contested in law and political science.2 The broader debates are then oft-ignored in mainstream political philosophy, resulting in conceptual confusion with important practical results discussed below.3

The following argues for adopting an “institutional” approach to federalism, rather than more common “ideological” approaches.4 A long tradition equates federalism with the US Founding Fathers' institutional proposals (Publius, 1788/1987). Yet, partly due to empirical developments, the dominant account outside philosophy now holds that federalism is a normative doctrine promoting a secure political organization combining “shared[-]rule and self-rule” and separates this federal “idea” from institutional forms that may realize it (Elazar, 1987; Watts, 2008). Philosophers often begin by accepting this ideological approach (as I discuss further in Da Silva, 2022).5 Popelier (2021, p. 33) even suggests “all” scholars view this combination as federalism's “normative core.” But philosophical strictures and practical realities demand a more circumscribed approach. The dominant ideological approach is too broad to be a distinct normative doctrine or cannot even apply to many paradigmatic federal bodies. Institutional approaches defining federalism by advocacy for the adoption of federations (defined below) for authority allocation are preferable.

To establish this, I first detail and defend criteria for evaluating philosophical accounts of federalism. I then elaborate the distinction between ideological and institutional approaches and apply the criteria to the dominant ideological approach and a new specification of an institutional approach inspired by Wheare (1946/1953, p. 11)'s classic, oft-critiqued account. I thereby demonstrate that ideological accounts fail to fulfill many normative adequacy criteria for a philosophical account of federalism and one can articulate a more action-guiding institutional account that avoids common critiques. I finally explain how this exemplary application grounds a broader case for institutional approaches to federalism and address pressing objections. The result is deceptively radical as it weakens a decades-old stark contrast between “federalism” and “federation.” The broader arguments challenge several orthodox positions in the study of federalism. However, the balance of reasons supports an institutional approach to federalism.

My arguments are conceptual and normative. I aim to clarify the concept of federalism in a way that maintains it as a distinct, action-guiding contribution to moral ontology. Rather than offer an alternative to leading accounts of why one should adopt federalism (e.g., Bellamy, 1996; Levy, 2007; Norman, 2006), I identify and specify the institutional normative concept they may support. I do not seek to defend all federations over other forms of governance. I instead demonstrate that advocacy for that institutional form is a normative doctrine one can justifiably adopt, albeit one with fewer necessary conceptual commitments than many claim. The concept is sufficiently distinct and compelling to warrant closer scrutiny if it does not best fit the “federalism” description. The concept matters, not the word. But findings below explain why one would adopt the institutional concept, why it deserves the label “federalism,” and other commitments a federalist should make. They thereby provide ample guidance for ongoing debates about the merits of federalism vis-à-vis other systems. The argument for institutionalism succeeds even if my specification is problematic. If, in turn, the general argument for institutionalism (rather than my neo-Whearean specification) fails, my analysis at least identifies burdens ideological accounts must meet and demonstrates that the dominant example does not meet them.

Existing practices and scholarship provide criteria for judging theories of federalism. A complete theory should be descriptively adequate. It should also serve federalism's professed normative functions, including guiding authority allocation within countries and judicial interpretation. It should do so in a way that is distinct, normatively compelling and explains its relationship to adjacent concepts. It should thereby assist the development of comparative law and politics and philosophical analysis of related concepts, like democracy. These are plausible conceptual desiderata even if no theory fulfills them all and can be evaluative criteria for comparing views.

Federalism is, in short, a normative ideal with numerous institutional forms. Federations are just one type of federal system that instantiate the combination of shared- and self-rule characteristics of the concept. Elazar developed this definition for the purposes of comparative political science and offers much more detail on which institutional forms plausibly qualify as “federal.” As discussed below, some institutional design features guide Elazar's own view. But Elazar is explicit in stating that all “federalist rather than monist or centralist” approaches to political life are connected by “some conception of the federal idea, some persuasive or ideology that endorsed federal solutions, some particular application of the federal principle, or some particular federal framework” (12–13). The basic idea that “federalism” does not simply refer to advocacy for particular institutional forms proved highly influential not only in political science but also in law and philosophy. Subsequent work in each builds on Elazar's framework and explicitly distinguishes the federal “idea” characteristic of federalism and particular federal institutional forms. Even the institutionalist Wheare's followers, like Watts (2008), use the federal idea—as contrasted with a particular federal form (e.g., federation)—as a framing device. It remains the starting point for most philosophical analyses. I accordingly present and then evaluate stylized versions of leading institutional and ideological approaches to federalism.

Applying the conceptual desiderata above suggests ideological approaches are less plausible and institutional ones less problematic than many suggest. Both face issues along some evaluative dimensions. But the strongest case for ideological federalism is weaker than many suppose; the balance of reasons supports a form of institutionalism. At a minimum, this application suggests the dominant ideological view is problematic and sets burdens for developing stronger examples.

I argue for this conclusion first by outlining the case for and limits of ideological federalism and then by explaining how institutional views fulfill the desiderata above better than many suppose. This section analyzes ideological federalism. However, I spend considerable time contrasting ideological approaches with their institutionalist rivals when specifying ideological federalism's strengths and weaknesses. This helps streamline presentation of institutional views below.

Using “federalism” to describe governance characterized by a combination of “rule” in the form of a set list of formal final decision-making powers for central powers and “rule” in distinct formal final decision-making powers for non-central units could save the term in a manner consistent with use post-1788. It also avoids many challenges with past approaches. I thus propose a thin institutional account of federalism inspired by, but distinct from, Wheare's classic. If it proves undesirable all things considered, it still helps motivate institutionalism generally.

In this proposal, federalism is advocacy for adopting the federation. Consistent with the institutional Wheare and rival ideological Elazar (along with most of their followers, like Watts, 2008), federations here require at least two levels of government, each of which has distinct domains of final decision-making authority, does not rely on the other to implement its authority, and is accountable to a public not completely overlapping with that of another level of government. There must be a constitutional division of powers and at least two entities must be able to wield powers independent of each other while being accountable to distinct entities.30

The United States, Canada, and Australia are paradigmatic. Federal and provincial (though not municipal) governments in those countries each have distinct constitutional authority over particular subjects. While powers may overlap in particular cases, each level of government can only validly act in a domain to the extent it is within their defined area of constitutional jurisdiction. It is, for example, possible that insurance promotion within banks can be considered part of a federal banking power and a provincial insurance power. However, federal and provincial governments can each only regulate aspects of insurance promotion within their defined powers. If a law fundamentally concerns banking, only the federal government can pass it. If conflicts between valid federal and provincial laws arise, country-specific rules resolve the conflicts.31

Each government should also be accountable to distinct constituencies. Elections for members of each should be (at least largely) distinct. The federal government should have members from each province (viz., United States.- or Australia-style constituent state, Swiss canton, German lander), but members should not only be members of provincial legislatures. Provinces, for example, should have representatives in the federal government. Some representatives could also serve in the provincial one. But personnel should be non-identical and roles should not collapse. This is necessary to safeguard distinct decision-making and accountability loci. If the same persons fulfill most roles at both levels, the possibility of distinctiveness minimizes. There should also be means for a province to make decisions alone. Provincial “rule” should not rely only on representation within a body that also maintains members from other constituent units.

The view on offer is still firmly institutional: It takes institutional form as conceptually prior to any ideas that may follow from it and accepts the concomitant narrower range of genuinely federal phenomena. Yet it has fewer institutional requirements than many predecessor views. Its less demanding definition of a federation permits a thinner concept of federalism. The proposal does not require negotiations to resolve issues, as Elazar (1987) suggests, or that federations result from pre-existing groups contracting in ways that maintain their status in new constitutional arrangements (contra id.; Tierney, 2022). This already suggests without proving that federalism itself does not entail a loyalty requirement. Multiple entities must have distinct domains of authority. The concept of federalism itself is agnostic on whether they must work together to do so or when. If a requirement exists, it must follow from the nature of the constitutive institutional form: Loyalty requirement proponents must explain how it is necessary for federations to exist. The same is true of subsidiarity. Likewise, the concept of federalism does not require many features frequently correlating with it, be they commitments to democracy or judicial review. The federal form may entail each. However, the concept does not include them.

This view shares Wheare's commitments to federations as the defining form of federal governance and federalism as a normative doctrine promoting adoption of that form. It adopts Whearean understandings of the federal form as requiring multiple decision-makers with final authority and the independence of their decision-making bodies such that, for example, the federal government is not just a collection of representatives of provincial governments and provincial governments do not rely on representation in a centralized body for much of their authority. Following Wheare, it further commits to distinct domains of authority in which governments are free to make decisions absent direct interference and views the United States as a paradigm case.

The proposal is nonetheless distinct from and helps avoid common criticisms of Wheare and thicker institutional models. Popelier (2021), for example, critiques federation-focused institutional views for their undermotivated commitments to democracy and the superiority of American-style federations, failing to account for non-democratic federations like the U.S.S.R or the normative desirability of German or Swiss governance.32 Tierney (2022), in turn, criticizes institutional theorists for taking the United States as exemplary and thereby failing to account for federalism's distinct constitutional commitments to cultural diversity. Wheare himself admittedly only counts the United States, Switzerland, Australia, and Canada as clear cases of federal governance (1946/1953, p. 22). While some of his limitations were the result of historical circumstance, like the then-nascent status of the Indian constitution (47), discussing Germany as quasi-federal (26–27) appears curious. Yet descriptive issues in Wheare do not undermine his broader institutionalist project. Closer attention to cases he dismisses suggests nuances in the basic federal form, not a need to go beyond institutionalism. India has the basic federal form characterizing the proposal on offer. And complications with the German division of powers can be accommodated within the view. For example, Germany's recognition of concurrent powers is unproblematic where exclusive federal and exclusive lander powers each remain. For another, lander delegate representatives in the upper house are acceptable where the lower, legislative house is distinct.33

Popelier and Tierney's concerns are not, in turn, inherent to institutional federalism and do not apply here. The proposed view does not, for example, consider the United States alone as exemplary of federalism, suggest federations are categorically normatively superior to other forms of governance, entail strong commitments to democracy, or rely on cultural homogeneity.34 The United States is merely one paradigmatic federation and I merely present advocacy for federalism as a plausibly normative view here without relying on commitments to democracy or a monoculture. The view on offer may not directly make the “cultural diversity” Tierney requires characteristic of federalism. But I respectfully see little reason to think federalism requires such diversity.

The proposed view, in other words, avoids many descriptive criticisms lodged at Wheare's original view by relaxing its institutional and ideological requirements. It may not address concerns that federalism ought to have further ideological commitments, but this is a feature, not a bug. Any ideological commitments should follow from the form or be argued for independently.

Applying our desiderata to this view demonstrates that many empirical issues with institutional views are not inherent to institutionalism and some form of institutional federalism, if not the present one, offers much stronger prospects for fulfilling other desiderata for a complete theory.

The preceding suggests one can construct a non-ad hoc institutional account of federalism that meets many desiderata of a complete theory and avoids the most common empirical challenges to other institutional approaches, including Wheare's account. Viewing federalism as a doctrine advocating the institutional form of the federation can, in short, maintain federalism as a distinct, plausibly justifiable concept that provides a unique solution to authority allocation problems, permits comparative inquiry, and explains (at least many) important historical developments. It does so in ways that can also serve other normative roles, like guiding judicial interpretation. While the idea matters regardless of its name, the concept is plausibly described as “federalism.”

Simply outlining this option for how to address important issues and contrasting it with its dominant ideological rival adds to our philosophical and political ontology and points to a more general case for institutionalism. If one does not find my particular view fully compelling, the manner in which it meets many burdens for a compelling theory of federalism supports adopting some institutional approach. It further supports moving away from the dominant ideological view(s). At a minimum, the forgoing demonstrates how one could construct a plausible institutional approach. There is no longer sufficient reason to assume institutional approaches must be empirically problematic or normatively inert. The quest for a distinct federal form and normatively compelling concept supporting its adoption need not be quixotic. If the distinct concept does not fit one's preferred use of the word “federalism,” scholars should still analyze it independently from other forms of decentralization. But calling it federalism now appears apt.

The forgoing identified how a thin institutional approach can avoid common empirical critiques. It first demonstrated that no form of institutionalism, including one focused on federations, must take the United States as its only paradigmatic case. If one finds the choices above too narrow, admitting further examples could provide a still stronger institutional view so long as all paradigm cases shared basic features distinct from other forms of governance. The forgoing then demonstrated that a core set of features found in the United States and other paradigms still permit great variety. The particular proposal admittedly did not account for all purportedly federal theories and practices. But it demonstrated that institutional accounts could have broader descriptive value than many expect. Where appeals to descriptive adequacy helped motivate distinguishing “the” federal idea and institutions and ideological accounts had to abandon institutional capaciousness to be action-guiding, the case for institutionalism seems strong. Where problems remain, they largely point toward details more complete views must address.

Any worries that institutionalism makes federalism a mere idealization prove too much. Institutional approaches describe an ideal type. Federal practice in most countries no longer requires strict divisions of powers. Overlapping areas of jurisdiction in which two entities can act under different powers are common in many federations such that a federal government can pass a public health law under a criminal law power and a provincial one can pass a public health law under a hospital regulation power. Institutional approaches committed to strict sovereignty within domains risk mere stipulation and may not account for real practices. Per Neumann (2005/1955, p. 207), even a “superficial” study reveals no “element common to all … [federal states] except a juristic one … [whereby citizens are] subject to two jurisdictions.” However, even the juristic conception meaningfully applies to paradigmatic federations. Such application provides benefits above even where paradigms imperfectly fit the institutionalist ideal in practice. And ideological conceptions have the same problems identifying non-trivial common features in all bodies, so idealization arguments threaten to make any form of “federalism” imaginary or trivial. If one wants to abandon the search for necessary and sufficient conditions for federalism on idealization grounds, one should recall that even conditions that do not perfectly mirror real-world challenges can serve normative functions above and ideological theories are no better here.

Further pressing objections cannot defeat this general case for institutional federalism. For instance, many forms of institutionalism permit problematic outcomes absent external commitments to other values. Philosophers traditionally avoided federalism partly due to the legacy of Jim Crow.41 Federalism has admittedly been used as a screen for injustice. Absent additional normative commitments, one may understandably worry that federalism will prove unjustifiable. If human rights norms avoided Jim Crow-like outcomes, other problems could remain. Institutionalism may not, for example, preclude inequities across sub-units within a country and country-wide solidarity-undermining competition between sub-units. Yet any conception deserving the name “federalism” will permit some wrongs. Justifications for federalism can limit bad outcomes. State stability norms may, for example, preclude divisions of powers fostering secession. But federalism divides sovereignty. A meaningful version with broad descriptive adequacy will likely provide someone with power to decide badly. Equal opportunities across states are, for example, desirable. But potential inequalities are a cost of federalism. One should not expand concepts beyond recognition to avoid problems, like inequality, when one can address the causes head-on.

Descriptively, in turn, if institutional approaches cannot describe all purportedly federal states as “federal,” they still provide meaningful guidance on how to identify them and capture more developments, like configurations providing for municipal authority, than some suppose. Not being able to describe confederations as “federal” may be unintuitive, but the balance of reasons supports it. Commitments to exclusive spheres of jurisdiction may, for example, struggle to describe the E.U. as federal. However, this result makes sense. Members claim to maintain complete sovereignty and the E.U. operates differently than countries such one may consider E.U. law international. This raises questions about why the U.N. is not federal ideological thinkers do not answer. Moreover, even those who view the E.U. as (con)federal recognize its incomplete federalization (Hueglin & Fenna, 2015, pp. xiii–xiv). One should not assume the E.U. is federal. The strongest accounts of federalism that would capture it above raise several problems. Giving up on institutional approaches just to cover the E.U. thus appears undermotivated.

Finally, the need for further work to see if conceptions of federalism using other possible justificatory principles are desirable should not lead us to abandon the concept of federalism as advocacy for a unique institutional solution, federations. A concept, once again, need not explain all its possible conceptions. Problems only arise when a concept cannot coherently explain what falls underneath it. Ideological approaches either fail to set a limit or set it too narrowly to fulfill their aims. Institutional approaches at least provide clear, plausible criteria for what counts as “federal.” Where they also better serve federalism's intended functions and do not face as many empirical problems as many believe, returning to some institutional approach is warranted.

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信