(嗨)讲故事:意大利另类历史与反事实历史导论

IF 0.6 3区 历史学 Q1 HISTORY
History Pub Date : 2023-05-23 DOI:10.1111/1468-229X.13355
Adriano Vinale
{"title":"(嗨)讲故事:意大利另类历史与反事实历史导论","authors":"Adriano Vinale","doi":"10.1111/1468-229X.13355","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>The dilemma of the history of the defeated is certainly not a novel topic for political and historical enquiry. The experience of the unspeakable forced the Auschwitz generation to question the meaning of historical memory. Walter Benjamin posed this question very early on, when he wrote in 1940 that ‘The only historian capable of fanning the spark of hope in the past is the one who is firmly convinced that <i>even the dead</i> will not be safe from the enemy if he is victorious’.1 The nagging for the memory of the unspeakable obviously ran through the writings of Primo Levi, who immediately recognised the fallacy and falsifiability of memory, both personal and historical. ‘The memories which lie within us are not carved in stone; not only they tend to become erased as the years go by, but often they change, or even grow, by incorporating extraneous features.’2 Years before the Eichmann trial, Hannah Arendt also put the question of memory and its manipulability. In <i>The Origins of Totalitarianism</i> (1951), she reflects on the relationship between narrative and politics in these terms: ‘The ideal subject of totalitarian rule – she argues – is not the convinced Nazi or the convinced Communist, but people for whom the distinction between fact and fiction […] and the distinction between true and false […] no longer exist’.3 Collective memory is hence a recurring question in the aftermath of the Second World War and in particular after the unaccountable experience of the concentration camp. The memory of the drowned is never safe, firstly because the <i>real</i> witnesses of Auschwitz are the ones who did not survive it, and secondly because the memory of the past is always exposed to its posthumous falsification.4</p><p>When <i>Metahistory</i> was published in 1973, the European historiographical debate had already been profoundly influenced by post-structuralism. As a matter of fact, in the preceding years, books such as Michel Foucault's <i>Le mots et les choses</i> (1966), Jacques Derrida's <i>De la grammatologie</i> (1967), or Gilles Deleuze's <i>Différence et répétition</i> (1968) had powerfully occupied the public discussion in France and Europe. In those same years, Roland Barthes had published <i>Le discours de l'histoire</i> (1967) and <i>L'effet du réel</i> (1968), two essays destined to have a great echo in the reflection on historiographical methodology. It is perhaps superfluous to recall how the debate on the writing of history continued in the years following <i>Metahistory</i>. Nonetheless, it seems important to point out that works such as Lynn Hunt's <i>The New Cultural History</i> (1989) and Linda Hutcheon's <i>The Politics of Postmodernism</i> (1989) show that the discussion on the writing of history has gone far beyond the seventies. The interplay hypothesised by White between history and fiction, between historiography and literature, has in some ways forced the historiography of the second half of the twentieth century into a process of self-reflection, starting with the recognition of the problematic connection between reality and language, truth, and storytelling.6</p><p>Another relevant aspect of intellectual discussions over collective historical memory after the Second World War was denialism. The publication of Arthur Butz's <i>Hoax of the Twentieth Century: The Case Against the Presumed Extermination of European Jewry</i> (1976), David Irving's <i>Hitler's War</i> (1977), and Robert Faurisson's <i>Le problème des chambres à gaz</i> (1978) constituted an authentic cultural trauma for the generation of scholars formed after the Second World War. The very fact that the extermination of the Jews, the concentration camps, and the gas chambers could be questioned as real events – as historical facts – made Benjamin's admonition dramatically relevant: <i>auch die Toten werden vor dem Feind, wenn er siegt, nicht sicher sein</i>. The enemy, in fact, became threatening again, taking on the guise of the historian. If the condemnation of denialism has occurred first and foremost in politics and public opinion, it is the reaction of European and American intellectuals that is of particular interest to us. As a matter of fact, in the intellectual debate, the condemnation of denialism has often been accompanied by an equally severe condemnation of post-structuralism and post-modernism.7 The reasons are rather easy to understand. The idea that the writing of history is equated with any other process of narrative invention, that rhetoric is in the background of both reconstructions of the past and works of fiction, is considered the conceptual matrix that allowed denialism to arise. For denialists, if nothing escapes the domain of appearance, if everything is an effect of reality, then even the Shoah can possibly be considered fiction.</p><p>In the same years in which the negationist scandal broke out, Jean-François Lyotard published his groundbreaking work: <i>La condition postmoderne</i> (1979). As Nancy Partner has convincingly pointed out in a recent essay, the reaction to postmodernism in the historical debate was quite disproportionate. As a matter of fact, Lyotard, in his <i>rapport sur le savoir</i>, did not examine history as a possible example of the crisis of metanarratives, nor was history central to the reflections of Fredric Jameson or Linda Hutcheon. ‘Postmodernism's founding definers and observers – Partner has then concluded, not concludes – seemed indifferent to academic history, yet professional historians eventually recognised in postmodernism a critical force of unprecedented threat’.8 Lyotard's book impacted on the pre-existing debate on the writing of history which had its origins in narrativism.9 From the 1950s onwards, Arthur Danto had insisted on the relationship between history and storytelling, showing in particular the mechanisms by which retrodiction works in the writing of history. According to Danto, the historian composes their narrative through a ‘retroactive re-alignment of the Past’.10 In other words, from the narrativist's standpoint, the historian is inevitably posthumous, and the historical (re)construction of the past is a retrospective story. Similarly, in the 1960s and 1970s, Louis Mink had presented historical knowledge as an imaginative construction, outlining the inescapable and structural link between history and fiction: ‘We could learn to tell stories of our lives – he says in 1970 – from nursery rhymes, or from culture-myths if we had any, but it is from history and fiction that we learn how to tell and understand <i>complex</i> stories, and how it is that stories answer questions’.11 It is in this context of historical-philosophical discussion that reactions to Lyotard's arguments and to postmodernism took place. The <i>liaison</i> between epistemological reflection and historiographical debate is, of course, represented by White. ‘The events are <i>made</i> into a story – he wrote in 1978 – by the suppression or subordination of certain of them and the highlighting of others, by […] all of the techniques that we would normally expect to find in the emplotment of a novel or a play’.12 In short, by the time the English translation of <i>La condition postmoderne</i> was published in 1984, the discussion on the writing of history had already taken on rather broad dimensions.</p><p>As Partner rightly points out, from 1989 onwards it has been the journal <i>History and Theory</i>, in particular, that has hosted the debate on history writing. Frank Ankersmit and Perez Zagorin in particular are the ones leading the dance.13 It is impossible, nor perhaps useful, to go back to the discussion between the two historians. Here, in fact, it seems more important to recall some positions taken by Ankersmit in <i>Narrative Logic</i>, which will later be reiterated in <i>History and Tropology</i>. In the first place, he advocates for the total autonomy of <i>narratio</i>: ‘There are no translation-rules – he wrote in 1983 – enabling us to “project” the past onto the narrative level of its historiographical representation’.14 This is what Ankersmit calls ‘narrative idealism’. Another of his fundamental theses is that postmodernism is to some extent a radicalisation of historism. As a matter of fact, according to Ankersmit, they share the idea of a ‘fragmentation of the historical world’, although the historical object of postmodern narrativism ‘it is not part of a reified past but situated in the distance or difference between past and present’.15 Finally, in a similar direction seems to go Keith Jenkins, who in <i>Why History?</i> takes both White and Ankersmit to the extreme. In a perspective of radical narrativist presentism, Jenkins claims the superfluity of history <i>tout court</i>. That is, starting from the assumption that history is and has always been mythologised and ideologised, rhetorically represented, and emplotted, Jenkins concludes that we should all realise that we live in a post-historical world and take on its emancipatory aspects: ‘If Derrida, Baudrillard, Lyotard, Rorty, Ermarth <i>et al.</i> can do without a historical consciousness and especially a modernist upper or lower case one, then we all can’.16</p><p>In my view, the most balanced reaction on this issue is that of Carlo Ginzburg, who polemicised against the spread of a postmodernist fashion and, on the other hand, reconstructed some crucial steps in the history of writing history. In doing so, Ginzburg managed to show how historiography used <i>ab origine</i> the weapons of rhetoric to make the truths in its discourse effective. In this regard, Ginzburg spoke of an <i>effect of truth</i> – explicitly polemicising against Barthes’ <i>effet du réel</i> – meaning that truth in general, and historical truth in particular, has to do not only with reality, but also with its transposition into a persuasive narrative.17</p><p>On these premises, it is not surprising that alongside the historiographical debate, the so-called <i>alternate history</i> proliferated during the second half of the twentieth century. Although it has to be considered literature in the strict sense, alternate history closely investigates the very conception of historical time, trying to question its deterministic linearity.18 The problem alternate history deals with may be posed in a rather simple way: could history have gone differently?</p><p>Karen Hellekson has defined this literary subgenre as follows: ‘The alternate history (also known as alternative history, alternate universe, allohistory, uchronia, and parahistory) is that branch of nonrealistic literature that concerns itself with history turning out differently than we know to be the case.’19 In brief, the narrative peculiarity of alternate history is to identify a specific point on the past timeline – indifferently referred to as <i>nexus point</i>, <i>nexus event</i>, <i>Jonbar hinge</i>, or <i>Jonbar point</i> – from which a different development of the (hi)story is hypothesised.20 The point of divergence from the acknowledged historical timeline is located in a moment considered particularly significant for the future development of events: Hitler's rise to power, the Allies’ victory in the Second World War, Kennedy's assassination, and so forth. From this standpoint, one may say that the main aim of alternate history is to show the precariousness of historical time as such: it really could have happened that the Axis Powers won the war, just as it could have happened, on the contrary, that the Nazis did not rise to power at all, that Hitler was not born or that JFK was not assassinated. On the other hand, though, narrating an alternative history induces a critical reflection on the present. In this sense, we may agree with Charles Renouvier when he defined uchrony as a ‘utopie dans l'histoire’, imagining a more auspicious progress of Western civilisation with its non-Christianisation.21 But we may also define it as a <i>dystopia in history</i> when the alternative course of history presented to the reader has, in reverse, frightening traits.</p><p>While historiography therefore uses logical arguments and documentary evidence, alternate history fiction, starting from real historical events, invents a deviation, sometimes even minimal – a bullet that misses its target (in the case of Kennedy) or, on the contrary, that hits it (in the case of Roosevelt) – to imagine a different historical reality and induce a critical reflection on the present.</p><p>Although it is often associated with it, the so-called <i>counterfactual history</i> does not actually have much to do with alternate history. In his extensive introduction to <i>Virtual History</i>, Niall Ferguson starts from some epistemological assumptions – mainly related to Heisenberg's uncertainty principle and Lorenz's butterfly effect – to promote the use of simulation in historical research. Assuming the aleatory nature of historical phenomena, which are subject more to the laws of probability than to those of causality, Ferguson proposes the use of counterfactual conjecture in historiographical reconstruction as a virtual stress-strain analysis of a research hypothesis. In epistemological terms, this means to adopt what in criminal law is called the <i>but-for test</i>, which is the hypothetical exclusion of certain causes that are supposed to have provoked a certain event in order to determine its actual causation.23 Would this specific event have happened if there had not been that specific cause?</p><p>As a matter of fact, all the essays collected in <i>Virtual History</i> aim to verify specific <i>what-ifs</i> of history: What if there had been no American War of Independence?24 What if England had remained neutral during the First World War?25 What if the Wehrmacht had defeated the Red Army?26 What if Kennedy had not been assassinated in Dallas?27 Here too, as in alternate history, the reader is placed before certain nexus points, from which the author of the article hypothesises an alternative development of events. The methodological difference is however very clear and is established in the introduction by Ferguson himself: ‘We should consider as plausible or probable – he argues – <i>only those alternatives which we can show on the basis of contemporary evidence that contemporaries actually considered</i>.’28 For the virtual historian, it is therefore a matter of standing somewhere in between the pure literary invention of fictional narrative and historicistic determinism. In other words, according to Ferguson, it is a question of assuming the aleatoric nature of history, of showing its possible alternatives, in order to emphasise how a given event could easily have had opposite outcomes – for example, Britain could have stayed neutral in 1914; <i>Operation Barbarossa</i> could have succeeded. But, as we have outlined, the counterfactual hypothesis first and foremost aims to show the main determining causes of a given event – for example, the hung Parliament resulting from UK general election in January 1910; Hitler disastrous interference with his High Command's strategies in USSR in December 1941.</p><p>Although the book edited by Ferguson was met with a rather tepid academic reception, it can certainly be said that <i>Virtual history</i> represents an important moment in the historiographical debate at the turn of the century.29 A few other historians have since tried to systematically adopt the approach proposed by Ferguson. An example is the book edited by Robert Cowley – <i>What If?</i> – where in their respective essays Cowley himself and John Keegan show how the First World War could have been avoided and how the Second World War could have been won by Germany.30 Nonetheless, it cannot be argued that virtual history fully succeeded in establishing itself as a historiographical research method. The reasons for this are most likely to be found in the understandable suspicion, following the spread of anti-Semitic denialism, of any approach that claimed the use of imagination, or fiction, as a tool for historiographical investigation. Denying the existence of the Shoah and verifying the causes of the Nazi defeat by hypothesising their victory were seen as two dangerously similar approaches.</p><p>It is probably for these same reasons that alternate history and counterfactual history have not had much editorial or academic success in the Italian scene. Apart from <i>Se Garibaldi avesse perso</i>31 and <i>La storia con i se</i>,32 there is not much other Italian research in this field. This silence has been recently broken by a special issue of <i>Rivista di Politica</i>.33 The essays written by Federico Trocini34 and Emiliano Marra,35 in particular, analyse the parable of the so-called <i>fantafascismo</i>. Their detailed reconstruction of a part of Italian uchronic literature, however, indirectly shows the main reason for its poor fortune: the ideological compromise of some Italian allohistory writers with fascism and neo-fascism. Starting from these general coordinates, it is possible to show the main research aims of the special section of the present issue of <i>History</i>. The three articles that follow are the result of a lengthy discussion between the authors. Our aim is to show how a tradition of alternate and counterfactual history exists in Italy as well, although it is not easy to detect. This difficulty in tracing alternate and counterfactual Italian writings, in our opinion, is due to the non-explicit adoption of the rules and methods of these genres of (hi)storytelling. As a matter of fact, writers such as Camillo Pellizzi, Delio Cantimori, Corrado Alvaro, Guido Morselli, Luigi Malerba, Wu Ming, and Antonio Scurati preferred to apparently assume the canon of historiography, future narrative, or historical novel in order to produce a hidden or implicit counterfactual effect.</p><p>From this standpoint, Patricia Chiantera-Stutte's opening article analyses some examples of narratives that present some of the typical features of counterfactual history. Her article analyses the <i>ante litteram</i> emergence of the counterfactual in historiographical discourse and in particular in the literature on the so-called ‘missed revolutions’ during Italian fascism. In this way, Chiantera-Stutte investigates the origins and common motives of the political revolt of the young generation who lived during Mussolini's regime. More specifically, her essay considers the interpretations of the ‘unfinished revolution’ given by Pellizzi and Cantimori. She considers the topic of the ‘missed revolution’ as a cluster of questions that the generation born at the turn of the twentieth century had to face. The main aim of her reconstruction is to observe the mutual connection of antifascist and fascist perspectives and, at the same time, to understand the different attitudes towards politics and political ideals, illustrating the different ways of being fascists during the <i>Ventennio</i>. The reconstruction of the ‘missed revolution’ debate, occurring as it did in a period of crisis, shows to what extent history became a terrain of appropriation in the political and intellectual discussion. It reveals not only the uses of history by political adversaries, but also the interplay between history and politics in that specific genre of historical writing which was on the borderline between historical reconstruction and hypothetical narrative. From this perspective, Chiantera-Stutte aims to show that the literature concerning ‘missed revolution’ is a true historical genre, in which the personality, and the political and social values of the writers eventually come into the light more clearly than in other historical works.</p><p>Angelo Arciero's article analyses the various uchronic reverberations of George Orwell's <i>Nineteen Eighty-Four</i> in the Italian literary context, trying to show their political implications. The author shows that Alvaro's novels <i>L'uomo è forte</i> and <i>Belmoro</i>, Morselli's uchronies <i>Roma senza papa and Contro-passato prossimo</i>, and Malerba's short story <i>4891</i> are grafted – albeit in different ways – onto the theoretical reflections and literary devices codified by Orwell. The comparison between Alvaro and Orwell is indirect and layered in time. On the one hand, <i>L'uomo è forte</i> represents a totalitarian dystopia by anticipating of several years the conceptual devices of <i>Nineteen Eighty-Four</i>. On the other hand, <i>Belmoro</i> – set after a hypothetical Third World War – is placed on a historical juncture similar to Orwell's last novel, developing in a science-fiction key the implications concerning the relationship between man, science, and technology. Arciero then outlines how the latent conceptual affinities with Orwell that can be traced in Morselli go side by side with Malerba's <i>4891</i> explicit reference to the author of <i>Nineteen Eighty-Four</i>. In both cases, he argues, allohistory and future narrative aim to show, in a critical form, the transformations that took place in the Italian society from the thirties to the eighties.</p><p>The third and last essay reconstructs the course of the European and Italian historical novel between the nineteenth and the twenty-first centuries. The central hypothesis is that the historical novel, from its origins, has supported traditional historiography. In the specific case of Italy, then, the canon of the Risorgimento's historical novel gradually lost its epic and glorious traits, to be taken on as an instrument of indirect criticism of post-Unification Italian society. The same function it had in republican Italy, where the genre never completely disappeared, continuing to exercise a role of historical reconstruction and social critique. But it is at the turn of the twentieth and the twenty-first centuries that the historical novel has experienced an unprecedented publishing fortune. From the publication of Luther Blissett's <i>Q</i> to Umberto Eco's <i>Il cimitero di Praga</i>, the Italian historical novel at the turn of the century has emerged as a renewed field of historical investigation on the transition from the First to the Second Republic. Finally, it is with Antonio Scurati's three historical-documentary novels – <i>M. Il figlio del secolo</i>, <i>M. L'uomo della provvidenza</i>, and <i>M. Gli ultimi giorni dell'Europa</i> – that the historical-reconstructive function becomes a perfect tool for a critical analysis of collective memory, in particular of the historical memory of fascism. If Scurati's operation succeeds in this intent – this is the author's hypothesis – it is precisely because he uses an innovative form of counterfactual narrative: the implicit uchrony.</p>","PeriodicalId":13162,"journal":{"name":"History","volume":"108 382","pages":"355-364"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6000,"publicationDate":"2023-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1468-229X.13355","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"(Hi)story-Telling: An Introduction to Italian Alternate and Counterfactual History\",\"authors\":\"Adriano Vinale\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1468-229X.13355\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>The dilemma of the history of the defeated is certainly not a novel topic for political and historical enquiry. The experience of the unspeakable forced the Auschwitz generation to question the meaning of historical memory. Walter Benjamin posed this question very early on, when he wrote in 1940 that ‘The only historian capable of fanning the spark of hope in the past is the one who is firmly convinced that <i>even the dead</i> will not be safe from the enemy if he is victorious’.1 The nagging for the memory of the unspeakable obviously ran through the writings of Primo Levi, who immediately recognised the fallacy and falsifiability of memory, both personal and historical. ‘The memories which lie within us are not carved in stone; not only they tend to become erased as the years go by, but often they change, or even grow, by incorporating extraneous features.’2 Years before the Eichmann trial, Hannah Arendt also put the question of memory and its manipulability. In <i>The Origins of Totalitarianism</i> (1951), she reflects on the relationship between narrative and politics in these terms: ‘The ideal subject of totalitarian rule – she argues – is not the convinced Nazi or the convinced Communist, but people for whom the distinction between fact and fiction […] and the distinction between true and false […] no longer exist’.3 Collective memory is hence a recurring question in the aftermath of the Second World War and in particular after the unaccountable experience of the concentration camp. The memory of the drowned is never safe, firstly because the <i>real</i> witnesses of Auschwitz are the ones who did not survive it, and secondly because the memory of the past is always exposed to its posthumous falsification.4</p><p>When <i>Metahistory</i> was published in 1973, the European historiographical debate had already been profoundly influenced by post-structuralism. As a matter of fact, in the preceding years, books such as Michel Foucault's <i>Le mots et les choses</i> (1966), Jacques Derrida's <i>De la grammatologie</i> (1967), or Gilles Deleuze's <i>Différence et répétition</i> (1968) had powerfully occupied the public discussion in France and Europe. In those same years, Roland Barthes had published <i>Le discours de l'histoire</i> (1967) and <i>L'effet du réel</i> (1968), two essays destined to have a great echo in the reflection on historiographical methodology. It is perhaps superfluous to recall how the debate on the writing of history continued in the years following <i>Metahistory</i>. Nonetheless, it seems important to point out that works such as Lynn Hunt's <i>The New Cultural History</i> (1989) and Linda Hutcheon's <i>The Politics of Postmodernism</i> (1989) show that the discussion on the writing of history has gone far beyond the seventies. The interplay hypothesised by White between history and fiction, between historiography and literature, has in some ways forced the historiography of the second half of the twentieth century into a process of self-reflection, starting with the recognition of the problematic connection between reality and language, truth, and storytelling.6</p><p>Another relevant aspect of intellectual discussions over collective historical memory after the Second World War was denialism. The publication of Arthur Butz's <i>Hoax of the Twentieth Century: The Case Against the Presumed Extermination of European Jewry</i> (1976), David Irving's <i>Hitler's War</i> (1977), and Robert Faurisson's <i>Le problème des chambres à gaz</i> (1978) constituted an authentic cultural trauma for the generation of scholars formed after the Second World War. The very fact that the extermination of the Jews, the concentration camps, and the gas chambers could be questioned as real events – as historical facts – made Benjamin's admonition dramatically relevant: <i>auch die Toten werden vor dem Feind, wenn er siegt, nicht sicher sein</i>. The enemy, in fact, became threatening again, taking on the guise of the historian. If the condemnation of denialism has occurred first and foremost in politics and public opinion, it is the reaction of European and American intellectuals that is of particular interest to us. As a matter of fact, in the intellectual debate, the condemnation of denialism has often been accompanied by an equally severe condemnation of post-structuralism and post-modernism.7 The reasons are rather easy to understand. The idea that the writing of history is equated with any other process of narrative invention, that rhetoric is in the background of both reconstructions of the past and works of fiction, is considered the conceptual matrix that allowed denialism to arise. For denialists, if nothing escapes the domain of appearance, if everything is an effect of reality, then even the Shoah can possibly be considered fiction.</p><p>In the same years in which the negationist scandal broke out, Jean-François Lyotard published his groundbreaking work: <i>La condition postmoderne</i> (1979). As Nancy Partner has convincingly pointed out in a recent essay, the reaction to postmodernism in the historical debate was quite disproportionate. As a matter of fact, Lyotard, in his <i>rapport sur le savoir</i>, did not examine history as a possible example of the crisis of metanarratives, nor was history central to the reflections of Fredric Jameson or Linda Hutcheon. ‘Postmodernism's founding definers and observers – Partner has then concluded, not concludes – seemed indifferent to academic history, yet professional historians eventually recognised in postmodernism a critical force of unprecedented threat’.8 Lyotard's book impacted on the pre-existing debate on the writing of history which had its origins in narrativism.9 From the 1950s onwards, Arthur Danto had insisted on the relationship between history and storytelling, showing in particular the mechanisms by which retrodiction works in the writing of history. According to Danto, the historian composes their narrative through a ‘retroactive re-alignment of the Past’.10 In other words, from the narrativist's standpoint, the historian is inevitably posthumous, and the historical (re)construction of the past is a retrospective story. Similarly, in the 1960s and 1970s, Louis Mink had presented historical knowledge as an imaginative construction, outlining the inescapable and structural link between history and fiction: ‘We could learn to tell stories of our lives – he says in 1970 – from nursery rhymes, or from culture-myths if we had any, but it is from history and fiction that we learn how to tell and understand <i>complex</i> stories, and how it is that stories answer questions’.11 It is in this context of historical-philosophical discussion that reactions to Lyotard's arguments and to postmodernism took place. The <i>liaison</i> between epistemological reflection and historiographical debate is, of course, represented by White. ‘The events are <i>made</i> into a story – he wrote in 1978 – by the suppression or subordination of certain of them and the highlighting of others, by […] all of the techniques that we would normally expect to find in the emplotment of a novel or a play’.12 In short, by the time the English translation of <i>La condition postmoderne</i> was published in 1984, the discussion on the writing of history had already taken on rather broad dimensions.</p><p>As Partner rightly points out, from 1989 onwards it has been the journal <i>History and Theory</i>, in particular, that has hosted the debate on history writing. Frank Ankersmit and Perez Zagorin in particular are the ones leading the dance.13 It is impossible, nor perhaps useful, to go back to the discussion between the two historians. Here, in fact, it seems more important to recall some positions taken by Ankersmit in <i>Narrative Logic</i>, which will later be reiterated in <i>History and Tropology</i>. In the first place, he advocates for the total autonomy of <i>narratio</i>: ‘There are no translation-rules – he wrote in 1983 – enabling us to “project” the past onto the narrative level of its historiographical representation’.14 This is what Ankersmit calls ‘narrative idealism’. Another of his fundamental theses is that postmodernism is to some extent a radicalisation of historism. As a matter of fact, according to Ankersmit, they share the idea of a ‘fragmentation of the historical world’, although the historical object of postmodern narrativism ‘it is not part of a reified past but situated in the distance or difference between past and present’.15 Finally, in a similar direction seems to go Keith Jenkins, who in <i>Why History?</i> takes both White and Ankersmit to the extreme. In a perspective of radical narrativist presentism, Jenkins claims the superfluity of history <i>tout court</i>. That is, starting from the assumption that history is and has always been mythologised and ideologised, rhetorically represented, and emplotted, Jenkins concludes that we should all realise that we live in a post-historical world and take on its emancipatory aspects: ‘If Derrida, Baudrillard, Lyotard, Rorty, Ermarth <i>et al.</i> can do without a historical consciousness and especially a modernist upper or lower case one, then we all can’.16</p><p>In my view, the most balanced reaction on this issue is that of Carlo Ginzburg, who polemicised against the spread of a postmodernist fashion and, on the other hand, reconstructed some crucial steps in the history of writing history. In doing so, Ginzburg managed to show how historiography used <i>ab origine</i> the weapons of rhetoric to make the truths in its discourse effective. In this regard, Ginzburg spoke of an <i>effect of truth</i> – explicitly polemicising against Barthes’ <i>effet du réel</i> – meaning that truth in general, and historical truth in particular, has to do not only with reality, but also with its transposition into a persuasive narrative.17</p><p>On these premises, it is not surprising that alongside the historiographical debate, the so-called <i>alternate history</i> proliferated during the second half of the twentieth century. Although it has to be considered literature in the strict sense, alternate history closely investigates the very conception of historical time, trying to question its deterministic linearity.18 The problem alternate history deals with may be posed in a rather simple way: could history have gone differently?</p><p>Karen Hellekson has defined this literary subgenre as follows: ‘The alternate history (also known as alternative history, alternate universe, allohistory, uchronia, and parahistory) is that branch of nonrealistic literature that concerns itself with history turning out differently than we know to be the case.’19 In brief, the narrative peculiarity of alternate history is to identify a specific point on the past timeline – indifferently referred to as <i>nexus point</i>, <i>nexus event</i>, <i>Jonbar hinge</i>, or <i>Jonbar point</i> – from which a different development of the (hi)story is hypothesised.20 The point of divergence from the acknowledged historical timeline is located in a moment considered particularly significant for the future development of events: Hitler's rise to power, the Allies’ victory in the Second World War, Kennedy's assassination, and so forth. From this standpoint, one may say that the main aim of alternate history is to show the precariousness of historical time as such: it really could have happened that the Axis Powers won the war, just as it could have happened, on the contrary, that the Nazis did not rise to power at all, that Hitler was not born or that JFK was not assassinated. On the other hand, though, narrating an alternative history induces a critical reflection on the present. In this sense, we may agree with Charles Renouvier when he defined uchrony as a ‘utopie dans l'histoire’, imagining a more auspicious progress of Western civilisation with its non-Christianisation.21 But we may also define it as a <i>dystopia in history</i> when the alternative course of history presented to the reader has, in reverse, frightening traits.</p><p>While historiography therefore uses logical arguments and documentary evidence, alternate history fiction, starting from real historical events, invents a deviation, sometimes even minimal – a bullet that misses its target (in the case of Kennedy) or, on the contrary, that hits it (in the case of Roosevelt) – to imagine a different historical reality and induce a critical reflection on the present.</p><p>Although it is often associated with it, the so-called <i>counterfactual history</i> does not actually have much to do with alternate history. In his extensive introduction to <i>Virtual History</i>, Niall Ferguson starts from some epistemological assumptions – mainly related to Heisenberg's uncertainty principle and Lorenz's butterfly effect – to promote the use of simulation in historical research. Assuming the aleatory nature of historical phenomena, which are subject more to the laws of probability than to those of causality, Ferguson proposes the use of counterfactual conjecture in historiographical reconstruction as a virtual stress-strain analysis of a research hypothesis. In epistemological terms, this means to adopt what in criminal law is called the <i>but-for test</i>, which is the hypothetical exclusion of certain causes that are supposed to have provoked a certain event in order to determine its actual causation.23 Would this specific event have happened if there had not been that specific cause?</p><p>As a matter of fact, all the essays collected in <i>Virtual History</i> aim to verify specific <i>what-ifs</i> of history: What if there had been no American War of Independence?24 What if England had remained neutral during the First World War?25 What if the Wehrmacht had defeated the Red Army?26 What if Kennedy had not been assassinated in Dallas?27 Here too, as in alternate history, the reader is placed before certain nexus points, from which the author of the article hypothesises an alternative development of events. The methodological difference is however very clear and is established in the introduction by Ferguson himself: ‘We should consider as plausible or probable – he argues – <i>only those alternatives which we can show on the basis of contemporary evidence that contemporaries actually considered</i>.’28 For the virtual historian, it is therefore a matter of standing somewhere in between the pure literary invention of fictional narrative and historicistic determinism. In other words, according to Ferguson, it is a question of assuming the aleatoric nature of history, of showing its possible alternatives, in order to emphasise how a given event could easily have had opposite outcomes – for example, Britain could have stayed neutral in 1914; <i>Operation Barbarossa</i> could have succeeded. But, as we have outlined, the counterfactual hypothesis first and foremost aims to show the main determining causes of a given event – for example, the hung Parliament resulting from UK general election in January 1910; Hitler disastrous interference with his High Command's strategies in USSR in December 1941.</p><p>Although the book edited by Ferguson was met with a rather tepid academic reception, it can certainly be said that <i>Virtual history</i> represents an important moment in the historiographical debate at the turn of the century.29 A few other historians have since tried to systematically adopt the approach proposed by Ferguson. An example is the book edited by Robert Cowley – <i>What If?</i> – where in their respective essays Cowley himself and John Keegan show how the First World War could have been avoided and how the Second World War could have been won by Germany.30 Nonetheless, it cannot be argued that virtual history fully succeeded in establishing itself as a historiographical research method. The reasons for this are most likely to be found in the understandable suspicion, following the spread of anti-Semitic denialism, of any approach that claimed the use of imagination, or fiction, as a tool for historiographical investigation. Denying the existence of the Shoah and verifying the causes of the Nazi defeat by hypothesising their victory were seen as two dangerously similar approaches.</p><p>It is probably for these same reasons that alternate history and counterfactual history have not had much editorial or academic success in the Italian scene. Apart from <i>Se Garibaldi avesse perso</i>31 and <i>La storia con i se</i>,32 there is not much other Italian research in this field. This silence has been recently broken by a special issue of <i>Rivista di Politica</i>.33 The essays written by Federico Trocini34 and Emiliano Marra,35 in particular, analyse the parable of the so-called <i>fantafascismo</i>. Their detailed reconstruction of a part of Italian uchronic literature, however, indirectly shows the main reason for its poor fortune: the ideological compromise of some Italian allohistory writers with fascism and neo-fascism. Starting from these general coordinates, it is possible to show the main research aims of the special section of the present issue of <i>History</i>. The three articles that follow are the result of a lengthy discussion between the authors. Our aim is to show how a tradition of alternate and counterfactual history exists in Italy as well, although it is not easy to detect. This difficulty in tracing alternate and counterfactual Italian writings, in our opinion, is due to the non-explicit adoption of the rules and methods of these genres of (hi)storytelling. As a matter of fact, writers such as Camillo Pellizzi, Delio Cantimori, Corrado Alvaro, Guido Morselli, Luigi Malerba, Wu Ming, and Antonio Scurati preferred to apparently assume the canon of historiography, future narrative, or historical novel in order to produce a hidden or implicit counterfactual effect.</p><p>From this standpoint, Patricia Chiantera-Stutte's opening article analyses some examples of narratives that present some of the typical features of counterfactual history. Her article analyses the <i>ante litteram</i> emergence of the counterfactual in historiographical discourse and in particular in the literature on the so-called ‘missed revolutions’ during Italian fascism. In this way, Chiantera-Stutte investigates the origins and common motives of the political revolt of the young generation who lived during Mussolini's regime. More specifically, her essay considers the interpretations of the ‘unfinished revolution’ given by Pellizzi and Cantimori. She considers the topic of the ‘missed revolution’ as a cluster of questions that the generation born at the turn of the twentieth century had to face. The main aim of her reconstruction is to observe the mutual connection of antifascist and fascist perspectives and, at the same time, to understand the different attitudes towards politics and political ideals, illustrating the different ways of being fascists during the <i>Ventennio</i>. The reconstruction of the ‘missed revolution’ debate, occurring as it did in a period of crisis, shows to what extent history became a terrain of appropriation in the political and intellectual discussion. It reveals not only the uses of history by political adversaries, but also the interplay between history and politics in that specific genre of historical writing which was on the borderline between historical reconstruction and hypothetical narrative. From this perspective, Chiantera-Stutte aims to show that the literature concerning ‘missed revolution’ is a true historical genre, in which the personality, and the political and social values of the writers eventually come into the light more clearly than in other historical works.</p><p>Angelo Arciero's article analyses the various uchronic reverberations of George Orwell's <i>Nineteen Eighty-Four</i> in the Italian literary context, trying to show their political implications. The author shows that Alvaro's novels <i>L'uomo è forte</i> and <i>Belmoro</i>, Morselli's uchronies <i>Roma senza papa and Contro-passato prossimo</i>, and Malerba's short story <i>4891</i> are grafted – albeit in different ways – onto the theoretical reflections and literary devices codified by Orwell. The comparison between Alvaro and Orwell is indirect and layered in time. On the one hand, <i>L'uomo è forte</i> represents a totalitarian dystopia by anticipating of several years the conceptual devices of <i>Nineteen Eighty-Four</i>. On the other hand, <i>Belmoro</i> – set after a hypothetical Third World War – is placed on a historical juncture similar to Orwell's last novel, developing in a science-fiction key the implications concerning the relationship between man, science, and technology. Arciero then outlines how the latent conceptual affinities with Orwell that can be traced in Morselli go side by side with Malerba's <i>4891</i> explicit reference to the author of <i>Nineteen Eighty-Four</i>. In both cases, he argues, allohistory and future narrative aim to show, in a critical form, the transformations that took place in the Italian society from the thirties to the eighties.</p><p>The third and last essay reconstructs the course of the European and Italian historical novel between the nineteenth and the twenty-first centuries. The central hypothesis is that the historical novel, from its origins, has supported traditional historiography. In the specific case of Italy, then, the canon of the Risorgimento's historical novel gradually lost its epic and glorious traits, to be taken on as an instrument of indirect criticism of post-Unification Italian society. The same function it had in republican Italy, where the genre never completely disappeared, continuing to exercise a role of historical reconstruction and social critique. But it is at the turn of the twentieth and the twenty-first centuries that the historical novel has experienced an unprecedented publishing fortune. From the publication of Luther Blissett's <i>Q</i> to Umberto Eco's <i>Il cimitero di Praga</i>, the Italian historical novel at the turn of the century has emerged as a renewed field of historical investigation on the transition from the First to the Second Republic. Finally, it is with Antonio Scurati's three historical-documentary novels – <i>M. Il figlio del secolo</i>, <i>M. L'uomo della provvidenza</i>, and <i>M. Gli ultimi giorni dell'Europa</i> – that the historical-reconstructive function becomes a perfect tool for a critical analysis of collective memory, in particular of the historical memory of fascism. If Scurati's operation succeeds in this intent – this is the author's hypothesis – it is precisely because he uses an innovative form of counterfactual narrative: the implicit uchrony.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":13162,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"History\",\"volume\":\"108 382\",\"pages\":\"355-364\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-05-23\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1468-229X.13355\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"History\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"90\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-229X.13355\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"历史学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"HISTORY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"History","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1468-229X.13355","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"HISTORY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

战败者的历史困境当然不是政治和历史研究的新颖话题。无法言说的经历迫使奥斯威辛一代质疑历史记忆的意义。Walter Benjamin很早就提出了这个问题,他在1940年写道:“过去唯一能够点燃希望火花的历史学家是坚信,如果他获胜,即使是死者也不会安全地远离敌人的人。”,他立即认识到记忆的谬误和可证伪性,无论是个人记忆还是历史记忆。”我们内心的记忆不是刻在石头上的;它们不仅会随着时间的推移而被抹去,而且往往会通过融入外来特征而发生变化,甚至增长在艾希曼审判的两年前,汉娜·阿伦特也提出了记忆及其可操作性的问题。在《极权主义的起源》(1951)中,她用这些术语反思了叙事和政治之间的关系:“极权主义统治的理想主体——她认为——不是被说服的纳粹或被说服的共产主义者,3因此,集体记忆在第二次世界大战之后,特别是在集中营经历了不负责任的经历之后,是一个反复出现的问题。对溺水者的记忆从来都不是安全的,首先是因为奥斯威辛集中营的真正见证者是那些没有活下来的人,其次是因为对过去的记忆总是暴露在其死后的证伪中。4当元史学于1973年出版时,欧洲的史学辩论已经受到后结构主义的深刻影响。事实上,在之前的几年里,米歇尔·福柯的《Le mots et les choses》(1966年)、雅克·德里达的《语法学》(1967年)或吉勒·德勒兹的《Différence et répétition》(1968年)等书有力地占据了法国和欧洲的公众讨论。同年,罗兰·巴特出版了《历史论》(1967年)和《réel的影响》(1968年),这两篇文章注定会在对史学方法论的反思中产生巨大反响。回忆一下在元史学之后的几年里,关于历史书写的争论是如何继续的,也许是多余的。尽管如此,重要的是要指出,林恩·亨特的《新文化史》(1989)和琳达·胡钦的《后现代主义的政治》(1989年)等作品表明,关于历史写作的讨论已经远远超出了70年代。怀特所假设的历史与小说、史学与文学之间的相互作用,在某种程度上迫使二十世纪下半叶的史学进入了一个自我反思的过程,首先是认识到现实与语言、真理、,6第二次世界大战后,知识分子讨论集体历史记忆的另一个相关方面是否认主义。Arthur Butz的《二十世纪的骗局:反对欧洲犹太人被假定灭绝的案例》(1976年)、David Irving的《希特勒的战争》(1977年)和Robert Faurisson的《chambresàgaz问题》(1978年)的出版,对第二次世界大战后形成的一代学者来说,构成了真正的文化创伤。事实上,灭绝犹太人、集中营和毒气室可以作为真实事件——作为历史事实——受到质疑,这使得本杰明的警告具有极大的相关性:“我的图腾是Feind,wenn er siegt,not sicher sein。”。事实上,敌人伪装成历史学家,再次构成威胁。如果说对否认主义的谴责首先发生在政治和舆论中,那么我们特别感兴趣的是欧美知识分子的反应,对否认主义的谴责往往伴随着对后结构主义和后现代主义的同样严厉的谴责。7原因很容易理解。历史写作等同于任何其他叙事发明过程,修辞是在重建过去和小说作品的背景下进行的,这种想法被认为是允许否认主义出现的概念矩阵。对于否认者来说,如果没有什么能逃脱表象的范畴,如果一切都是现实的影响,那么即使是《幕府》也可能被认为是虚构的。在否定主义丑闻爆发的同一年,让-弗朗索瓦·利奥塔出版了他的开创性作品:《后现代条件》(1979)。 尽管它必须被严格意义上的文学看待,但《交替历史》仔细研究了历史时间的概念,试图质疑其确定性线性。18《交替史》处理的问题可以用一种相当简单的方式提出:历史会有不同的发展吗?Karen Hellekson对这一文学亚类的定义如下:“另类历史(也称为另类历史、另类宇宙、异历史、乌切罗尼亚和准历史)是非现实主义文学的一个分支,它关注的是历史的结果与我们所知的情况不同。”19简言之,交替历史的叙事特点是在过去的时间线上确定一个特定的点——通常被称为连接点、连接事件、Jonbar铰链,20与公认的历史时间线的分歧点位于对事件未来发展特别重要的时刻:希特勒掌权、盟军在第二次世界大战中获胜、肯尼迪遇刺等等。从这个角度来看,有人可能会说,交替历史的主要目的是显示历史时代的不稳定:轴心国赢得战争确实是可能的,就像纳粹根本没有掌权、希特勒没有出生或肯尼迪没有被暗杀一样。然而,另一方面,讲述一段另类历史引发了对当下的批判性反思。从这个意义上说,我们可能同意查尔斯·雷诺维尔的观点,他将乌切罗尼定义为“历史上的乌托邦”,想象西方文明在非基督教的情况下取得更为吉利的进步。21但我们也可能将其定义为历史上的反乌托邦,因为呈现给读者的另类历史进程反过来具有可怕的特征。因此,尽管史学使用逻辑论证和文献证据,但另类历史小说从真实的历史事件开始,创造了一种偏差,有时甚至是最小的偏差——一颗子弹没有击中目标(就肯尼迪而言),或者相反,这击中了它(在罗斯福的案例中)——想象一个不同的历史现实,并引发对当下的批判性反思。尽管它经常与之联系在一起,但所谓的反事实历史实际上与替代历史没有太大关系。在对虚拟历史的广泛介绍中,尼尔·弗格森从一些认识论假设开始——主要与海森堡的不确定性原理和洛伦茨的蝴蝶效应有关——以促进模拟在历史研究中的应用。Ferguson假设历史现象的偶然性,这些现象更多地受到概率定律的约束,而不是因果律的约束,他提出在历史重建中使用反事实猜想,作为对研究假设的虚拟应力-应变分析。从认识论的角度来看,这意味着采用刑法中所谓的“但为测试”,即假设排除某些本应引发某一事件的原因,以确定其实际原因。23如果没有特定原因,这个特定事件会发生吗?事实上,《虚拟历史》中收集的所有文章都旨在验证历史的具体假设:如果没有美国独立战争会怎样?24如果英国在第一次世界大战期间保持中立呢?25如果国防军打败了红军怎么办?26如果肯尼迪没有在达拉斯遇刺怎么办?27在这里,就像在另类历史中一样,读者也被置于某些联系点之前,文章作者从这些联系点假设了事件的另类发展。然而,方法上的差异非常明显,弗格森本人在引言中也确立了这一点:“他认为,我们应该只考虑那些我们可以根据同时代人实际考虑的当代证据证明的替代方案。”28因此,对于虚拟历史学家来说,这是一个介于虚构叙事的纯粹文学发明和历史决定论之间的问题。换言之,根据弗格森的说法,这是一个假设历史的任意性的问题,展示其可能的替代方案,以强调某一事件如何容易地产生相反的结果——例如,英国本可以在1914年保持中立;巴巴罗萨行动本可以成功。但是,正如我们所概述的,反事实假设首先旨在展示特定事件的主要决定因素——例如,1910年1月英国大选产生的无党派议会;1941年12月,希特勒对其最高司令部在苏联的战略进行了灾难性的干预。 阿尔瓦罗和奥威尔之间的比较是间接的,在时间上是分层的。一方面,L'uomoèforte通过对1984年概念装置的几年预测,代表了极权主义的反乌托邦。另一方面,《贝尔莫罗》以一场假想的第三次世界大战为背景,被置于一个与奥威尔上一部小说相似的历史转折点,在一部科幻小说中发展了关于人、科学和技术之间关系的含义。然后,Arciero概述了在Morselli中可以追溯到的与Orwell潜在的概念上的相似性,与Malerba 4891年明确提到的《一九八四》的作者是如何并列的。他认为,在这两种情况下,异历史和未来叙事都旨在以批判的形式展示意大利社会从三十年代到八十年代发生的转变。第三篇也是最后一篇文章重构了十九世纪至二十一世纪欧洲和意大利历史小说的发展历程。中心假设是,历史小说从其起源就支持了传统史学。在意大利的具体情况下,《文艺复兴》历史小说的正典逐渐失去了其史诗性和光辉性,被视为对统一后的意大利社会进行间接批判的工具。它在共和国意大利也发挥着同样的作用,在那里,这一流派从未完全消失,继续发挥着历史重建和社会批判的作用。但正是在二十世纪和二十一世纪之交,这部历史小说经历了前所未有的出版财富。从Luther Blissett的《Q》到Umberto Eco的《Il cimitro di Praga》,世纪之交的意大利历史小说已经成为从第一共和国到第二共和国过渡的一个新的历史调查领域。最后,正是凭借安东尼奥·斯卡拉蒂的三部历史纪实小说——《Il figlio del secolo》、《L’uomo della providenza》和《M·Gli ultimi giorni dell’Europa》,历史重建功能成为批判性分析集体记忆,特别是法西斯主义历史记忆的完美工具。如果斯库拉蒂的操作成功实现了这一意图——这是作者的假设——那正是因为他使用了一种创新的反事实叙事形式:隐含的uchrony。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
(Hi)story-Telling: An Introduction to Italian Alternate and Counterfactual History

The dilemma of the history of the defeated is certainly not a novel topic for political and historical enquiry. The experience of the unspeakable forced the Auschwitz generation to question the meaning of historical memory. Walter Benjamin posed this question very early on, when he wrote in 1940 that ‘The only historian capable of fanning the spark of hope in the past is the one who is firmly convinced that even the dead will not be safe from the enemy if he is victorious’.1 The nagging for the memory of the unspeakable obviously ran through the writings of Primo Levi, who immediately recognised the fallacy and falsifiability of memory, both personal and historical. ‘The memories which lie within us are not carved in stone; not only they tend to become erased as the years go by, but often they change, or even grow, by incorporating extraneous features.’2 Years before the Eichmann trial, Hannah Arendt also put the question of memory and its manipulability. In The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951), she reflects on the relationship between narrative and politics in these terms: ‘The ideal subject of totalitarian rule – she argues – is not the convinced Nazi or the convinced Communist, but people for whom the distinction between fact and fiction […] and the distinction between true and false […] no longer exist’.3 Collective memory is hence a recurring question in the aftermath of the Second World War and in particular after the unaccountable experience of the concentration camp. The memory of the drowned is never safe, firstly because the real witnesses of Auschwitz are the ones who did not survive it, and secondly because the memory of the past is always exposed to its posthumous falsification.4

When Metahistory was published in 1973, the European historiographical debate had already been profoundly influenced by post-structuralism. As a matter of fact, in the preceding years, books such as Michel Foucault's Le mots et les choses (1966), Jacques Derrida's De la grammatologie (1967), or Gilles Deleuze's Différence et répétition (1968) had powerfully occupied the public discussion in France and Europe. In those same years, Roland Barthes had published Le discours de l'histoire (1967) and L'effet du réel (1968), two essays destined to have a great echo in the reflection on historiographical methodology. It is perhaps superfluous to recall how the debate on the writing of history continued in the years following Metahistory. Nonetheless, it seems important to point out that works such as Lynn Hunt's The New Cultural History (1989) and Linda Hutcheon's The Politics of Postmodernism (1989) show that the discussion on the writing of history has gone far beyond the seventies. The interplay hypothesised by White between history and fiction, between historiography and literature, has in some ways forced the historiography of the second half of the twentieth century into a process of self-reflection, starting with the recognition of the problematic connection between reality and language, truth, and storytelling.6

Another relevant aspect of intellectual discussions over collective historical memory after the Second World War was denialism. The publication of Arthur Butz's Hoax of the Twentieth Century: The Case Against the Presumed Extermination of European Jewry (1976), David Irving's Hitler's War (1977), and Robert Faurisson's Le problème des chambres à gaz (1978) constituted an authentic cultural trauma for the generation of scholars formed after the Second World War. The very fact that the extermination of the Jews, the concentration camps, and the gas chambers could be questioned as real events – as historical facts – made Benjamin's admonition dramatically relevant: auch die Toten werden vor dem Feind, wenn er siegt, nicht sicher sein. The enemy, in fact, became threatening again, taking on the guise of the historian. If the condemnation of denialism has occurred first and foremost in politics and public opinion, it is the reaction of European and American intellectuals that is of particular interest to us. As a matter of fact, in the intellectual debate, the condemnation of denialism has often been accompanied by an equally severe condemnation of post-structuralism and post-modernism.7 The reasons are rather easy to understand. The idea that the writing of history is equated with any other process of narrative invention, that rhetoric is in the background of both reconstructions of the past and works of fiction, is considered the conceptual matrix that allowed denialism to arise. For denialists, if nothing escapes the domain of appearance, if everything is an effect of reality, then even the Shoah can possibly be considered fiction.

In the same years in which the negationist scandal broke out, Jean-François Lyotard published his groundbreaking work: La condition postmoderne (1979). As Nancy Partner has convincingly pointed out in a recent essay, the reaction to postmodernism in the historical debate was quite disproportionate. As a matter of fact, Lyotard, in his rapport sur le savoir, did not examine history as a possible example of the crisis of metanarratives, nor was history central to the reflections of Fredric Jameson or Linda Hutcheon. ‘Postmodernism's founding definers and observers – Partner has then concluded, not concludes – seemed indifferent to academic history, yet professional historians eventually recognised in postmodernism a critical force of unprecedented threat’.8 Lyotard's book impacted on the pre-existing debate on the writing of history which had its origins in narrativism.9 From the 1950s onwards, Arthur Danto had insisted on the relationship between history and storytelling, showing in particular the mechanisms by which retrodiction works in the writing of history. According to Danto, the historian composes their narrative through a ‘retroactive re-alignment of the Past’.10 In other words, from the narrativist's standpoint, the historian is inevitably posthumous, and the historical (re)construction of the past is a retrospective story. Similarly, in the 1960s and 1970s, Louis Mink had presented historical knowledge as an imaginative construction, outlining the inescapable and structural link between history and fiction: ‘We could learn to tell stories of our lives – he says in 1970 – from nursery rhymes, or from culture-myths if we had any, but it is from history and fiction that we learn how to tell and understand complex stories, and how it is that stories answer questions’.11 It is in this context of historical-philosophical discussion that reactions to Lyotard's arguments and to postmodernism took place. The liaison between epistemological reflection and historiographical debate is, of course, represented by White. ‘The events are made into a story – he wrote in 1978 – by the suppression or subordination of certain of them and the highlighting of others, by […] all of the techniques that we would normally expect to find in the emplotment of a novel or a play’.12 In short, by the time the English translation of La condition postmoderne was published in 1984, the discussion on the writing of history had already taken on rather broad dimensions.

As Partner rightly points out, from 1989 onwards it has been the journal History and Theory, in particular, that has hosted the debate on history writing. Frank Ankersmit and Perez Zagorin in particular are the ones leading the dance.13 It is impossible, nor perhaps useful, to go back to the discussion between the two historians. Here, in fact, it seems more important to recall some positions taken by Ankersmit in Narrative Logic, which will later be reiterated in History and Tropology. In the first place, he advocates for the total autonomy of narratio: ‘There are no translation-rules – he wrote in 1983 – enabling us to “project” the past onto the narrative level of its historiographical representation’.14 This is what Ankersmit calls ‘narrative idealism’. Another of his fundamental theses is that postmodernism is to some extent a radicalisation of historism. As a matter of fact, according to Ankersmit, they share the idea of a ‘fragmentation of the historical world’, although the historical object of postmodern narrativism ‘it is not part of a reified past but situated in the distance or difference between past and present’.15 Finally, in a similar direction seems to go Keith Jenkins, who in Why History? takes both White and Ankersmit to the extreme. In a perspective of radical narrativist presentism, Jenkins claims the superfluity of history tout court. That is, starting from the assumption that history is and has always been mythologised and ideologised, rhetorically represented, and emplotted, Jenkins concludes that we should all realise that we live in a post-historical world and take on its emancipatory aspects: ‘If Derrida, Baudrillard, Lyotard, Rorty, Ermarth et al. can do without a historical consciousness and especially a modernist upper or lower case one, then we all can’.16

In my view, the most balanced reaction on this issue is that of Carlo Ginzburg, who polemicised against the spread of a postmodernist fashion and, on the other hand, reconstructed some crucial steps in the history of writing history. In doing so, Ginzburg managed to show how historiography used ab origine the weapons of rhetoric to make the truths in its discourse effective. In this regard, Ginzburg spoke of an effect of truth – explicitly polemicising against Barthes’ effet du réel – meaning that truth in general, and historical truth in particular, has to do not only with reality, but also with its transposition into a persuasive narrative.17

On these premises, it is not surprising that alongside the historiographical debate, the so-called alternate history proliferated during the second half of the twentieth century. Although it has to be considered literature in the strict sense, alternate history closely investigates the very conception of historical time, trying to question its deterministic linearity.18 The problem alternate history deals with may be posed in a rather simple way: could history have gone differently?

Karen Hellekson has defined this literary subgenre as follows: ‘The alternate history (also known as alternative history, alternate universe, allohistory, uchronia, and parahistory) is that branch of nonrealistic literature that concerns itself with history turning out differently than we know to be the case.’19 In brief, the narrative peculiarity of alternate history is to identify a specific point on the past timeline – indifferently referred to as nexus point, nexus event, Jonbar hinge, or Jonbar point – from which a different development of the (hi)story is hypothesised.20 The point of divergence from the acknowledged historical timeline is located in a moment considered particularly significant for the future development of events: Hitler's rise to power, the Allies’ victory in the Second World War, Kennedy's assassination, and so forth. From this standpoint, one may say that the main aim of alternate history is to show the precariousness of historical time as such: it really could have happened that the Axis Powers won the war, just as it could have happened, on the contrary, that the Nazis did not rise to power at all, that Hitler was not born or that JFK was not assassinated. On the other hand, though, narrating an alternative history induces a critical reflection on the present. In this sense, we may agree with Charles Renouvier when he defined uchrony as a ‘utopie dans l'histoire’, imagining a more auspicious progress of Western civilisation with its non-Christianisation.21 But we may also define it as a dystopia in history when the alternative course of history presented to the reader has, in reverse, frightening traits.

While historiography therefore uses logical arguments and documentary evidence, alternate history fiction, starting from real historical events, invents a deviation, sometimes even minimal – a bullet that misses its target (in the case of Kennedy) or, on the contrary, that hits it (in the case of Roosevelt) – to imagine a different historical reality and induce a critical reflection on the present.

Although it is often associated with it, the so-called counterfactual history does not actually have much to do with alternate history. In his extensive introduction to Virtual History, Niall Ferguson starts from some epistemological assumptions – mainly related to Heisenberg's uncertainty principle and Lorenz's butterfly effect – to promote the use of simulation in historical research. Assuming the aleatory nature of historical phenomena, which are subject more to the laws of probability than to those of causality, Ferguson proposes the use of counterfactual conjecture in historiographical reconstruction as a virtual stress-strain analysis of a research hypothesis. In epistemological terms, this means to adopt what in criminal law is called the but-for test, which is the hypothetical exclusion of certain causes that are supposed to have provoked a certain event in order to determine its actual causation.23 Would this specific event have happened if there had not been that specific cause?

As a matter of fact, all the essays collected in Virtual History aim to verify specific what-ifs of history: What if there had been no American War of Independence?24 What if England had remained neutral during the First World War?25 What if the Wehrmacht had defeated the Red Army?26 What if Kennedy had not been assassinated in Dallas?27 Here too, as in alternate history, the reader is placed before certain nexus points, from which the author of the article hypothesises an alternative development of events. The methodological difference is however very clear and is established in the introduction by Ferguson himself: ‘We should consider as plausible or probable – he argues – only those alternatives which we can show on the basis of contemporary evidence that contemporaries actually considered.’28 For the virtual historian, it is therefore a matter of standing somewhere in between the pure literary invention of fictional narrative and historicistic determinism. In other words, according to Ferguson, it is a question of assuming the aleatoric nature of history, of showing its possible alternatives, in order to emphasise how a given event could easily have had opposite outcomes – for example, Britain could have stayed neutral in 1914; Operation Barbarossa could have succeeded. But, as we have outlined, the counterfactual hypothesis first and foremost aims to show the main determining causes of a given event – for example, the hung Parliament resulting from UK general election in January 1910; Hitler disastrous interference with his High Command's strategies in USSR in December 1941.

Although the book edited by Ferguson was met with a rather tepid academic reception, it can certainly be said that Virtual history represents an important moment in the historiographical debate at the turn of the century.29 A few other historians have since tried to systematically adopt the approach proposed by Ferguson. An example is the book edited by Robert Cowley – What If? – where in their respective essays Cowley himself and John Keegan show how the First World War could have been avoided and how the Second World War could have been won by Germany.30 Nonetheless, it cannot be argued that virtual history fully succeeded in establishing itself as a historiographical research method. The reasons for this are most likely to be found in the understandable suspicion, following the spread of anti-Semitic denialism, of any approach that claimed the use of imagination, or fiction, as a tool for historiographical investigation. Denying the existence of the Shoah and verifying the causes of the Nazi defeat by hypothesising their victory were seen as two dangerously similar approaches.

It is probably for these same reasons that alternate history and counterfactual history have not had much editorial or academic success in the Italian scene. Apart from Se Garibaldi avesse perso31 and La storia con i se,32 there is not much other Italian research in this field. This silence has been recently broken by a special issue of Rivista di Politica.33 The essays written by Federico Trocini34 and Emiliano Marra,35 in particular, analyse the parable of the so-called fantafascismo. Their detailed reconstruction of a part of Italian uchronic literature, however, indirectly shows the main reason for its poor fortune: the ideological compromise of some Italian allohistory writers with fascism and neo-fascism. Starting from these general coordinates, it is possible to show the main research aims of the special section of the present issue of History. The three articles that follow are the result of a lengthy discussion between the authors. Our aim is to show how a tradition of alternate and counterfactual history exists in Italy as well, although it is not easy to detect. This difficulty in tracing alternate and counterfactual Italian writings, in our opinion, is due to the non-explicit adoption of the rules and methods of these genres of (hi)storytelling. As a matter of fact, writers such as Camillo Pellizzi, Delio Cantimori, Corrado Alvaro, Guido Morselli, Luigi Malerba, Wu Ming, and Antonio Scurati preferred to apparently assume the canon of historiography, future narrative, or historical novel in order to produce a hidden or implicit counterfactual effect.

From this standpoint, Patricia Chiantera-Stutte's opening article analyses some examples of narratives that present some of the typical features of counterfactual history. Her article analyses the ante litteram emergence of the counterfactual in historiographical discourse and in particular in the literature on the so-called ‘missed revolutions’ during Italian fascism. In this way, Chiantera-Stutte investigates the origins and common motives of the political revolt of the young generation who lived during Mussolini's regime. More specifically, her essay considers the interpretations of the ‘unfinished revolution’ given by Pellizzi and Cantimori. She considers the topic of the ‘missed revolution’ as a cluster of questions that the generation born at the turn of the twentieth century had to face. The main aim of her reconstruction is to observe the mutual connection of antifascist and fascist perspectives and, at the same time, to understand the different attitudes towards politics and political ideals, illustrating the different ways of being fascists during the Ventennio. The reconstruction of the ‘missed revolution’ debate, occurring as it did in a period of crisis, shows to what extent history became a terrain of appropriation in the political and intellectual discussion. It reveals not only the uses of history by political adversaries, but also the interplay between history and politics in that specific genre of historical writing which was on the borderline between historical reconstruction and hypothetical narrative. From this perspective, Chiantera-Stutte aims to show that the literature concerning ‘missed revolution’ is a true historical genre, in which the personality, and the political and social values of the writers eventually come into the light more clearly than in other historical works.

Angelo Arciero's article analyses the various uchronic reverberations of George Orwell's Nineteen Eighty-Four in the Italian literary context, trying to show their political implications. The author shows that Alvaro's novels L'uomo è forte and Belmoro, Morselli's uchronies Roma senza papa and Contro-passato prossimo, and Malerba's short story 4891 are grafted – albeit in different ways – onto the theoretical reflections and literary devices codified by Orwell. The comparison between Alvaro and Orwell is indirect and layered in time. On the one hand, L'uomo è forte represents a totalitarian dystopia by anticipating of several years the conceptual devices of Nineteen Eighty-Four. On the other hand, Belmoro – set after a hypothetical Third World War – is placed on a historical juncture similar to Orwell's last novel, developing in a science-fiction key the implications concerning the relationship between man, science, and technology. Arciero then outlines how the latent conceptual affinities with Orwell that can be traced in Morselli go side by side with Malerba's 4891 explicit reference to the author of Nineteen Eighty-Four. In both cases, he argues, allohistory and future narrative aim to show, in a critical form, the transformations that took place in the Italian society from the thirties to the eighties.

The third and last essay reconstructs the course of the European and Italian historical novel between the nineteenth and the twenty-first centuries. The central hypothesis is that the historical novel, from its origins, has supported traditional historiography. In the specific case of Italy, then, the canon of the Risorgimento's historical novel gradually lost its epic and glorious traits, to be taken on as an instrument of indirect criticism of post-Unification Italian society. The same function it had in republican Italy, where the genre never completely disappeared, continuing to exercise a role of historical reconstruction and social critique. But it is at the turn of the twentieth and the twenty-first centuries that the historical novel has experienced an unprecedented publishing fortune. From the publication of Luther Blissett's Q to Umberto Eco's Il cimitero di Praga, the Italian historical novel at the turn of the century has emerged as a renewed field of historical investigation on the transition from the First to the Second Republic. Finally, it is with Antonio Scurati's three historical-documentary novels – M. Il figlio del secolo, M. L'uomo della provvidenza, and M. Gli ultimi giorni dell'Europa – that the historical-reconstructive function becomes a perfect tool for a critical analysis of collective memory, in particular of the historical memory of fascism. If Scurati's operation succeeds in this intent – this is the author's hypothesis – it is precisely because he uses an innovative form of counterfactual narrative: the implicit uchrony.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
History
History HISTORY-
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: First published in 1912, History has been a leader in its field ever since. It is unique in its range and variety, packing its pages with stimulating articles and extensive book reviews. History balances its broad chronological coverage with a wide geographical spread of articles featuring contributions from social, political, cultural, economic and ecclesiastical historians. History seeks to publish articles on broad, challenging themes, which not only display sound scholarship which is embedded within current historiographical debates, but push those debates forward. History encourages submissions which are also attractively and clearly written. Reviews: An integral part of each issue is the review section giving critical analysis of the latest scholarship across an extensive chronological and geographical range.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信