辩证亚里士多德主义:论马克思关于我们与动物的区别

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Tom Whyman
{"title":"辩证亚里士多德主义:论马克思关于我们与动物的区别","authors":"Tom Whyman","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12712","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>I have noticed, in Anglophone philosophy, a certain way of invoking Marx. The pattern here is—understandably, given the relative scarcity of substantial engagement with Marx outside of (radical) political theory—a rather loose one. But I've spotted it in the work of John McDowell, Michael Thompson, and Mary Midgley. In each of these thinkers, Marx is invoked in the context of an inquiry into human nature: into the question of what (if anything) separates us from the animals.</p><p>In this paper, I propose to adjudicate a certain debate between these three thinkers—a debate which their shared invocation of Marx allows us to stage. I will argue that this debate between McDowell, Thompson, and Midgley, such as it is, is doomed to remain interminable, unless we clear up a confusion about Marx which all three share. Clearing up this confusion will allow us to get in focus an account of human nature I label “Dialectical Aristotelianism”. I am unable to offer a detailed defense of this position here—rather, I offer it as something which might be worked out more comprehensively in other work.<sup>1</sup></p><p>The point I wish to make here, and the way I wish to make it, unfortunately demands a structure which might at first glance seem a little obscure. To spell it out: in Section 1, I introduce the perennial philosophical problem of “what separates us from the animals”—working my way toward Midgley's critique of the “single distinguishing factor” conception of what separates human beings from other animals in <i>Beast and Man</i>. Sections 2 and 3 relate an existing debate between McDowell and Thompson, who both incorporate Marx into their attempts to find such a single distinguishing factor. In Section 4, I introduce Midgley's specific criticisms of what she sees as Marx's attempt to identify a “single distinguishing factor” answer to the question of what separates us from the animals—criticisms which would seem to do for McDowell and Thompson as well. In Section 5, I explain why (in my view) Midgley was wrong about Marx—and then proceed to demonstrate that, in <i>The German Ideology</i>, he and Engels (albeit in an incomplete, increasingly disputed text) can be read as providing us with a “single distinguishing factor” answer to the question of what separates us from the animals that does <i>not</i> suffer from the problems Midgley identifies with (usual) attempts to identify such a factor. The result is an account which is, handily, able to incorporate the best of Midgley's, McDowell's, and Thompson's views. This is the position that, in the conclusion, I label “Dialectical Aristotelianism”.</p><p>As human beings, we have some notion of ourselves as a species, and not only that, we have a sense of ourselves as a different kind of species, distinct somehow from all other animals. This sense of difference is perhaps best articulated as the Aristotelian notion that humans, as rational animals, are in some important sense “between beast and god”.<sup>2</sup></p><p>We bear the kind of animal life which is capable of doing things like living in great cities, building cathedrals, and of writing <i>The Simpsons</i> seasons 2–8. Over time, we have invented agriculture, industrialism, and the internet. Our economic activity is capable, we now know, of making the rest of planet unlivable; our weapons could destroy all life on earth in a few seconds, if we cued them up to detonate at the right time. Other animals are impressive—brilliant and beautiful and terrible—in all sorts of ways. But not, you know, like <i>us</i>.</p><p>And yet, almost invariably, whenever philosophers have attempted to articulate the source of this difference, to give an account of what precisely the distinction between human and animal life consists in, they have ended up saying things that can sound basically rather <i>silly</i>. The danger here is perhaps best expressed in that story about Plato—presumably apocryphal, although based on a remark from the <i>Statesman</i> (266e)—where he was lecturing one day in the academy, and asked to provide a definition of “man”. He defined man as a “featherless biped”—only for Diogenes the Cynic to pull out a plucked chicken.</p><p>Thus Descartes identified human life as being distinguished by our ability to use language in novel and spontaneous ways—only to leave us with no way of distinguishing “lower” animals from convincing automata (Descartes, <span>1968</span>, p. 72ff). Thus Kant identified us as being distinguished by our faculty of reason—as being a creature that has a “rational nature” capable of existing as “an end in itself” (Kant, <span>1997</span>, p. 37)—only to be left with no real way of distinguishing human beings from rational Martians (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 701).<sup>3</sup></p><p>First, Midgley notes, for all that humans really “do things differently” from other animals, we are all too inclined to be forgetful of the fact that the form of life we bear is (at least) <i>also</i> an animal one. We should therefore limit ourselves to only asking what distinguishes man <i>among</i> the animals, not what separates us from other animals entirely (ibid.).</p><p>Second, Midgley states: “as the question is usually put, it asks for a single, simple, final distinction, and for one that confers praise” (ibid.). But we have no real way of backing up our commonplace assumption that the human form of life is an especially <i>good</i> one. No other animal, Midgley notes, is as aggressive toward their own kind (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 27); no other animal is as wantonly cruel to, and exploitative of, other species (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 30).</p><p>Midgley thus recommends a deflationary, therapeutic approach, emphasizing humanity's continuity with the rest of nature. Rather than attempt to develop a robust and philosophical account of what single thing ultimately, finally distinguishes human life, we should look instead for a “knot of general structural properties,” which might include things like language, rationality, and culture—all of which, Midgley specifies, are contiguous with, not distinct from, “nature” more broadly understood (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 309).</p><p>Sound advice, perhaps. But it is not as if every single philosopher since Midgley has taken it to heart. Even if ideas in general really could be demolished by a single, somewhat well-known thinker calling them convincingly into question: the heritage of the “single distinguishing factor” conception of human life is vast; its temptations, for all the problems with it that Midgley diagnoses, are in many ways wired into our understanding of ourselves. As Midgley herself notes, the linguistic construction I am exploiting in this paper, “that's what distinguishes us from the animals” is an almost everyday one (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 35).</p><p>It should hardly be surprising, then, that we continue to find advocates of some form of “single distinguishing factor” (henceforth, SDF) view. Arguably, Midgley has only shown that we <i>must</i> abandon SDF. To paraphrase John McDowell in the Introduction to <i>Mind and World</i>, she has not (yet) shown that we <i>can</i>.<sup>4</sup></p><p>McDowell, as it happens, is among the more sophisticated contemporary exponents of SDF.<sup>5</sup> It is his attempt to articulate a sophisticated version of SDF, which motivates his appropriation of Marx. Reporting McDowell's appropriation of Marx will be the first contribution to the “debate” that I wish to stage in this paper.</p><p>If we can ascribe subjective experiences to ourselves, then we can become aware of the world—which is thus able to operate as a rational constraint on our thought.<sup>6</sup> This power, McDowell claims, is identical to “spontaneity of the understanding” and thus also to “the power of conceptual thinking” (ibid.). Self-conscious subjectivity, then, separates us from the animals by making reason and language possible.</p><p>McDowell thus clearly holds a version of SDF. What makes him a <i>more sophisticated exponent</i> of such a view, as I have claimed, is that he appears to have identified—and moved to mitigate—certain problems with it.</p><p>The first of these problems consists in what we might call a <i>Descartes-type worry</i>.<sup>7</sup> As McDowell points out, if we require self-conscious subjectivity to experience the world, but other animals lack it, then surely it follows that nonhuman animals have no external experience at all? “And that can seem to commit me to the Cartesian idea that brutes are automata” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 114). “Mere animals cannot enjoy ‘outer experience’,” McDowell tells us, “on the conception of ‘outer experience’ I have recommended.” And yet, “it is a plain fact that we share perception with mere animals” (ibid.).</p><p>In order to short-circuit the Descartes-type worry, McDowell borrows the distinction between “world” and “environment” from Hans-Georg Gadamer. For Gadamer too, language distinguishes human beings from other animals—and this is identical to the fact that we exist in a “world,” which we can have a “free orientation” toward (Gadamer, <span>2004</span>, pp. 440–441).</p><p>The “environment”, by contrast, is something which “all living beings… possess” (ibid.), a “milieu” of problems and opportunities, which—unlike the “world”—one is not as such freely oriented toward (ibid.). “World” means thought, thus freedom; “environment” means instinct, thus its opposite.</p><p>When it comes to perception, mere animals might well be oriented toward the exact same <i>object</i> as us world-havers—but <i>subjectively</i> speaking, their orientation could not be more different. In the absence of self-conscious subjectivity, what sentience animals do have is “in the service of a mode of life that is structured exclusively by immediate biological imperatives… the animal's behaviour at a given moment is an immediate outcome of biological forces” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 115). Gadamer, thus, allows us to affirm McDowell's account of what separates us from the animals without succumbing to the Descartes-type worry.</p><p>But there remains a further problem with McDowell's view. This we might express as consisting in a <i>Kant-type worry</i>. McDowell's notion of “self-conscious subjectivity” is lifted almost verbatim from Kant: as the “spontaneity of understanding”, which is identical with “the power of conceptual thinking,” McDowell's “self-conscious subjectivity” is essentially what Kant named, in the Transcendental Deduction, as “the original synthetic unity of apperception.”<sup>8</sup></p><p>But, as McDowell himself notes, Kant “lacks a pregnant notion of second nature” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 110).<sup>9</sup> This amounts to the accusation that Kant, by conceiving of “nature” only in the law-like terms of mechanistic natural science, was unable to think “nature” and “reason” together. This means that self-conscious subjectivity as Kant defines it—the original synthetic unity of apperception—“could not be something substantially present in the world; it is at best a point of view” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 111).</p><p>The invocation of Gadamer's distinction between world and environment has, McDowell thinks, resolved what I have called the “Descartes-type worry”. But it has not yet done enough against the Kant-type worry. Our “world” after all, in being the sort of thing we are able to assume a “free and distanced” orientation toward, might not be quite enough of an “environment”—might, one supposes, be the sort of thing we are only <i>disinterestedly</i> oriented within. In short, we would be oriented toward our world not as “human animals”, but as something rather closer to gods. “Self-conscious subjectivity” cannot account for our animal nature satisfactorily, because it does not have enough to do with the “animal” world.<sup>10</sup></p><p>To read Marx, McDowell seems to be telling us, is to understand that self-conscious human subjects cannot be mere, disinterested, Kantian transcendental points of view. This is because our form of life requires us to live off and “make over” nature—“the sensuous exterior world.” Nevertheless, with that necessity can come freedom. It is in our productive relationship to the world that we live off, that our freedom is expressed.</p><p>It is worth mentioning that McDowell's reading of Marx is at least somewhat restricted. While in Marx, alienation has four moments,<sup>11</sup> for McDowell alienation appears to consist fundamentally in the rendering for the worker of the Gadamerian “world” into a mere “environment”. It is this point that unites all four moments of alienated labor: an “alienated” existence would be an unfree one, because the worker would find their lives governed by a necessity that is, in McDowell's understanding, baldly natural.</p><p>An “unalienated” existence, by contrast, would not, McDowell thinks, be an “easy” one, but would rather be “distinctively free.” We would still need to produce things from nature in order to survive, but we would do so in such a way that our humanity was affirmed—realising our humanity in the act of making.<sup>12</sup> McDowell notes, for instance, that Marx tells us in “Alienated Labour” that “man is unique in producing ‘according to the laws of beauty’.” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 119).</p><p>It is this sort of thing—an awareness of the “laws of beauty” and suchlike—that McDowell thinks indicates that we are a creature defined by our “self-conscious subjectivity”: the single distinguishing capacity which allows us, from our position within nature, to resonate with whatever it is that reason, free in some sense from nature's law, happens to demand. Free, seemingly, of both the Descartes-type and Kant-type worries, McDowell is able to cite “self-conscious subjectivity” as what distinguishes us from the animals, quite regardless of any Midgleyan critique.</p><p>McDowell's account of human nature, however, has been directly criticized by Michael Thompson. Thompson's critique essentially consists in the claim that McDowell fails to do enough work to avoid the Kant-type worry—in part because he has not really understood the early Marx.</p><p>This critique is expressed in the text of Thompson's 2013 lecture, “Forms of nature: ‘first’, ‘second’, ‘living’, ‘rational’ and ‘phronetic’.” There, Thompson's overarching concern is to assert the claims of what he calls a “naïve Aristotelianism”, “opposed to the sophisticated naturalism of ‘second nature’ that has been occasionally proposed by John McDowell” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 701). Here then, the debate between Thompson and McDowell is very much a direct one. What is important to me here is how Thompson uses Marx in it—for the sake of clarity if not brevity (both in terms of Thompson vs. McDowell, and also in terms of the positive position I will be arriving at by the end of this paper), I will unpack what is at stake in it beforehand.</p><p>For McDowell, “first nature” is identified as the object of the natural-scientific intelligibility—in <i>Mind and World</i>, this means it is aligned with the realm of law.<sup>13</sup> It is thus perhaps natural to assume that second nature is supposed to align with the realm of law's McDowell-Sellarsian opposite, the normative “space of reasons”—but this is not quite the case.</p><p>“Our human second nature,” it is true, “makes us inhabitants of the logical space of reasons” (McDowell, <span>2008</span>, p. 220). But the idea of second nature in fact “fits any propensities of animals that are not already possessed at birth, and not acquired in merely biological maturation (like, for instance, the propensity to grow facial hair on the part of male human beings), but imparted by education, habituation, or training” (ibid.). Thus, McDowell tells us, “trained dogs have a second nature” (ibid.). But, because trained dogs are not able to think critically about their commands as we can, they are not therefore inhabitants of the space of reasons.</p><p>From this then, for McDowell, it seems, reason is not substantially part of nature—the two realms turn no particular gears with each other. As rational animals our second nature—appropriately formed—gives us access to the space of reasons. But the space of reasons itself does not, as such, have anything in particular to do with nature: “the dictates of reason are there anyway, whether or not one's eyes are opened to them” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 91).</p><p>McDowell, naturally, does not think this is a problem, in fact, he thinks it is the only way we're going to be able to make sense of the distinctive relationship between reason and nature at all. In his essay, “Two Sorts of Naturalism”, an important supplement to <i>Mind and World</i>, McDowell gives the example of a pack of wolves who suddenly and collectively acquire reason (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 169). What, McDowell asks, can the wolves now do, that they could not before? Each wolf, McDowell answers, now has the ability to “step back” from their natural impulses and assume a “critical stance” toward them. To anything a wolf might instinctively do (hunt in packs, for instance), the wolf can now ask: “Why should I do this?” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 171).</p><p>As McDowell notes, this example shows up the “deep connection between reason and freedom” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 170). Wolfish nature—from which individual wolves might derive, for instance, the need to eat meat—continues to present each wolf with various demands, problems, and opportunities. But we could not make sense of the wolves actually being rational if they were not free to let their minds range over pretty much every possibility, hypothetical or concrete, that their world and their imaginations now present them with. The wolves would have to be able to entertain the possibility of being vegetarian, for instance: no matter how their stomachs were constituted.</p><p>“This allows,” McDowell tells us, “for radical ethical reflection” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 189). The model McDowell invokes for this form of reflection—both in “Two Sorts of Naturalism” and <i>Mind and World</i>—is that of “Neurath's Boat”, “in which a sailor overhauls his ship while it is afloat” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 81). In this image, the sailor has complete free reign to overhaul their boat however they may wish to—given the materials they have to hand. The only proviso is that the ship must always remain minimally functional as they do so. In time, of course, Neurath's Boat could become like Theseus's Ship, in which nothing of the original remains.<sup>14</sup></p><p>First nature, as McDowell specifies, puts “limits on the courses reflection can intelligibly take” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 190). But it does not do any more than that: there are not, that is, any <i>reasons</i> on the level of first nature itself. The natural fact that “wolves hunt in packs” is not a <i>reason</i> for rational wolves to hunt in packs. By contrast, the rational consideration that “wolves do best, in obtaining the things they need in order to survive, if they hunt in packs” <i>is</i>.</p><p>For Thompson, however, this Neurathian conception of reflection is deeply problematic. According to him, this way of conceiving of the relation between nature and reason is evidence that McDowell—like Kant—thinks that, as “rational animals” we must in effect share the same nature as any hypothetical rational Martians (or wolves). He has not, in short, done enough to overcome the “Kant-type worry”. Any finite rational beings—be they humans or Martians or wolves or whatever—must, for Kant (and so for McDowell) have an understanding structured, as per the results of the Transcendental Deduction, in accordance with the categories, and be subject to the moral law (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 704).</p><p>What this means is that, if we were to identify human nature (as McDowell does) with “self-conscious subjectivity”, we would not really have picked out anything like a <i>specifically human</i> nature at all. Rather, we would have identified human nature with rationality in general—distinct from the animals, but not from, say, rational Martians, angels, or gods.</p><p>It is to overcome this vestigial Kantianism—which for him results from McDowell's overly “sophisticated” version of naturalism—that Thompson asserts the claims of his “naïve Aristotelianism”. According to naïve Aristotelianism, human “is in a certain way put on a level with words like ‘Norway rat’ and ‘coastal redwood’.” Ethical reflection is a possibility for the sorts of creatures that we are—human beings. But it is not carried on in relation to anything else immutably beyond us—some heaven of reason, which would show up the same for any sufficiently rational beings. Rather, it is just another function of the human form of life. To put this point in another way: to make sense of ourselves as rational animals we do not, for Thompson, need to posit some supplementary realm of “second nature” which “opens our eyes” to the requirements of reason. Rather, the requirements of reason, for us, are just the first natural ones. So, first nature is all we need.</p><p>Of course there is an obvious problem here, one which Thompson is aware of, namely, that any such “naïve” form of naturalism, in which reflection is—necessarily and only—guided by the facts of human first nature, might understandably be thought to imply an “alarming and idiotic moral conservatism” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 702). This idiocy would present us with practical syllogisms of the form: “Men dance, dancing is something that belongs to human nature, dancing is what is natural to them—<i>so</i> I'll dance too.” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 705). Obviously, this is also the sort of picture of (natural) reflection that McDowell is looking to avoid, one on which the “free play of reason” is made the slave of whatever, in nature, already exists. So, what resources might Thompson's naïve Aristotelianism be able to access to avoid it?<sup>15</sup></p><p>Thompson's solution here turns on a distinction which Aristotle makes, but which Thompson accuses McDowell of missing, between two modes of knowledge: <i>sophia</i> and <i>phronesis</i>. <i>Sophia</i> for Aristotle is “like the straight and the white, everywhere the same” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 710). It is the mode of knowledge appropriate for things like “the constituents of the heavens” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 711). By contrast, <i>phronesis</i>—‘“practical wisdom”—is “like healthy and good—different for man and fish” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 710).</p><p>To make sense of the object of <i>phronesis</i>, Thompson turns to the work of G.E.M. Anscombe. In her <i>Intention</i>, Anscombe draws a distinction between practical and observational knowledge (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 713). Observational knowledge involves a relation to some object independent of the observer. It is, essentially, “scientific” knowledge: to know something observationally would be to know it as it would appear “objectively”, from nowhere.</p><p>Practical knowledge, by contrast, is known “from the inside” of some practice that the knower is engaged in—it is thus in some sense “productive of the thing known” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 714).<sup>16</sup> We have already seen how, for Marx, we “produce” the things we need in order to survive. Here our activity manifests itself as an object—thus as something potentially alien to us. What Anscombe means by “production” is related to this, but by no means the same.</p><p>One example would be something like the knowledge of how to play a sport. Granted, when a sport is codified, one can write down the rules and someone could study them, without ever playing it. One could even become an expert on the sport, purely as a spectator or a journalist. All of this would count as “observational” knowledge of, say, football. But one would not know <i>how</i> to play it, unless one actually played a match. The practical knowledge of how to play football, for instance, is something both realized and sustained by the players, as they play the game themselves. Certain aspects of it might be explicable in the abstract, for example, where the players are supposed to be positioned. But others —like knowing when or how to shoot, how to psych the keeper out in the split-second where he has to decide which way to go when taking a penalty—can only be known in the flow of the moment from within. Armchair observers might believe themselves to have a great deal of expertise, but that does not mean they could manage the England side.</p><p>Another example would, according to Thompson at least, be “human”. For Thompson, “human” is something that we (human beings) manifest over the course of our lives—just as, I have claimed, footballers manifest the knowledge of how to play football in their playing it. “Human” is thus, Thompson claims, an (Anscombian) practical concept.</p><p>It is in this way that he is able to avoid the charge of conservatism. Of course, we are free to reflect on our species-life: reflection is just one of the things human beings do. Given that “human” is a practical concept, we <i>manifest</i> our species-life as we reflect on what we ought, or ought not, to do. But we do not do this by relating human beings to the sphere of “pure rationality”—this would only be possible if <i>phronesis</i> were like <i>sophia</i>, the same anywhere in the universe, at any particular historical moment. Practical reflection is, for human beings, both immanent and internal. In ethical reflection, we only have human things to go by: living, material, human needs, and concerns.</p><p>It is with this in mind that Thompson relates his criticisms of McDowell to the early Marx. McDowell, as we have seen, turns to Marx to guard against the possibility that the self-conscious subject is somehow an <i>over-rational</i>, disinterested observer in relation to their world. For Thompson, however, McDowell's invocation of Marx is inopportune—as by implication, all it shows is that McDowell has not realized that the Marx of “Alienated Labour” is in fact a powerful <i>critic</i> of McDowell's Kant-inflected understanding of the intersection of reason and nature.</p><p>The key concept that Thompson is interested in is that of “species-being”—alienation from “species-being” being one of the “four moments” of alienation that Marx discusses in his essay. Thompson defines this thing—species-being—as “the registering of the (first natural) universal one comes under… a condition of all universal representation… a condition of having concepts.” On this Marxist view, then “‘Human’ is, for each of us, the original universal.” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 728).</p><p>This point does not necessarily come across all that strongly in “Alienated Labour” itself, where Marx defines “species-being” only very vaguely (Marx, <span>2000a</span>, p. 89; 90). It does however shine forth a lot more clearly when we consider the work of Ludwig Feuerbach—the thinker whose jargon Marx was, back then, largely still employing.</p><p>In <i>The Essence of Christianity</i>, Feuerbach tells us that “the essential difference between man and the animal” is “consciousness” (Feuerbach, <span>2012</span>, p. 97). But he does not mean “consciousness in the sense of the feeling of the self, in the sense of the ability to distinguish one sensuous object from another, to perceive—even judge,” since this sort of consciousness, he takes it, obviously cannot be denied of every animal (ibid.).</p><p>As soon as one sees the “human” as a practical rather than a theoretical concept, then we must ground self-conscious subjectivity in species-being. This, then, is what Thompson believes—and also what he thinks Marx believed, and what he thinks McDowell <i>should</i> believe—distinguishes human from animal life: the fact that we are able to relate to ourselves <i>as a species</i>.</p><p>Thus, we have seen, so far, how McDowell and Thompson invoke Marx in the context of a discussion of what distinguishes us from other animals in two different ways. McDowell uses Marx to help vindicate his citing of “self-conscious subjectivity” as what distinguishes human life (our ability to relate to ourselves). Thompson, however, uses Marx to, more comprehensively, naturalize McDowell's liberal naturalism, by arguing that self-conscious subjectivity is grounded in species-being (our ability to relate to ourselves as a species). I will now bring this controversy between McDowell and Thompson, back around to Midgley.</p><p>At first glance, this point might seem fair enough. If by “producing” is meant “the processing of materials, rather than simply gathering them,” then—as Midgley states—“bees, beavers, and termites do at least as well as the simple hunting-and-gathering human tribes.” “Which shows,” as she then states, “that you have to consider <i>which</i> animals you are distinguishing yourself from” (ibid.). “Producing” cannot do enough work to separate us from the animals.</p><p>But this, Midgley goes on to explain, is not the only understanding of what “producing” means that Marx might have had in mind. He could also, she says, have meant the “free and deliberate planning of what one does, whether it be gathering, processing, or anything else” (ibid.). The problem here, however, is that while this way of understanding “producing” as the single factor which distinguishes human from animal life does indeed seem to put man “in a special position,” “but then he is so for everything he does, not just for production” (ibid.). In short, the problem with this reading, is that it seems to turn “producing” into something like McDowell's free “self-conscious subjectivity”. Perhaps this is a better distinguishing factor (although, of course, Thompson would disagree), but it is not the one that Marx appears to cite in <i>The German Ideology</i>.</p><p>Midgley then precisely discovers this criterion of “self-conscious subjectivity” in “Alienated Labour”, and likewise moves to dismiss it. Here, she claims, the “main emphasis” is not on production, but rather on “free conscious choice.” “This,” she comments, “is something found over a much wider range of activity than mere production, and certainly is a human structural characteristic, though by no means our only one… Man is, indeed, essentially rational for Marx but his reason is actualized in productive activity.’” (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, pp. 199–200).</p><p>Midgley thus seems to be reading Marx as McDowell does—it's just that she doesn't think the resulting position <i>works</i>. For Midgley, Marx's whole approach is misguided because he insists, perversely, on holding SDF. “If another species were… found which did just what Marx meant by producing, it would not damage his argument about the structure of human life at all” (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 200).</p><p>We can thus reconstruct Midgley's argument as follows. Marx and McDowell both attempt to cite “self-conscious subjectivity’” as an SDF. This cannot work—the story has to be at least somewhat more ambiguous and complicated than that.</p><p>Midgley, then, might seem at this point like she would (or should) be in agreement with Thompson. Implicitly, at any rate, her understanding of how human life is related to the rest of nature might be thought to commit her to an Aristotelianism that Thompson would recognize as being laudably “naïve.”<sup>18</sup> Thompson, likewise, still thinks that human beings are distinguished, at least in part, by our ability to operate “free conscious choice.” But this capacity does not, as such, cleave off a wholesale distinction between us and other animals—since it is, for Thompson, a first-natural thing that we do; inherently limited by the fact that we manifest our species-nature through it. “Man” is the original universal and thus it not only liberates, but also limits us.</p><p>But on consideration of Thompson's reading of Marx, it seems clear that any tentative alliance between himself and Midgley, against McDowell, would be unsustainable. Thompson, with Marx, thinks what distinguishes human life is our ability to relate to ourselves as a species: that we have what he calls “species-being.” Midgley, however, as per the quotes given above, only seems able to read Marx's early “species-talk” as asserting the existence of some sort of simple, universal human essence.</p><p>Interestingly, this is an aspect of Marx's early thought that he is usually thought (if not by Thompson) to have rejected. In “Theses on Feuerbach” VI, Marx writes that Feuerbach ‘‘resolves the religious essence into the human essence. “But,” he says, “the human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations” (Marx, <span>2000c</span>, p. 172).</p><p>Feuerbach is thus, Marx claims, “compelled… to abstract from the historical process and to fix the religious sentiment as something by itself and to presuppose an abstract—isolated—human individual” (ibid.). For this reason, “essence”, in Feuerbach, “can be comprehended only as ‘genus’ [<i>Gattung</i>], as an internal, dumb generality which naturally unites the many individuals” (ibid.).</p><p>Marx, then, might have been an SDF theorist in 1844, when he wrote “Alienated Labour.” But by April 1845, when he wrote the “Theses”, he was not. It is therefore <i>prima facie</i> rather odd that Midgley started her dismissal of Marx's understanding of what distinguishes human life with a quote from <i>The German Ideology</i>—which was written around a year after the “Theses”. Did Marx simply regress (rather quickly) from the high point of the “Theses”? Or is there something deeper going on here?</p><p>As we saw at the start of Section 4 above, Midgley quotes this line from the “Feuerbach” chapter of <i>The German Ideology</i> as evidence for the charge that Marx is an SDF theorist—one who believes that humans are distinguished from the animals by “production” (whatever exactly that means). And certainly, when these are the only words from this passage that one cites, it can seem like this reading of Marx is both natural and fair.</p><p>Initially, then, what seems important to grasp is that, while Marx and Engels are talking in this passage about how human and animal life are distinguished from each other, “production” only enters the scene <i>after</i> the “physical organisation” of human individuals has in some sense been “established.” The distinguishing of human life through “production”, then, is very much a process that is supposed to be contiguous with the rest of nature (both human and otherwise).</p><p>Thus whereas—we must suppose—sharks and squirrels, bees and bugs, and so on and so forth, are able to obtain the things they need in order to survive <i>without</i> inadvertently producing new needs for themselves, we human beings are not so lucky.</p><p>We learn to plant seeds to have enough crops to feed ourselves; then we produce the need for land. We divide up the land among our community to ensure that everyone will have enough to plant on; then some of the land turns out to be bad, and we need more, but it belongs to our neighbors and now we need to go to war. So, we need swords, shields, walls, catapults, barrels full of boiling tar, tanks, and bombs, and the UN, and who knows what else.</p><p>If there is indeed a certain sort of practical rationality in operation here—through this grand historical process, after all, we produce pretty much everything we “know”—then it is an <i>alienated</i> one: we have no transparent insight into our products. These things—not least, our <i>needs</i>—loom horribly above us, urging us ever onward, to do evermore stupid and destructive things, just to satisfy our material wants.</p><p>This ever-expanding, evermore complex network of needs, the satisfaction of which produces other new needs, informs the story that Marx and Engels then give of the development of the family and then of society (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, pp. 182–183). Crucially, Marx and Engels claim that it is only with these developments that “consciousness”—that is, what we have been calling “self-conscious subjectivity” enters the scene (ibid.). Even then, consciousness of this sort never appears in a completely “pure” form. Thought, after all, is for Marx and Engels determined by life (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 181).</p><p>It may well be, of course, that Marx continues to affirm some notion of “species-being”. But if he does, then our “species-being” could not be an <i>abstract</i> universal. If in “Alienated Labour”, production was a function of our species, now our species-essence is a function of production.</p><p>And this means that Man is, at least to a certain extent, malleable. It is in <i>The German Ideology</i> that we get what looks like<sup>20</sup> Marx's most comprehensive account of how history is supposed somehow to culminate in the establishment of some sort of universal communist state (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 187). But this is a teleology that in no sense assumes the existence of some sort of pre-established human essence (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 190). Rather, the establishing of communism must be seen to involve a qualitative transformation: “the alteration of men on a mass scale” (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 195). Under communism, we will be able to produce just as we have been prevented from producing up until now, in the way that “lower” animals do, that is without inadvertently producing new needs. It is, in fact, at this point and only at this point that freedom and activity will, for Marx, genuinely coincide.</p><p>Thus, no longer will our activity stand as “an objective power above us, growing out of our control” (ibid.)—it will be something we can exercise with all the grace and pleasure that so-called lower animals seem to take in their own movements. And so, at the end of this process, we will have ceased to be the unhappy “rational animals” that we are now: these strange creatures who find themselves subject to all these conflicting compulsions and are yet aware, somehow, that they should not be. The history of our species will culminate, with our finally having transcended our own nature.<sup>21</sup></p><p>It is here, at the end of this unfortunately rather knotty, winding road, that I have arrived at a position where I am able to spell out the positive point of this paper. Call the position that results from this discussion of Marx (and Engels, Midgley, Thompson, and McDowell) a “Dialectical Aristotelianism”. According to Dialectical Aristotelianism, “Human” is the type of unity that can <i>never</i> exist comfortably in the world, in the way that other animals, in their natural habitats, might seem to. “Human” is the type of species-unity that necessarily <i>lacks</i> a habitat, that has been doomed to evolve constantly and vertiginously: ever upwards, perhaps, but hardly in a way that “makes us better” in any independent sense.<sup>22</sup> Until the revolution comes, of course, and the proletariat rise up, and “the riddle of history” is solved. Perhaps this would be the realization of our nature; on the other hand perhaps it would represent our transformation into a different sort of unity. As of now, the Dialectical Aristotelian can be happy to remain agnostic on this score.</p><p>It is my view that Dialectical Aristotelianism can provide us with a robust, <i>anti-essentialist</i> account of what separates human beings from other animals—an account of our species' distinctiveness, that nevertheless satisfies the various constraints that Midgley would want to put on any such account: no oversimplification; no biologically provincial moral elevation; no cleaving off of “rational” humanity from the rest of nature.</p><p>This is something that other, competing accounts are unable to do. While Dialectical Aristotelianism might still point to something analogous “species-being,” it posits our species-essence as something <i>historical</i>. What it points to is thus not a <i>simple</i>, essential factor—as it is not something that all human animals are supposed to share in the same way over time. The ‘distinguishing factor’ here is one that can change, be transformed, go wrong; if we believe Marx, it can even be overthrown entirely.<sup>23</sup></p><p>As yet, of course, there is more work to be done here—this paper only sketches ‘Dialectical Aristotelianism’ as a position and gives us some reason to believe that Marx and Engels, at least at one stage, held it. <i>Why</i> does humanity produce in the way that it does? To what extent is this account of human nature necessarily bound up with Marx and Engels's political aims? And how does it relate to other accounts of human nature that have recently been proposed in the literature (not least the authors listed in footnote 5 above)? All these must remain, for now, open questions. Consider this the seed of a research project.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-08-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12712","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Dialectical Aristotelianism: On Marx's account of what separates us from the animals\",\"authors\":\"Tom Whyman\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12712\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>I have noticed, in Anglophone philosophy, a certain way of invoking Marx. The pattern here is—understandably, given the relative scarcity of substantial engagement with Marx outside of (radical) political theory—a rather loose one. But I've spotted it in the work of John McDowell, Michael Thompson, and Mary Midgley. In each of these thinkers, Marx is invoked in the context of an inquiry into human nature: into the question of what (if anything) separates us from the animals.</p><p>In this paper, I propose to adjudicate a certain debate between these three thinkers—a debate which their shared invocation of Marx allows us to stage. I will argue that this debate between McDowell, Thompson, and Midgley, such as it is, is doomed to remain interminable, unless we clear up a confusion about Marx which all three share. Clearing up this confusion will allow us to get in focus an account of human nature I label “Dialectical Aristotelianism”. I am unable to offer a detailed defense of this position here—rather, I offer it as something which might be worked out more comprehensively in other work.<sup>1</sup></p><p>The point I wish to make here, and the way I wish to make it, unfortunately demands a structure which might at first glance seem a little obscure. To spell it out: in Section 1, I introduce the perennial philosophical problem of “what separates us from the animals”—working my way toward Midgley's critique of the “single distinguishing factor” conception of what separates human beings from other animals in <i>Beast and Man</i>. Sections 2 and 3 relate an existing debate between McDowell and Thompson, who both incorporate Marx into their attempts to find such a single distinguishing factor. In Section 4, I introduce Midgley's specific criticisms of what she sees as Marx's attempt to identify a “single distinguishing factor” answer to the question of what separates us from the animals—criticisms which would seem to do for McDowell and Thompson as well. In Section 5, I explain why (in my view) Midgley was wrong about Marx—and then proceed to demonstrate that, in <i>The German Ideology</i>, he and Engels (albeit in an incomplete, increasingly disputed text) can be read as providing us with a “single distinguishing factor” answer to the question of what separates us from the animals that does <i>not</i> suffer from the problems Midgley identifies with (usual) attempts to identify such a factor. The result is an account which is, handily, able to incorporate the best of Midgley's, McDowell's, and Thompson's views. This is the position that, in the conclusion, I label “Dialectical Aristotelianism”.</p><p>As human beings, we have some notion of ourselves as a species, and not only that, we have a sense of ourselves as a different kind of species, distinct somehow from all other animals. This sense of difference is perhaps best articulated as the Aristotelian notion that humans, as rational animals, are in some important sense “between beast and god”.<sup>2</sup></p><p>We bear the kind of animal life which is capable of doing things like living in great cities, building cathedrals, and of writing <i>The Simpsons</i> seasons 2–8. Over time, we have invented agriculture, industrialism, and the internet. Our economic activity is capable, we now know, of making the rest of planet unlivable; our weapons could destroy all life on earth in a few seconds, if we cued them up to detonate at the right time. Other animals are impressive—brilliant and beautiful and terrible—in all sorts of ways. But not, you know, like <i>us</i>.</p><p>And yet, almost invariably, whenever philosophers have attempted to articulate the source of this difference, to give an account of what precisely the distinction between human and animal life consists in, they have ended up saying things that can sound basically rather <i>silly</i>. The danger here is perhaps best expressed in that story about Plato—presumably apocryphal, although based on a remark from the <i>Statesman</i> (266e)—where he was lecturing one day in the academy, and asked to provide a definition of “man”. He defined man as a “featherless biped”—only for Diogenes the Cynic to pull out a plucked chicken.</p><p>Thus Descartes identified human life as being distinguished by our ability to use language in novel and spontaneous ways—only to leave us with no way of distinguishing “lower” animals from convincing automata (Descartes, <span>1968</span>, p. 72ff). Thus Kant identified us as being distinguished by our faculty of reason—as being a creature that has a “rational nature” capable of existing as “an end in itself” (Kant, <span>1997</span>, p. 37)—only to be left with no real way of distinguishing human beings from rational Martians (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 701).<sup>3</sup></p><p>First, Midgley notes, for all that humans really “do things differently” from other animals, we are all too inclined to be forgetful of the fact that the form of life we bear is (at least) <i>also</i> an animal one. We should therefore limit ourselves to only asking what distinguishes man <i>among</i> the animals, not what separates us from other animals entirely (ibid.).</p><p>Second, Midgley states: “as the question is usually put, it asks for a single, simple, final distinction, and for one that confers praise” (ibid.). But we have no real way of backing up our commonplace assumption that the human form of life is an especially <i>good</i> one. No other animal, Midgley notes, is as aggressive toward their own kind (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 27); no other animal is as wantonly cruel to, and exploitative of, other species (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 30).</p><p>Midgley thus recommends a deflationary, therapeutic approach, emphasizing humanity's continuity with the rest of nature. Rather than attempt to develop a robust and philosophical account of what single thing ultimately, finally distinguishes human life, we should look instead for a “knot of general structural properties,” which might include things like language, rationality, and culture—all of which, Midgley specifies, are contiguous with, not distinct from, “nature” more broadly understood (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 309).</p><p>Sound advice, perhaps. But it is not as if every single philosopher since Midgley has taken it to heart. Even if ideas in general really could be demolished by a single, somewhat well-known thinker calling them convincingly into question: the heritage of the “single distinguishing factor” conception of human life is vast; its temptations, for all the problems with it that Midgley diagnoses, are in many ways wired into our understanding of ourselves. As Midgley herself notes, the linguistic construction I am exploiting in this paper, “that's what distinguishes us from the animals” is an almost everyday one (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 35).</p><p>It should hardly be surprising, then, that we continue to find advocates of some form of “single distinguishing factor” (henceforth, SDF) view. Arguably, Midgley has only shown that we <i>must</i> abandon SDF. To paraphrase John McDowell in the Introduction to <i>Mind and World</i>, she has not (yet) shown that we <i>can</i>.<sup>4</sup></p><p>McDowell, as it happens, is among the more sophisticated contemporary exponents of SDF.<sup>5</sup> It is his attempt to articulate a sophisticated version of SDF, which motivates his appropriation of Marx. Reporting McDowell's appropriation of Marx will be the first contribution to the “debate” that I wish to stage in this paper.</p><p>If we can ascribe subjective experiences to ourselves, then we can become aware of the world—which is thus able to operate as a rational constraint on our thought.<sup>6</sup> This power, McDowell claims, is identical to “spontaneity of the understanding” and thus also to “the power of conceptual thinking” (ibid.). Self-conscious subjectivity, then, separates us from the animals by making reason and language possible.</p><p>McDowell thus clearly holds a version of SDF. What makes him a <i>more sophisticated exponent</i> of such a view, as I have claimed, is that he appears to have identified—and moved to mitigate—certain problems with it.</p><p>The first of these problems consists in what we might call a <i>Descartes-type worry</i>.<sup>7</sup> As McDowell points out, if we require self-conscious subjectivity to experience the world, but other animals lack it, then surely it follows that nonhuman animals have no external experience at all? “And that can seem to commit me to the Cartesian idea that brutes are automata” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 114). “Mere animals cannot enjoy ‘outer experience’,” McDowell tells us, “on the conception of ‘outer experience’ I have recommended.” And yet, “it is a plain fact that we share perception with mere animals” (ibid.).</p><p>In order to short-circuit the Descartes-type worry, McDowell borrows the distinction between “world” and “environment” from Hans-Georg Gadamer. For Gadamer too, language distinguishes human beings from other animals—and this is identical to the fact that we exist in a “world,” which we can have a “free orientation” toward (Gadamer, <span>2004</span>, pp. 440–441).</p><p>The “environment”, by contrast, is something which “all living beings… possess” (ibid.), a “milieu” of problems and opportunities, which—unlike the “world”—one is not as such freely oriented toward (ibid.). “World” means thought, thus freedom; “environment” means instinct, thus its opposite.</p><p>When it comes to perception, mere animals might well be oriented toward the exact same <i>object</i> as us world-havers—but <i>subjectively</i> speaking, their orientation could not be more different. In the absence of self-conscious subjectivity, what sentience animals do have is “in the service of a mode of life that is structured exclusively by immediate biological imperatives… the animal's behaviour at a given moment is an immediate outcome of biological forces” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 115). Gadamer, thus, allows us to affirm McDowell's account of what separates us from the animals without succumbing to the Descartes-type worry.</p><p>But there remains a further problem with McDowell's view. This we might express as consisting in a <i>Kant-type worry</i>. McDowell's notion of “self-conscious subjectivity” is lifted almost verbatim from Kant: as the “spontaneity of understanding”, which is identical with “the power of conceptual thinking,” McDowell's “self-conscious subjectivity” is essentially what Kant named, in the Transcendental Deduction, as “the original synthetic unity of apperception.”<sup>8</sup></p><p>But, as McDowell himself notes, Kant “lacks a pregnant notion of second nature” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 110).<sup>9</sup> This amounts to the accusation that Kant, by conceiving of “nature” only in the law-like terms of mechanistic natural science, was unable to think “nature” and “reason” together. This means that self-conscious subjectivity as Kant defines it—the original synthetic unity of apperception—“could not be something substantially present in the world; it is at best a point of view” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 111).</p><p>The invocation of Gadamer's distinction between world and environment has, McDowell thinks, resolved what I have called the “Descartes-type worry”. But it has not yet done enough against the Kant-type worry. Our “world” after all, in being the sort of thing we are able to assume a “free and distanced” orientation toward, might not be quite enough of an “environment”—might, one supposes, be the sort of thing we are only <i>disinterestedly</i> oriented within. In short, we would be oriented toward our world not as “human animals”, but as something rather closer to gods. “Self-conscious subjectivity” cannot account for our animal nature satisfactorily, because it does not have enough to do with the “animal” world.<sup>10</sup></p><p>To read Marx, McDowell seems to be telling us, is to understand that self-conscious human subjects cannot be mere, disinterested, Kantian transcendental points of view. This is because our form of life requires us to live off and “make over” nature—“the sensuous exterior world.” Nevertheless, with that necessity can come freedom. It is in our productive relationship to the world that we live off, that our freedom is expressed.</p><p>It is worth mentioning that McDowell's reading of Marx is at least somewhat restricted. While in Marx, alienation has four moments,<sup>11</sup> for McDowell alienation appears to consist fundamentally in the rendering for the worker of the Gadamerian “world” into a mere “environment”. It is this point that unites all four moments of alienated labor: an “alienated” existence would be an unfree one, because the worker would find their lives governed by a necessity that is, in McDowell's understanding, baldly natural.</p><p>An “unalienated” existence, by contrast, would not, McDowell thinks, be an “easy” one, but would rather be “distinctively free.” We would still need to produce things from nature in order to survive, but we would do so in such a way that our humanity was affirmed—realising our humanity in the act of making.<sup>12</sup> McDowell notes, for instance, that Marx tells us in “Alienated Labour” that “man is unique in producing ‘according to the laws of beauty’.” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 119).</p><p>It is this sort of thing—an awareness of the “laws of beauty” and suchlike—that McDowell thinks indicates that we are a creature defined by our “self-conscious subjectivity”: the single distinguishing capacity which allows us, from our position within nature, to resonate with whatever it is that reason, free in some sense from nature's law, happens to demand. Free, seemingly, of both the Descartes-type and Kant-type worries, McDowell is able to cite “self-conscious subjectivity” as what distinguishes us from the animals, quite regardless of any Midgleyan critique.</p><p>McDowell's account of human nature, however, has been directly criticized by Michael Thompson. Thompson's critique essentially consists in the claim that McDowell fails to do enough work to avoid the Kant-type worry—in part because he has not really understood the early Marx.</p><p>This critique is expressed in the text of Thompson's 2013 lecture, “Forms of nature: ‘first’, ‘second’, ‘living’, ‘rational’ and ‘phronetic’.” There, Thompson's overarching concern is to assert the claims of what he calls a “naïve Aristotelianism”, “opposed to the sophisticated naturalism of ‘second nature’ that has been occasionally proposed by John McDowell” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 701). Here then, the debate between Thompson and McDowell is very much a direct one. What is important to me here is how Thompson uses Marx in it—for the sake of clarity if not brevity (both in terms of Thompson vs. McDowell, and also in terms of the positive position I will be arriving at by the end of this paper), I will unpack what is at stake in it beforehand.</p><p>For McDowell, “first nature” is identified as the object of the natural-scientific intelligibility—in <i>Mind and World</i>, this means it is aligned with the realm of law.<sup>13</sup> It is thus perhaps natural to assume that second nature is supposed to align with the realm of law's McDowell-Sellarsian opposite, the normative “space of reasons”—but this is not quite the case.</p><p>“Our human second nature,” it is true, “makes us inhabitants of the logical space of reasons” (McDowell, <span>2008</span>, p. 220). But the idea of second nature in fact “fits any propensities of animals that are not already possessed at birth, and not acquired in merely biological maturation (like, for instance, the propensity to grow facial hair on the part of male human beings), but imparted by education, habituation, or training” (ibid.). Thus, McDowell tells us, “trained dogs have a second nature” (ibid.). But, because trained dogs are not able to think critically about their commands as we can, they are not therefore inhabitants of the space of reasons.</p><p>From this then, for McDowell, it seems, reason is not substantially part of nature—the two realms turn no particular gears with each other. As rational animals our second nature—appropriately formed—gives us access to the space of reasons. But the space of reasons itself does not, as such, have anything in particular to do with nature: “the dictates of reason are there anyway, whether or not one's eyes are opened to them” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 91).</p><p>McDowell, naturally, does not think this is a problem, in fact, he thinks it is the only way we're going to be able to make sense of the distinctive relationship between reason and nature at all. In his essay, “Two Sorts of Naturalism”, an important supplement to <i>Mind and World</i>, McDowell gives the example of a pack of wolves who suddenly and collectively acquire reason (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 169). What, McDowell asks, can the wolves now do, that they could not before? Each wolf, McDowell answers, now has the ability to “step back” from their natural impulses and assume a “critical stance” toward them. To anything a wolf might instinctively do (hunt in packs, for instance), the wolf can now ask: “Why should I do this?” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 171).</p><p>As McDowell notes, this example shows up the “deep connection between reason and freedom” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 170). Wolfish nature—from which individual wolves might derive, for instance, the need to eat meat—continues to present each wolf with various demands, problems, and opportunities. But we could not make sense of the wolves actually being rational if they were not free to let their minds range over pretty much every possibility, hypothetical or concrete, that their world and their imaginations now present them with. The wolves would have to be able to entertain the possibility of being vegetarian, for instance: no matter how their stomachs were constituted.</p><p>“This allows,” McDowell tells us, “for radical ethical reflection” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 189). The model McDowell invokes for this form of reflection—both in “Two Sorts of Naturalism” and <i>Mind and World</i>—is that of “Neurath's Boat”, “in which a sailor overhauls his ship while it is afloat” (McDowell, <span>1996</span>, p. 81). In this image, the sailor has complete free reign to overhaul their boat however they may wish to—given the materials they have to hand. The only proviso is that the ship must always remain minimally functional as they do so. In time, of course, Neurath's Boat could become like Theseus's Ship, in which nothing of the original remains.<sup>14</sup></p><p>First nature, as McDowell specifies, puts “limits on the courses reflection can intelligibly take” (McDowell, <span>1998</span>, p. 190). But it does not do any more than that: there are not, that is, any <i>reasons</i> on the level of first nature itself. The natural fact that “wolves hunt in packs” is not a <i>reason</i> for rational wolves to hunt in packs. By contrast, the rational consideration that “wolves do best, in obtaining the things they need in order to survive, if they hunt in packs” <i>is</i>.</p><p>For Thompson, however, this Neurathian conception of reflection is deeply problematic. According to him, this way of conceiving of the relation between nature and reason is evidence that McDowell—like Kant—thinks that, as “rational animals” we must in effect share the same nature as any hypothetical rational Martians (or wolves). He has not, in short, done enough to overcome the “Kant-type worry”. Any finite rational beings—be they humans or Martians or wolves or whatever—must, for Kant (and so for McDowell) have an understanding structured, as per the results of the Transcendental Deduction, in accordance with the categories, and be subject to the moral law (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 704).</p><p>What this means is that, if we were to identify human nature (as McDowell does) with “self-conscious subjectivity”, we would not really have picked out anything like a <i>specifically human</i> nature at all. Rather, we would have identified human nature with rationality in general—distinct from the animals, but not from, say, rational Martians, angels, or gods.</p><p>It is to overcome this vestigial Kantianism—which for him results from McDowell's overly “sophisticated” version of naturalism—that Thompson asserts the claims of his “naïve Aristotelianism”. According to naïve Aristotelianism, human “is in a certain way put on a level with words like ‘Norway rat’ and ‘coastal redwood’.” Ethical reflection is a possibility for the sorts of creatures that we are—human beings. But it is not carried on in relation to anything else immutably beyond us—some heaven of reason, which would show up the same for any sufficiently rational beings. Rather, it is just another function of the human form of life. To put this point in another way: to make sense of ourselves as rational animals we do not, for Thompson, need to posit some supplementary realm of “second nature” which “opens our eyes” to the requirements of reason. Rather, the requirements of reason, for us, are just the first natural ones. So, first nature is all we need.</p><p>Of course there is an obvious problem here, one which Thompson is aware of, namely, that any such “naïve” form of naturalism, in which reflection is—necessarily and only—guided by the facts of human first nature, might understandably be thought to imply an “alarming and idiotic moral conservatism” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 702). This idiocy would present us with practical syllogisms of the form: “Men dance, dancing is something that belongs to human nature, dancing is what is natural to them—<i>so</i> I'll dance too.” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 705). Obviously, this is also the sort of picture of (natural) reflection that McDowell is looking to avoid, one on which the “free play of reason” is made the slave of whatever, in nature, already exists. So, what resources might Thompson's naïve Aristotelianism be able to access to avoid it?<sup>15</sup></p><p>Thompson's solution here turns on a distinction which Aristotle makes, but which Thompson accuses McDowell of missing, between two modes of knowledge: <i>sophia</i> and <i>phronesis</i>. <i>Sophia</i> for Aristotle is “like the straight and the white, everywhere the same” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 710). It is the mode of knowledge appropriate for things like “the constituents of the heavens” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 711). By contrast, <i>phronesis</i>—‘“practical wisdom”—is “like healthy and good—different for man and fish” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 710).</p><p>To make sense of the object of <i>phronesis</i>, Thompson turns to the work of G.E.M. Anscombe. In her <i>Intention</i>, Anscombe draws a distinction between practical and observational knowledge (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 713). Observational knowledge involves a relation to some object independent of the observer. It is, essentially, “scientific” knowledge: to know something observationally would be to know it as it would appear “objectively”, from nowhere.</p><p>Practical knowledge, by contrast, is known “from the inside” of some practice that the knower is engaged in—it is thus in some sense “productive of the thing known” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 714).<sup>16</sup> We have already seen how, for Marx, we “produce” the things we need in order to survive. Here our activity manifests itself as an object—thus as something potentially alien to us. What Anscombe means by “production” is related to this, but by no means the same.</p><p>One example would be something like the knowledge of how to play a sport. Granted, when a sport is codified, one can write down the rules and someone could study them, without ever playing it. One could even become an expert on the sport, purely as a spectator or a journalist. All of this would count as “observational” knowledge of, say, football. But one would not know <i>how</i> to play it, unless one actually played a match. The practical knowledge of how to play football, for instance, is something both realized and sustained by the players, as they play the game themselves. Certain aspects of it might be explicable in the abstract, for example, where the players are supposed to be positioned. But others —like knowing when or how to shoot, how to psych the keeper out in the split-second where he has to decide which way to go when taking a penalty—can only be known in the flow of the moment from within. Armchair observers might believe themselves to have a great deal of expertise, but that does not mean they could manage the England side.</p><p>Another example would, according to Thompson at least, be “human”. For Thompson, “human” is something that we (human beings) manifest over the course of our lives—just as, I have claimed, footballers manifest the knowledge of how to play football in their playing it. “Human” is thus, Thompson claims, an (Anscombian) practical concept.</p><p>It is in this way that he is able to avoid the charge of conservatism. Of course, we are free to reflect on our species-life: reflection is just one of the things human beings do. Given that “human” is a practical concept, we <i>manifest</i> our species-life as we reflect on what we ought, or ought not, to do. But we do not do this by relating human beings to the sphere of “pure rationality”—this would only be possible if <i>phronesis</i> were like <i>sophia</i>, the same anywhere in the universe, at any particular historical moment. Practical reflection is, for human beings, both immanent and internal. In ethical reflection, we only have human things to go by: living, material, human needs, and concerns.</p><p>It is with this in mind that Thompson relates his criticisms of McDowell to the early Marx. McDowell, as we have seen, turns to Marx to guard against the possibility that the self-conscious subject is somehow an <i>over-rational</i>, disinterested observer in relation to their world. For Thompson, however, McDowell's invocation of Marx is inopportune—as by implication, all it shows is that McDowell has not realized that the Marx of “Alienated Labour” is in fact a powerful <i>critic</i> of McDowell's Kant-inflected understanding of the intersection of reason and nature.</p><p>The key concept that Thompson is interested in is that of “species-being”—alienation from “species-being” being one of the “four moments” of alienation that Marx discusses in his essay. Thompson defines this thing—species-being—as “the registering of the (first natural) universal one comes under… a condition of all universal representation… a condition of having concepts.” On this Marxist view, then “‘Human’ is, for each of us, the original universal.” (Thompson, <span>2013</span>, p. 728).</p><p>This point does not necessarily come across all that strongly in “Alienated Labour” itself, where Marx defines “species-being” only very vaguely (Marx, <span>2000a</span>, p. 89; 90). It does however shine forth a lot more clearly when we consider the work of Ludwig Feuerbach—the thinker whose jargon Marx was, back then, largely still employing.</p><p>In <i>The Essence of Christianity</i>, Feuerbach tells us that “the essential difference between man and the animal” is “consciousness” (Feuerbach, <span>2012</span>, p. 97). But he does not mean “consciousness in the sense of the feeling of the self, in the sense of the ability to distinguish one sensuous object from another, to perceive—even judge,” since this sort of consciousness, he takes it, obviously cannot be denied of every animal (ibid.).</p><p>As soon as one sees the “human” as a practical rather than a theoretical concept, then we must ground self-conscious subjectivity in species-being. This, then, is what Thompson believes—and also what he thinks Marx believed, and what he thinks McDowell <i>should</i> believe—distinguishes human from animal life: the fact that we are able to relate to ourselves <i>as a species</i>.</p><p>Thus, we have seen, so far, how McDowell and Thompson invoke Marx in the context of a discussion of what distinguishes us from other animals in two different ways. McDowell uses Marx to help vindicate his citing of “self-conscious subjectivity” as what distinguishes human life (our ability to relate to ourselves). Thompson, however, uses Marx to, more comprehensively, naturalize McDowell's liberal naturalism, by arguing that self-conscious subjectivity is grounded in species-being (our ability to relate to ourselves as a species). I will now bring this controversy between McDowell and Thompson, back around to Midgley.</p><p>At first glance, this point might seem fair enough. If by “producing” is meant “the processing of materials, rather than simply gathering them,” then—as Midgley states—“bees, beavers, and termites do at least as well as the simple hunting-and-gathering human tribes.” “Which shows,” as she then states, “that you have to consider <i>which</i> animals you are distinguishing yourself from” (ibid.). “Producing” cannot do enough work to separate us from the animals.</p><p>But this, Midgley goes on to explain, is not the only understanding of what “producing” means that Marx might have had in mind. He could also, she says, have meant the “free and deliberate planning of what one does, whether it be gathering, processing, or anything else” (ibid.). The problem here, however, is that while this way of understanding “producing” as the single factor which distinguishes human from animal life does indeed seem to put man “in a special position,” “but then he is so for everything he does, not just for production” (ibid.). In short, the problem with this reading, is that it seems to turn “producing” into something like McDowell's free “self-conscious subjectivity”. Perhaps this is a better distinguishing factor (although, of course, Thompson would disagree), but it is not the one that Marx appears to cite in <i>The German Ideology</i>.</p><p>Midgley then precisely discovers this criterion of “self-conscious subjectivity” in “Alienated Labour”, and likewise moves to dismiss it. Here, she claims, the “main emphasis” is not on production, but rather on “free conscious choice.” “This,” she comments, “is something found over a much wider range of activity than mere production, and certainly is a human structural characteristic, though by no means our only one… Man is, indeed, essentially rational for Marx but his reason is actualized in productive activity.’” (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, pp. 199–200).</p><p>Midgley thus seems to be reading Marx as McDowell does—it's just that she doesn't think the resulting position <i>works</i>. For Midgley, Marx's whole approach is misguided because he insists, perversely, on holding SDF. “If another species were… found which did just what Marx meant by producing, it would not damage his argument about the structure of human life at all” (Midgley, <span>2002</span>, p. 200).</p><p>We can thus reconstruct Midgley's argument as follows. Marx and McDowell both attempt to cite “self-conscious subjectivity’” as an SDF. This cannot work—the story has to be at least somewhat more ambiguous and complicated than that.</p><p>Midgley, then, might seem at this point like she would (or should) be in agreement with Thompson. Implicitly, at any rate, her understanding of how human life is related to the rest of nature might be thought to commit her to an Aristotelianism that Thompson would recognize as being laudably “naïve.”<sup>18</sup> Thompson, likewise, still thinks that human beings are distinguished, at least in part, by our ability to operate “free conscious choice.” But this capacity does not, as such, cleave off a wholesale distinction between us and other animals—since it is, for Thompson, a first-natural thing that we do; inherently limited by the fact that we manifest our species-nature through it. “Man” is the original universal and thus it not only liberates, but also limits us.</p><p>But on consideration of Thompson's reading of Marx, it seems clear that any tentative alliance between himself and Midgley, against McDowell, would be unsustainable. Thompson, with Marx, thinks what distinguishes human life is our ability to relate to ourselves as a species: that we have what he calls “species-being.” Midgley, however, as per the quotes given above, only seems able to read Marx's early “species-talk” as asserting the existence of some sort of simple, universal human essence.</p><p>Interestingly, this is an aspect of Marx's early thought that he is usually thought (if not by Thompson) to have rejected. In “Theses on Feuerbach” VI, Marx writes that Feuerbach ‘‘resolves the religious essence into the human essence. “But,” he says, “the human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations” (Marx, <span>2000c</span>, p. 172).</p><p>Feuerbach is thus, Marx claims, “compelled… to abstract from the historical process and to fix the religious sentiment as something by itself and to presuppose an abstract—isolated—human individual” (ibid.). For this reason, “essence”, in Feuerbach, “can be comprehended only as ‘genus’ [<i>Gattung</i>], as an internal, dumb generality which naturally unites the many individuals” (ibid.).</p><p>Marx, then, might have been an SDF theorist in 1844, when he wrote “Alienated Labour.” But by April 1845, when he wrote the “Theses”, he was not. It is therefore <i>prima facie</i> rather odd that Midgley started her dismissal of Marx's understanding of what distinguishes human life with a quote from <i>The German Ideology</i>—which was written around a year after the “Theses”. Did Marx simply regress (rather quickly) from the high point of the “Theses”? Or is there something deeper going on here?</p><p>As we saw at the start of Section 4 above, Midgley quotes this line from the “Feuerbach” chapter of <i>The German Ideology</i> as evidence for the charge that Marx is an SDF theorist—one who believes that humans are distinguished from the animals by “production” (whatever exactly that means). And certainly, when these are the only words from this passage that one cites, it can seem like this reading of Marx is both natural and fair.</p><p>Initially, then, what seems important to grasp is that, while Marx and Engels are talking in this passage about how human and animal life are distinguished from each other, “production” only enters the scene <i>after</i> the “physical organisation” of human individuals has in some sense been “established.” The distinguishing of human life through “production”, then, is very much a process that is supposed to be contiguous with the rest of nature (both human and otherwise).</p><p>Thus whereas—we must suppose—sharks and squirrels, bees and bugs, and so on and so forth, are able to obtain the things they need in order to survive <i>without</i> inadvertently producing new needs for themselves, we human beings are not so lucky.</p><p>We learn to plant seeds to have enough crops to feed ourselves; then we produce the need for land. We divide up the land among our community to ensure that everyone will have enough to plant on; then some of the land turns out to be bad, and we need more, but it belongs to our neighbors and now we need to go to war. So, we need swords, shields, walls, catapults, barrels full of boiling tar, tanks, and bombs, and the UN, and who knows what else.</p><p>If there is indeed a certain sort of practical rationality in operation here—through this grand historical process, after all, we produce pretty much everything we “know”—then it is an <i>alienated</i> one: we have no transparent insight into our products. These things—not least, our <i>needs</i>—loom horribly above us, urging us ever onward, to do evermore stupid and destructive things, just to satisfy our material wants.</p><p>This ever-expanding, evermore complex network of needs, the satisfaction of which produces other new needs, informs the story that Marx and Engels then give of the development of the family and then of society (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, pp. 182–183). Crucially, Marx and Engels claim that it is only with these developments that “consciousness”—that is, what we have been calling “self-conscious subjectivity” enters the scene (ibid.). Even then, consciousness of this sort never appears in a completely “pure” form. Thought, after all, is for Marx and Engels determined by life (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 181).</p><p>It may well be, of course, that Marx continues to affirm some notion of “species-being”. But if he does, then our “species-being” could not be an <i>abstract</i> universal. If in “Alienated Labour”, production was a function of our species, now our species-essence is a function of production.</p><p>And this means that Man is, at least to a certain extent, malleable. It is in <i>The German Ideology</i> that we get what looks like<sup>20</sup> Marx's most comprehensive account of how history is supposed somehow to culminate in the establishment of some sort of universal communist state (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 187). But this is a teleology that in no sense assumes the existence of some sort of pre-established human essence (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 190). Rather, the establishing of communism must be seen to involve a qualitative transformation: “the alteration of men on a mass scale” (Marx, <span>2000d</span>, p. 195). Under communism, we will be able to produce just as we have been prevented from producing up until now, in the way that “lower” animals do, that is without inadvertently producing new needs. It is, in fact, at this point and only at this point that freedom and activity will, for Marx, genuinely coincide.</p><p>Thus, no longer will our activity stand as “an objective power above us, growing out of our control” (ibid.)—it will be something we can exercise with all the grace and pleasure that so-called lower animals seem to take in their own movements. And so, at the end of this process, we will have ceased to be the unhappy “rational animals” that we are now: these strange creatures who find themselves subject to all these conflicting compulsions and are yet aware, somehow, that they should not be. The history of our species will culminate, with our finally having transcended our own nature.<sup>21</sup></p><p>It is here, at the end of this unfortunately rather knotty, winding road, that I have arrived at a position where I am able to spell out the positive point of this paper. Call the position that results from this discussion of Marx (and Engels, Midgley, Thompson, and McDowell) a “Dialectical Aristotelianism”. According to Dialectical Aristotelianism, “Human” is the type of unity that can <i>never</i> exist comfortably in the world, in the way that other animals, in their natural habitats, might seem to. “Human” is the type of species-unity that necessarily <i>lacks</i> a habitat, that has been doomed to evolve constantly and vertiginously: ever upwards, perhaps, but hardly in a way that “makes us better” in any independent sense.<sup>22</sup> Until the revolution comes, of course, and the proletariat rise up, and “the riddle of history” is solved. Perhaps this would be the realization of our nature; on the other hand perhaps it would represent our transformation into a different sort of unity. As of now, the Dialectical Aristotelian can be happy to remain agnostic on this score.</p><p>It is my view that Dialectical Aristotelianism can provide us with a robust, <i>anti-essentialist</i> account of what separates human beings from other animals—an account of our species' distinctiveness, that nevertheless satisfies the various constraints that Midgley would want to put on any such account: no oversimplification; no biologically provincial moral elevation; no cleaving off of “rational” humanity from the rest of nature.</p><p>This is something that other, competing accounts are unable to do. While Dialectical Aristotelianism might still point to something analogous “species-being,” it posits our species-essence as something <i>historical</i>. What it points to is thus not a <i>simple</i>, essential factor—as it is not something that all human animals are supposed to share in the same way over time. The ‘distinguishing factor’ here is one that can change, be transformed, go wrong; if we believe Marx, it can even be overthrown entirely.<sup>23</sup></p><p>As yet, of course, there is more work to be done here—this paper only sketches ‘Dialectical Aristotelianism’ as a position and gives us some reason to believe that Marx and Engels, at least at one stage, held it. <i>Why</i> does humanity produce in the way that it does? To what extent is this account of human nature necessarily bound up with Marx and Engels's political aims? And how does it relate to other accounts of human nature that have recently been proposed in the literature (not least the authors listed in footnote 5 above)? All these must remain, for now, open questions. Consider this the seed of a research project.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-08-24\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12712\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12712\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12712","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

我注意到,在英语哲学中,有一种援引马克思的方式。鉴于在(激进)政治理论之外与马克思的实质性接触相对匮乏,这里的模式相当松散,这是可以理解的。但我在约翰-麦克道尔(John McDowell)、迈克尔-汤普森(Michael Thompson)和玛丽-米德利(Mary Midgley)的著作中发现了这种模式。在这些思想家中,马克思都是在探究人性的背景下被引用的:探究我们与动物之间的区别(如果有的话)。在本文中,我提议对这三位思想家之间的某场辩论进行裁决--他们对马克思的共同引用让我们得以上演这场辩论。我将论证,麦克道尔、汤普森和米德利之间的这场争论注定是无休止的,除非我们厘清三人共同对马克思的困惑。厘清这一困惑将使我们能够聚焦于我称之为 "辩证亚里士多德主义 "的人性论。我无法在此为这一立场提供详细的辩护--相反,我将其作为一种可能在其他著作中得到更全面阐述的东西1。1 我想在这里阐述的观点以及阐述的方式,不幸的是,需要一个乍看之下可能有点晦涩难懂的结构。具体来说:在第 1 节中,我介绍了 "是什么将我们与动物区分开来 "这一长期存在的哲学问题--我的研究方向是米奇雷在《野兽与人》一书中对 "单一区分因素 "概念的批判,即人类与其他动物的区别所在。第 2 节和第 3 节讲述了麦克道尔和汤普森之间现有的一场辩论,他们都将马克思纳入了寻找这种单一区分因素的尝试中。在第 4 节中,我将介绍米德格利对她所认为的马克思试图找出 "单一区分因素 "来回答 "我们与动物的区别 "这一问题的具体批评--这些批评似乎也适用于麦克道尔和汤普森。在第 5 节中,我将解释为什么(在我看来)米德莱对马克思的看法是错误的--然后继续证明,在《德意志意识形态》中,马克思和恩格斯(尽管是在一个不完整的、争议越来越多的文本中)可以被解读为为我们提供了一个 "单一区分因素 "的答案,来回答我们与动物的区别是什么,而这个答案并不存在米德莱所指出的(通常的)试图找出这样一个因素的问题。其结果是,我们能够轻松地将米德利、麦克道尔和汤普森的观点集大成。作为人类,我们对自己作为一个物种有某种概念,不仅如此,我们还认为自己是一个与众不同的物种,在某种程度上有别于其他所有动物。亚里士多德认为,人类作为有理性的动物,在某种重要意义上 "介于兽与神之间"。2 我们拥有动物生命,能够在大城市生活、建造大教堂、创作《辛普森一家》2-8 季等。随着时间的推移,我们发明了农业、工业和互联网。我们现在知道,我们的经济活动能够让地球上的其他生物无法生存;我们的武器可以在几秒钟内摧毁地球上的所有生命,只要我们在正确的时间引爆它们。其他动物在各方面都令人印象深刻--聪明、美丽、可怕。然而,几乎无一例外的是,每当哲学家们试图阐明这种差异的根源,解释人类生命与动物生命之间的区别时,他们最终都会说出一些听起来基本上相当愚蠢的话。柏拉图有一天在学院里演讲,被要求给 "人 "下一个定义,他把人定义为 "没有羽毛的动物"。他把人定义为 "没有羽毛的两足动物",结果犬儒学派的第欧根尼(Diogenes the Cynic)拿出了一只拔了毛的鸡。因此,笛卡尔认为人类生命的区别在于我们能够以新颖和自发的方式使用语言,但却无法将 "低等 "动物与令人信服的自动机区分开来(Descartes, 1968, p. 72ff)。因此,康德认为我们的区别在于我们的理性能力--我们是一种具有 "理性本质 "的生物,能够作为 "目的本身 "而存在(Kant, 1997, p.37)--但却无法真正将人类与理性的火星人区分开来(Thompson, 2013, p.701)。因此,我们应该只问人与动物的区别,而不是问我们与其他动物的区别(同上)。 根据天真的亚里士多德主义,人类 "在某种程度上与'挪威鼠'和'海岸红杉'等词平起平坐"。对于我们人类这种生物来说,伦理反思是一种可能性。但这种反思并不是与我们之外的任何其他永恒不变的东西--某种理性的天堂--相关联的,任何足够理性的生物都会出现同样的反思。相反,它只是人类生命形式的另一种功能。换一种说法:为了使我们自己作为理性动物变得有意义,对汤普森来说,我们并不需要假定某种 "第二自然 "的补充领域,让我们 "睁开眼睛 "看理性的要求。相反,理性的要求对我们来说只是第一自然的要求。当然,这里有一个显而易见的问题,汤普森也意识到了这个问题,即任何这种 "天真 "形式的自然主义,即反思必然且唯一受人类第一性事实的指导,可能会被认为意味着一种 "令人震惊的、愚蠢的道德保守主义"(汤普森,2013 年,第 702 页),这是可以理解的。这种愚蠢会给我们带来如下形式的实用论证:"男人会跳舞,跳舞是属于人类本性的东西,跳舞是他们的天性,所以我也会跳舞"。(汤普森,2013 年,第 705 页)。显然,这也是麦克道尔想要避免的那种(自然)反思的图景,在这种图景上,"理性的自由发挥 "成了自然界中已经存在的任何东西的奴隶。那么,汤普森的天真亚里士多德主义可以利用哪些资源来避免这种情况呢?15 汤普森的解决方案在此转向亚里士多德所做的区分,但汤普森却指责麦克道尔忽略了这一点,即两种知识模式之间的区分:索菲亚和phronesis。对亚里士多德而言,索非亚 "就像直的和白的,到处都一样"(Thompson, 2013, p.710)。它是一种适合于 "天的成分 "等事物的知识模式(Thompson,2013 年,第 711 页)。相比之下,phronesis--"实践智慧"--"就像健康和良好--对人和鱼来说是不同的"(Thompson, 2013, p.710)。为了理解phronesis的对象,Thompson转向了G.E.M. Anscombe的著作。安斯科姆在她的《意向》中区分了实践知识和观察知识(Thompson, 2013, p.713)。观察性知识涉及与观察者无关的某个对象的关系。本质上,它是 "科学 "知识:观察性知识是 "客观 "地、无中生有地认识某物。与此相反,实践性知识是 "从 "认识者所参与的某种实践的 "内部 "认识的--因此,在某种意义上,它是 "对被认识事物的生产"(Thompson, 2013, p.714)16 。我们已经看到,在马克思看来,我们是如何 "生产 "我们生存所需的事物的。在这里,我们的活动表现为一种客体,因此是一种可能与我们格格不入的东西。安斯科姆所说的 "生产 "与此相关,但绝不相同。当然,当一项运动被编成法典时,人们可以把规则写下来,有人可以研究这些规则,而不需要进行比赛。一个人甚至可以纯粹以观众或记者的身份成为这项运动的专家。所有这些都可以算作对足球的 "观察 "知识。但是,除非真正踢过一场比赛,否则就不会知道如何踢球。例如,关于如何踢足球的实践知识,是球员们在自己踢球的过程中实现和保持的。其中某些方面可能是抽象的,例如球员应该在什么位置。但其他方面,比如知道何时或如何射门,如何在守门员判罚点球时的一刹那让他做出心理准备,则只有在比赛过程中才能了解。旁观者可能会认为自己拥有丰富的专业知识,但这并不意味着他们可以管理英格兰队。在汤普森看来,"人 "是我们(人类)在生活中表现出来的东西--正如我所说的,足球运动员在踢球时表现出如何踢球的知识。因此,汤普森声称,"人 "是一个(安斯康比的)实践概念。正是通过这种方式,他得以避免保守主义的指控。当然,我们可以自由地反思我们的物种生活:反思只是人类要做的事情之一。鉴于 "人 "是一个实际的概念,我们在反思我们应该做什么或不应该做什么时,就会表现出我们的物种生活。但是,我们并不是通过将人类与 "纯粹理性 "的领域联系起来来实现这一点的--只有当phronesis像sophia一样,在宇宙的任何地方,在任何特定的历史时刻都是一样的时候,这才是可能的。对人类而言,实践反思既是内在的,也是内在的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Dialectical Aristotelianism: On Marx's account of what separates us from the animals

I have noticed, in Anglophone philosophy, a certain way of invoking Marx. The pattern here is—understandably, given the relative scarcity of substantial engagement with Marx outside of (radical) political theory—a rather loose one. But I've spotted it in the work of John McDowell, Michael Thompson, and Mary Midgley. In each of these thinkers, Marx is invoked in the context of an inquiry into human nature: into the question of what (if anything) separates us from the animals.

In this paper, I propose to adjudicate a certain debate between these three thinkers—a debate which their shared invocation of Marx allows us to stage. I will argue that this debate between McDowell, Thompson, and Midgley, such as it is, is doomed to remain interminable, unless we clear up a confusion about Marx which all three share. Clearing up this confusion will allow us to get in focus an account of human nature I label “Dialectical Aristotelianism”. I am unable to offer a detailed defense of this position here—rather, I offer it as something which might be worked out more comprehensively in other work.1

The point I wish to make here, and the way I wish to make it, unfortunately demands a structure which might at first glance seem a little obscure. To spell it out: in Section 1, I introduce the perennial philosophical problem of “what separates us from the animals”—working my way toward Midgley's critique of the “single distinguishing factor” conception of what separates human beings from other animals in Beast and Man. Sections 2 and 3 relate an existing debate between McDowell and Thompson, who both incorporate Marx into their attempts to find such a single distinguishing factor. In Section 4, I introduce Midgley's specific criticisms of what she sees as Marx's attempt to identify a “single distinguishing factor” answer to the question of what separates us from the animals—criticisms which would seem to do for McDowell and Thompson as well. In Section 5, I explain why (in my view) Midgley was wrong about Marx—and then proceed to demonstrate that, in The German Ideology, he and Engels (albeit in an incomplete, increasingly disputed text) can be read as providing us with a “single distinguishing factor” answer to the question of what separates us from the animals that does not suffer from the problems Midgley identifies with (usual) attempts to identify such a factor. The result is an account which is, handily, able to incorporate the best of Midgley's, McDowell's, and Thompson's views. This is the position that, in the conclusion, I label “Dialectical Aristotelianism”.

As human beings, we have some notion of ourselves as a species, and not only that, we have a sense of ourselves as a different kind of species, distinct somehow from all other animals. This sense of difference is perhaps best articulated as the Aristotelian notion that humans, as rational animals, are in some important sense “between beast and god”.2

We bear the kind of animal life which is capable of doing things like living in great cities, building cathedrals, and of writing The Simpsons seasons 2–8. Over time, we have invented agriculture, industrialism, and the internet. Our economic activity is capable, we now know, of making the rest of planet unlivable; our weapons could destroy all life on earth in a few seconds, if we cued them up to detonate at the right time. Other animals are impressive—brilliant and beautiful and terrible—in all sorts of ways. But not, you know, like us.

And yet, almost invariably, whenever philosophers have attempted to articulate the source of this difference, to give an account of what precisely the distinction between human and animal life consists in, they have ended up saying things that can sound basically rather silly. The danger here is perhaps best expressed in that story about Plato—presumably apocryphal, although based on a remark from the Statesman (266e)—where he was lecturing one day in the academy, and asked to provide a definition of “man”. He defined man as a “featherless biped”—only for Diogenes the Cynic to pull out a plucked chicken.

Thus Descartes identified human life as being distinguished by our ability to use language in novel and spontaneous ways—only to leave us with no way of distinguishing “lower” animals from convincing automata (Descartes, 1968, p. 72ff). Thus Kant identified us as being distinguished by our faculty of reason—as being a creature that has a “rational nature” capable of existing as “an end in itself” (Kant, 1997, p. 37)—only to be left with no real way of distinguishing human beings from rational Martians (Thompson, 2013, p. 701).3

First, Midgley notes, for all that humans really “do things differently” from other animals, we are all too inclined to be forgetful of the fact that the form of life we bear is (at least) also an animal one. We should therefore limit ourselves to only asking what distinguishes man among the animals, not what separates us from other animals entirely (ibid.).

Second, Midgley states: “as the question is usually put, it asks for a single, simple, final distinction, and for one that confers praise” (ibid.). But we have no real way of backing up our commonplace assumption that the human form of life is an especially good one. No other animal, Midgley notes, is as aggressive toward their own kind (Midgley, 2002, p. 27); no other animal is as wantonly cruel to, and exploitative of, other species (Midgley, 2002, p. 30).

Midgley thus recommends a deflationary, therapeutic approach, emphasizing humanity's continuity with the rest of nature. Rather than attempt to develop a robust and philosophical account of what single thing ultimately, finally distinguishes human life, we should look instead for a “knot of general structural properties,” which might include things like language, rationality, and culture—all of which, Midgley specifies, are contiguous with, not distinct from, “nature” more broadly understood (Midgley, 2002, p. 309).

Sound advice, perhaps. But it is not as if every single philosopher since Midgley has taken it to heart. Even if ideas in general really could be demolished by a single, somewhat well-known thinker calling them convincingly into question: the heritage of the “single distinguishing factor” conception of human life is vast; its temptations, for all the problems with it that Midgley diagnoses, are in many ways wired into our understanding of ourselves. As Midgley herself notes, the linguistic construction I am exploiting in this paper, “that's what distinguishes us from the animals” is an almost everyday one (Midgley, 2002, p. 35).

It should hardly be surprising, then, that we continue to find advocates of some form of “single distinguishing factor” (henceforth, SDF) view. Arguably, Midgley has only shown that we must abandon SDF. To paraphrase John McDowell in the Introduction to Mind and World, she has not (yet) shown that we can.4

McDowell, as it happens, is among the more sophisticated contemporary exponents of SDF.5 It is his attempt to articulate a sophisticated version of SDF, which motivates his appropriation of Marx. Reporting McDowell's appropriation of Marx will be the first contribution to the “debate” that I wish to stage in this paper.

If we can ascribe subjective experiences to ourselves, then we can become aware of the world—which is thus able to operate as a rational constraint on our thought.6 This power, McDowell claims, is identical to “spontaneity of the understanding” and thus also to “the power of conceptual thinking” (ibid.). Self-conscious subjectivity, then, separates us from the animals by making reason and language possible.

McDowell thus clearly holds a version of SDF. What makes him a more sophisticated exponent of such a view, as I have claimed, is that he appears to have identified—and moved to mitigate—certain problems with it.

The first of these problems consists in what we might call a Descartes-type worry.7 As McDowell points out, if we require self-conscious subjectivity to experience the world, but other animals lack it, then surely it follows that nonhuman animals have no external experience at all? “And that can seem to commit me to the Cartesian idea that brutes are automata” (McDowell, 1996, p. 114). “Mere animals cannot enjoy ‘outer experience’,” McDowell tells us, “on the conception of ‘outer experience’ I have recommended.” And yet, “it is a plain fact that we share perception with mere animals” (ibid.).

In order to short-circuit the Descartes-type worry, McDowell borrows the distinction between “world” and “environment” from Hans-Georg Gadamer. For Gadamer too, language distinguishes human beings from other animals—and this is identical to the fact that we exist in a “world,” which we can have a “free orientation” toward (Gadamer, 2004, pp. 440–441).

The “environment”, by contrast, is something which “all living beings… possess” (ibid.), a “milieu” of problems and opportunities, which—unlike the “world”—one is not as such freely oriented toward (ibid.). “World” means thought, thus freedom; “environment” means instinct, thus its opposite.

When it comes to perception, mere animals might well be oriented toward the exact same object as us world-havers—but subjectively speaking, their orientation could not be more different. In the absence of self-conscious subjectivity, what sentience animals do have is “in the service of a mode of life that is structured exclusively by immediate biological imperatives… the animal's behaviour at a given moment is an immediate outcome of biological forces” (McDowell, 1996, p. 115). Gadamer, thus, allows us to affirm McDowell's account of what separates us from the animals without succumbing to the Descartes-type worry.

But there remains a further problem with McDowell's view. This we might express as consisting in a Kant-type worry. McDowell's notion of “self-conscious subjectivity” is lifted almost verbatim from Kant: as the “spontaneity of understanding”, which is identical with “the power of conceptual thinking,” McDowell's “self-conscious subjectivity” is essentially what Kant named, in the Transcendental Deduction, as “the original synthetic unity of apperception.”8

But, as McDowell himself notes, Kant “lacks a pregnant notion of second nature” (McDowell, 1996, p. 110).9 This amounts to the accusation that Kant, by conceiving of “nature” only in the law-like terms of mechanistic natural science, was unable to think “nature” and “reason” together. This means that self-conscious subjectivity as Kant defines it—the original synthetic unity of apperception—“could not be something substantially present in the world; it is at best a point of view” (McDowell, 1996, p. 111).

The invocation of Gadamer's distinction between world and environment has, McDowell thinks, resolved what I have called the “Descartes-type worry”. But it has not yet done enough against the Kant-type worry. Our “world” after all, in being the sort of thing we are able to assume a “free and distanced” orientation toward, might not be quite enough of an “environment”—might, one supposes, be the sort of thing we are only disinterestedly oriented within. In short, we would be oriented toward our world not as “human animals”, but as something rather closer to gods. “Self-conscious subjectivity” cannot account for our animal nature satisfactorily, because it does not have enough to do with the “animal” world.10

To read Marx, McDowell seems to be telling us, is to understand that self-conscious human subjects cannot be mere, disinterested, Kantian transcendental points of view. This is because our form of life requires us to live off and “make over” nature—“the sensuous exterior world.” Nevertheless, with that necessity can come freedom. It is in our productive relationship to the world that we live off, that our freedom is expressed.

It is worth mentioning that McDowell's reading of Marx is at least somewhat restricted. While in Marx, alienation has four moments,11 for McDowell alienation appears to consist fundamentally in the rendering for the worker of the Gadamerian “world” into a mere “environment”. It is this point that unites all four moments of alienated labor: an “alienated” existence would be an unfree one, because the worker would find their lives governed by a necessity that is, in McDowell's understanding, baldly natural.

An “unalienated” existence, by contrast, would not, McDowell thinks, be an “easy” one, but would rather be “distinctively free.” We would still need to produce things from nature in order to survive, but we would do so in such a way that our humanity was affirmed—realising our humanity in the act of making.12 McDowell notes, for instance, that Marx tells us in “Alienated Labour” that “man is unique in producing ‘according to the laws of beauty’.” (McDowell, 1996, p. 119).

It is this sort of thing—an awareness of the “laws of beauty” and suchlike—that McDowell thinks indicates that we are a creature defined by our “self-conscious subjectivity”: the single distinguishing capacity which allows us, from our position within nature, to resonate with whatever it is that reason, free in some sense from nature's law, happens to demand. Free, seemingly, of both the Descartes-type and Kant-type worries, McDowell is able to cite “self-conscious subjectivity” as what distinguishes us from the animals, quite regardless of any Midgleyan critique.

McDowell's account of human nature, however, has been directly criticized by Michael Thompson. Thompson's critique essentially consists in the claim that McDowell fails to do enough work to avoid the Kant-type worry—in part because he has not really understood the early Marx.

This critique is expressed in the text of Thompson's 2013 lecture, “Forms of nature: ‘first’, ‘second’, ‘living’, ‘rational’ and ‘phronetic’.” There, Thompson's overarching concern is to assert the claims of what he calls a “naïve Aristotelianism”, “opposed to the sophisticated naturalism of ‘second nature’ that has been occasionally proposed by John McDowell” (Thompson, 2013, p. 701). Here then, the debate between Thompson and McDowell is very much a direct one. What is important to me here is how Thompson uses Marx in it—for the sake of clarity if not brevity (both in terms of Thompson vs. McDowell, and also in terms of the positive position I will be arriving at by the end of this paper), I will unpack what is at stake in it beforehand.

For McDowell, “first nature” is identified as the object of the natural-scientific intelligibility—in Mind and World, this means it is aligned with the realm of law.13 It is thus perhaps natural to assume that second nature is supposed to align with the realm of law's McDowell-Sellarsian opposite, the normative “space of reasons”—but this is not quite the case.

“Our human second nature,” it is true, “makes us inhabitants of the logical space of reasons” (McDowell, 2008, p. 220). But the idea of second nature in fact “fits any propensities of animals that are not already possessed at birth, and not acquired in merely biological maturation (like, for instance, the propensity to grow facial hair on the part of male human beings), but imparted by education, habituation, or training” (ibid.). Thus, McDowell tells us, “trained dogs have a second nature” (ibid.). But, because trained dogs are not able to think critically about their commands as we can, they are not therefore inhabitants of the space of reasons.

From this then, for McDowell, it seems, reason is not substantially part of nature—the two realms turn no particular gears with each other. As rational animals our second nature—appropriately formed—gives us access to the space of reasons. But the space of reasons itself does not, as such, have anything in particular to do with nature: “the dictates of reason are there anyway, whether or not one's eyes are opened to them” (McDowell, 1996, p. 91).

McDowell, naturally, does not think this is a problem, in fact, he thinks it is the only way we're going to be able to make sense of the distinctive relationship between reason and nature at all. In his essay, “Two Sorts of Naturalism”, an important supplement to Mind and World, McDowell gives the example of a pack of wolves who suddenly and collectively acquire reason (McDowell, 1998, p. 169). What, McDowell asks, can the wolves now do, that they could not before? Each wolf, McDowell answers, now has the ability to “step back” from their natural impulses and assume a “critical stance” toward them. To anything a wolf might instinctively do (hunt in packs, for instance), the wolf can now ask: “Why should I do this?” (McDowell, 1998, p. 171).

As McDowell notes, this example shows up the “deep connection between reason and freedom” (McDowell, 1998, p. 170). Wolfish nature—from which individual wolves might derive, for instance, the need to eat meat—continues to present each wolf with various demands, problems, and opportunities. But we could not make sense of the wolves actually being rational if they were not free to let their minds range over pretty much every possibility, hypothetical or concrete, that their world and their imaginations now present them with. The wolves would have to be able to entertain the possibility of being vegetarian, for instance: no matter how their stomachs were constituted.

“This allows,” McDowell tells us, “for radical ethical reflection” (McDowell, 1998, p. 189). The model McDowell invokes for this form of reflection—both in “Two Sorts of Naturalism” and Mind and World—is that of “Neurath's Boat”, “in which a sailor overhauls his ship while it is afloat” (McDowell, 1996, p. 81). In this image, the sailor has complete free reign to overhaul their boat however they may wish to—given the materials they have to hand. The only proviso is that the ship must always remain minimally functional as they do so. In time, of course, Neurath's Boat could become like Theseus's Ship, in which nothing of the original remains.14

First nature, as McDowell specifies, puts “limits on the courses reflection can intelligibly take” (McDowell, 1998, p. 190). But it does not do any more than that: there are not, that is, any reasons on the level of first nature itself. The natural fact that “wolves hunt in packs” is not a reason for rational wolves to hunt in packs. By contrast, the rational consideration that “wolves do best, in obtaining the things they need in order to survive, if they hunt in packs” is.

For Thompson, however, this Neurathian conception of reflection is deeply problematic. According to him, this way of conceiving of the relation between nature and reason is evidence that McDowell—like Kant—thinks that, as “rational animals” we must in effect share the same nature as any hypothetical rational Martians (or wolves). He has not, in short, done enough to overcome the “Kant-type worry”. Any finite rational beings—be they humans or Martians or wolves or whatever—must, for Kant (and so for McDowell) have an understanding structured, as per the results of the Transcendental Deduction, in accordance with the categories, and be subject to the moral law (Thompson, 2013, p. 704).

What this means is that, if we were to identify human nature (as McDowell does) with “self-conscious subjectivity”, we would not really have picked out anything like a specifically human nature at all. Rather, we would have identified human nature with rationality in general—distinct from the animals, but not from, say, rational Martians, angels, or gods.

It is to overcome this vestigial Kantianism—which for him results from McDowell's overly “sophisticated” version of naturalism—that Thompson asserts the claims of his “naïve Aristotelianism”. According to naïve Aristotelianism, human “is in a certain way put on a level with words like ‘Norway rat’ and ‘coastal redwood’.” Ethical reflection is a possibility for the sorts of creatures that we are—human beings. But it is not carried on in relation to anything else immutably beyond us—some heaven of reason, which would show up the same for any sufficiently rational beings. Rather, it is just another function of the human form of life. To put this point in another way: to make sense of ourselves as rational animals we do not, for Thompson, need to posit some supplementary realm of “second nature” which “opens our eyes” to the requirements of reason. Rather, the requirements of reason, for us, are just the first natural ones. So, first nature is all we need.

Of course there is an obvious problem here, one which Thompson is aware of, namely, that any such “naïve” form of naturalism, in which reflection is—necessarily and only—guided by the facts of human first nature, might understandably be thought to imply an “alarming and idiotic moral conservatism” (Thompson, 2013, p. 702). This idiocy would present us with practical syllogisms of the form: “Men dance, dancing is something that belongs to human nature, dancing is what is natural to them—so I'll dance too.” (Thompson, 2013, p. 705). Obviously, this is also the sort of picture of (natural) reflection that McDowell is looking to avoid, one on which the “free play of reason” is made the slave of whatever, in nature, already exists. So, what resources might Thompson's naïve Aristotelianism be able to access to avoid it?15

Thompson's solution here turns on a distinction which Aristotle makes, but which Thompson accuses McDowell of missing, between two modes of knowledge: sophia and phronesis. Sophia for Aristotle is “like the straight and the white, everywhere the same” (Thompson, 2013, p. 710). It is the mode of knowledge appropriate for things like “the constituents of the heavens” (Thompson, 2013, p. 711). By contrast, phronesis—‘“practical wisdom”—is “like healthy and good—different for man and fish” (Thompson, 2013, p. 710).

To make sense of the object of phronesis, Thompson turns to the work of G.E.M. Anscombe. In her Intention, Anscombe draws a distinction between practical and observational knowledge (Thompson, 2013, p. 713). Observational knowledge involves a relation to some object independent of the observer. It is, essentially, “scientific” knowledge: to know something observationally would be to know it as it would appear “objectively”, from nowhere.

Practical knowledge, by contrast, is known “from the inside” of some practice that the knower is engaged in—it is thus in some sense “productive of the thing known” (Thompson, 2013, p. 714).16 We have already seen how, for Marx, we “produce” the things we need in order to survive. Here our activity manifests itself as an object—thus as something potentially alien to us. What Anscombe means by “production” is related to this, but by no means the same.

One example would be something like the knowledge of how to play a sport. Granted, when a sport is codified, one can write down the rules and someone could study them, without ever playing it. One could even become an expert on the sport, purely as a spectator or a journalist. All of this would count as “observational” knowledge of, say, football. But one would not know how to play it, unless one actually played a match. The practical knowledge of how to play football, for instance, is something both realized and sustained by the players, as they play the game themselves. Certain aspects of it might be explicable in the abstract, for example, where the players are supposed to be positioned. But others —like knowing when or how to shoot, how to psych the keeper out in the split-second where he has to decide which way to go when taking a penalty—can only be known in the flow of the moment from within. Armchair observers might believe themselves to have a great deal of expertise, but that does not mean they could manage the England side.

Another example would, according to Thompson at least, be “human”. For Thompson, “human” is something that we (human beings) manifest over the course of our lives—just as, I have claimed, footballers manifest the knowledge of how to play football in their playing it. “Human” is thus, Thompson claims, an (Anscombian) practical concept.

It is in this way that he is able to avoid the charge of conservatism. Of course, we are free to reflect on our species-life: reflection is just one of the things human beings do. Given that “human” is a practical concept, we manifest our species-life as we reflect on what we ought, or ought not, to do. But we do not do this by relating human beings to the sphere of “pure rationality”—this would only be possible if phronesis were like sophia, the same anywhere in the universe, at any particular historical moment. Practical reflection is, for human beings, both immanent and internal. In ethical reflection, we only have human things to go by: living, material, human needs, and concerns.

It is with this in mind that Thompson relates his criticisms of McDowell to the early Marx. McDowell, as we have seen, turns to Marx to guard against the possibility that the self-conscious subject is somehow an over-rational, disinterested observer in relation to their world. For Thompson, however, McDowell's invocation of Marx is inopportune—as by implication, all it shows is that McDowell has not realized that the Marx of “Alienated Labour” is in fact a powerful critic of McDowell's Kant-inflected understanding of the intersection of reason and nature.

The key concept that Thompson is interested in is that of “species-being”—alienation from “species-being” being one of the “four moments” of alienation that Marx discusses in his essay. Thompson defines this thing—species-being—as “the registering of the (first natural) universal one comes under… a condition of all universal representation… a condition of having concepts.” On this Marxist view, then “‘Human’ is, for each of us, the original universal.” (Thompson, 2013, p. 728).

This point does not necessarily come across all that strongly in “Alienated Labour” itself, where Marx defines “species-being” only very vaguely (Marx, 2000a, p. 89; 90). It does however shine forth a lot more clearly when we consider the work of Ludwig Feuerbach—the thinker whose jargon Marx was, back then, largely still employing.

In The Essence of Christianity, Feuerbach tells us that “the essential difference between man and the animal” is “consciousness” (Feuerbach, 2012, p. 97). But he does not mean “consciousness in the sense of the feeling of the self, in the sense of the ability to distinguish one sensuous object from another, to perceive—even judge,” since this sort of consciousness, he takes it, obviously cannot be denied of every animal (ibid.).

As soon as one sees the “human” as a practical rather than a theoretical concept, then we must ground self-conscious subjectivity in species-being. This, then, is what Thompson believes—and also what he thinks Marx believed, and what he thinks McDowell should believe—distinguishes human from animal life: the fact that we are able to relate to ourselves as a species.

Thus, we have seen, so far, how McDowell and Thompson invoke Marx in the context of a discussion of what distinguishes us from other animals in two different ways. McDowell uses Marx to help vindicate his citing of “self-conscious subjectivity” as what distinguishes human life (our ability to relate to ourselves). Thompson, however, uses Marx to, more comprehensively, naturalize McDowell's liberal naturalism, by arguing that self-conscious subjectivity is grounded in species-being (our ability to relate to ourselves as a species). I will now bring this controversy between McDowell and Thompson, back around to Midgley.

At first glance, this point might seem fair enough. If by “producing” is meant “the processing of materials, rather than simply gathering them,” then—as Midgley states—“bees, beavers, and termites do at least as well as the simple hunting-and-gathering human tribes.” “Which shows,” as she then states, “that you have to consider which animals you are distinguishing yourself from” (ibid.). “Producing” cannot do enough work to separate us from the animals.

But this, Midgley goes on to explain, is not the only understanding of what “producing” means that Marx might have had in mind. He could also, she says, have meant the “free and deliberate planning of what one does, whether it be gathering, processing, or anything else” (ibid.). The problem here, however, is that while this way of understanding “producing” as the single factor which distinguishes human from animal life does indeed seem to put man “in a special position,” “but then he is so for everything he does, not just for production” (ibid.). In short, the problem with this reading, is that it seems to turn “producing” into something like McDowell's free “self-conscious subjectivity”. Perhaps this is a better distinguishing factor (although, of course, Thompson would disagree), but it is not the one that Marx appears to cite in The German Ideology.

Midgley then precisely discovers this criterion of “self-conscious subjectivity” in “Alienated Labour”, and likewise moves to dismiss it. Here, she claims, the “main emphasis” is not on production, but rather on “free conscious choice.” “This,” she comments, “is something found over a much wider range of activity than mere production, and certainly is a human structural characteristic, though by no means our only one… Man is, indeed, essentially rational for Marx but his reason is actualized in productive activity.’” (Midgley, 2002, pp. 199–200).

Midgley thus seems to be reading Marx as McDowell does—it's just that she doesn't think the resulting position works. For Midgley, Marx's whole approach is misguided because he insists, perversely, on holding SDF. “If another species were… found which did just what Marx meant by producing, it would not damage his argument about the structure of human life at all” (Midgley, 2002, p. 200).

We can thus reconstruct Midgley's argument as follows. Marx and McDowell both attempt to cite “self-conscious subjectivity’” as an SDF. This cannot work—the story has to be at least somewhat more ambiguous and complicated than that.

Midgley, then, might seem at this point like she would (or should) be in agreement with Thompson. Implicitly, at any rate, her understanding of how human life is related to the rest of nature might be thought to commit her to an Aristotelianism that Thompson would recognize as being laudably “naïve.”18 Thompson, likewise, still thinks that human beings are distinguished, at least in part, by our ability to operate “free conscious choice.” But this capacity does not, as such, cleave off a wholesale distinction between us and other animals—since it is, for Thompson, a first-natural thing that we do; inherently limited by the fact that we manifest our species-nature through it. “Man” is the original universal and thus it not only liberates, but also limits us.

But on consideration of Thompson's reading of Marx, it seems clear that any tentative alliance between himself and Midgley, against McDowell, would be unsustainable. Thompson, with Marx, thinks what distinguishes human life is our ability to relate to ourselves as a species: that we have what he calls “species-being.” Midgley, however, as per the quotes given above, only seems able to read Marx's early “species-talk” as asserting the existence of some sort of simple, universal human essence.

Interestingly, this is an aspect of Marx's early thought that he is usually thought (if not by Thompson) to have rejected. In “Theses on Feuerbach” VI, Marx writes that Feuerbach ‘‘resolves the religious essence into the human essence. “But,” he says, “the human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations” (Marx, 2000c, p. 172).

Feuerbach is thus, Marx claims, “compelled… to abstract from the historical process and to fix the religious sentiment as something by itself and to presuppose an abstract—isolated—human individual” (ibid.). For this reason, “essence”, in Feuerbach, “can be comprehended only as ‘genus’ [Gattung], as an internal, dumb generality which naturally unites the many individuals” (ibid.).

Marx, then, might have been an SDF theorist in 1844, when he wrote “Alienated Labour.” But by April 1845, when he wrote the “Theses”, he was not. It is therefore prima facie rather odd that Midgley started her dismissal of Marx's understanding of what distinguishes human life with a quote from The German Ideology—which was written around a year after the “Theses”. Did Marx simply regress (rather quickly) from the high point of the “Theses”? Or is there something deeper going on here?

As we saw at the start of Section 4 above, Midgley quotes this line from the “Feuerbach” chapter of The German Ideology as evidence for the charge that Marx is an SDF theorist—one who believes that humans are distinguished from the animals by “production” (whatever exactly that means). And certainly, when these are the only words from this passage that one cites, it can seem like this reading of Marx is both natural and fair.

Initially, then, what seems important to grasp is that, while Marx and Engels are talking in this passage about how human and animal life are distinguished from each other, “production” only enters the scene after the “physical organisation” of human individuals has in some sense been “established.” The distinguishing of human life through “production”, then, is very much a process that is supposed to be contiguous with the rest of nature (both human and otherwise).

Thus whereas—we must suppose—sharks and squirrels, bees and bugs, and so on and so forth, are able to obtain the things they need in order to survive without inadvertently producing new needs for themselves, we human beings are not so lucky.

We learn to plant seeds to have enough crops to feed ourselves; then we produce the need for land. We divide up the land among our community to ensure that everyone will have enough to plant on; then some of the land turns out to be bad, and we need more, but it belongs to our neighbors and now we need to go to war. So, we need swords, shields, walls, catapults, barrels full of boiling tar, tanks, and bombs, and the UN, and who knows what else.

If there is indeed a certain sort of practical rationality in operation here—through this grand historical process, after all, we produce pretty much everything we “know”—then it is an alienated one: we have no transparent insight into our products. These things—not least, our needs—loom horribly above us, urging us ever onward, to do evermore stupid and destructive things, just to satisfy our material wants.

This ever-expanding, evermore complex network of needs, the satisfaction of which produces other new needs, informs the story that Marx and Engels then give of the development of the family and then of society (Marx, 2000d, pp. 182–183). Crucially, Marx and Engels claim that it is only with these developments that “consciousness”—that is, what we have been calling “self-conscious subjectivity” enters the scene (ibid.). Even then, consciousness of this sort never appears in a completely “pure” form. Thought, after all, is for Marx and Engels determined by life (Marx, 2000d, p. 181).

It may well be, of course, that Marx continues to affirm some notion of “species-being”. But if he does, then our “species-being” could not be an abstract universal. If in “Alienated Labour”, production was a function of our species, now our species-essence is a function of production.

And this means that Man is, at least to a certain extent, malleable. It is in The German Ideology that we get what looks like20 Marx's most comprehensive account of how history is supposed somehow to culminate in the establishment of some sort of universal communist state (Marx, 2000d, p. 187). But this is a teleology that in no sense assumes the existence of some sort of pre-established human essence (Marx, 2000d, p. 190). Rather, the establishing of communism must be seen to involve a qualitative transformation: “the alteration of men on a mass scale” (Marx, 2000d, p. 195). Under communism, we will be able to produce just as we have been prevented from producing up until now, in the way that “lower” animals do, that is without inadvertently producing new needs. It is, in fact, at this point and only at this point that freedom and activity will, for Marx, genuinely coincide.

Thus, no longer will our activity stand as “an objective power above us, growing out of our control” (ibid.)—it will be something we can exercise with all the grace and pleasure that so-called lower animals seem to take in their own movements. And so, at the end of this process, we will have ceased to be the unhappy “rational animals” that we are now: these strange creatures who find themselves subject to all these conflicting compulsions and are yet aware, somehow, that they should not be. The history of our species will culminate, with our finally having transcended our own nature.21

It is here, at the end of this unfortunately rather knotty, winding road, that I have arrived at a position where I am able to spell out the positive point of this paper. Call the position that results from this discussion of Marx (and Engels, Midgley, Thompson, and McDowell) a “Dialectical Aristotelianism”. According to Dialectical Aristotelianism, “Human” is the type of unity that can never exist comfortably in the world, in the way that other animals, in their natural habitats, might seem to. “Human” is the type of species-unity that necessarily lacks a habitat, that has been doomed to evolve constantly and vertiginously: ever upwards, perhaps, but hardly in a way that “makes us better” in any independent sense.22 Until the revolution comes, of course, and the proletariat rise up, and “the riddle of history” is solved. Perhaps this would be the realization of our nature; on the other hand perhaps it would represent our transformation into a different sort of unity. As of now, the Dialectical Aristotelian can be happy to remain agnostic on this score.

It is my view that Dialectical Aristotelianism can provide us with a robust, anti-essentialist account of what separates human beings from other animals—an account of our species' distinctiveness, that nevertheless satisfies the various constraints that Midgley would want to put on any such account: no oversimplification; no biologically provincial moral elevation; no cleaving off of “rational” humanity from the rest of nature.

This is something that other, competing accounts are unable to do. While Dialectical Aristotelianism might still point to something analogous “species-being,” it posits our species-essence as something historical. What it points to is thus not a simple, essential factor—as it is not something that all human animals are supposed to share in the same way over time. The ‘distinguishing factor’ here is one that can change, be transformed, go wrong; if we believe Marx, it can even be overthrown entirely.23

As yet, of course, there is more work to be done here—this paper only sketches ‘Dialectical Aristotelianism’ as a position and gives us some reason to believe that Marx and Engels, at least at one stage, held it. Why does humanity produce in the way that it does? To what extent is this account of human nature necessarily bound up with Marx and Engels's political aims? And how does it relate to other accounts of human nature that have recently been proposed in the literature (not least the authors listed in footnote 5 above)? All these must remain, for now, open questions. Consider this the seed of a research project.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信