临时公共产品的重要性

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS
Friedemann Bieber
{"title":"临时公共产品的重要性","authors":"Friedemann Bieber","doi":"10.1111/josp.12516","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Public goods have recently received increasing attention by philosophers. In addition to work on the historical origins of the notion of public goods (Desmarais-Tremblay, <span>2017</span>), their relevance to the thinking of particular political theorists (de Jongh, <span>2022</span>) and the justifiability of particular public goods, such as the arts (Kessler, <span>2018</span>), there have been a number of systematic attempts to develop a normative theory of public goods (see e.g., Kallhoff, <span>2011</span>; Miller, <span>2004</span>). Asking which public goods the state ought to provide, and how the benefits and burdens of their provision ought to be distributed, these contributions can roughly be divided into two camps. One group of authors has addressed these questions within political liberalism, remaining committed to the principle of state neutrality. By taking individual preferences as given, they note that many public goods promise net efficiency gains and ask according to what principles these benefits ought to be distributed (see e.g., Claassen, <span>2013</span>; Cullity, <span>2008</span>; Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2001</span>). In so doing, they see themselves as complementing existing theories of justice, which remain mostly silent on the allocation of costs and benefits of public goods (Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, p. 556). Another group of authors has moved beyond the principle of state neutrality, putting forward arguments in favor of the state provision of public goods that are at least in part independent of individual preferences, such as their potential to foster solidarity and to connect people (see e.g., Ferdman, <span>2018</span>; Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>; Kohn, <span>2020</span>). These authors contend that the social value of public goods remains underappreciated, and that the state may be justified in providing them even if doing so does not result in efficiency gains and reject the view that efficiency is the central criterion by which to judge whether the provision of a public good can be justified. This philosophical interest has coincided with a broader sense of neglect of public goods, which has been voiced by journalists and public intellectuals, in particular in Britain and the United States (Irvin, <span>2012</span>; Judt, <span>2010</span>; Lehrer, <span>2020</span>). Yet, despite the recent surge in attention, the philosophical and, more generally, the “scholarly literature on public goods is relatively thin” (Kohn, <span>2020</span>, p. 2).<sup>1</sup></p><p>This article aims to contribute to the philosophical thinking about public goods in three ways. First, highlighting an ambiguity in how the term “public good” is used, Section 2 proposes to distinguish between <i>inherently public goods</i>, which cohere to the economist's definition of a good that is non-rivalrous and non-excludable, and <i>contingently public goods</i>, which are non-rivalrous and, though in principle excludable, provided in a non-exclusionary form. Section 3 then draws on the notion of contingently public goods to develop two novel objections to a variety of benefit principles that have been proposed to govern the allocation of burdens and benefits in the provision of public goods. These principles are generally offered as complements to theories of distributive justice and aim to take care of an alleged blind spot resulting from the possibility of welfare gains from the provision of public good that are not required for initial conditions of justice. In engaging with these principles, the article operates at the level of ideal theory. It argues that because contingently public goods could also have been provided as club goods, the benefit principles, unless further qualified, demand unacceptable transfers to the wealthy as well as to people who object to their inclusive mode of provision. Section 4 then draws on the notion of contingently public goods to explore the potential of public goods in addressing existing social injustices. This section thus operates at the level of nonideal theory. It argues that providing public goods can be an alternative to transfer payments, or a universal basic income, in addressing injustices that are a result of economic inequality and that we have good reason to think that it can, at least at times, be more effective as well as politically more feasible. While this is true of public goods in general, several features set contingently public goods apart: they may at times be provided at little to no cost, their provision may require only more limited market interference (or even none), it can more powerfully express a commitment to status equality, and it may be particularly effective where injustices stem from unequal access to club goods.</p><p>This section argues that there is an important, though frequently overlooked ambiguity in how the term “public good” is used in philosophical discourse. While some authors require a good to be <i>in principle non-excludable</i> in order to qualify, others merely require it to be provided <i>in a non-exclusionary form</i>. While there are benefits to each terminological choice, the section argues, it is important to keep them apart. Accordingly, it proposes to distinguish between <i>inherently public goods</i> and <i>contingently public goods</i>. The later sections draw on the notion of a contingently public good, attempting to show how it can advance philosophical thinking about public goods in the context of ideal as well as nonideal theory.</p><p>Many philosophers have remained somewhat vague about how they understand the notion of public goods. For instance, Avigail Ferdman refers to what she calls the “standard economic understanding” according to which “public goods […] are material goods that the private market cannot provide efficiently” (2018, p. 662). Although she insists that there can also be nonmaterial public goods (2018, pp. 662–63), she otherwise relies on this characterization. Accordingly, public goods on her account constitute a market failure; but a market may fail to efficiently provide goods for various reasons and Ferdman does not specify which of these are defining of public goods. Even where explicit definitions have been put forward, however, they tend to be mutually inconsistent. The central rift is exemplified by the definitions proposed by Jonathan Anomaly (<span>2015</span>) and David Miller (<span>2004</span>).<sup>2</sup> Anomaly writes that “[g]oods are public if they exhibit <i>nonrivalry</i> and <i>nonexcludability</i>” (2015, p. 109, italics original), invoking the standard definition of economic theory, where a good is said to be <i>non-rivalrous</i> if its consumption by one person does not diminish its availability to others, and <i>non-excludable</i> if it is infeasible to exclude some people from consumption. By contrast, Miller writes that by public goods, “I shall mean goods that are made available to everyone without charge, and that each person can enjoy without diminishing the opportunity of others to enjoy the same good” (2004, pp. 127–28). Miller's notion of a public good encompasses Anomaly's but is broader: Miller's criterion that a goods is provided to everyone without charge may be fulfilled because of the good's inherent non-excludability (think of the view of the starry sky) or because of a deliberate choice to provide it for free (think of museums in England). As a result, they will not only classify certain goods differently, but will find different questions pertinent, and even sensible: while both may ask whether the state should provide <i>certain public goods</i>, only Miller can sensibly ask whether it should provide certain goods <i>as public goods</i>.</p><p>It is evident, then, that Anomaly and Miller are at risk of talking past each other, but less obvious which definition to prefer. Anomaly's definition fits with the classificatory scheme employed by economists, where public goods are contrasted with <i>private goods</i> (rivalrous, excludable; e.g., apples), <i>club goods</i> (non-rivalrous, excludable; e.g., pay-tv) and <i>common-pool goods</i> (rivalrous, non-excludable; e.g., fishing stocks). It also captures the market-failure aspect that Ferdman alludes to: since, by definition, no one can be excluded from the use of public goods, everyone has an incentive to contribute as little as possible. Due to this so-called <i>free-rider problem</i>, markets will not provide public goods at efficient levels.<sup>3</sup> In conflating what economists call “club goods” and “public goods,” Miller appears to give up a valuable distinction. For him, a library qualifies as a public good so long as access is <i>in fact</i> offered to everyone free of charge. But as private collections like the London Library prove, markets can provide libraries as club goods. Even club goods typically involve a market failure: unless perfect price-discrimination is feasible, markets will not provide club goods at efficient levels. But this market failure is more limited—because people can be excluded, a market can at least in principle provide these goods. At the same time, Miller's account better captures the ordinary use of the term “public good”. It seems neither uncommon, nor unreasonable to speak of parks as public goods—but while they are often freely accessible to everyone, it is, as London's Belgrave Square Garden demonstrates, possible to restrict access to those willing (and able) to purchase a key.</p><p>Because the definitions of a public good advanced by Miller and Anomaly each pick out important aspects, we have reason to preserve them both. But in order to avoid misunderstandings, we need to keep them distinct. To achieve this, I propose to distinguish between <i>inherently public goods</i> and <i>contingently public goods</i>.<sup>4</sup> More specifically, I propose to define an <i>inherently public good</i> (along Anomaly's lines) as a good that is (i) non-rivalrous and (ii) non-excludable and a <i>contingently public good</i> (in Millerian spirit) as a good that is (i) non-rivalrous and (ii) <i>as a matter of choice</i>, provided in a non-exclusionary form. The qualifier “as a matter of choice” is important because in so far as inherently public goods are non-excludable, they are necessarily provided in non-exclusionary form, so the mere condition that certain goods are provided to everyone for free fails to mark the distinction. As Miller does not add this qualification, his notion encompasses both types of public goods. Moreover, I understand the term “non-exclusionary form” broadly: while a good can be provided in a non-exclusionary form by making it accessible to everyone free of charge, it can also be so provided if there is a token charge, yet one that every person can easily afford.<sup>5</sup></p><p>The distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is important because it allows us to keep two things apart: the deliberate choice about the <i>mode of provision</i> of goods and the <i>market failure</i> resulting from the inability to exclude others. The distinction is close in spirit to, but not identical with, one that Vaughn Bryan Baltzly (<span>2021</span>) and Anomaly (<span>2021</span>) have recently drawn between <i>public goods</i> and <i>publicized goods</i>. For Baltzly, publicized goods are goods “whose ‘public’ character results only from a policy decision to make some (otherwise private) good freely and universally available” (2021, p. 376). Anomaly, discussing public health measures, characterizes as publicized “goods that are made public through the incentives created by government mandates” (2021, p. 2), where a good being public primarily means that its consumption imposes externalities on others (2021, p. 6). The notion of publicized goods, like that of contingently public goods, picks up on the fact that society can frequently decide whether to offer universal, free access to a specific good. Yet, unlike the notion of contingently public goods, it imposes no restriction on the extent to which a good is rivalrous. It is, for this reason, much broader: if a state provides apples for free, they become a publicized good, but not a contingently public good. As comes out in the discussion below, having the narrower, more precise term “contingently public goods” is valuable because it allows us to pick out those goods whose public provision promises efficiency gains.</p><p>The remainder of the article is an attempt to show that the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is valuable and that the importance of contingently public goods has been underappreciated. Three points should be noted at the outset though. First, the distinction is arguably better conceived of as demarcating a spectrum than a categorical divide: few goods are inherently non-excludable; instead, exclusion may be more or less costly. Second, whether some good is non-excludable, and for this reason inherently public, depends on the state of technology and may change<sup>6</sup>: if, in some dystopian future, people need to pay for access to biodomes, then clean air will have turned into a contingently public good. Finally, just as few goods are entirely non-rivalrous, few are non-excludable: the fact that I go for a run in the park does not diminish its availability, but if a crowd of people clogs pathways and occupies all picnic spots, this does diminish the park's availability (or value) to others—at the limit, the park becomes a rivalrous good. So, the criterion of non-rivalry should not be interpreted too strictly; instead, we may distinguish between public goods that are more pure or impure depending on their degree of rivalry—at a given level of consumption, or across a range of levels.</p><p>Note, moreover, that the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is orthogonal to several other distinctions that have been drawn within the debate on public goods. For example, Ferdman (2018) distinguishes between universal and nonuniversal public goods, where the former are valued by all whereas the latter are only valued by some. Even more prominently, some authors (see e.g., Claassen, <span>2013</span>; Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>) have drawn a distinction between essential (or necessary) and discretionary public goods, where the provision of the former, but not the latter, is required by justice.<sup>7</sup> But the fact that some good is an inherently public good (or a contingently public one) neither affects whether it is universal, nor whether it is essential.<sup>8</sup> This is explained by the fact that the classification of a good as inherently or contingently public is based merely on its structural properties, namely on whether it is excludable in principle or merely provided in a non-exclusionary form; but these structural properties evidently determine neither whether a good is valued by everyone, nor whether it is critical for justice.<sup>9</sup> So, the terminological distinction advocated here is new and independent of the existing ones. At the same time, the different specifications can of course be combined; we can, for example, have a contingently public goods that is essential and universal.</p><p>An important strand of the recent philosophical debate of public goods has operated at the level of ideal theory and has focused on the question of justice: according to which criteria should burdens and benefits of the provision of public goods be distributed to preserve conditions of justice (see e.g., Claassen, <span>2013</span>; Miller, <span>2004</span>; Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2001</span>)? This section puts forward two novel objections against the various benefit principles that have been proposed in response to this question. The <i>objection from unequal access to club goods</i> asserts that these benefit principles mandate unacceptable transfer payments to the privately wealthy. The <i>objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods</i> asserts that the benefit principles, unless qualified, mandate unacceptable transfer payments to people who disvalue their inclusive mode of provision. Both these objections draw on the case of contingently public goods: in each case, it is the possibility of providing the respective public goods as club goods that generates a problem. More specifically, these objections draw on a specific subset of contingently public goods: those whose provision is not directly required by justice (and which are therefore also discretionary in the sense further explored below).</p><p>The discussion of the demands of justice in the provision of public goods is motivated by two observations (see Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, esp. 562–64). On the one hand, there are some public goods that are required for justice. Consider the rule of law. Broadly understood as the effective restraint on arbitrary use of power through enforcement of legal rules and procedures, it qualifies as an (immaterial) public good. Moreover, it is presupposed by virtually all theories of justice: for what would be the point of allocating resources, if individuals were subject to the arbitrary exercise of power by others who could take them away (or impose physical harm)? On the other hand, there are goods whose provision is not required by justice, but generates a concern of justice: assuming an initially just society, how should the benefits and costs of their provision be allocated?<sup>10</sup> Goods of the former type, “whose provision is itself a matter of justice”, are typically called “essential public goods” (Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, p. 564) or “necessary public goods” (Claassen, <span>2013</span>, p. 273). Goods of the latter type, whose provision is not required by justice, are labeled “discretionary public goods” (Claassen, <span>2013</span>, p. 273; Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, p. 564).<sup>11</sup></p><p>Proponents of social theories of justice have not given much thought to discretionary public goods, and where they have considered them at all, they have typically endorsed procedural criteria.<sup>12</sup> John Rawls, for instance, initially stipulated that the state may provide (discretionary) public goods only “when they satisfy Wicksell's unanimity criterion” (1999, p. 248), which makes their legitimate provision dependent on everyone's consent to a proposal specifying (i) the good to be provided and (ii) the tax schedule to pay for it (Wicksell, <span>1958</span>). In his later work (Rawls, <span>2001</span>), Rawls came to relax the unanimity condition, proposing instead a simple majority vote.<sup>13</sup> As noted by Miller (<span>2004</span>), the problem with procedural approaches is that even if one thinks that they provide an account of <i>legitimacy</i>, they are silent on the question of <i>distributive justice</i>. But the surplus from the provision of discretionary public goods can be distributed in various ways—and not all appear (equally) just.</p><p>In light of the weaknesses of procedural accounts, some authors have advocated substantive criteria (Miller, <span>2004</span>; Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2001</span>). They propose to address the question of justice in the provision of public goods in two steps. First, we identify the set of essential public goods, whose provision is required by justice; for these goods, the distribution of costs is determined by our theory of justice. In a second step, we consider discretionary public goods, and it is at this stage that we need an additional principle to determine the distribution of costs and benefits. The most basic such principle is the <i>benefit principle</i>, which requires the provision of discretionary public goods to benefit everyone. But this principle is highly permissive; assuming self-interested voting, even the unanimity condition implies that the benefit principle is met. Two more restrictive principles have been advanced. Murphy and Nagel (<span>2001</span>) propose<sup>14</sup> that every person should contribute to the cost of providing discretionary public goods <i>in proportion</i> to the benefits she receives; call this the <i>proportional benefit principle</i>. Miller (<span>2004</span>) proposes that discretionary public goods should be provided so as to <i>equalize the net benefits</i> individuals receive; call this the <i>equal benefit principle</i>.</p><p>These principles have prompted objections. For example, Miller has criticized the proportional benefit principle as treating the state like an enterprise: insisting on contributions in proportion to benefits, he claims, contradicts the idea of a political community “whose foundational principle is that each member holds an equal stake” (2004, 144). Yet, Miller's equal benefit principle appears vulnerable to a related objection. In insisting on strictly equal benefits, one seems to adopt toward society the perspective of a jealous child. Among siblings, the equal benefit principle might have some bite: if one child does not like chocolate, but her brother does, she might insist that, if chocolates are the only sweets available, then, for reasons of justice, neither of them should get any. But at the level of society, insisting on a principle that prohibits the provision of public goods in circumstances where it would harm no one and benefit many seems to reveal a pathological insistence on an “equal share,” exposing a lack of generosity that can be expected toward fellow citizens. In addition, Miller and Taylor (<span>2018</span>, 568) have argued that the proportional benefit principle is incomplete. If two distinct sets of discretionary public goods satisfy the proportionality requirement, the principle does not tell us which one to choose.<sup>15</sup> Assuming that we aim to maximize benefits, the equal benefit principle avoids this problem. But it is highly restrictive in other regards: unless benefits can be equalized, a good cannot be provided, even if everyone were to benefit from it. As Miller and Taylor note (<span>2018</span>, 569), this appears to render the equal benefit principle vulnerable to a leveling-down objection (though transfer schemes might help address this problem).<sup>16</sup></p><p>Contingently public goods motivate two additional, and more fundamental objections, which apply to the various benefit principles simultaneously. First, there is the <i>objection from unequal access to club goods</i>: because contingently public goods are in principle exclusionary, they could be provided as club goods, but an unequal initial distribution of private resources implies unequal access to such club goods, which affects the distribution of benefits from their provision as public goods; as a result, the benefit principles mandate implausible transfers to the individually wealthy. This objection can be illustrated by reference to the case of a public swimming pool. A swimming pool that is accessible to everyone free of charge, or for a token fee, is an (impure) public good. We may initially think that all swimmers benefit from it. But suppose an individually wealthy swimmer argues that she does not benefit: because she is a member to a fitness club that offers pool access, she claims to gain nothing from a public pool. The proportional benefit principle, she holds, implies that she must contribute nothing, whereas the benefit principle and the equal benefit principle imply that she is even owed compensation.</p><p>Of course, how the public pool affects the wealthy swimmer depends on the exact specification of the case. If her sole motivation for purchasing membership to the club was to gain pool access, she can cancel her membership once the public pool has been built and her benefit is captured by the money saved on the club membership. As a result, she benefits from the public pool and has to contribute to its costs of provision. Even in this case, however, part of her benefit may escape accounting. For if she had been willing to pay more for the club membership than was required, she was able to secure a <i>surplus benefit</i> privately, and this surplus benefit does not count toward her benefit from access to the public pool. By contrast, the entire benefit from pool access is taken into account for those who initially lacked all pool access. But, one might argue, if the initial distribution was just, then this is fine: while part of the benefit the wealthy gain from public goods escapes accounting, it is the part they had already obtained from access to the club good—so, the provision of a public pool maintains but does not increase their advantage.</p><p>Next, however, consider a variation of the case. Suppose that the well-off swimmer decides not to use the public pool, but to keep her club membership. As she does not derive any benefit from the public pool, the equal benefit principle mandates a compensatory payment to the wealthy swimmer, provided there is a surplus benefit to building the public pool.<sup>17</sup> The proportional benefit principle similarly justifies compensation if the public pool disbenefits the wealthy swimmer. Suppose that, once the public pool is built, some club members leave the fitness club, prompting a fee hike. If a wealthy swimmer decides to maintain her club membership, for example because she sufficiently values the other benefits of membership, then the provision of the public pool generates a <i>disbenefit</i> to her. Even according to the proportional benefit principle, she should thus make a negative contribution to the costs of providing the public pool, that is, she is owed compensation.</p><p>These implications of the benefit principles appear puzzling. If an initial distribution of private goods is just, one might grant the well-off any benefit they obtain from purchasing club goods that are unaffordable to others. One might perhaps even accept that, if they prefer their respective club goods, they do not need to contribute to the costs of providing public goods. But it does not seem plausible to assign them claims to compensation. If a group of people is willing to carry <i>all costs</i> of making some good freely available <i>to everyone</i>, can they really be required to fund transfer payments to wealthy people who prefer to consume an equivalent club good, yet are not made any worse off? Now, it is important to be cautious here. If we make a judgment on whether some person can reasonably claim compensation in a particular case, this judgment will ultimately rest in part on our intuitions about this case (as well as our intuitions about relevant other cases, to which the systematic account that underpins our judgment extends). Since the argument here proceeds at the level of ideal theory, we need to ensure that we are not led astray by intuitions about nonideal cases. Perhaps, one might worry, we deem the claim to compensation unreasonable simply because, in the world we inhabit, it would be absurd to compensate those who are wealthy and already have access to club goods. But assuming an initially just allocation of private goods, might it not simply be correct that we need to compensate those who receive less benefit, or even a disbenefit, because they already had access to the relevant goods in the form of club goods?</p><p>In my view, even under ideal circumstances, the demand for compensation is not plausible. The difference between cases where some are exempt from contributing and cases where they deserve compensation can be drawn by reference to the market as an alternative mode of provision. If those who favor a given public good could secure it by coordinating in a market, then they could provide it privately—in this case, the person with access to a corresponding club good would make no contribution, but they would also not be compensated. So, the outcome of the first type of case—no contribution by those with access to club goods—aligns with the market outcome, whereas the outcome of the second type of case—compensation to those with existing access to club goods—diverges from the market outcome. Of course, the mere fact that the hypothetical market outcome would involve no compensation does not imply that this is the correct view in a case where the state provides a good: the demands on the state differ from those on private market participants. But the divergence to the market-based outcome indicates that compensation is harder to justify than non-contribution, and especially where it is owed for a relative lack of benefit rather than for an indirect harm (due to costlier club goods). Note, moreover, that the state's involvement in the provision of the respective public goods may here be quite minimal—the state may simply provide an enforcement mechanism that allows those individuals who consent to chip in to collectively provide a public good that is then available to everyone. At least in such a case, even under initial conditions of justice, admitting the demand for compensation would effectively allow the better off to leverage their initial advantage to secure settlements from the worse off even though they already shoulder the entire cost of the state's provision of goods that are valuable and accessible to everyone. But this does not appear just—and even if the initial advantage attained through greater access to club goods was just.</p><p>But suppose one were to reject this argument and insist that, because the state always must treat everyone equally, as soon as it gets involved in the provision of discretionary public goods, compensation is indeed owed. In this case, the argument from unequal access to club goods points to a more fundamental concern: relative to which baseline is equal treatment to be ensured? In addressing this concern, it is helpful to first summarize an insight by Claassen (<span>2013</span>). Claassen argues that Miller's equal benefit principle disadvantages people whose conception of the good life relies heavily on the consumption of public goods relative to market goods (2013, pp. 278–81). In a pure market economy, he notes, those who favor public goods find themselves at a disadvantage relative to those who favor market goods—few public goods are provided. But this disadvantage is preserved, if we introduce public goods, yet require that everyone benefits equally from their provision: for while everyone will now be better off, everyone will be <i>equally</i> better off, so relative positions remain unchanged. This casts doubt on the justifiability of the benchmark of a pure market economy. The objection from unequal access to club goods casts further doubt on this benchmark, but on different grounds. For it shows that, with a pure market economy as our starting point, part of the benefit that wealthier people obtain from the provision of contingently public goods escapes accounting—namely the part they had managed to already secure in a private market for club goods that serve as substitutes. The benchmark used by the benefit principles thus not only disadvantages those who prefer public goods, but also the less wealthy.</p><p>The argument from unequal access to club goods reveals that regardless of people's conceptions of the good life (and whether preferences for public goods qualify as constitutive of such conceptions), the extent to which one stands to reap net benefits from access to contingently public goods will, <i>ceteris paribus</i>, correlate negatively with one's initial wealth. This reveals the benefit principles to be implausible, as it shows that they demand highly regressive compensation in the context of public good provision. This line of argument aligns with Claassen's in casting doubt on the starting point endorsed by the benefit principles, but is distinct in three ways. First, whereas Claassen focuses on preferences for public versus market goods, the concern here are wealth inequalities: my argument contends that the starting point of a pure market society disadvantages some people regardless of their preferences, simply because the less wealthy stand to gain more from the provision of contingently public goods relative to a pure market economy, and the assumption of such an economy as our reference point therefore relatively disadvantages these people. Second, the argument put forward here draws explicitly on the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods: contingently public goods are those that could alternatively have been provided in a more exclusionary form as club goods, and it is the unequal initial access to such club goods that generates the implausibly regressive distributive demands of the benefit principles. Finally, Claassen draws a more modest conclusion: instead of rejecting the benefit principles, he only maintains that one could reasonably take a different view, advocating for what one could call a position of “meta-neutrality”: he proposes to remain neutral as to whether one should remain neutral toward individuals' preferences (and distribute resources across all market and public goods to equalize welfare levels) or whether one should remain neutral toward individuals' preferences against the backdrop of a pure market society (and thus endorse the equal benefit principle).<sup>18</sup> By contrast, my claim is stronger: it is that, at least given their benchmark of a pure market economy, the proposed benefit principles are implausible because they demand highly regressive compensation payments for the provision of contingently public goods.</p><p>In addition, there is an <i>objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods</i>: the benefit principles, implausibly, mandate compensation to people who disvalue the provision of contingently public goods merely because they disvalue their inclusive <i>mode of provision</i>. As Claassen's argument summarized above reveals, the assumption of neutrality toward individual preferences concerning the provision of discretionary public goods is not as innocent as is generally presumed. But while Claassen presents the question about the preference for market versus public goods as being primarily about <i>which goods</i> are provided, in the case of contingently public goods, we need to distinguish between the specific <i>good provided</i> (e.g., a park) and its <i>mode of provision</i> (as a public good or a club good). We need to draw this distinction because a market could provide such goods as club goods; and the distinction matters because people can value a good itself as well as its mode of provision. Ferdman (2018, pp. 666–67) notes this possibility of <i>intrinsically valuing</i> public goods: a person may value a good, like a public park, for its universal accessibility. The person who intrinsically values public parks would, <i>ceteris paribus</i>, prefer a public park to a private park to which she, but not everyone else, had access.<sup>19</sup> But there is also the corresponding possibility of <i>intrinsically disvaluing</i> public goods: just as one can value public goods because of their mode of provision, so one can disvalue them due to their inclusive mode of provision. And this attitude is not just a theoretical possibility: in racist societies, people have historically objected to the provision of public goods, like beaches, public transportation, and libraries, on the ground that such goods should not be equally available to everyone.</p><p>The possibility of intrinsically disvaluing public goods gives rise to a challenge to the benefit principles, but its precise form depends on one's interpretation of the principle of neutrality that underpins them. The benefit principles are embedded in a liberal framework, which demands neutrality toward the preferences of citizens. The proponents of the benefit principles do not qualify, nor further discuss, the underlying notion of neutrality. According to a literal interpretation, (i) neutrality demands that one be neutral toward all preferences unless explicitly specified otherwise. On this interpretation, the possibility of an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods generates an objection. Consider person <i>A</i>, living in a class-based society, who deems herself a member of the upper class, and objects to the provision of public parks on the sole ground that their universal accessibility fails to respect a status distinction among members of different classes. Moreover, suppose that <i>A</i> is an indoors person, who enters neither public, nor private parks, and would never have learned of the public parks had she not read about it in her upper-class gazette. In this case, <i>A</i>'s, preference against public provision contradicts the spirit of the political community, negating a basic understanding of others <i>as equals</i>. It is for this reason that I believe it would not warrant consideration: <i>A</i> could not reasonably demand compensation for the disbenefit the provision of public parks imposes on her. But this shows that the benefit principles must be qualified: their statement needs to expressly exclude some instances of intrinsic disvaluation of public goods.</p><p>However, at this point, one might interject that the principle of neutrality could also be interpreted differently. Indeed, its literal, unqualified interpretation may be deemed naïve: it requires remaining neutral regarding all preferences, including immoral ones. Although this is not explicitly stated, one might therefore insist, proponents of the benefit principles implicitly assume that at least some immoral preferences be excluded from consideration. But if one adopts this view, then one might respond that the above example is moralized and therefore needs to be rejected: <i>A</i>'s preference not to have parks as public goods is immoral because it is based on immoral classist preferences; therefore, the principle of neutrality does not apply here, so <i>A</i>'s preference does not warrant compensation, and no problem arises for the benefit principles. This response prompts the question: can we find a non-moralized example, which is not excluded by the principle of neutrality, but where a person's intrinsic disvaluation of a public good does not warrant compensation?</p><p>In addressing this question, note first that while the claim that the principle of neutrality should not include immoral preferences rules out its literal interpretation (i), it does not entail a specific alternative. Instead, it is consistent with at least three different interpretations of the principle: (ii) it demands neutrality toward all preferences except for a set implicitly put aside as immoral; (iii) it demands neutrality toward all preferences bar those that are in fact immoral; (iv) it stipulates that a preference is immoral if and only we need not remain neutral toward it. Now, on interpretation (iv), a non-moralized example is ruled out by definition. This is because (iv) stipulates that, whenever we should not remain neutral toward a preference, then this preference is to count as immoral. It follows, by definition, that when we should not compensate a person for intrinsically disvaluing a public good (i.e., should not be neutral), then this preference is immoral—so, there can be no non-moralized example. In this way, interpretation (iv) rules out any objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods. But this comes at a high cost. If interpreted in this way, the principle of neutrality makes a conceptual, rather than a substantial claim. This not only renders it uninformative: nothing is said about how extensive the set of immoral preferences is, nor why we should not be neutral toward them. More importantly, it turns the order of explanation upside down: the claim no longer is that we should not remain neutral toward a preference because it is immoral, but instead that a preference qualifies as immoral because we should not remain neutral toward it. In my view, this implication renders implausible the interpretation of the principle of neutrality as making a conceptual claim. But note that, even if one were to insist on interpretation (iv), the above argument about <i>A</i>'s intrinsic disvaluation of public parks would be of some value: it would identify a specific type of preference with regard to which we should not remain neutral and provide reasons as why.</p><p>By contrast, interpretations (ii) and (iii), which make a substantial claim, allow for the possibility of a non-moralized example. I believe that such an example can be given. Consider <i>B</i>, who lives in an egalitarian republic. <i>B</i>, too, is an indoors person, who never uses parks. Still, she dislikes parks being provided as public goods because she dislikes universal accessibility. This is not due to classist or racist views; it just so happens that <i>B</i> prefers for goods to be privately rather than publicly available. <i>B</i>'s case thus differs from <i>A</i>'s: <i>B</i>'s intrinsic disvaluation of public parks is not based on any other morally tainted preferences or beliefs. <i>B</i> does not object to the public provision because it would fail to respect a status difference; she simply has a preference for private goods. This preference on its own, I contend, is too innocent to qualify as immoral; it is a preference that does not express any disrespect toward, or repugnant views about, other people. But at the same time, and like in the case of <i>A</i>, <i>B</i>'s intrinsic disvaluation of the public goods it is not a preference that warrants consideration when assessing the benefits and damages from the provision of public parks. This is because <i>B</i>'s preference not to have parks as public goods is not well-motivated: by assumption, <i>B</i> does not intend to use the parks, so whether they are publicly accessible is of no relevance to <i>B</i>'s ability to enjoy them (or any other goods), and <i>B</i> therefore suffers no meaningful harm from their provision as public goods. In assessing benefits, we need to take into consideration that, as an indoors person, <i>B</i> fails to benefit from the provision of public parks, but not that <i>B</i> disvalues their mode of provision.</p><p>If this line of argument is correct, then <i>B</i>'s case qualifies as a non-moralized example, which shows that, according to the qualified interpretations (ii) and (iii) of the principle of neutrality, the benefit principles must be restricted: at least sometimes, disbenefits that result from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods should be disregarded. Yet, even if one were to dispute this by insisting that <i>B</i>'s preference is immoral or that <i>B</i> has a claim to compensation, my argument would still highlight the need for proponents of benefit principles to address the following question: under which conditions is an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods an immoral preference that may thus be ignored, and why? This is a serious question, because the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods does not always appear to be immoral: vulnerable groups and minorities for instance arguably have good reason to demand spaces which are not accessible to everyone. It is less evident whether an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods could be justified if one never intends to use the respective good, however, or would not notice its use by others: may a religious group justifiably object to some mountain's universal accessibility because they consider it sacred, even if they would never notice if anyone else were to go there?</p><p>If sound, then the two objections put forward in this section have two implications. At the substantial level, they show that the existing benefit principles, which have been proposed to complement existing theories of justice to account for discretionary public goods, are deficient in ways that have so far escaped notice. At the theoretical level, they reveal the importance of taking account of contingently public goods in examining the demands of justice in the provision of discretionary public goods. This is because neither of the objections put forward in this section could have been raised with equal effect by reference to inherently public goods. Inherently public goods could not alternatively have been provided as club goods (though imperfect substitutes might), so concerns about unequal access to these goods in a market do not arise in their case (or, at least, not in exactly the same way). And because these goods are, by definition, non-excludable, it would be incoherent to welcome the good itself, yet object to its inclusive mode of provision.</p><p>But the two objections also indicate a more constructive task, namely, to specify the benefit principle one should adopt instead.<sup>20</sup> While the arguments put forward imply two conditions that an alternative benefit principle would have to meet, they do not yield comprehensive specification of such a principle. The two conditions they imply are as follows: first, the principle must be “club-good sensitive,” that is, it needs to specify under which conditions those who already had access to a club good that is then provided as a public good lack a claim to compensation; second, it must qualify the demand for neutrality, or more specifically, it needs to specify under which conditions preferences against public goods may or must be disregarded. But these two conditions can evidently be satisfied in numerous ways, and the above arguments do not yield any specific principle. Regarding club goods, for example, I have argued that those who had access to a club good cannot plausibly demand compensation for the provision of corresponding public good, if this provision does not make them worse off; but this leaves undetermined whether they can claim compensation if the provision in fact does make them worse off, and how much they must contribute if they benefit, but less so than everyone else. Meanwhile, regarding the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods, I have only argued that it <i>sometimes</i> cannot ground a claim to compensation, while admitting that it may in certain other contexts.</p><p>There are three reasons for which I refrain from attempting to defend any alternative principle here. First, I believe that good reasons can be put forward in favor of the equal as well as the proportional benefit principle (and perhaps also in favor of intermediary ones), so it is not evident which baseline to choose. But defending a specific view within this debate would divert from the article's argumentative trajectory. Second, I believe that one can reasonably disagree on how exactly the two conditions identified above should be met. In particular, as noted above, it does not appear obvious under exactly which conditions one may be justified in objecting to the inclusive mode of provision of contingently public goods. Finally, while relevant, the task of specifying an alternative is not critical to the aim of this article: it is not needed to show that contingently public goods are a neglected subset of public goods that is of relevance to the philosophical debate.</p><p>The preceding section has operated at the level of ideal theory, raising objections to principles that have been proposed to govern the provision of public goods in the context of an initially just society. In the actual world, circumstances are less favorable: we confront the provision of public goods against a background of numerous social injustices. In addition to injustices in the distribution of private resources, there are other types of social injustices, like unwarranted inequalities in opportunity and status. This section therefore moves on to discuss the provision of public goods under initially unjust or imperfectly just conditions. In so doing, part of its argument applies to public goods in general, while part of it applies specifically to contingently public goods. The central claim about public goods in general is that their provision holds the potential to render economic inequalities less relevant and to reduce inequalities in opportunity by reducing the importance of access to private resources, and that this can at times be an attractive alternative to other, transfer-based policies. Evidently, the provision of public goods will not always have this effect: it could instead even exacerbate existing injustices, as would happen, for instance, in an unjustly inegalitarian society where expensive, tax-funded public goods cater exclusively to the interests of the rich.<sup>21</sup> With regard to contingently public goods more specifically, the section claims that they hold a distinctive, fourfold potential which arises from the fact that they in principle allow exclusion and could have been provided in the form of club goods. First, because it can be possible to provide a contingently public good simply by removing restrictions on access to an existing club good, it can be especially efficient at addressing injustices. Moreover, and relatedly, because their provision can at times be costless, contingently public goods can, at least under certain conditions, avoid the standard objection of involving a market interference. Third, because contingently public goods could have been provided as exclusionary club goods, their public mode of provision can be an especially powerful expression of a commitment to inclusiveness, which is critical where status inequalities are of concern. Finally, the provision of contingently public goods has a special potential to undermine the relevance of club goods, and to thereby remove a critical barrier to equality of opportunity.</p><p>In making the case that public goods have the potential to rectify injustices, I begin by considering injustices that are the result of economic inequality. Of course, not all economic inequalities are injustices; some reflect inequalities in desert or are otherwise justified (in fact, economic equality could reflect an injustice). The following arguments therefore apply only to inequalities that in fact amount to injustices. Economic inequality is typically measured by the inequality in personal income, or earning power, and wealth. Prominent measures, like the Gini coefficient, illustrate this. The Gini coefficient is an aggregate measure of the extent of economic inequality, and it is typically computed for the distribution of wealth and for the distribution of income. It can also be used to assess the extent to which redistributive measures like taxation and social subsidies affect income inequality. While important, measures like the Gini coefficient are in an important sense incomplete. They fail to capture how important ownership of private material resources is in the first place. But the importance of ownership of private resources may vary significantly. In a society where all lakeshores are privatized, individuals need private resources that enable them to purchase access if they want to swim in a lake. In a society where lakes are publicly accessible, private resources are not required for this purpose. This point generalizes: societies can be set up in ways that render the possession of private material resources more important or less. One critical factor determining the importance of ownership of private resources is the extent to which a society provides public goods. While there appears to be no straightforward way of quantifying, for a given society, the importance of ownership of private resources or the extent of the provision of public goods, both are significant concerns. Conceiving of economic inequality exclusively in terms of the distribution of private resources therefore ignores the extent to which ownership of such resources is necessary for access to valuable goods. But it appears sensible to be concerned with economic inequality not simply in the sense of being concerned about the distribution of income and wealth, but rather in the sense of being concerned about differences in what people are able to do, given the current distribution of income and wealth.</p><p>These considerations reveal that the provision of public goods can be a means to indirectly address inequalities in income and wealth—by reducing their relevance. But not merely can they be a means to do so: it appears plausible that their outright provision is, at least sometimes, more efficient, and politically more feasible, than the redistribution of private resources. There is an economic rationale for why it may be more efficient. In so far as public goods are non-rivalrous (or imperfectly rivalrous), their consumption by some does not (or does not significantly) diminish their availability for consumption by others. This means that providing a good as a contingently public good rather than as a club good typically comes with efficiency gains—it increases accessibility at no additional cost. If we are, concerned with economic inequality because of the resulting differences in what people can do given the economic resources they have, then the provision of public goods may thus be more effective: it may be possible to achieve greater progress toward economic equality for any given level of taxation. In addition, and relatedly, there is a political rationale for why addressing economic inequalities by providing public goods may be practically more feasible. In so far as the public good is available to all, and therefore potentially benefits everyone, the wealthy may be more willing to pay taxes for its direct provision than to finance targeted transfer payments to the less well-off. As Kohn notes, “[u]niversal benefits tend to have higher levels of political support than means-tested programs” (2020, p. 9).</p><p>While this argument holds for public goods quite generally, contingently public goods promise to be particularly efficient at achieving this. For because corresponding club goods may already exist, it may be possible to turn a club good into a contingently public good at effectively no cost, thereby increasing access without making anyone worse off. For the purpose of illustration, consider a company operating a pay-tv channel in a society experiencing high levels of economic inequality. Suppose that this company cannot use price discrimination, so it attempts to set its universal subscription rate at the profit-maximizing price. As a result, there will be some people who would value access to the channel, but do not subscribe, either because they do not value it sufficiently or because they simply lack the means to pay for the subscription.<sup>22</sup> If the channel could be made accessible to everyone at no additional cost, then transforming it into a contingently public good promises efficiency gains. Moreover, if those willing to subscribe can be taxed at the current subscription rate, then doing so would not make anyone worse off. Now picture a society where economic inequality is of concern primarily because it results in unequal access to pay-tv. In this case, the best way for the state to address economic inequality may be to pay a lump sum subsidy to the tv-channel if it makes the program available to everyone. This ensures universal access and it may do so in a more efficient way than redistributive transfer payments could. Moreover, it may be more feasible as even existing subscribers may not object to being taxed at the current subscription rate to pay for universal access.</p><p>Of course, this scenario is schematic and avoids important complications. In all likelihood, it will not be possible to tax exactly those who would otherwise subscribe to a channel, so using general tax revenue may force some to contribute to goods they would prefer not to be provided. Moreover, subsidies eliminate the need for tv-channels to convince customers to subscribe by providing desired content. This highlights that, once we consider specific contingently public goods, we must weigh the benefits and disbenefits of providing these goods <i>as public goods</i>. The public provision of goods will be justifiable, on the basis of concerns about economic equality, only where access is sufficiently central to our concerns about economic inequality. In this regard, public libraries are arguably a more compelling case because economic inequalities are of greater concern if they limit access to education than if they limit access to pay-tv.<sup>23</sup> At the same time, building libraries that offer free and universal access instead of relying on transfer payments to ensure that everyone is in a position to become a patron at a private library may well be the more economically efficient and the more feasible choice politically. But regardless of one's view about specific cases, the general point holds: sometimes, the provision of contingently public goods can help address economic inequalities in an effective and targeted (if perhaps partial) way.</p><p>Moreover, and this is a second feature that sets contingently public goods apart, they can at times escape the standard objection that the provision of public goods always needs justification because it requires taxation. Advocates and opponents of public goods alike typically suggest that unless we are in the fortunate position where their provision can be secured through assurance contracts or is financed by charities, it requires a state to tax firms or individuals to then use these funds to provide the goods (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Schmidtz, <span>1991</span>). It is for this reason that it is typically the provision of public goods that is taken to require justification. Even those (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>) who argue in favor of the provision of an extensive set of public goods implicitly accept that it is the provision of public goods that needs to be justified and offer such justifications. But there are at least two alternative ways in which a state can secure the provision of contingently public goods. First, where a non-rivalrous good already exists in the form of a club good, but some are excluded based on noneconomic criteria like gender, the state can issue regulations that prohibit such grounds of exclusion, thereby enlarging access and turning the good into a public good. Consider a privately run swimming pool, which is the only one far and near. If this pool excludes a specific group based on noneconomic criteria (e.g., men or persons of Asian descent), then we have a club good. Now, suppose the state introduces regulation prohibiting exclusion on such grounds and that the fee charged by the pool is small enough to effectively ensure universal access. In this case, the swimming pool (or, more precisely, pool access), has turned from a club good into a public good. Such a solution will not be available for all contingently public goods. Yet, it shows that at least sometimes, the state can ensure the provision of a public good without directly providing it, namely be prohibiting certain grounds of exclusion. Doing so does not require any state expenditure and consequently no taxation, though one might insist that issuing such regulation still amounst to a form of market interference.</p><p>In addition, whether certain contingently public goods are provided may directly depend on the initial allocation and specification of property rights. Public lands, such as woods, lakes, and plains, have a public good character: being accessible to everyone, they offer opportunities for recreation. But the decision to assign private property rights in these lands precedes the existence of a market, so it does not constitute a market interference. Moreover, a public good character can be preserved even for private goods if property rights are restricted in ways that grant everyone access. In the Nordic countries, the “right to roam” has existed for centuries, whereas private landowners in England and the United States have enjoyed much greater discretion in excluding others. Contingently public goods thus indicate that not all decisions on the provision of public goods amount to a market interference—some simply concern the market's set-up. Of course, this point holds most immediately at a rather abstract level: in the world we live in, property rights in most assets (though not in all, note for instance the oceans and outer space) have already been assigned, so any change to these property rights amounts to a form of market interference. Still, the fact that the initial decision to assign a particular set of property rights to specific assets affected the availability of contingently public goods provides at least a principled justification for such an interference: because the initial decision, which did not precede the market's existence, simultaneously determined the availability of public goods, amending existing property right claims is easier to justify (provided adequate compensation is offered where applicable).</p><p>While economic inequalities can constitute one sort of social injustice, social injustices can take other forms as well. In fact, the proposal to address economic inequalities through the provision of public goods presupposes that these inequalities are a concern primarily because they result in inequalities of opportunity and access: the provision of contingently public goods may leave existing inequalities in the ownership of private resources unchanged yet ensure greater equality of opportunity and access by offering an alternative to market consumption. And while inequalities in opportunity, access, and status may arise from economic ones, they need not. The case of a private country club illustrates this. Typically, such clubs charge hefty membership fees, which effectively exclude those who are not wealthy. But there can also be other grounds for exclusion. Historically, membership to country clubs has frequently been restricted on the basis of gender and race. Such restrictions are in one sense correlated with access money: if those excluded had the means to establish their own clubs, their lack of access could be alleviated. But at least from the perspective of the individual, it may well be the case that their exclusion is due to their gender or race rather than due to a lack of personal wealth.</p><p>This points to two additional ways in which contingently public goods hold a distinctive potential for addressing injustices. Where some members of society are deprived of access and thereby of opportunity and status on nonmaterial grounds, public goods can offer respite in two ways. First, in so far as public goods are freely available to all, they directly provide a shared realm of experience and social interaction and thereby constitute what Kallhoff calls “connectivity goods” (2014, pp. 642–44)—goods that not only enlarge access, but constitute a point of interaction and symbolize the commitment to shared space and equality. This is true not only, but especially of contingently public ones: because contingently public goods could have been provided in an exclusionary form, their public provision is a more decisive expression of this commitment to equality. In a society where status inequalities are a concern—think, for example, of a state with a strong divide among castes or ethnicities or religious groups—the provision of a contingently public good can be of great symbolic significance: due to the deliberate mode of its universally accessible mode of provision, it can be a powerful expression of a commitment to the equality of all citizens (and in a way not quite achievable with an inherently public good, which could not have been provided in a more exclusive form).</p><p>Second, and more indirectly, the provision of public goods tends to undermine the market's more exclusive modes of provision, and thereby the relevance of club goods in particular. Again, this is true of all public goods, but in particular of contingently public goods, because their provision can more directly diminish the attractiveness of the club goods to which they correspond. Our earlier example of the swimming pool illustrates this: once a public pool exists, people have less incentive to pay for access to private pools. In this sense, contingently public goods have the tendency to crowd out the corresponding club goods. This point is rarely highlighted, but important: the most promising long-term strategy for addressing inequalities of access that are the result of powerful structures of private clubs may consist in the provision of corresponding public goods that serve as substitutes. In this way, contingently public goods can gradually break the appeal and thereby the power of the more exclusive, private institutions, thereby reducing the inequality in access, and thus the inequalities in opportunity and perceived status it gives rise to.</p><p>If this examination is sound, then public goods—and contingently public goods in particular—constitute a natural, but underappreciated focal point for effectively rectifying existing injustices. Specifically, it appears plausible that the provision of contingently public good is a superior alternative to the introduction of a universal basic income (UBI) in at least certain contexts. Although a UBI has been advocated on various grounds, ranging from the justified claims of individuals to their share of the fruits of natural and social resources (see e.g., Van Parijs <span>1991</span>, pp. 130–31) to its ability to address existing gender and racial injustices (see Bidadanure, <span>2019</span>, pp. 492–95), it always aims to redistribute <i>private resources</i> relative to the status quo. There are, as indicated above, good reasons to believe that the provision of public goods can be the economically more efficient and politically more feasible policy. This will be the case, for instance, when non-rivalrous goods already exist in form of club goods and access can be universalized at little additional cost. It might also be the case where we can slightly amend private property rights, for instance in land, to ensure that some public good is provided. Moreover, where we confront injustices that are not due to inequalities in material resources, but rules and norms that exclude individuals from participating on equal terms, only the provision of contingently public goods, but not that of a UBI, may be able to rectify them—by effectively enlarging access and by creating a shared realm of interaction.<sup>24</sup></p><p>This leaves us with a question: under what circumstances ought the state address injustices by providing public goods and when should it resort to other, redistributive measures? Or, more generally, which principles determine what sorts of public goods the state ought to provide? This article does not aim to provide any comprehensive answer to these questions, and for two reasons. On the one hand, the normative question whether a state ought to provide a particular public good must always be evaluated against the current social background conditions. For instance, whether a state ought to provide free sports grounds or ought to take redistributive measures to address an inequality in access to recreational facilities will depend on numerous factors, such as the costs of provision, the availability of information on individual preferences regarding types of sports grounds and the availability of alternative means of provision. So, in any particular case, a specific argument needs to be put forward in favor of the provision of contingently public goods. On the other hand, the account leaves open how different considerations are to be weighed: it remains silent, for instance, on how important economic efficiency is compared to equal access, and on how much weight attaches to the value of solidarity. Instead of providing a normative theory of public goods, this section primarily aims to highlight the potential of public goods to rectify existing injustices—and that this potential is especially pronounced in the case of contingently public goods. The account is thus open-ended, allowing proponents of specific views of the value of public goods and the criteria for injustice to draw on it in evaluating whether, according to them, a given public good ought to be provided.</p><p>The potential to rectify existing injustices provides at least a <i>pro tanto</i> justification for the provision of some contingently public goods—and it does so even if this provision is not currently favored by everyone or is not favored by the sum of individual preferences (regardless of how they are to be aggregated). This injustice-based justification of contingently public goods is distinct from the perfectionist justifications that have been advocated elsewhere. It has for instance been argued (compellingly in my view) that public goods can help create conditions of a good life by curbing harmful competition for scarce resources (Ferdman, 2018, p. 670; see also Hussain, <span>2018</span>) and that they can contribute to a shared feeling of purpose, thereby strengthening “a sense of solidarity” (Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>, p. 641), and that these benefits support an argument against state-neutrality and can justify the state provision of public goods. The argument put forward here is more modest: it claims that the provision of public goods may be justified by their ability to address existing social injustices, rather than by some independently valuable objective. This is not to say that there is no link: it seems reasonable, for example, to believe that a greater sense of solidarity will prevent certain social injustices from arising in the first place. But the focus differs: the <i>pro tanto</i> justification for public goods that has been proposed here appeals directly to their ability to rectify existing injustices. This, it seems reasonable to think, should make the argument less controversial because the existence of injustices provides a stronger case for action than more perfectionist proposals.</p><p>This article falls in line with several recent attempts (de Jongh, <span>2022</span>; Ferdman &amp; Kohn <span>2018</span>; Judt, <span>2010</span>; Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>; Kohn, <span>2020</span>) to reassess the role of public goods for a well-ordered society and to elevate them to a more prominent place in political thinking. In response to an ambiguity in how philosophers use the term “public good,” this article has proposed, in Section 2, to draw a distinction between inherently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and non-excludable, and contingently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and, as a matter of choice, provided in a non-exclusionary form. Sections 3 and 4 drew on this distinction to show how the category of contingently public goods is fruitful to philosophical debate. As Section 3 argued, contingently public goods pose a challenge to the various benefit principles that have been proposed to govern the distribution of costs and benefits in the provision of public goods. Because these goods could alternatively be provided in the form of exclusionary club goods, the proposed benefit principles mandate unreasonable transfer payments to the individually wealthy as well as to those who disvalue the public goods' inclusive mode of provision. As Section 4 argued, contingently public goods at the same time provide a natural, yet underappreciated focal point for addressing unwarranted economic inequalities, as well as inequalities in opportunity, access, and status, and thus for rectifying social injustices. Because public goods are equally accessible to everyone, they render the ownership of private resources less important, thereby diminishing the relevance of inequalities in income and wealth and broadening opportunity and access. Contingently public goods are special in four regards: their provision may be costless; it may not require any market interference; it holds the potential to be a particularly powerful expression of everyone's equal status; and it holds a particular potential to undermine the relevance of exclusionary club goods.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"56 2","pages":"202-222"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12516","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The importance of contingently public goods\",\"authors\":\"Friedemann Bieber\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/josp.12516\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Public goods have recently received increasing attention by philosophers. In addition to work on the historical origins of the notion of public goods (Desmarais-Tremblay, <span>2017</span>), their relevance to the thinking of particular political theorists (de Jongh, <span>2022</span>) and the justifiability of particular public goods, such as the arts (Kessler, <span>2018</span>), there have been a number of systematic attempts to develop a normative theory of public goods (see e.g., Kallhoff, <span>2011</span>; Miller, <span>2004</span>). Asking which public goods the state ought to provide, and how the benefits and burdens of their provision ought to be distributed, these contributions can roughly be divided into two camps. One group of authors has addressed these questions within political liberalism, remaining committed to the principle of state neutrality. By taking individual preferences as given, they note that many public goods promise net efficiency gains and ask according to what principles these benefits ought to be distributed (see e.g., Claassen, <span>2013</span>; Cullity, <span>2008</span>; Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2001</span>). In so doing, they see themselves as complementing existing theories of justice, which remain mostly silent on the allocation of costs and benefits of public goods (Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, p. 556). Another group of authors has moved beyond the principle of state neutrality, putting forward arguments in favor of the state provision of public goods that are at least in part independent of individual preferences, such as their potential to foster solidarity and to connect people (see e.g., Ferdman, <span>2018</span>; Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>; Kohn, <span>2020</span>). These authors contend that the social value of public goods remains underappreciated, and that the state may be justified in providing them even if doing so does not result in efficiency gains and reject the view that efficiency is the central criterion by which to judge whether the provision of a public good can be justified. This philosophical interest has coincided with a broader sense of neglect of public goods, which has been voiced by journalists and public intellectuals, in particular in Britain and the United States (Irvin, <span>2012</span>; Judt, <span>2010</span>; Lehrer, <span>2020</span>). Yet, despite the recent surge in attention, the philosophical and, more generally, the “scholarly literature on public goods is relatively thin” (Kohn, <span>2020</span>, p. 2).<sup>1</sup></p><p>This article aims to contribute to the philosophical thinking about public goods in three ways. First, highlighting an ambiguity in how the term “public good” is used, Section 2 proposes to distinguish between <i>inherently public goods</i>, which cohere to the economist's definition of a good that is non-rivalrous and non-excludable, and <i>contingently public goods</i>, which are non-rivalrous and, though in principle excludable, provided in a non-exclusionary form. Section 3 then draws on the notion of contingently public goods to develop two novel objections to a variety of benefit principles that have been proposed to govern the allocation of burdens and benefits in the provision of public goods. These principles are generally offered as complements to theories of distributive justice and aim to take care of an alleged blind spot resulting from the possibility of welfare gains from the provision of public good that are not required for initial conditions of justice. In engaging with these principles, the article operates at the level of ideal theory. It argues that because contingently public goods could also have been provided as club goods, the benefit principles, unless further qualified, demand unacceptable transfers to the wealthy as well as to people who object to their inclusive mode of provision. Section 4 then draws on the notion of contingently public goods to explore the potential of public goods in addressing existing social injustices. This section thus operates at the level of nonideal theory. It argues that providing public goods can be an alternative to transfer payments, or a universal basic income, in addressing injustices that are a result of economic inequality and that we have good reason to think that it can, at least at times, be more effective as well as politically more feasible. While this is true of public goods in general, several features set contingently public goods apart: they may at times be provided at little to no cost, their provision may require only more limited market interference (or even none), it can more powerfully express a commitment to status equality, and it may be particularly effective where injustices stem from unequal access to club goods.</p><p>This section argues that there is an important, though frequently overlooked ambiguity in how the term “public good” is used in philosophical discourse. While some authors require a good to be <i>in principle non-excludable</i> in order to qualify, others merely require it to be provided <i>in a non-exclusionary form</i>. While there are benefits to each terminological choice, the section argues, it is important to keep them apart. Accordingly, it proposes to distinguish between <i>inherently public goods</i> and <i>contingently public goods</i>. The later sections draw on the notion of a contingently public good, attempting to show how it can advance philosophical thinking about public goods in the context of ideal as well as nonideal theory.</p><p>Many philosophers have remained somewhat vague about how they understand the notion of public goods. For instance, Avigail Ferdman refers to what she calls the “standard economic understanding” according to which “public goods […] are material goods that the private market cannot provide efficiently” (2018, p. 662). Although she insists that there can also be nonmaterial public goods (2018, pp. 662–63), she otherwise relies on this characterization. Accordingly, public goods on her account constitute a market failure; but a market may fail to efficiently provide goods for various reasons and Ferdman does not specify which of these are defining of public goods. Even where explicit definitions have been put forward, however, they tend to be mutually inconsistent. The central rift is exemplified by the definitions proposed by Jonathan Anomaly (<span>2015</span>) and David Miller (<span>2004</span>).<sup>2</sup> Anomaly writes that “[g]oods are public if they exhibit <i>nonrivalry</i> and <i>nonexcludability</i>” (2015, p. 109, italics original), invoking the standard definition of economic theory, where a good is said to be <i>non-rivalrous</i> if its consumption by one person does not diminish its availability to others, and <i>non-excludable</i> if it is infeasible to exclude some people from consumption. By contrast, Miller writes that by public goods, “I shall mean goods that are made available to everyone without charge, and that each person can enjoy without diminishing the opportunity of others to enjoy the same good” (2004, pp. 127–28). Miller's notion of a public good encompasses Anomaly's but is broader: Miller's criterion that a goods is provided to everyone without charge may be fulfilled because of the good's inherent non-excludability (think of the view of the starry sky) or because of a deliberate choice to provide it for free (think of museums in England). As a result, they will not only classify certain goods differently, but will find different questions pertinent, and even sensible: while both may ask whether the state should provide <i>certain public goods</i>, only Miller can sensibly ask whether it should provide certain goods <i>as public goods</i>.</p><p>It is evident, then, that Anomaly and Miller are at risk of talking past each other, but less obvious which definition to prefer. Anomaly's definition fits with the classificatory scheme employed by economists, where public goods are contrasted with <i>private goods</i> (rivalrous, excludable; e.g., apples), <i>club goods</i> (non-rivalrous, excludable; e.g., pay-tv) and <i>common-pool goods</i> (rivalrous, non-excludable; e.g., fishing stocks). It also captures the market-failure aspect that Ferdman alludes to: since, by definition, no one can be excluded from the use of public goods, everyone has an incentive to contribute as little as possible. Due to this so-called <i>free-rider problem</i>, markets will not provide public goods at efficient levels.<sup>3</sup> In conflating what economists call “club goods” and “public goods,” Miller appears to give up a valuable distinction. For him, a library qualifies as a public good so long as access is <i>in fact</i> offered to everyone free of charge. But as private collections like the London Library prove, markets can provide libraries as club goods. Even club goods typically involve a market failure: unless perfect price-discrimination is feasible, markets will not provide club goods at efficient levels. But this market failure is more limited—because people can be excluded, a market can at least in principle provide these goods. At the same time, Miller's account better captures the ordinary use of the term “public good”. It seems neither uncommon, nor unreasonable to speak of parks as public goods—but while they are often freely accessible to everyone, it is, as London's Belgrave Square Garden demonstrates, possible to restrict access to those willing (and able) to purchase a key.</p><p>Because the definitions of a public good advanced by Miller and Anomaly each pick out important aspects, we have reason to preserve them both. But in order to avoid misunderstandings, we need to keep them distinct. To achieve this, I propose to distinguish between <i>inherently public goods</i> and <i>contingently public goods</i>.<sup>4</sup> More specifically, I propose to define an <i>inherently public good</i> (along Anomaly's lines) as a good that is (i) non-rivalrous and (ii) non-excludable and a <i>contingently public good</i> (in Millerian spirit) as a good that is (i) non-rivalrous and (ii) <i>as a matter of choice</i>, provided in a non-exclusionary form. The qualifier “as a matter of choice” is important because in so far as inherently public goods are non-excludable, they are necessarily provided in non-exclusionary form, so the mere condition that certain goods are provided to everyone for free fails to mark the distinction. As Miller does not add this qualification, his notion encompasses both types of public goods. Moreover, I understand the term “non-exclusionary form” broadly: while a good can be provided in a non-exclusionary form by making it accessible to everyone free of charge, it can also be so provided if there is a token charge, yet one that every person can easily afford.<sup>5</sup></p><p>The distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is important because it allows us to keep two things apart: the deliberate choice about the <i>mode of provision</i> of goods and the <i>market failure</i> resulting from the inability to exclude others. The distinction is close in spirit to, but not identical with, one that Vaughn Bryan Baltzly (<span>2021</span>) and Anomaly (<span>2021</span>) have recently drawn between <i>public goods</i> and <i>publicized goods</i>. For Baltzly, publicized goods are goods “whose ‘public’ character results only from a policy decision to make some (otherwise private) good freely and universally available” (2021, p. 376). Anomaly, discussing public health measures, characterizes as publicized “goods that are made public through the incentives created by government mandates” (2021, p. 2), where a good being public primarily means that its consumption imposes externalities on others (2021, p. 6). The notion of publicized goods, like that of contingently public goods, picks up on the fact that society can frequently decide whether to offer universal, free access to a specific good. Yet, unlike the notion of contingently public goods, it imposes no restriction on the extent to which a good is rivalrous. It is, for this reason, much broader: if a state provides apples for free, they become a publicized good, but not a contingently public good. As comes out in the discussion below, having the narrower, more precise term “contingently public goods” is valuable because it allows us to pick out those goods whose public provision promises efficiency gains.</p><p>The remainder of the article is an attempt to show that the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is valuable and that the importance of contingently public goods has been underappreciated. Three points should be noted at the outset though. First, the distinction is arguably better conceived of as demarcating a spectrum than a categorical divide: few goods are inherently non-excludable; instead, exclusion may be more or less costly. Second, whether some good is non-excludable, and for this reason inherently public, depends on the state of technology and may change<sup>6</sup>: if, in some dystopian future, people need to pay for access to biodomes, then clean air will have turned into a contingently public good. Finally, just as few goods are entirely non-rivalrous, few are non-excludable: the fact that I go for a run in the park does not diminish its availability, but if a crowd of people clogs pathways and occupies all picnic spots, this does diminish the park's availability (or value) to others—at the limit, the park becomes a rivalrous good. So, the criterion of non-rivalry should not be interpreted too strictly; instead, we may distinguish between public goods that are more pure or impure depending on their degree of rivalry—at a given level of consumption, or across a range of levels.</p><p>Note, moreover, that the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is orthogonal to several other distinctions that have been drawn within the debate on public goods. For example, Ferdman (2018) distinguishes between universal and nonuniversal public goods, where the former are valued by all whereas the latter are only valued by some. Even more prominently, some authors (see e.g., Claassen, <span>2013</span>; Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>) have drawn a distinction between essential (or necessary) and discretionary public goods, where the provision of the former, but not the latter, is required by justice.<sup>7</sup> But the fact that some good is an inherently public good (or a contingently public one) neither affects whether it is universal, nor whether it is essential.<sup>8</sup> This is explained by the fact that the classification of a good as inherently or contingently public is based merely on its structural properties, namely on whether it is excludable in principle or merely provided in a non-exclusionary form; but these structural properties evidently determine neither whether a good is valued by everyone, nor whether it is critical for justice.<sup>9</sup> So, the terminological distinction advocated here is new and independent of the existing ones. At the same time, the different specifications can of course be combined; we can, for example, have a contingently public goods that is essential and universal.</p><p>An important strand of the recent philosophical debate of public goods has operated at the level of ideal theory and has focused on the question of justice: according to which criteria should burdens and benefits of the provision of public goods be distributed to preserve conditions of justice (see e.g., Claassen, <span>2013</span>; Miller, <span>2004</span>; Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2001</span>)? This section puts forward two novel objections against the various benefit principles that have been proposed in response to this question. The <i>objection from unequal access to club goods</i> asserts that these benefit principles mandate unacceptable transfer payments to the privately wealthy. The <i>objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods</i> asserts that the benefit principles, unless qualified, mandate unacceptable transfer payments to people who disvalue their inclusive mode of provision. Both these objections draw on the case of contingently public goods: in each case, it is the possibility of providing the respective public goods as club goods that generates a problem. More specifically, these objections draw on a specific subset of contingently public goods: those whose provision is not directly required by justice (and which are therefore also discretionary in the sense further explored below).</p><p>The discussion of the demands of justice in the provision of public goods is motivated by two observations (see Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, esp. 562–64). On the one hand, there are some public goods that are required for justice. Consider the rule of law. Broadly understood as the effective restraint on arbitrary use of power through enforcement of legal rules and procedures, it qualifies as an (immaterial) public good. Moreover, it is presupposed by virtually all theories of justice: for what would be the point of allocating resources, if individuals were subject to the arbitrary exercise of power by others who could take them away (or impose physical harm)? On the other hand, there are goods whose provision is not required by justice, but generates a concern of justice: assuming an initially just society, how should the benefits and costs of their provision be allocated?<sup>10</sup> Goods of the former type, “whose provision is itself a matter of justice”, are typically called “essential public goods” (Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, p. 564) or “necessary public goods” (Claassen, <span>2013</span>, p. 273). Goods of the latter type, whose provision is not required by justice, are labeled “discretionary public goods” (Claassen, <span>2013</span>, p. 273; Miller &amp; Taylor, <span>2018</span>, p. 564).<sup>11</sup></p><p>Proponents of social theories of justice have not given much thought to discretionary public goods, and where they have considered them at all, they have typically endorsed procedural criteria.<sup>12</sup> John Rawls, for instance, initially stipulated that the state may provide (discretionary) public goods only “when they satisfy Wicksell's unanimity criterion” (1999, p. 248), which makes their legitimate provision dependent on everyone's consent to a proposal specifying (i) the good to be provided and (ii) the tax schedule to pay for it (Wicksell, <span>1958</span>). In his later work (Rawls, <span>2001</span>), Rawls came to relax the unanimity condition, proposing instead a simple majority vote.<sup>13</sup> As noted by Miller (<span>2004</span>), the problem with procedural approaches is that even if one thinks that they provide an account of <i>legitimacy</i>, they are silent on the question of <i>distributive justice</i>. But the surplus from the provision of discretionary public goods can be distributed in various ways—and not all appear (equally) just.</p><p>In light of the weaknesses of procedural accounts, some authors have advocated substantive criteria (Miller, <span>2004</span>; Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2001</span>). They propose to address the question of justice in the provision of public goods in two steps. First, we identify the set of essential public goods, whose provision is required by justice; for these goods, the distribution of costs is determined by our theory of justice. In a second step, we consider discretionary public goods, and it is at this stage that we need an additional principle to determine the distribution of costs and benefits. The most basic such principle is the <i>benefit principle</i>, which requires the provision of discretionary public goods to benefit everyone. But this principle is highly permissive; assuming self-interested voting, even the unanimity condition implies that the benefit principle is met. Two more restrictive principles have been advanced. Murphy and Nagel (<span>2001</span>) propose<sup>14</sup> that every person should contribute to the cost of providing discretionary public goods <i>in proportion</i> to the benefits she receives; call this the <i>proportional benefit principle</i>. Miller (<span>2004</span>) proposes that discretionary public goods should be provided so as to <i>equalize the net benefits</i> individuals receive; call this the <i>equal benefit principle</i>.</p><p>These principles have prompted objections. For example, Miller has criticized the proportional benefit principle as treating the state like an enterprise: insisting on contributions in proportion to benefits, he claims, contradicts the idea of a political community “whose foundational principle is that each member holds an equal stake” (2004, 144). Yet, Miller's equal benefit principle appears vulnerable to a related objection. In insisting on strictly equal benefits, one seems to adopt toward society the perspective of a jealous child. Among siblings, the equal benefit principle might have some bite: if one child does not like chocolate, but her brother does, she might insist that, if chocolates are the only sweets available, then, for reasons of justice, neither of them should get any. But at the level of society, insisting on a principle that prohibits the provision of public goods in circumstances where it would harm no one and benefit many seems to reveal a pathological insistence on an “equal share,” exposing a lack of generosity that can be expected toward fellow citizens. In addition, Miller and Taylor (<span>2018</span>, 568) have argued that the proportional benefit principle is incomplete. If two distinct sets of discretionary public goods satisfy the proportionality requirement, the principle does not tell us which one to choose.<sup>15</sup> Assuming that we aim to maximize benefits, the equal benefit principle avoids this problem. But it is highly restrictive in other regards: unless benefits can be equalized, a good cannot be provided, even if everyone were to benefit from it. As Miller and Taylor note (<span>2018</span>, 569), this appears to render the equal benefit principle vulnerable to a leveling-down objection (though transfer schemes might help address this problem).<sup>16</sup></p><p>Contingently public goods motivate two additional, and more fundamental objections, which apply to the various benefit principles simultaneously. First, there is the <i>objection from unequal access to club goods</i>: because contingently public goods are in principle exclusionary, they could be provided as club goods, but an unequal initial distribution of private resources implies unequal access to such club goods, which affects the distribution of benefits from their provision as public goods; as a result, the benefit principles mandate implausible transfers to the individually wealthy. This objection can be illustrated by reference to the case of a public swimming pool. A swimming pool that is accessible to everyone free of charge, or for a token fee, is an (impure) public good. We may initially think that all swimmers benefit from it. But suppose an individually wealthy swimmer argues that she does not benefit: because she is a member to a fitness club that offers pool access, she claims to gain nothing from a public pool. The proportional benefit principle, she holds, implies that she must contribute nothing, whereas the benefit principle and the equal benefit principle imply that she is even owed compensation.</p><p>Of course, how the public pool affects the wealthy swimmer depends on the exact specification of the case. If her sole motivation for purchasing membership to the club was to gain pool access, she can cancel her membership once the public pool has been built and her benefit is captured by the money saved on the club membership. As a result, she benefits from the public pool and has to contribute to its costs of provision. Even in this case, however, part of her benefit may escape accounting. For if she had been willing to pay more for the club membership than was required, she was able to secure a <i>surplus benefit</i> privately, and this surplus benefit does not count toward her benefit from access to the public pool. By contrast, the entire benefit from pool access is taken into account for those who initially lacked all pool access. But, one might argue, if the initial distribution was just, then this is fine: while part of the benefit the wealthy gain from public goods escapes accounting, it is the part they had already obtained from access to the club good—so, the provision of a public pool maintains but does not increase their advantage.</p><p>Next, however, consider a variation of the case. Suppose that the well-off swimmer decides not to use the public pool, but to keep her club membership. As she does not derive any benefit from the public pool, the equal benefit principle mandates a compensatory payment to the wealthy swimmer, provided there is a surplus benefit to building the public pool.<sup>17</sup> The proportional benefit principle similarly justifies compensation if the public pool disbenefits the wealthy swimmer. Suppose that, once the public pool is built, some club members leave the fitness club, prompting a fee hike. If a wealthy swimmer decides to maintain her club membership, for example because she sufficiently values the other benefits of membership, then the provision of the public pool generates a <i>disbenefit</i> to her. Even according to the proportional benefit principle, she should thus make a negative contribution to the costs of providing the public pool, that is, she is owed compensation.</p><p>These implications of the benefit principles appear puzzling. If an initial distribution of private goods is just, one might grant the well-off any benefit they obtain from purchasing club goods that are unaffordable to others. One might perhaps even accept that, if they prefer their respective club goods, they do not need to contribute to the costs of providing public goods. But it does not seem plausible to assign them claims to compensation. If a group of people is willing to carry <i>all costs</i> of making some good freely available <i>to everyone</i>, can they really be required to fund transfer payments to wealthy people who prefer to consume an equivalent club good, yet are not made any worse off? Now, it is important to be cautious here. If we make a judgment on whether some person can reasonably claim compensation in a particular case, this judgment will ultimately rest in part on our intuitions about this case (as well as our intuitions about relevant other cases, to which the systematic account that underpins our judgment extends). Since the argument here proceeds at the level of ideal theory, we need to ensure that we are not led astray by intuitions about nonideal cases. Perhaps, one might worry, we deem the claim to compensation unreasonable simply because, in the world we inhabit, it would be absurd to compensate those who are wealthy and already have access to club goods. But assuming an initially just allocation of private goods, might it not simply be correct that we need to compensate those who receive less benefit, or even a disbenefit, because they already had access to the relevant goods in the form of club goods?</p><p>In my view, even under ideal circumstances, the demand for compensation is not plausible. The difference between cases where some are exempt from contributing and cases where they deserve compensation can be drawn by reference to the market as an alternative mode of provision. If those who favor a given public good could secure it by coordinating in a market, then they could provide it privately—in this case, the person with access to a corresponding club good would make no contribution, but they would also not be compensated. So, the outcome of the first type of case—no contribution by those with access to club goods—aligns with the market outcome, whereas the outcome of the second type of case—compensation to those with existing access to club goods—diverges from the market outcome. Of course, the mere fact that the hypothetical market outcome would involve no compensation does not imply that this is the correct view in a case where the state provides a good: the demands on the state differ from those on private market participants. But the divergence to the market-based outcome indicates that compensation is harder to justify than non-contribution, and especially where it is owed for a relative lack of benefit rather than for an indirect harm (due to costlier club goods). Note, moreover, that the state's involvement in the provision of the respective public goods may here be quite minimal—the state may simply provide an enforcement mechanism that allows those individuals who consent to chip in to collectively provide a public good that is then available to everyone. At least in such a case, even under initial conditions of justice, admitting the demand for compensation would effectively allow the better off to leverage their initial advantage to secure settlements from the worse off even though they already shoulder the entire cost of the state's provision of goods that are valuable and accessible to everyone. But this does not appear just—and even if the initial advantage attained through greater access to club goods was just.</p><p>But suppose one were to reject this argument and insist that, because the state always must treat everyone equally, as soon as it gets involved in the provision of discretionary public goods, compensation is indeed owed. In this case, the argument from unequal access to club goods points to a more fundamental concern: relative to which baseline is equal treatment to be ensured? In addressing this concern, it is helpful to first summarize an insight by Claassen (<span>2013</span>). Claassen argues that Miller's equal benefit principle disadvantages people whose conception of the good life relies heavily on the consumption of public goods relative to market goods (2013, pp. 278–81). In a pure market economy, he notes, those who favor public goods find themselves at a disadvantage relative to those who favor market goods—few public goods are provided. But this disadvantage is preserved, if we introduce public goods, yet require that everyone benefits equally from their provision: for while everyone will now be better off, everyone will be <i>equally</i> better off, so relative positions remain unchanged. This casts doubt on the justifiability of the benchmark of a pure market economy. The objection from unequal access to club goods casts further doubt on this benchmark, but on different grounds. For it shows that, with a pure market economy as our starting point, part of the benefit that wealthier people obtain from the provision of contingently public goods escapes accounting—namely the part they had managed to already secure in a private market for club goods that serve as substitutes. The benchmark used by the benefit principles thus not only disadvantages those who prefer public goods, but also the less wealthy.</p><p>The argument from unequal access to club goods reveals that regardless of people's conceptions of the good life (and whether preferences for public goods qualify as constitutive of such conceptions), the extent to which one stands to reap net benefits from access to contingently public goods will, <i>ceteris paribus</i>, correlate negatively with one's initial wealth. This reveals the benefit principles to be implausible, as it shows that they demand highly regressive compensation in the context of public good provision. This line of argument aligns with Claassen's in casting doubt on the starting point endorsed by the benefit principles, but is distinct in three ways. First, whereas Claassen focuses on preferences for public versus market goods, the concern here are wealth inequalities: my argument contends that the starting point of a pure market society disadvantages some people regardless of their preferences, simply because the less wealthy stand to gain more from the provision of contingently public goods relative to a pure market economy, and the assumption of such an economy as our reference point therefore relatively disadvantages these people. Second, the argument put forward here draws explicitly on the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods: contingently public goods are those that could alternatively have been provided in a more exclusionary form as club goods, and it is the unequal initial access to such club goods that generates the implausibly regressive distributive demands of the benefit principles. Finally, Claassen draws a more modest conclusion: instead of rejecting the benefit principles, he only maintains that one could reasonably take a different view, advocating for what one could call a position of “meta-neutrality”: he proposes to remain neutral as to whether one should remain neutral toward individuals' preferences (and distribute resources across all market and public goods to equalize welfare levels) or whether one should remain neutral toward individuals' preferences against the backdrop of a pure market society (and thus endorse the equal benefit principle).<sup>18</sup> By contrast, my claim is stronger: it is that, at least given their benchmark of a pure market economy, the proposed benefit principles are implausible because they demand highly regressive compensation payments for the provision of contingently public goods.</p><p>In addition, there is an <i>objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods</i>: the benefit principles, implausibly, mandate compensation to people who disvalue the provision of contingently public goods merely because they disvalue their inclusive <i>mode of provision</i>. As Claassen's argument summarized above reveals, the assumption of neutrality toward individual preferences concerning the provision of discretionary public goods is not as innocent as is generally presumed. But while Claassen presents the question about the preference for market versus public goods as being primarily about <i>which goods</i> are provided, in the case of contingently public goods, we need to distinguish between the specific <i>good provided</i> (e.g., a park) and its <i>mode of provision</i> (as a public good or a club good). We need to draw this distinction because a market could provide such goods as club goods; and the distinction matters because people can value a good itself as well as its mode of provision. Ferdman (2018, pp. 666–67) notes this possibility of <i>intrinsically valuing</i> public goods: a person may value a good, like a public park, for its universal accessibility. The person who intrinsically values public parks would, <i>ceteris paribus</i>, prefer a public park to a private park to which she, but not everyone else, had access.<sup>19</sup> But there is also the corresponding possibility of <i>intrinsically disvaluing</i> public goods: just as one can value public goods because of their mode of provision, so one can disvalue them due to their inclusive mode of provision. And this attitude is not just a theoretical possibility: in racist societies, people have historically objected to the provision of public goods, like beaches, public transportation, and libraries, on the ground that such goods should not be equally available to everyone.</p><p>The possibility of intrinsically disvaluing public goods gives rise to a challenge to the benefit principles, but its precise form depends on one's interpretation of the principle of neutrality that underpins them. The benefit principles are embedded in a liberal framework, which demands neutrality toward the preferences of citizens. The proponents of the benefit principles do not qualify, nor further discuss, the underlying notion of neutrality. According to a literal interpretation, (i) neutrality demands that one be neutral toward all preferences unless explicitly specified otherwise. On this interpretation, the possibility of an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods generates an objection. Consider person <i>A</i>, living in a class-based society, who deems herself a member of the upper class, and objects to the provision of public parks on the sole ground that their universal accessibility fails to respect a status distinction among members of different classes. Moreover, suppose that <i>A</i> is an indoors person, who enters neither public, nor private parks, and would never have learned of the public parks had she not read about it in her upper-class gazette. In this case, <i>A</i>'s, preference against public provision contradicts the spirit of the political community, negating a basic understanding of others <i>as equals</i>. It is for this reason that I believe it would not warrant consideration: <i>A</i> could not reasonably demand compensation for the disbenefit the provision of public parks imposes on her. But this shows that the benefit principles must be qualified: their statement needs to expressly exclude some instances of intrinsic disvaluation of public goods.</p><p>However, at this point, one might interject that the principle of neutrality could also be interpreted differently. Indeed, its literal, unqualified interpretation may be deemed naïve: it requires remaining neutral regarding all preferences, including immoral ones. Although this is not explicitly stated, one might therefore insist, proponents of the benefit principles implicitly assume that at least some immoral preferences be excluded from consideration. But if one adopts this view, then one might respond that the above example is moralized and therefore needs to be rejected: <i>A</i>'s preference not to have parks as public goods is immoral because it is based on immoral classist preferences; therefore, the principle of neutrality does not apply here, so <i>A</i>'s preference does not warrant compensation, and no problem arises for the benefit principles. This response prompts the question: can we find a non-moralized example, which is not excluded by the principle of neutrality, but where a person's intrinsic disvaluation of a public good does not warrant compensation?</p><p>In addressing this question, note first that while the claim that the principle of neutrality should not include immoral preferences rules out its literal interpretation (i), it does not entail a specific alternative. Instead, it is consistent with at least three different interpretations of the principle: (ii) it demands neutrality toward all preferences except for a set implicitly put aside as immoral; (iii) it demands neutrality toward all preferences bar those that are in fact immoral; (iv) it stipulates that a preference is immoral if and only we need not remain neutral toward it. Now, on interpretation (iv), a non-moralized example is ruled out by definition. This is because (iv) stipulates that, whenever we should not remain neutral toward a preference, then this preference is to count as immoral. It follows, by definition, that when we should not compensate a person for intrinsically disvaluing a public good (i.e., should not be neutral), then this preference is immoral—so, there can be no non-moralized example. In this way, interpretation (iv) rules out any objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods. But this comes at a high cost. If interpreted in this way, the principle of neutrality makes a conceptual, rather than a substantial claim. This not only renders it uninformative: nothing is said about how extensive the set of immoral preferences is, nor why we should not be neutral toward them. More importantly, it turns the order of explanation upside down: the claim no longer is that we should not remain neutral toward a preference because it is immoral, but instead that a preference qualifies as immoral because we should not remain neutral toward it. In my view, this implication renders implausible the interpretation of the principle of neutrality as making a conceptual claim. But note that, even if one were to insist on interpretation (iv), the above argument about <i>A</i>'s intrinsic disvaluation of public parks would be of some value: it would identify a specific type of preference with regard to which we should not remain neutral and provide reasons as why.</p><p>By contrast, interpretations (ii) and (iii), which make a substantial claim, allow for the possibility of a non-moralized example. I believe that such an example can be given. Consider <i>B</i>, who lives in an egalitarian republic. <i>B</i>, too, is an indoors person, who never uses parks. Still, she dislikes parks being provided as public goods because she dislikes universal accessibility. This is not due to classist or racist views; it just so happens that <i>B</i> prefers for goods to be privately rather than publicly available. <i>B</i>'s case thus differs from <i>A</i>'s: <i>B</i>'s intrinsic disvaluation of public parks is not based on any other morally tainted preferences or beliefs. <i>B</i> does not object to the public provision because it would fail to respect a status difference; she simply has a preference for private goods. This preference on its own, I contend, is too innocent to qualify as immoral; it is a preference that does not express any disrespect toward, or repugnant views about, other people. But at the same time, and like in the case of <i>A</i>, <i>B</i>'s intrinsic disvaluation of the public goods it is not a preference that warrants consideration when assessing the benefits and damages from the provision of public parks. This is because <i>B</i>'s preference not to have parks as public goods is not well-motivated: by assumption, <i>B</i> does not intend to use the parks, so whether they are publicly accessible is of no relevance to <i>B</i>'s ability to enjoy them (or any other goods), and <i>B</i> therefore suffers no meaningful harm from their provision as public goods. In assessing benefits, we need to take into consideration that, as an indoors person, <i>B</i> fails to benefit from the provision of public parks, but not that <i>B</i> disvalues their mode of provision.</p><p>If this line of argument is correct, then <i>B</i>'s case qualifies as a non-moralized example, which shows that, according to the qualified interpretations (ii) and (iii) of the principle of neutrality, the benefit principles must be restricted: at least sometimes, disbenefits that result from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods should be disregarded. Yet, even if one were to dispute this by insisting that <i>B</i>'s preference is immoral or that <i>B</i> has a claim to compensation, my argument would still highlight the need for proponents of benefit principles to address the following question: under which conditions is an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods an immoral preference that may thus be ignored, and why? This is a serious question, because the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods does not always appear to be immoral: vulnerable groups and minorities for instance arguably have good reason to demand spaces which are not accessible to everyone. It is less evident whether an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods could be justified if one never intends to use the respective good, however, or would not notice its use by others: may a religious group justifiably object to some mountain's universal accessibility because they consider it sacred, even if they would never notice if anyone else were to go there?</p><p>If sound, then the two objections put forward in this section have two implications. At the substantial level, they show that the existing benefit principles, which have been proposed to complement existing theories of justice to account for discretionary public goods, are deficient in ways that have so far escaped notice. At the theoretical level, they reveal the importance of taking account of contingently public goods in examining the demands of justice in the provision of discretionary public goods. This is because neither of the objections put forward in this section could have been raised with equal effect by reference to inherently public goods. Inherently public goods could not alternatively have been provided as club goods (though imperfect substitutes might), so concerns about unequal access to these goods in a market do not arise in their case (or, at least, not in exactly the same way). And because these goods are, by definition, non-excludable, it would be incoherent to welcome the good itself, yet object to its inclusive mode of provision.</p><p>But the two objections also indicate a more constructive task, namely, to specify the benefit principle one should adopt instead.<sup>20</sup> While the arguments put forward imply two conditions that an alternative benefit principle would have to meet, they do not yield comprehensive specification of such a principle. The two conditions they imply are as follows: first, the principle must be “club-good sensitive,” that is, it needs to specify under which conditions those who already had access to a club good that is then provided as a public good lack a claim to compensation; second, it must qualify the demand for neutrality, or more specifically, it needs to specify under which conditions preferences against public goods may or must be disregarded. But these two conditions can evidently be satisfied in numerous ways, and the above arguments do not yield any specific principle. Regarding club goods, for example, I have argued that those who had access to a club good cannot plausibly demand compensation for the provision of corresponding public good, if this provision does not make them worse off; but this leaves undetermined whether they can claim compensation if the provision in fact does make them worse off, and how much they must contribute if they benefit, but less so than everyone else. Meanwhile, regarding the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods, I have only argued that it <i>sometimes</i> cannot ground a claim to compensation, while admitting that it may in certain other contexts.</p><p>There are three reasons for which I refrain from attempting to defend any alternative principle here. First, I believe that good reasons can be put forward in favor of the equal as well as the proportional benefit principle (and perhaps also in favor of intermediary ones), so it is not evident which baseline to choose. But defending a specific view within this debate would divert from the article's argumentative trajectory. Second, I believe that one can reasonably disagree on how exactly the two conditions identified above should be met. In particular, as noted above, it does not appear obvious under exactly which conditions one may be justified in objecting to the inclusive mode of provision of contingently public goods. Finally, while relevant, the task of specifying an alternative is not critical to the aim of this article: it is not needed to show that contingently public goods are a neglected subset of public goods that is of relevance to the philosophical debate.</p><p>The preceding section has operated at the level of ideal theory, raising objections to principles that have been proposed to govern the provision of public goods in the context of an initially just society. In the actual world, circumstances are less favorable: we confront the provision of public goods against a background of numerous social injustices. In addition to injustices in the distribution of private resources, there are other types of social injustices, like unwarranted inequalities in opportunity and status. This section therefore moves on to discuss the provision of public goods under initially unjust or imperfectly just conditions. In so doing, part of its argument applies to public goods in general, while part of it applies specifically to contingently public goods. The central claim about public goods in general is that their provision holds the potential to render economic inequalities less relevant and to reduce inequalities in opportunity by reducing the importance of access to private resources, and that this can at times be an attractive alternative to other, transfer-based policies. Evidently, the provision of public goods will not always have this effect: it could instead even exacerbate existing injustices, as would happen, for instance, in an unjustly inegalitarian society where expensive, tax-funded public goods cater exclusively to the interests of the rich.<sup>21</sup> With regard to contingently public goods more specifically, the section claims that they hold a distinctive, fourfold potential which arises from the fact that they in principle allow exclusion and could have been provided in the form of club goods. First, because it can be possible to provide a contingently public good simply by removing restrictions on access to an existing club good, it can be especially efficient at addressing injustices. Moreover, and relatedly, because their provision can at times be costless, contingently public goods can, at least under certain conditions, avoid the standard objection of involving a market interference. Third, because contingently public goods could have been provided as exclusionary club goods, their public mode of provision can be an especially powerful expression of a commitment to inclusiveness, which is critical where status inequalities are of concern. Finally, the provision of contingently public goods has a special potential to undermine the relevance of club goods, and to thereby remove a critical barrier to equality of opportunity.</p><p>In making the case that public goods have the potential to rectify injustices, I begin by considering injustices that are the result of economic inequality. Of course, not all economic inequalities are injustices; some reflect inequalities in desert or are otherwise justified (in fact, economic equality could reflect an injustice). The following arguments therefore apply only to inequalities that in fact amount to injustices. Economic inequality is typically measured by the inequality in personal income, or earning power, and wealth. Prominent measures, like the Gini coefficient, illustrate this. The Gini coefficient is an aggregate measure of the extent of economic inequality, and it is typically computed for the distribution of wealth and for the distribution of income. It can also be used to assess the extent to which redistributive measures like taxation and social subsidies affect income inequality. While important, measures like the Gini coefficient are in an important sense incomplete. They fail to capture how important ownership of private material resources is in the first place. But the importance of ownership of private resources may vary significantly. In a society where all lakeshores are privatized, individuals need private resources that enable them to purchase access if they want to swim in a lake. In a society where lakes are publicly accessible, private resources are not required for this purpose. This point generalizes: societies can be set up in ways that render the possession of private material resources more important or less. One critical factor determining the importance of ownership of private resources is the extent to which a society provides public goods. While there appears to be no straightforward way of quantifying, for a given society, the importance of ownership of private resources or the extent of the provision of public goods, both are significant concerns. Conceiving of economic inequality exclusively in terms of the distribution of private resources therefore ignores the extent to which ownership of such resources is necessary for access to valuable goods. But it appears sensible to be concerned with economic inequality not simply in the sense of being concerned about the distribution of income and wealth, but rather in the sense of being concerned about differences in what people are able to do, given the current distribution of income and wealth.</p><p>These considerations reveal that the provision of public goods can be a means to indirectly address inequalities in income and wealth—by reducing their relevance. But not merely can they be a means to do so: it appears plausible that their outright provision is, at least sometimes, more efficient, and politically more feasible, than the redistribution of private resources. There is an economic rationale for why it may be more efficient. In so far as public goods are non-rivalrous (or imperfectly rivalrous), their consumption by some does not (or does not significantly) diminish their availability for consumption by others. This means that providing a good as a contingently public good rather than as a club good typically comes with efficiency gains—it increases accessibility at no additional cost. If we are, concerned with economic inequality because of the resulting differences in what people can do given the economic resources they have, then the provision of public goods may thus be more effective: it may be possible to achieve greater progress toward economic equality for any given level of taxation. In addition, and relatedly, there is a political rationale for why addressing economic inequalities by providing public goods may be practically more feasible. In so far as the public good is available to all, and therefore potentially benefits everyone, the wealthy may be more willing to pay taxes for its direct provision than to finance targeted transfer payments to the less well-off. As Kohn notes, “[u]niversal benefits tend to have higher levels of political support than means-tested programs” (2020, p. 9).</p><p>While this argument holds for public goods quite generally, contingently public goods promise to be particularly efficient at achieving this. For because corresponding club goods may already exist, it may be possible to turn a club good into a contingently public good at effectively no cost, thereby increasing access without making anyone worse off. For the purpose of illustration, consider a company operating a pay-tv channel in a society experiencing high levels of economic inequality. Suppose that this company cannot use price discrimination, so it attempts to set its universal subscription rate at the profit-maximizing price. As a result, there will be some people who would value access to the channel, but do not subscribe, either because they do not value it sufficiently or because they simply lack the means to pay for the subscription.<sup>22</sup> If the channel could be made accessible to everyone at no additional cost, then transforming it into a contingently public good promises efficiency gains. Moreover, if those willing to subscribe can be taxed at the current subscription rate, then doing so would not make anyone worse off. Now picture a society where economic inequality is of concern primarily because it results in unequal access to pay-tv. In this case, the best way for the state to address economic inequality may be to pay a lump sum subsidy to the tv-channel if it makes the program available to everyone. This ensures universal access and it may do so in a more efficient way than redistributive transfer payments could. Moreover, it may be more feasible as even existing subscribers may not object to being taxed at the current subscription rate to pay for universal access.</p><p>Of course, this scenario is schematic and avoids important complications. In all likelihood, it will not be possible to tax exactly those who would otherwise subscribe to a channel, so using general tax revenue may force some to contribute to goods they would prefer not to be provided. Moreover, subsidies eliminate the need for tv-channels to convince customers to subscribe by providing desired content. This highlights that, once we consider specific contingently public goods, we must weigh the benefits and disbenefits of providing these goods <i>as public goods</i>. The public provision of goods will be justifiable, on the basis of concerns about economic equality, only where access is sufficiently central to our concerns about economic inequality. In this regard, public libraries are arguably a more compelling case because economic inequalities are of greater concern if they limit access to education than if they limit access to pay-tv.<sup>23</sup> At the same time, building libraries that offer free and universal access instead of relying on transfer payments to ensure that everyone is in a position to become a patron at a private library may well be the more economically efficient and the more feasible choice politically. But regardless of one's view about specific cases, the general point holds: sometimes, the provision of contingently public goods can help address economic inequalities in an effective and targeted (if perhaps partial) way.</p><p>Moreover, and this is a second feature that sets contingently public goods apart, they can at times escape the standard objection that the provision of public goods always needs justification because it requires taxation. Advocates and opponents of public goods alike typically suggest that unless we are in the fortunate position where their provision can be secured through assurance contracts or is financed by charities, it requires a state to tax firms or individuals to then use these funds to provide the goods (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Schmidtz, <span>1991</span>). It is for this reason that it is typically the provision of public goods that is taken to require justification. Even those (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>) who argue in favor of the provision of an extensive set of public goods implicitly accept that it is the provision of public goods that needs to be justified and offer such justifications. But there are at least two alternative ways in which a state can secure the provision of contingently public goods. First, where a non-rivalrous good already exists in the form of a club good, but some are excluded based on noneconomic criteria like gender, the state can issue regulations that prohibit such grounds of exclusion, thereby enlarging access and turning the good into a public good. Consider a privately run swimming pool, which is the only one far and near. If this pool excludes a specific group based on noneconomic criteria (e.g., men or persons of Asian descent), then we have a club good. Now, suppose the state introduces regulation prohibiting exclusion on such grounds and that the fee charged by the pool is small enough to effectively ensure universal access. In this case, the swimming pool (or, more precisely, pool access), has turned from a club good into a public good. Such a solution will not be available for all contingently public goods. Yet, it shows that at least sometimes, the state can ensure the provision of a public good without directly providing it, namely be prohibiting certain grounds of exclusion. Doing so does not require any state expenditure and consequently no taxation, though one might insist that issuing such regulation still amounst to a form of market interference.</p><p>In addition, whether certain contingently public goods are provided may directly depend on the initial allocation and specification of property rights. Public lands, such as woods, lakes, and plains, have a public good character: being accessible to everyone, they offer opportunities for recreation. But the decision to assign private property rights in these lands precedes the existence of a market, so it does not constitute a market interference. Moreover, a public good character can be preserved even for private goods if property rights are restricted in ways that grant everyone access. In the Nordic countries, the “right to roam” has existed for centuries, whereas private landowners in England and the United States have enjoyed much greater discretion in excluding others. Contingently public goods thus indicate that not all decisions on the provision of public goods amount to a market interference—some simply concern the market's set-up. Of course, this point holds most immediately at a rather abstract level: in the world we live in, property rights in most assets (though not in all, note for instance the oceans and outer space) have already been assigned, so any change to these property rights amounts to a form of market interference. Still, the fact that the initial decision to assign a particular set of property rights to specific assets affected the availability of contingently public goods provides at least a principled justification for such an interference: because the initial decision, which did not precede the market's existence, simultaneously determined the availability of public goods, amending existing property right claims is easier to justify (provided adequate compensation is offered where applicable).</p><p>While economic inequalities can constitute one sort of social injustice, social injustices can take other forms as well. In fact, the proposal to address economic inequalities through the provision of public goods presupposes that these inequalities are a concern primarily because they result in inequalities of opportunity and access: the provision of contingently public goods may leave existing inequalities in the ownership of private resources unchanged yet ensure greater equality of opportunity and access by offering an alternative to market consumption. And while inequalities in opportunity, access, and status may arise from economic ones, they need not. The case of a private country club illustrates this. Typically, such clubs charge hefty membership fees, which effectively exclude those who are not wealthy. But there can also be other grounds for exclusion. Historically, membership to country clubs has frequently been restricted on the basis of gender and race. Such restrictions are in one sense correlated with access money: if those excluded had the means to establish their own clubs, their lack of access could be alleviated. But at least from the perspective of the individual, it may well be the case that their exclusion is due to their gender or race rather than due to a lack of personal wealth.</p><p>This points to two additional ways in which contingently public goods hold a distinctive potential for addressing injustices. Where some members of society are deprived of access and thereby of opportunity and status on nonmaterial grounds, public goods can offer respite in two ways. First, in so far as public goods are freely available to all, they directly provide a shared realm of experience and social interaction and thereby constitute what Kallhoff calls “connectivity goods” (2014, pp. 642–44)—goods that not only enlarge access, but constitute a point of interaction and symbolize the commitment to shared space and equality. This is true not only, but especially of contingently public ones: because contingently public goods could have been provided in an exclusionary form, their public provision is a more decisive expression of this commitment to equality. In a society where status inequalities are a concern—think, for example, of a state with a strong divide among castes or ethnicities or religious groups—the provision of a contingently public good can be of great symbolic significance: due to the deliberate mode of its universally accessible mode of provision, it can be a powerful expression of a commitment to the equality of all citizens (and in a way not quite achievable with an inherently public good, which could not have been provided in a more exclusive form).</p><p>Second, and more indirectly, the provision of public goods tends to undermine the market's more exclusive modes of provision, and thereby the relevance of club goods in particular. Again, this is true of all public goods, but in particular of contingently public goods, because their provision can more directly diminish the attractiveness of the club goods to which they correspond. Our earlier example of the swimming pool illustrates this: once a public pool exists, people have less incentive to pay for access to private pools. In this sense, contingently public goods have the tendency to crowd out the corresponding club goods. This point is rarely highlighted, but important: the most promising long-term strategy for addressing inequalities of access that are the result of powerful structures of private clubs may consist in the provision of corresponding public goods that serve as substitutes. In this way, contingently public goods can gradually break the appeal and thereby the power of the more exclusive, private institutions, thereby reducing the inequality in access, and thus the inequalities in opportunity and perceived status it gives rise to.</p><p>If this examination is sound, then public goods—and contingently public goods in particular—constitute a natural, but underappreciated focal point for effectively rectifying existing injustices. Specifically, it appears plausible that the provision of contingently public good is a superior alternative to the introduction of a universal basic income (UBI) in at least certain contexts. Although a UBI has been advocated on various grounds, ranging from the justified claims of individuals to their share of the fruits of natural and social resources (see e.g., Van Parijs <span>1991</span>, pp. 130–31) to its ability to address existing gender and racial injustices (see Bidadanure, <span>2019</span>, pp. 492–95), it always aims to redistribute <i>private resources</i> relative to the status quo. There are, as indicated above, good reasons to believe that the provision of public goods can be the economically more efficient and politically more feasible policy. This will be the case, for instance, when non-rivalrous goods already exist in form of club goods and access can be universalized at little additional cost. It might also be the case where we can slightly amend private property rights, for instance in land, to ensure that some public good is provided. Moreover, where we confront injustices that are not due to inequalities in material resources, but rules and norms that exclude individuals from participating on equal terms, only the provision of contingently public goods, but not that of a UBI, may be able to rectify them—by effectively enlarging access and by creating a shared realm of interaction.<sup>24</sup></p><p>This leaves us with a question: under what circumstances ought the state address injustices by providing public goods and when should it resort to other, redistributive measures? Or, more generally, which principles determine what sorts of public goods the state ought to provide? This article does not aim to provide any comprehensive answer to these questions, and for two reasons. On the one hand, the normative question whether a state ought to provide a particular public good must always be evaluated against the current social background conditions. For instance, whether a state ought to provide free sports grounds or ought to take redistributive measures to address an inequality in access to recreational facilities will depend on numerous factors, such as the costs of provision, the availability of information on individual preferences regarding types of sports grounds and the availability of alternative means of provision. So, in any particular case, a specific argument needs to be put forward in favor of the provision of contingently public goods. On the other hand, the account leaves open how different considerations are to be weighed: it remains silent, for instance, on how important economic efficiency is compared to equal access, and on how much weight attaches to the value of solidarity. Instead of providing a normative theory of public goods, this section primarily aims to highlight the potential of public goods to rectify existing injustices—and that this potential is especially pronounced in the case of contingently public goods. The account is thus open-ended, allowing proponents of specific views of the value of public goods and the criteria for injustice to draw on it in evaluating whether, according to them, a given public good ought to be provided.</p><p>The potential to rectify existing injustices provides at least a <i>pro tanto</i> justification for the provision of some contingently public goods—and it does so even if this provision is not currently favored by everyone or is not favored by the sum of individual preferences (regardless of how they are to be aggregated). This injustice-based justification of contingently public goods is distinct from the perfectionist justifications that have been advocated elsewhere. It has for instance been argued (compellingly in my view) that public goods can help create conditions of a good life by curbing harmful competition for scarce resources (Ferdman, 2018, p. 670; see also Hussain, <span>2018</span>) and that they can contribute to a shared feeling of purpose, thereby strengthening “a sense of solidarity” (Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>, p. 641), and that these benefits support an argument against state-neutrality and can justify the state provision of public goods. The argument put forward here is more modest: it claims that the provision of public goods may be justified by their ability to address existing social injustices, rather than by some independently valuable objective. This is not to say that there is no link: it seems reasonable, for example, to believe that a greater sense of solidarity will prevent certain social injustices from arising in the first place. But the focus differs: the <i>pro tanto</i> justification for public goods that has been proposed here appeals directly to their ability to rectify existing injustices. This, it seems reasonable to think, should make the argument less controversial because the existence of injustices provides a stronger case for action than more perfectionist proposals.</p><p>This article falls in line with several recent attempts (de Jongh, <span>2022</span>; Ferdman &amp; Kohn <span>2018</span>; Judt, <span>2010</span>; Kallhoff, <span>2014</span>; Kohn, <span>2020</span>) to reassess the role of public goods for a well-ordered society and to elevate them to a more prominent place in political thinking. In response to an ambiguity in how philosophers use the term “public good,” this article has proposed, in Section 2, to draw a distinction between inherently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and non-excludable, and contingently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and, as a matter of choice, provided in a non-exclusionary form. Sections 3 and 4 drew on this distinction to show how the category of contingently public goods is fruitful to philosophical debate. As Section 3 argued, contingently public goods pose a challenge to the various benefit principles that have been proposed to govern the distribution of costs and benefits in the provision of public goods. Because these goods could alternatively be provided in the form of exclusionary club goods, the proposed benefit principles mandate unreasonable transfer payments to the individually wealthy as well as to those who disvalue the public goods' inclusive mode of provision. As Section 4 argued, contingently public goods at the same time provide a natural, yet underappreciated focal point for addressing unwarranted economic inequalities, as well as inequalities in opportunity, access, and status, and thus for rectifying social injustices. Because public goods are equally accessible to everyone, they render the ownership of private resources less important, thereby diminishing the relevance of inequalities in income and wealth and broadening opportunity and access. Contingently public goods are special in four regards: their provision may be costless; it may not require any market interference; it holds the potential to be a particularly powerful expression of everyone's equal status; and it holds a particular potential to undermine the relevance of exclusionary club goods.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46756,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"volume\":\"56 2\",\"pages\":\"202-222\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-03-21\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12516\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12516\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12516","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

公共产品最近受到了哲学家们越来越多的关注。除了研究公共物品概念的历史起源(Desmarais-Tremblay, 2017)、它们与特定政治理论家的思想的相关性(de Jongh, 2022)和特定公共物品(如艺术)的正当性(Kessler, 2018)之外,还有一些系统的尝试来发展公共物品的规范理论(见e.g., Kallhoff, 2011;米勒,2004)。如果要问国家应该提供哪些公共产品,以及提供这些产品的利益和负担应该如何分配,这些贡献大致可以分为两大阵营。一组作者在政治自由主义范围内解决了这些问题,仍然致力于国家中立的原则。通过将个人偏好视为给定,他们注意到许多公共产品承诺净效率收益,并询问应该根据什么原则分配这些收益(例如,Claassen, 2013;Cullity, 2008;墨菲,内格尔,2001)。在这样做的过程中,他们认为自己是对现有的正义理论的补充,这些理论在公共产品的成本和收益分配方面大多保持沉默(Miller &;Taylor, 2018,第556页)。另一组作者已经超越了国家中立原则,提出了支持国家提供公共产品的论点,这些公共产品至少在一定程度上独立于个人偏好,例如它们有可能促进团结和连接人们(参见e.g., Ferdman, 2018;Kallhoff, 2014;科恩,2020)。这些作者认为,公共产品的社会价值仍然没有得到充分的重视,即使这样做不会带来效率的提高,国家也可能有理由提供它们,并拒绝将效率作为判断提供公共产品是否合理的中心标准的观点。这种哲学上的兴趣与对公共产品的更广泛的忽视相吻合,这是记者和公共知识分子所表达的,特别是在英国和美国(Irvin, 2012;朱蒂,2010;莱勒,2020)。然而,尽管最近的关注激增,哲学,更普遍地说,“关于公共产品的学术文献相对较少”(Kohn, 2020,第2页)。本文旨在以三种方式为公共产品的哲学思考做出贡献。首先,第2节强调了“公共产品”一词如何使用的模糊性,建议区分固有公共产品和偶然公共产品,前者符合经济学家对非竞争性和非排他性商品的定义,后者是非竞争性的,尽管原则上是可排他性的,但以非排他性形式提供。然后,第3节利用偶然公共产品的概念,对各种利益原则提出了两种新的反对意见,这些原则被提议用于管理公共产品提供中的负担和利益的分配。这些原则通常是作为分配正义理论的补充而提出的,旨在解决所谓的盲点,这种盲点是由于提供公共利益可能带来的福利收益,而这些福利不是正义的初始条件所必需的。在运用这些原则时,这篇文章是在理想理论的层面上运作的。它认为,由于公共物品偶尔也可以作为俱乐部物品提供,除非有进一步的限定,否则利益原则要求向富人和反对其包容性提供模式的人转移,这是不可接受的。然后,第4节利用偶然公共产品的概念来探索公共产品在解决现有社会不公正方面的潜力。因此,本节在非理想理论的水平上进行操作。它认为,在解决经济不平等造成的不公正问题方面,提供公共产品可以作为转移支付或普遍基本收入的替代方案,我们有充分的理由认为,至少在某些时候,它可以更有效,在政治上也更可行。虽然这对一般的公共产品来说是正确的,但有几个特征将偶然公共产品区分开来:它们有时可能以很少或没有成本的方式提供,它们的提供可能只需要更有限的市场干预(甚至没有),它可以更有力地表达对地位平等的承诺,它可能特别有效,当不公正源于对俱乐部产品的不平等获取。本节认为,在哲学话语中如何使用“公共利益”一词,存在一个重要的、但经常被忽视的歧义。虽然一些作者要求商品在原则上不可排他性才能符合资格,但其他作者仅要求以非排他性形式提供商品。本节认为,尽管每种术语的选择都有好处,但重要的是要将它们分开。 例如,关于俱乐部物品,我认为,那些获得俱乐部物品的人不能合理地要求赔偿相应的公共物品的提供,如果这种提供没有使他们的情况更糟;但是,如果该条款实际上使他们的境况更糟,他们是否可以要求赔偿,以及如果他们受益,但比其他人少,他们必须贡献多少,这些都是不确定的。与此同时,关于公共产品的内在贬值,我只是认为它有时不能作为索赔的基础,同时承认在某些其他情况下可能是这样。出于三个原因,我不想在这里为任何其他原则辩护。首先,我认为有充分的理由支持平等和比例利益原则(也许也支持中间利益原则),因此选择哪个基线并不明显。但在这场辩论中捍卫一个特定的观点会偏离文章的论证轨迹。其次,我认为人们可以合理地不同意上述两个条件究竟应该如何满足。特别是,如上所述,究竟在哪些条件下,人们有理由反对提供偶然公共产品的包容性模式,这一点似乎并不明显。最后,虽然相关,但指定替代方案的任务对本文的目的并不重要:不需要表明偶然公共产品是与哲学辩论相关的公共产品的一个被忽视的子集。前一节在理想理论的层面上运作,对在最初公正的社会背景下管理公共产品提供的原则提出了反对意见。在现实世界中,情况就不那么有利了:我们在众多社会不公正的背景下提供公共产品。除了私人资源分配方面的不公正之外,还有其他类型的社会不公正,例如机会和地位方面的无理不平等。因此,本节继续讨论在最初不公正或不完全公正的条件下提供公共产品。在这样做的过程中,它的部分论点适用于一般的公共产品,而部分适用于偶然的公共产品。一般来说,关于公共产品的核心主张是,提供公共产品有可能使经济不平等变得不那么重要,并通过降低获得私人资源的重要性来减少机会不平等,这有时可能是其他以转移为基础的政策的一个有吸引力的替代方案。显然,公共品的提供并不总是有这种效果:相反,它甚至会加剧现有的不公正,例如,在一个不公正的不平等的社会中,昂贵的、由税收资助的公共品专门迎合富人的利益更具体地说,关于偶然的公共物品,本节声称它们具有独特的四倍潜力,这是因为它们原则上允许排除,并且可以以俱乐部物品的形式提供。首先,由于仅仅通过取消对获取现有俱乐部产品的限制就有可能提供偶然的公共产品,因此它在解决不公正问题方面可能特别有效。此外,与此相关的是,由于公共产品的提供有时可以是无成本的,因此,至少在某些条件下,偶然的公共产品可以避免涉及市场干预的标准反对意见。第三,由于偶然的公共产品可以作为排他性的俱乐部产品提供,它们的公共提供模式可以特别有力地表达对包容性的承诺,这在关注地位不平等的地方是至关重要的。最后,偶然公共产品的提供有一种特殊的潜力,可以破坏俱乐部产品的相关性,从而消除机会平等的一个关键障碍。为了证明公共产品有可能纠正不公正,我首先考虑了由经济不平等造成的不公正。当然,并非所有的经济不平等都是不公正的;有些反映了沙漠中的不平等,或者在其他方面是合理的(事实上,经济平等可能反映了不公正)。因此,以下论点只适用于实际上构成不公正的不平等。经济不平等通常是通过个人收入或赚钱能力和财富的不平等来衡量的。一些重要的指标,比如基尼系数,就说明了这一点。基尼系数是衡量经济不平等程度的综合指标,通常用于计算财富分配和收入分配。 它还可以用来评估税收和社会补贴等再分配措施对收入不平等的影响程度。虽然重要,但像基尼系数这样的指标在重要意义上是不完整的。他们首先没有意识到私有物质资源的所有权有多重要。但是私有资源所有权的重要性可能会有很大的不同。在一个所有湖岸都被私有化的社会中,如果个人想在湖中游泳,他们需要私人资源,使他们能够购买使用权。在一个湖泊向公众开放的社会里,不需要私人资源来实现这一目的。这一点可以概括为:社会的建立方式可以使私有物质资源的占有变得更重要或更不重要。决定私有资源所有权重要性的一个关键因素是社会提供公共产品的程度。虽然对于一个特定的社会来说,似乎没有直接的方法来量化私有资源所有权的重要性或提供公共产品的程度,但这两者都是值得关注的重大问题。因此,只从私人资源分配的角度来考虑经济不平等,忽略了对这些资源的所有权对于获得有价值的商品所必需的程度。但关注经济不平等似乎是明智的,不仅要关注收入和财富的分配,而且要关注在当前收入和财富分配的情况下,人们所能做的事情的差异。这些考虑表明,提供公共产品可以间接解决收入和财富不平等问题——通过降低其相关性。但它们不仅可以成为实现这一目标的一种手段:至少有时,它们的直接提供比私人资源的再分配更有效,在政治上也更可行,这似乎是合理的。有一个经济原理可以解释为什么它可能更有效率。只要公共产品是非竞争性的(或不完全竞争性的),一些人的消费不会(或不会显著)减少其他人消费的可得性。这意味着提供一种产品作为偶然的公共产品,而不是作为俱乐部产品,通常会带来效率的提高——它在不增加成本的情况下增加了可获得性。如果我们关注经济不平等是因为人们在给定经济资源的情况下所能做的事情的差异,那么公共产品的提供可能因此更有效:在任何给定的税收水平下,都有可能在经济平等方面取得更大的进展。此外,与此相关的是,通过提供公共产品来解决经济不平等问题实际上可能更可行,这是有政治依据的。只要公共产品对所有人开放,并因此潜在地惠及所有人,富人可能更愿意为其直接提供纳税,而不是为不太富裕的人提供定向转移支付资金。正如科恩所指出的那样,“普遍福利往往比经济状况调查项目获得更高水平的政治支持”(2020年,第9页)。虽然这一论点普遍适用于公共产品,但偶然的公共产品有望特别有效地实现这一目标。因为相应的俱乐部商品可能已经存在,所以有可能在没有成本的情况下将俱乐部商品转变为偶然的公共产品,从而在不使任何人变得更糟的情况下增加获取机会。为了便于说明,请考虑在一个经历高度经济不平等的社会中运营付费电视频道的公司。假设该公司不能使用价格歧视,因此它试图将其普遍认购率设定为利润最大化的价格。因此,将会有一些人看重收看频道的机会,但不订阅,要么是因为他们不够重视,要么是因为他们根本没有支付订阅费的手段如果每个人都可以在不增加成本的情况下使用该渠道,那么将其转化为附带公共产品就有望提高效率。此外,如果那些愿意认购的人可以按照当前的认购率征税,那么这样做不会让任何人变得更糟。现在想象一下这样一个社会:经济不平等之所以引起人们的关注,主要是因为它导致人们获得付费电视的机会不平等。在这种情况下,国家解决经济不平等的最佳方式可能是向电视频道一次性支付一笔补贴,前提是它能让每个人都能看到节目。这确保了普遍获取,而且可能以比再分配转移支付更有效的方式实现。此外,这可能更可行,因为即使是现有的用户也可能不会反对按照目前的订阅率征税,以支付普遍接入的费用。 当然,这个场景是示意图,避免了重要的复杂性。十有八九,不可能完全对那些订阅频道的人征税,因此使用一般税收可能会迫使一些人为他们不愿意提供的商品做出贡献。此外,补贴消除了电视频道通过提供所需内容来说服客户订阅的需要。这表明,一旦我们考虑具体的偶然公共产品,我们必须权衡将这些产品作为公共产品提供的利与弊。基于对经济平等的关注,只有当获取对我们对经济不平等的关注足够重要时,公共提供商品才是合理的。在这方面,公共图书馆可以说是一个更令人信服的例子,因为如果经济不平等限制了受教育的机会,而不是限制了付费电视的机会,那么经济不平等更令人担忧与此同时,建设提供免费和普遍访问的图书馆,而不是依靠转移支付来确保每个人都有机会成为私人图书馆的赞助人,这在经济上可能更有效,在政治上也更可行。但无论个人对具体案例的看法如何,一般观点都是成立的:有时,偶发公共产品的提供可以帮助以有效和有针对性(如果可能是部分地)的方式解决经济不平等问题。此外,这是将偶然公共产品区分开来的第二个特征,它们有时可以逃脱标准的反对意见,即公共产品的提供总是需要理由,因为它需要税收。公共产品的支持者和反对者通常都认为,除非我们有幸能够通过担保合同或由慈善机构提供资金,否则它需要国家对公司或个人征税,然后使用这些资金来提供商品(例如,Ferdman, 2018;Schmidtz, 1991)。正是由于这个原因,公共产品的提供通常需要辩护。即使是那些(参见e.g., Ferdman, 2018;Kallhoff, 2014),他们主张提供广泛的公共产品,含蓄地接受公共产品的提供需要被证明是合理的,并提供这样的理由。但至少有两种可供选择的方式,可以让一个国家确保偶发公共产品的提供。首先,如果一种非竞争性商品已经以俱乐部商品的形式存在,但其中一些基于性别等非经济标准被排除在外,国家可以颁布法规禁止这种排除理由,从而扩大获取范围,并将该商品转变为公共产品。考虑一个私人经营的游泳池,这是远近唯一的一个。如果这个池子根据非经济标准排除了一个特定的群体(例如,男性或亚洲血统的人),那么我们就有了一个好的俱乐部。现在,假设国家出台法规,禁止基于这种理由的排斥,并且游泳池收取的费用足够小,可以有效地确保普遍使用。在这种情况下,游泳池(或者更准确地说,泳池使用权)已经从一种俱乐部产品变成了一种公共产品。这种解决方案并不适用于所有附带的公共产品。然而,它表明,至少有时,国家可以在不直接提供公共产品的情况下确保公共产品的提供,即禁止某些排除理由。这样做不需要任何国家支出,因此也不需要征税,尽管有人可能会坚持认为,发布这样的规定仍然相当于一种形式的市场干预。此外,是否提供某些偶然公共产品可能直接取决于产权的初始配置和规范。公共土地,如森林、湖泊和平原,具有公益性质:每个人都可以进入,它们提供了娱乐的机会。但在这些土地上分配私有产权的决定是在市场存在之前做出的,因此不构成对市场的干预。此外,如果产权受到限制,允许每个人都可以使用,那么即使是私人物品,也可以保持公共产品的特性。在北欧国家,“漫游权”已经存在了几个世纪,而英国和美国的私人土地所有者在排斥他人方面享有更大的自由裁量权。因此,偶然的公共产品表明,并非所有关于提供公共产品的决定都相当于对市场的干预——有些只是与市场的设置有关。当然,这一点在相当抽象的层面上最为直接:在我们生活的世界中,大多数资产的产权(尽管不是全部,请注意,例如海洋和外层空间)已经被分配,因此对这些产权的任何改变都相当于一种市场干预。 尽管如此,将一组特定产权分配给特定资产的最初决定影响了偶然公共品的可得性,这一事实至少为这种干预提供了一个原则性的理由:因为在市场存在之前没有做出的最初决定同时决定了公共品的可得性,因此修改现有的产权主张更容易证明是合理的(只要在适用的情况下提供足够的补偿)。虽然经济不平等可以构成一种社会不公正,但社会不公正也可以采取其他形式。事实上,通过提供公共品来解决经济不平等的提议,预设了这些不平等之所以令人担忧,主要是因为它们导致了机会和获取途径的不平等:偶发公共品的提供可能会使现有的私人资源所有权不平等保持不变,但通过提供市场消费的替代方案,确保了机会和获取途径的更大平等。虽然机会、准入和地位方面的不平等可能源于经济因素,但它们不必如此。一家私人乡村俱乐部的案例说明了这一点。通常情况下,这些俱乐部收取高昂的会员费,这实际上排除了那些不富裕的人。但也可能有其他理由将其排除在外。从历史上看,乡村俱乐部的成员资格经常受到性别和种族的限制。这种限制在某种意义上与准入资金有关:如果那些被排除在外的人有办法建立自己的俱乐部,他们缺乏准入的问题就可以得到缓解。但至少从个人的角度来看,他们被排斥的原因很可能是性别或种族,而不是因为缺乏个人财富。这指出了另外两种方式,即偶然的公共产品在解决不公正问题方面具有独特的潜力。当一些社会成员因非物质原因而被剥夺了获得机会和地位的机会时,公共产品可以通过两种方式提供缓解。首先,就公共产品对所有人免费提供而言,它们直接提供了一个共享的经验和社会互动领域,从而构成了Kallhoff所谓的“连接产品”(2014,pp. 642-44)——这些产品不仅扩大了访问范围,而且构成了一个互动点,象征着对共享空间和平等的承诺。这不仅适用于偶发公共产品,而且尤其适用于偶发公共产品:因为偶发公共产品本来可以以排他性的形式提供,它们的公共提供是这种对平等承诺的更决定性的表达。在一个关注地位不平等的社会中——例如,一个种姓、种族或宗教团体之间存在严重分歧的国家——偶发公共产品的提供可能具有重大的象征意义:由于其深思熟虑的普遍可及的提供模式,它可以有力地表达对所有公民平等的承诺(并且在某种程度上无法实现固有的公共利益,这是不可能以更排他性的形式提供的)。其次,更为间接的是,公共产品的提供往往会破坏市场上更为排他性的提供模式,从而削弱俱乐部产品的相关性。同样,这适用于所有公共产品,但特别适用于偶然性公共产品,因为偶然性公共产品的提供会更直接地降低与之相对应的俱乐部产品的吸引力。我们前面的游泳池例子说明了这一点:一旦有了公共游泳池,人们就不太愿意为私人游泳池付费。从这个意义上说,偶然公共产品有排挤相应的俱乐部产品的趋势。这一点很少被强调,但很重要:解决私人俱乐部强大结构导致的不平等的最有希望的长期战略可能是提供相应的公共产品,作为替代品。通过这种方式,偶然的公共产品可以逐渐打破更具排他性的私人机构的吸引力,从而削弱其权力,从而减少获取机会的不平等,从而减少由此产生的机会和感知地位的不平等。如果这种检查是合理的,那么公共产品——特别是偶然的公共产品——就会成为有效纠正现有不公正现象的一个自然的、但未得到充分重视的焦点。具体来说,至少在某些情况下,提供附带公共产品是引入全民基本收入(UBI)的更好选择,这似乎是合理的。尽管全民基本收入的主张基于各种理由,从个人的合理要求到他们对自然和社会资源成果的分享(例如,Van Parijs, 1991, pp. 6)。 130-31)解决现有性别和种族不公正问题的能力(见Bidadanure, 2019,第492-95页),它的目标始终是相对于现状重新分配私人资源。如上所述,有充分的理由相信,提供公共产品在经济上是更有效的,在政治上是更可行的政策。例如,当非竞争性商品已经以俱乐部商品的形式存在,并且可以以很少的额外费用普及时,情况就是这样。还有一种情况是,我们可以稍微修改私有产权,例如土地,以确保提供一些公共产品。此外,当我们面临的不公正不是由于物质资源的不平等,而是由于规则和规范将个人排除在平等条件下参与的时候,只有提供偶然的公共产品,而不是提供全民基本收入,才能通过有效地扩大获取和创造一个共享的互动领域来纠正它们。这给我们留下了一个问题:在什么情况下,国家应该通过提供公共产品来解决不公正问题,什么时候应该采取其他再分配措施?或者,更一般地说,哪些原则决定了国家应该提供什么样的公共产品?本文不打算对这些问题提供全面的答案,原因有二。一方面,一个国家是否应该提供特定的公共产品的规范性问题必须始终在当前的社会背景条件下进行评估。例如,一个国家是应该提供免费的运动场地,还是应该采取再分配措施来解决在获得娱乐设施方面的不平等问题,将取决于许多因素,例如提供的成本、关于个人对运动场地类型的偏好的信息的可得性,以及提供其他方法的可得性。因此,在任何特定情况下,都需要提出一个支持附带公共产品提供的具体论证。另一方面,该报告没有说明如何权衡不同的考虑因素:例如,对于经济效率与平等机会相比有多重要,以及团结的价值有多重要,它保持沉默。本节不是提供公共产品的规范理论,而是主要旨在强调公共产品纠正现有不公正的潜力,并且这种潜力在偶然公共产品的情况下尤其明显。因此,这种解释是开放式的,允许对公共物品的价值和不公正标准持特定观点的支持者在评估是否应该提供某种特定的公共物品时,利用这种观点。纠正现有不公正现象的潜力至少为提供一些偶然的公共产品提供了一个间接的理由——即使这种提供目前并不受到每个人的青睐,或者不受个人偏好(无论如何汇总)的青睐,它也会这样做。这种以不公正为基础的偶然性公共产品的正当性与其他地方提倡的完美主义正当性截然不同。例如,有人认为(在我看来很有说服力),公共产品可以通过遏制对稀缺资源的有害竞争,帮助创造美好生活的条件(费德曼,2018,第670页;另见Hussain, 2018),它们可以促进共同的目标感,从而加强“团结感”(Kallhoff, 2014, p. 641),这些好处支持反对国家中立的论点,并可以证明国家提供公共产品的合理性。这里提出的论点更为温和:它声称,公共产品的提供可能是由它们解决现有社会不公的能力来证明的,而不是由一些独立的有价值的目标来证明的。这并不是说两者之间没有联系:例如,我们似乎有理由相信,更大的团结意识将首先防止某些社会不公正现象的产生。但重点不同:这里提出的对公共产品的临时辩护直接诉诸于它们纠正现有不公正的能力。我们似乎有理由认为,这应该使这一论点不那么有争议,因为不公正的存在为采取行动提供了比完美主义建议更有力的理由。这篇文章符合最近的几次尝试(de Jongh, 2022;Ferdman,科恩2018;朱蒂,2010;Kallhoff, 2014;Kohn, 2020)重新评估公共产品在秩序良好的社会中的作用,并将其提升到政治思维中更突出的位置。 为了回应哲学家如何使用“公共利益”一词的模糊性,本文在第2节中提出,在固有公共利益(非竞争性和非排他性)和偶然公共利益(非竞争性,作为一种选择,以非排他性的形式提供)之间做出区分。第3节和第4节利用这一区别来展示偶然公共产品的类别如何在哲学辩论中富有成果。正如第三节所论述的,偶然的公共产品对各种利益原则提出了挑战,这些原则是用来管理公共产品提供过程中的成本和收益分配的。由于这些商品可以以排他性俱乐部商品的形式提供,因此拟议的利益原则要求向个别富人以及那些不重视公共产品包容性提供模式的人支付不合理的转移支付。正如第4节所述,偶然的公共产品同时为解决不合理的经济不平等,以及机会、准入和地位方面的不平等,从而纠正社会不公正,提供了一个自然的、但未得到充分重视的焦点。由于公共品对每个人都是平等的,它们使得私人资源的所有权变得不那么重要,从而减少了收入和财富不平等的相关性,扩大了机会和获取途径。偶然公共品在四个方面是特殊的:它们的提供可能是无成本的;可能不需要任何市场干预;它有可能成为表达每个人平等地位的特别有力的方式;而且,它特别有可能削弱排他性俱乐部商品的相关性。 因此,它建议区分固有公共产品和偶然公共产品。后面的章节借鉴了偶然性公共产品的概念,试图展示它如何在理想和非理想理论的背景下推进关于公共产品的哲学思考。许多哲学家对于他们如何理解公共产品的概念仍然有些模糊。例如,Avigail Ferdman引用了她所谓的“标准经济理解”,根据该理解,“公共产品[…]是私人市场无法有效提供的物质产品”(2018年,第662页)。尽管她坚持认为也可以有非物质的公共产品(2018年,第662-63页),但她还是依赖于这一特征。因此,对她来说,公共产品构成了市场失灵;但市场可能由于各种原因而不能有效地提供商品,费德曼没有具体说明哪些是公共商品的定义。然而,即使提出了明确的定义,它们也往往是相互矛盾的。Jonathan Anomaly(2015)和David Miller(2004)提出的定义是中央裂谷的例证Anomaly写道,“如果商品表现出非竞争性和非排他性,那么它们就是公共的”(2015年,第109页,斜体原文),引用经济理论的标准定义,如果一个人的消费不会减少其他人对它的可用性,那么一种商品就被称为非竞争性,如果将某些人排除在消费之外是不可行的,那么这种商品就被称为非排他性。相比之下,米勒写道,所谓公共物品,“我指的是每个人都可以免费获得的物品,每个人都可以享受,而不会减少其他人享受同样物品的机会”(2004年,第127-28页)。米勒关于公共产品的概念包含了反常的概念,但范围更广:米勒的标准是,一件商品免费提供给所有人,这可能是因为该商品固有的非排他性(想想星空的景色),也可能是因为故意选择免费提供(想想英国的博物馆)。因此,他们不仅会对某些商品进行不同的分类,而且会发现不同的相关问题,甚至是合理的问题:虽然两者都可能问国家是否应该提供某些公共产品,但只有米勒能明智地问国家是否应该将某些产品作为公共产品提供。因此,很明显,“反常”和米勒可能会各说各话,但更倾向于哪种定义就不那么明显了。反常的定义符合经济学家使用的分类方案,即公共产品与私人产品(竞争性、排他性;例如,苹果),俱乐部物品(非竞争性,排他性;例如,付费电视)和公共财产(竞争性的、非排他性的;例如,渔业资源)。它还抓住了费德曼所暗示的市场失灵的一面:因为,根据定义,没有人可以被排除在公共产品的使用之外,每个人都有尽可能少贡献的动机。由于这种所谓的搭便车问题,市场将不会在有效水平上提供公共产品在将经济学家所说的“俱乐部产品”和“公共产品”混为一谈时,米勒似乎放弃了一个有价值的区别。对他来说,只要图书馆实际上是免费提供给每个人,就有资格成为公共产品。但正如伦敦图书馆这样的私人收藏所证明的那样,市场可以将图书馆作为俱乐部商品提供。甚至俱乐部商品也通常涉及市场失灵:除非完全的价格歧视是可行的,否则市场不会有效地提供俱乐部商品。但这种市场失灵是有限的——因为人们可以被排除在外,市场至少在原则上可以提供这些商品。与此同时,米勒的描述更好地抓住了“公共产品”一词的一般用法。把公园说成是公共物品似乎既不罕见,也不不合理——但是,虽然公园通常对每个人都是免费开放的,但正如伦敦贝尔格雷夫广场花园(Belgrave Square Garden)所展示的那样,限制那些愿意(并且有能力)购买钥匙的人进入公园是可能的。由于米勒和Anomaly对公共产品的定义各自挑出了重要的方面,我们有理由保留它们。但是为了避免误解,我们需要把它们区分开来。为了实现这一点,我建议区分固有公共产品和偶然公共产品更具体地说,我建议将固有公共产品(按照Anomaly的思路)定义为(I)非竞争性和(ii)非排他性的产品,将偶然公共产品(在米勒精神中)定义为(I)非竞争性和(ii)以非排他性形式提供的选择问题。 限定词“作为一种选择问题”很重要,因为就本质上来说,公共产品是非排他性的,它们必然以非排他性的形式提供,因此,某些产品免费提供给每个人的条件并不能标志出这种区别。由于米勒没有加上这一限定,他的概念包含了两种类型的公共产品。此外,我对“非排他性形式”一词的理解也很宽泛:虽然一种商品可以通过让每个人都能免费获得而以非排他性形式提供,但如果有一个象征性的收费,但每个人都能轻松负担得起,它也可以这样提供。固有公共产品和偶然公共产品之间的区别是很重要的,因为它使我们能够区分两件事:对提供商品的模式的深思熟虑的选择,以及由于无法排除其他产品而导致的市场失灵。这种区别在精神上与沃恩·布莱恩·巴尔茨利(Vaughn Bryan Baltzly, 2021)和Anomaly(2021)最近对公共产品和公共产品所做的区分很接近,但并不完全相同。对于Baltzly来说,公开的物品是“其‘公共’特性仅来自于一项政策决定,即让某些(其他方面是私人的)物品自由和普遍获得”(2021年,第376页)。在讨论公共卫生措施时,异常现象将其定性为公开的“通过政府命令创造的激励而公开的商品”(2021年,第2页),其中一种商品的公共性主要意味着其消费对他人施加了外部性(2021年,第6页)。公共产品的概念,就像偶然公共产品的概念一样,是基于这样一个事实,即社会可以经常决定是否提供对特定产品的普遍、免费访问。然而,与偶发公共产品的概念不同,它对一种产品的竞争程度没有限制。由于这个原因,它的意义要广泛得多:如果一个国家免费提供苹果,它们就成为一种公开的产品,而不是偶然的公共产品。正如下面的讨论所表明的那样,拥有更狭义、更精确的术语“偶然公共产品”是有价值的,因为它使我们能够挑选出那些公共提供有望提高效率的产品。本文的其余部分试图表明,固有公共产品和偶然公共产品之间的区别是有价值的,而偶然公共产品的重要性一直被低估。不过,一开始就应该注意三点。首先,这种区别可以被更好地理解为划分一个范围,而不是一个绝对的划分:很少有商品本质上是不可排除的;相反,排斥可能或多或少代价高昂。其次,某些产品是否具有不可排他性,因此是否具有固有的公共性,取决于技术水平,并可能发生变化:如果在某个反乌托邦的未来,人们需要为进入生物穹顶付费,那么清洁的空气就会偶然变成一种公共品。最后,正如很少有商品是完全非竞争性的,也很少有商品是不可排他性的:我去公园跑步并不会减少它的可用性,但如果一群人堵塞了道路,占据了所有的野餐地点,这确实会减少公园对其他人的可用性(或价值)——在极限情况下,公园变成了竞争性商品。因此,不应过于严格地解释非竞争标准;相反,我们可以根据它们的竞争程度来区分更纯净或不纯净的公共产品——在给定的消费水平上,或在一系列水平上。此外,请注意,固有公共产品和偶然公共产品之间的区别与在公共产品辩论中得出的其他几种区别是正交的。例如,费德曼(2018)区分了普遍公共品和非普遍公共品,前者受到所有人的重视,而后者只受到一些人的重视。更突出的是,一些作者(例如Claassen, 2013;米勒,Taylor, 2018)已经区分了必要的(或必要的)和自由裁量的公共产品,其中提供前者,而不是后者,是司法所要求的但是,某种善是固有的公共善(或偶然的公共善)这一事实并不影响它是否是普遍的,也不影响它是否是本质的这可以用以下事实来解释:将一种商品分类为固有的公共商品还是偶然的公共商品,仅仅是基于其结构属性,即它是原则上可排除的,还是仅仅以非排他性的形式提供的;但是,这些结构性质显然既不能决定一种商品是否受到每个人的重视,也不能决定它是否对正义至关重要因此,这里提倡的术语区分是新的,独立于现有的术语区分。同时,不同的规格当然可以进行组合;例如,我们可以拥有一种必要的、普遍的偶然性公共产品。 最近关于公共品的哲学辩论的一个重要方面是在理想理论的层面上进行的,并集中在正义问题上:提供公共品的负担和利益应根据何种标准进行分配,以保持正义的条件(例如,Claassen, 2013;米勒,2004;墨菲,内格尔,2001年)?本节针对这个问题提出的各种利益原则提出了两个新的反对意见。不平等获得俱乐部商品的反对主张,这些利益原则要求向私人富人支付不可接受的转移支付。来自公共产品内在贬值的反对意见断言,除非有资格,否则利益原则会强制向那些低估其包容性提供模式的人支付不可接受的转移支付。这两种反对意见都基于附带公共产品的情况:在每种情况下,都是将各自的公共产品作为俱乐部产品提供的可能性产生了问题。更具体地说,这些反对意见针对的是偶发公共产品的一个特定子集:那些不是司法直接要求提供的公共产品(因此在下文进一步探讨的意义上也是自由裁量的)。关于公共品供给中的正义要求的讨论是由两个观察结果推动的(见Miller &;Taylor, 2018,特别是562-64)。一方面,有一些公共品是正义所必需的。以法治为例。它被广泛理解为通过执行法律规则和程序对任意使用权力的有效限制,它有资格作为一种(非物质的)公共产品。此外,几乎所有的正义理论都以它为前提:因为,如果个人受制于他人任意行使权力(或施加人身伤害),那么分配资源的意义何在?另一方面,有些商品的供应不是正义所要求的,但却引起了人们对正义的关注:假设一个最初公正的社会,提供这些商品的收益和成本应该如何分配?前一类商品“其供应本身就是一个正义问题”,通常被称为“基本公共物品”(米勒&;Taylor, 2018,第564页)或“必要的公共产品”(Claassen, 2013,第273页)。后一种类型的商品,其提供不需要司法,被称为“自由裁量公共产品”(Claassen, 2013, p. 273;米勒,Taylor, 2018,第564页)。社会正义理论的支持者对自由裁量的公共品没有给予太多的考虑,即使他们考虑过公共品,他们也典型地支持程序标准例如,约翰·罗尔斯(John Rawls)最初规定,国家只有在“满足威克塞尔的一致标准”(1999,第248页)时才可以提供(自由裁量的)公共产品,这使得它们的合法提供取决于每个人对一项提案的同意,该提案规定了(i)要提供的商品和(ii)支付该商品的税收时间表(Wicksell, 1958)。在他后来的著作(罗尔斯,2001)中,罗尔斯放宽了一致同意的条件,提议以简单多数投票代替正如Miller(2004)所指出的那样,程序方法的问题在于,即使人们认为它们提供了合法性的解释,它们在分配正义的问题上也保持沉默。但是,可自由支配的公共产品提供的盈余可以以各种方式进行分配——并不是所有的分配都(同样)公平。鉴于程序性会计的弱点,一些作者主张采用实质性标准(Miller, 2004;墨菲,内格尔,2001)。他们建议分两个步骤处理提供公共物品中的正义问题。首先,我们确定了一套基本公共产品,其提供是正义所要求的;对于这些商品,成本的分配是由我们的正义理论决定的。在第二步,我们考虑可自由支配的公共产品,正是在这个阶段,我们需要一个额外的原则来确定成本和收益的分配。这种原则中最基本的是利益原则,它要求提供可自由支配的公共物品以使每个人受益。但这个原则是高度宽容的;在自利投票的假设下,即使全体一致条件也意味着利益原则得到满足。提出了两个更严格的原则。Murphy和Nagel(2001)提出,每个人都应该为提供可自由支配的公共品的成本做出贡献,比例与她所获得的利益成正比;我们称之为比例效益原则。Miller(2004)提出,应提供可自由支配的公共产品,以平衡个人获得的净收益;我们称之为平等利益原则。这些原则遭到了反对。 例如,米勒批评比例利益原则将国家视为企业:他声称,坚持按比例贡献与利益成比例,这与政治共同体的理念相矛盾,“政治共同体的基本原则是每个成员拥有平等的股份”(2004,144)。然而,米勒的平等利益原则似乎容易受到相关反对意见的影响。在坚持严格平等的利益时,一个人似乎对社会采取了一个嫉妒的孩子的观点。在兄弟姐妹中,平等利益原则可能会产生一些影响:如果一个孩子不喜欢巧克力,但她的兄弟喜欢,她可能会坚持认为,如果巧克力是唯一可用的糖果,那么出于公正的原因,他们两个都不应该得到巧克力。但在社会层面上,坚持一项原则,即禁止在不会伤害任何人而使许多人受益的情况下提供公共产品,似乎揭示了一种对“平等分享”的病态坚持,暴露了对公民同胞缺乏慷慨的期望。此外,Miller和Taylor(2018,568)认为比例利益原则是不完整的。如果两组不同的可自由支配的公共物品满足比例性要求,该原则并没有告诉我们应该选择哪一个假设我们的目标是利益最大化,平等利益原则避免了这个问题。但在其他方面,它具有高度的限制性:除非利益能够平等,否则就无法提供一种商品,即使每个人都能从中受益。正如Miller和Taylor所指出的(2018,569),这似乎使平等利益原则容易受到贬低反对(尽管转移计划可能有助于解决这个问题)。偶然地,公共产品激发了两个额外的、更基本的反对意见,这些反对意见同时适用于各种利益原则。首先,存在对俱乐部物品获取不平等的反对意见:因为偶发公共物品原则上是排他性的,它们可以作为俱乐部物品提供,但私人资源的不平等初始分配意味着获得俱乐部物品的不平等,这影响了作为公共物品提供的利益分配;因此,福利原则强制要求向个别富人进行不合理的转移。这种反对意见可以通过公共游泳池的例子来说明。每个人都可以免费或象征性地付费使用的游泳池是一种(不纯粹的)公共产品。我们最初可能会认为所有的游泳者都从中受益。但假设一位个人富有的游泳运动员辩称,她没有从中受益:因为她是一家提供泳池服务的健身俱乐部的会员,她声称从公共泳池中没有获得任何好处。她认为,比例利益原则意味着她不必贡献任何东西,而利益原则和平等利益原则意味着她甚至应该得到补偿。当然,公共游泳池对富有的游泳运动员的影响取决于具体情况。如果她购买俱乐部会员资格的唯一动机是获得泳池使用权,她可以在公共泳池建成后取消会员资格,她的利益被俱乐部会员资格节省的钱所抵消。因此,她从公共游泳池中受益,并必须为其提供成本做出贡献。然而,即使在这种情况下,她的部分收益也可能逃避会计核算。因为如果她愿意为俱乐部会员支付比要求更多的钱,她就能私下获得剩余的利益,而这个剩余的利益不计入她从公共游泳池获得的利益。相比之下,对于那些最初缺乏所有池访问权限的人来说,池访问的全部好处都被考虑在内了。但是,有人可能会说,如果最初的分配是公正的,那么这就没问题了:尽管富人从公共产品中获得的部分利益没有被计入,但这部分利益是他们已经从进入俱乐部的机会中获得的——因此,公共泳池的提供维持了他们的优势,但并没有增加他们的优势。然而,接下来,考虑这种情况的一个变体。假设这位富裕的游泳运动员决定不使用公共游泳池,而是保留她的俱乐部会员资格。由于她没有从公共游泳池中获得任何利益,平等利益原则要求向富有的游泳运动员支付补偿费,前提是建造公共游泳池有盈余利益同样,如果公共游泳池对富有的游泳者不利,比例效益原则也证明了补偿是合理的。假设,一旦公共游泳池建成,一些俱乐部成员离开了健身俱乐部,导致费用上涨。例如,如果一个富有的游泳运动员决定保持她的俱乐部会员资格,因为她充分重视会员资格的其他好处,那么公共游泳池的提供对她不利。 即使根据比例利益原则,她也应该对提供公共池的成本做出负贡献,即欠她补偿。利益原则的这些含义似乎令人困惑。如果私人物品的初始分配是公正的,那么人们可能会给予富人从购买其他人买不起的俱乐部物品中获得的任何好处。人们甚至可以接受,如果他们喜欢各自的俱乐部产品,他们就不需要为提供公共产品的成本做出贡献。但将他们的索赔要求归为赔偿似乎是不合理的。如果一群人愿意承担所有成本,让所有人都能免费获得某种商品,那么真的可以要求他们为那些更愿意消费同等俱乐部商品、但却没有变得更糟的富人提供转移支付吗?现在,重要的是要谨慎。如果我们判断某人是否可以在特定情况下合理地要求赔偿,这个判断最终将部分取决于我们对这个案件的直觉(以及我们对相关其他案件的直觉,支撑我们判断的系统解释延伸到这些直觉)。由于这里的论证是在理想理论的层面上进行的,我们需要确保我们不会被关于非理想情况的直觉引入歧途。也许有人会担心,我们认为要求赔偿是不合理的,仅仅是因为,在我们生活的世界里,赔偿那些富有的、已经可以享用俱乐部商品的人是荒谬的。但是,假设最初的私人物品分配是公平的,那么我们需要补偿那些获得较少利益,甚至是不利利益的人,因为他们已经以俱乐部商品的形式获得了相关商品,这难道不是正确的吗?在我看来,即使在理想的情况下,要求赔偿也是不合理的。一些人免于缴纳会费的情况与他们应得到赔偿的情况之间的差别,可以参照市场作为另一种提供方式来加以区分。如果那些喜欢某种公共产品的人可以通过市场协调来获得它,那么他们就可以私下提供它——在这种情况下,获得相应俱乐部产品的人不会做出任何贡献,但他们也不会得到补偿。因此,第一类案例的结果与市场结果一致,而第二类案例的结果与市场结果不同,即对那些有机会获得俱乐部物品的人进行补偿。当然,假设的市场结果不涉及补偿这一事实,并不意味着在国家提供商品的情况下,这是正确的观点:对国家的需求不同于对私人市场参与者的需求。但与基于市场的结果的差异表明,补偿比不贡献更难以证明是合理的,尤其是在由于相对缺乏利益而不是间接伤害(由于俱乐部商品更昂贵)而欠下补偿的情况下。此外,请注意,在这里,国家在提供各自公共产品方面的参与可能是相当少的——国家可能只是提供一种强制机制,允许那些同意出资的个人共同提供公共产品,然后每个人都可以使用。至少在这种情况下,即使在正义的初始条件下,承认赔偿要求也会有效地让富人利用他们的初始优势,从穷人那里获得解决方案,即使他们已经承担了国家提供的所有有价值的、人人都能获得的商品的全部成本。但这似乎并不公平——即使通过更容易获得俱乐部商品而获得的最初优势是公平的。但假设有人拒绝这一论点,并坚持认为,由于国家总是必须平等对待每个人,一旦它参与提供可自由支配的公共产品,就确实应该得到补偿。在这种情况下,关于不平等获得俱乐部商品的论点指向了一个更根本的问题:相对于哪个基线,可以确保平等待遇?为了解决这个问题,首先总结一下Claassen(2013)的见解是有帮助的。Claassen认为,米勒的平等利益原则不利于那些对美好生活的概念严重依赖于公共产品消费而不是市场产品的人(2013,pp. 278-81)。他指出,在纯粹的市场经济中,那些支持公共产品的人发现自己相对于那些支持市场产品的人处于不利地位——几乎没有提供公共产品。但是,如果我们引入公共产品,但又要求每个人都能从提供的公共产品中平等受益,那么这种劣势就会保留下来:因为虽然现在每个人的境况都变好了,但每个人的境况都会变好,因此相对地位保持不变。 从本质上贬低公共产品价值的可能性引发了对利益原则的挑战,但其确切形式取决于人们对支撑它们的中立原则的解释。利益原则植根于自由主义框架,要求对公民的偏好保持中立。利益原则的支持者没有限定,也没有进一步讨论中立性的基本概念。根据字面解释,(i)中立性要求一个人对所有偏好保持中立,除非另有明确规定。根据这种解释,公共产品内在贬值的可能性产生了反对意见。以A为例,她生活在一个以阶级为基础的社会中,她认为自己是上层阶级的一员,她反对提供公园,唯一的理由是公园的普遍可达性没有尊重不同阶级成员之间的地位区别。此外,假设A是一个宅男,既不进入公共公园,也不进入私人公园,如果她没有在上流社会的公报上读到公园的消息,她永远不会知道公园的存在。在这种情况下,A对公共供给的偏好违背了政治共同体的精神,否定了对他人平等的基本理解。正是由于这个原因,我认为它不值得考虑:A不能合理地要求赔偿提供公园给她带来的不利影响。但这表明,利益原则必须是限定的:它们的声明需要明确排除某些公共产品内在贬值的情况。然而,在这一点上,有人可能会插话说,中立原则也可以有不同的解释。事实上,其字面上的,不合格的解释可以被视为naïve:它要求对所有偏好保持中立,包括不道德的偏好。尽管没有明确说明这一点,但人们可能会因此坚持认为,利益原则的支持者隐含地假设,至少一些不道德的偏好被排除在考虑之外。但如果一个人接受这种观点,那么他可能会回应说,上面的例子是道德化的,因此需要被拒绝:A不把公园作为公共产品的偏好是不道德的,因为它是基于不道德的阶级偏好;因此,这里不适用中立性原则,因此A的偏好不能作为补偿的理由,利益原则也不存在问题。这一回应引发了一个问题:我们能否找到一个非道德化的例子,它不被中立原则排除在外,但一个人对公共利益的内在贬低并不构成补偿的理由?在解决这个问题时,首先要注意的是,虽然声称中立原则不应包括不道德的偏好排除了其字面解释(i),但它并不需要具体的替代方案。相反,它至少与对该原则的三种不同解释是一致的:(ii)它要求对所有偏好保持中立,除了一组隐含地被视为不道德的偏好;(iii)它要求对所有偏好保持中立,除了那些实际上不道德的偏好;(iv)它规定,当且仅当我们不必对偏好保持中立时,偏好是不道德的。现在,根据解释(iv),定义排除了非道德化的例子。这是因为(iv)规定,无论何时我们不应该对某种偏好保持中立,那么这种偏好就被视为不道德。根据定义,当我们不应该补偿一个人在本质上对公共利益的贬低(即,不应该是中立的),那么这种偏好是不道德的——因此,不可能有非道德的例子。这样,解释(iv)排除了公共产品内在贬值的任何异议。但这需要付出高昂的代价。如果以这种方式解释,中立原则是一种概念性的主张,而不是实质性的主张。这不仅使它缺乏信息:没有提到不道德偏好的范围有多广,也没有提到为什么我们不应该对它们保持中立。更重要的是,它颠倒了解释的顺序:不再是我们不应该因为偏好不道德而对其保持中立,而是因为我们不应该对其保持中立而认为偏好是不道德的。在我看来,这一含义使得将中立原则解释为一种概念性主张变得难以置信。但请注意,即使有人坚持解释(iv),上述关于A对公园的内在贬值的论点也会有一些价值:它会确定一种特定类型的偏好,我们不应该对此保持中立,并提供原因。相比之下,作出实质性主张的解释(ii)和(iii)允许出现非道德化例子的可能性。 我相信可以举出这样一个例子。以生活在平等主义共和国的B为例。B也是一个宅男,从不去公园。不过,她不喜欢把公园作为公共产品来提供,因为她不喜欢普遍的可达性。这不是由于阶级或种族主义观点;碰巧B更喜欢商品是私人的,而不是公开的。因此,B的情况不同于A的情况:B对公园的内在贬低不是基于任何其他道德败坏的偏好或信仰。B不反对公共规定,因为它不尊重地位差异;她只是偏爱私人物品。我认为,这种偏好本身太天真了,不足以被称为不道德;这是一种偏好,并不表示对他人的不尊重或令人反感的观点。但与此同时,就像A的情况一样,B对公共产品的内在贬值在评估提供公园的收益和损害时并不是一种值得考虑的偏好。这是因为B不愿意将公园作为公共物品的动机并不充分:假设B不打算使用公园,因此公园是否可供公众使用与B享受公园(或任何其他物品)的能力无关,因此B不会因将公园作为公共物品提供而遭受有意义的伤害。在评估收益时,我们需要考虑的是,作为一个室内人,B没有从提供公园中受益,而不是B不重视他们提供公园的方式。如果这一论点是正确的,那么B的案例就有资格成为一个非道德化的例子,这表明,根据对中立原则的限定解释(ii)和(iii),利益原则必须受到限制:至少有时,由于公共产品的内在贬值而产生的不利影响应该被忽略。然而,即使有人坚持认为B的偏好是不道德的,或者B有权要求赔偿,我的论点仍然会强调利益原则的支持者需要解决以下问题:在哪些条件下,对公共产品的内在贬值是一种不道德的偏好,因此可能被忽视,为什么?这是一个严肃的问题,因为公共产品的内在贬值并不总是不道德的:例如,弱势群体和少数群体可以说有充分的理由要求并非所有人都可以使用的空间。然而,如果一个人从不打算使用公共产品,或者不会注意到其他人使用公共产品,那么对公共产品的内在贬值是否合理就不那么明显了:一个宗教团体是否有理由反对某些山的普遍可达性,因为他们认为它是神圣的,即使他们永远不会注意到是否有人要去那里?如果这一节中提出的两个反对意见是正确的,那么它就有两个含义。在实质层面上,它们表明了现有的利益原则,这些原则是为了补充现有的正义理论而提出的,以解释可自由支配的公共物品,在一些方面存在缺陷,迄今为止尚未引起人们的注意。在理论层面上,它们揭示了在审查自由裁量公共产品提供中的正义要求时考虑偶然公共产品的重要性。这是因为本节中提出的两种反对意见都不可能在涉及固有公共产品时产生同样的效果。本质上,公共产品不可能作为俱乐部产品提供(尽管不完全替代品可能),因此,在他们的情况下,不会出现对市场上这些产品获取不平等的担忧(或者,至少不是以完全相同的方式)。因为这些商品,根据定义,是非排他性的,欢迎商品本身,反对其提供的包容性模式,这将是不连贯的。但是,这两种反对意见也表明了一项更具建设性的任务,即具体说明应该采用的利益原则虽然提出的论点暗示了另一项利益原则必须满足的两个条件,但它们并没有对这一原则作出全面的说明。它们隐含的两个条件如下:首先,该原则必须是“俱乐部产品敏感”的,也就是说,它需要具体说明,在哪些条件下,那些已经获得俱乐部产品并作为公共产品提供的人缺乏赔偿要求;其次,它必须限定对中立的要求,或者更具体地说,它需要规定在哪些条件下可以或必须无视对公共产品的偏好。但这两个条件显然可以用许多方法来满足,而上述论证并不能产生任何具体的原则。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The importance of contingently public goods

Public goods have recently received increasing attention by philosophers. In addition to work on the historical origins of the notion of public goods (Desmarais-Tremblay, 2017), their relevance to the thinking of particular political theorists (de Jongh, 2022) and the justifiability of particular public goods, such as the arts (Kessler, 2018), there have been a number of systematic attempts to develop a normative theory of public goods (see e.g., Kallhoff, 2011; Miller, 2004). Asking which public goods the state ought to provide, and how the benefits and burdens of their provision ought to be distributed, these contributions can roughly be divided into two camps. One group of authors has addressed these questions within political liberalism, remaining committed to the principle of state neutrality. By taking individual preferences as given, they note that many public goods promise net efficiency gains and ask according to what principles these benefits ought to be distributed (see e.g., Claassen, 2013; Cullity, 2008; Murphy & Nagel, 2001). In so doing, they see themselves as complementing existing theories of justice, which remain mostly silent on the allocation of costs and benefits of public goods (Miller & Taylor, 2018, p. 556). Another group of authors has moved beyond the principle of state neutrality, putting forward arguments in favor of the state provision of public goods that are at least in part independent of individual preferences, such as their potential to foster solidarity and to connect people (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Kallhoff, 2014; Kohn, 2020). These authors contend that the social value of public goods remains underappreciated, and that the state may be justified in providing them even if doing so does not result in efficiency gains and reject the view that efficiency is the central criterion by which to judge whether the provision of a public good can be justified. This philosophical interest has coincided with a broader sense of neglect of public goods, which has been voiced by journalists and public intellectuals, in particular in Britain and the United States (Irvin, 2012; Judt, 2010; Lehrer, 2020). Yet, despite the recent surge in attention, the philosophical and, more generally, the “scholarly literature on public goods is relatively thin” (Kohn, 2020, p. 2).1

This article aims to contribute to the philosophical thinking about public goods in three ways. First, highlighting an ambiguity in how the term “public good” is used, Section 2 proposes to distinguish between inherently public goods, which cohere to the economist's definition of a good that is non-rivalrous and non-excludable, and contingently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and, though in principle excludable, provided in a non-exclusionary form. Section 3 then draws on the notion of contingently public goods to develop two novel objections to a variety of benefit principles that have been proposed to govern the allocation of burdens and benefits in the provision of public goods. These principles are generally offered as complements to theories of distributive justice and aim to take care of an alleged blind spot resulting from the possibility of welfare gains from the provision of public good that are not required for initial conditions of justice. In engaging with these principles, the article operates at the level of ideal theory. It argues that because contingently public goods could also have been provided as club goods, the benefit principles, unless further qualified, demand unacceptable transfers to the wealthy as well as to people who object to their inclusive mode of provision. Section 4 then draws on the notion of contingently public goods to explore the potential of public goods in addressing existing social injustices. This section thus operates at the level of nonideal theory. It argues that providing public goods can be an alternative to transfer payments, or a universal basic income, in addressing injustices that are a result of economic inequality and that we have good reason to think that it can, at least at times, be more effective as well as politically more feasible. While this is true of public goods in general, several features set contingently public goods apart: they may at times be provided at little to no cost, their provision may require only more limited market interference (or even none), it can more powerfully express a commitment to status equality, and it may be particularly effective where injustices stem from unequal access to club goods.

This section argues that there is an important, though frequently overlooked ambiguity in how the term “public good” is used in philosophical discourse. While some authors require a good to be in principle non-excludable in order to qualify, others merely require it to be provided in a non-exclusionary form. While there are benefits to each terminological choice, the section argues, it is important to keep them apart. Accordingly, it proposes to distinguish between inherently public goods and contingently public goods. The later sections draw on the notion of a contingently public good, attempting to show how it can advance philosophical thinking about public goods in the context of ideal as well as nonideal theory.

Many philosophers have remained somewhat vague about how they understand the notion of public goods. For instance, Avigail Ferdman refers to what she calls the “standard economic understanding” according to which “public goods […] are material goods that the private market cannot provide efficiently” (2018, p. 662). Although she insists that there can also be nonmaterial public goods (2018, pp. 662–63), she otherwise relies on this characterization. Accordingly, public goods on her account constitute a market failure; but a market may fail to efficiently provide goods for various reasons and Ferdman does not specify which of these are defining of public goods. Even where explicit definitions have been put forward, however, they tend to be mutually inconsistent. The central rift is exemplified by the definitions proposed by Jonathan Anomaly (2015) and David Miller (2004).2 Anomaly writes that “[g]oods are public if they exhibit nonrivalry and nonexcludability” (2015, p. 109, italics original), invoking the standard definition of economic theory, where a good is said to be non-rivalrous if its consumption by one person does not diminish its availability to others, and non-excludable if it is infeasible to exclude some people from consumption. By contrast, Miller writes that by public goods, “I shall mean goods that are made available to everyone without charge, and that each person can enjoy without diminishing the opportunity of others to enjoy the same good” (2004, pp. 127–28). Miller's notion of a public good encompasses Anomaly's but is broader: Miller's criterion that a goods is provided to everyone without charge may be fulfilled because of the good's inherent non-excludability (think of the view of the starry sky) or because of a deliberate choice to provide it for free (think of museums in England). As a result, they will not only classify certain goods differently, but will find different questions pertinent, and even sensible: while both may ask whether the state should provide certain public goods, only Miller can sensibly ask whether it should provide certain goods as public goods.

It is evident, then, that Anomaly and Miller are at risk of talking past each other, but less obvious which definition to prefer. Anomaly's definition fits with the classificatory scheme employed by economists, where public goods are contrasted with private goods (rivalrous, excludable; e.g., apples), club goods (non-rivalrous, excludable; e.g., pay-tv) and common-pool goods (rivalrous, non-excludable; e.g., fishing stocks). It also captures the market-failure aspect that Ferdman alludes to: since, by definition, no one can be excluded from the use of public goods, everyone has an incentive to contribute as little as possible. Due to this so-called free-rider problem, markets will not provide public goods at efficient levels.3 In conflating what economists call “club goods” and “public goods,” Miller appears to give up a valuable distinction. For him, a library qualifies as a public good so long as access is in fact offered to everyone free of charge. But as private collections like the London Library prove, markets can provide libraries as club goods. Even club goods typically involve a market failure: unless perfect price-discrimination is feasible, markets will not provide club goods at efficient levels. But this market failure is more limited—because people can be excluded, a market can at least in principle provide these goods. At the same time, Miller's account better captures the ordinary use of the term “public good”. It seems neither uncommon, nor unreasonable to speak of parks as public goods—but while they are often freely accessible to everyone, it is, as London's Belgrave Square Garden demonstrates, possible to restrict access to those willing (and able) to purchase a key.

Because the definitions of a public good advanced by Miller and Anomaly each pick out important aspects, we have reason to preserve them both. But in order to avoid misunderstandings, we need to keep them distinct. To achieve this, I propose to distinguish between inherently public goods and contingently public goods.4 More specifically, I propose to define an inherently public good (along Anomaly's lines) as a good that is (i) non-rivalrous and (ii) non-excludable and a contingently public good (in Millerian spirit) as a good that is (i) non-rivalrous and (ii) as a matter of choice, provided in a non-exclusionary form. The qualifier “as a matter of choice” is important because in so far as inherently public goods are non-excludable, they are necessarily provided in non-exclusionary form, so the mere condition that certain goods are provided to everyone for free fails to mark the distinction. As Miller does not add this qualification, his notion encompasses both types of public goods. Moreover, I understand the term “non-exclusionary form” broadly: while a good can be provided in a non-exclusionary form by making it accessible to everyone free of charge, it can also be so provided if there is a token charge, yet one that every person can easily afford.5

The distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is important because it allows us to keep two things apart: the deliberate choice about the mode of provision of goods and the market failure resulting from the inability to exclude others. The distinction is close in spirit to, but not identical with, one that Vaughn Bryan Baltzly (2021) and Anomaly (2021) have recently drawn between public goods and publicized goods. For Baltzly, publicized goods are goods “whose ‘public’ character results only from a policy decision to make some (otherwise private) good freely and universally available” (2021, p. 376). Anomaly, discussing public health measures, characterizes as publicized “goods that are made public through the incentives created by government mandates” (2021, p. 2), where a good being public primarily means that its consumption imposes externalities on others (2021, p. 6). The notion of publicized goods, like that of contingently public goods, picks up on the fact that society can frequently decide whether to offer universal, free access to a specific good. Yet, unlike the notion of contingently public goods, it imposes no restriction on the extent to which a good is rivalrous. It is, for this reason, much broader: if a state provides apples for free, they become a publicized good, but not a contingently public good. As comes out in the discussion below, having the narrower, more precise term “contingently public goods” is valuable because it allows us to pick out those goods whose public provision promises efficiency gains.

The remainder of the article is an attempt to show that the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is valuable and that the importance of contingently public goods has been underappreciated. Three points should be noted at the outset though. First, the distinction is arguably better conceived of as demarcating a spectrum than a categorical divide: few goods are inherently non-excludable; instead, exclusion may be more or less costly. Second, whether some good is non-excludable, and for this reason inherently public, depends on the state of technology and may change6: if, in some dystopian future, people need to pay for access to biodomes, then clean air will have turned into a contingently public good. Finally, just as few goods are entirely non-rivalrous, few are non-excludable: the fact that I go for a run in the park does not diminish its availability, but if a crowd of people clogs pathways and occupies all picnic spots, this does diminish the park's availability (or value) to others—at the limit, the park becomes a rivalrous good. So, the criterion of non-rivalry should not be interpreted too strictly; instead, we may distinguish between public goods that are more pure or impure depending on their degree of rivalry—at a given level of consumption, or across a range of levels.

Note, moreover, that the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods is orthogonal to several other distinctions that have been drawn within the debate on public goods. For example, Ferdman (2018) distinguishes between universal and nonuniversal public goods, where the former are valued by all whereas the latter are only valued by some. Even more prominently, some authors (see e.g., Claassen, 2013; Miller & Taylor, 2018) have drawn a distinction between essential (or necessary) and discretionary public goods, where the provision of the former, but not the latter, is required by justice.7 But the fact that some good is an inherently public good (or a contingently public one) neither affects whether it is universal, nor whether it is essential.8 This is explained by the fact that the classification of a good as inherently or contingently public is based merely on its structural properties, namely on whether it is excludable in principle or merely provided in a non-exclusionary form; but these structural properties evidently determine neither whether a good is valued by everyone, nor whether it is critical for justice.9 So, the terminological distinction advocated here is new and independent of the existing ones. At the same time, the different specifications can of course be combined; we can, for example, have a contingently public goods that is essential and universal.

An important strand of the recent philosophical debate of public goods has operated at the level of ideal theory and has focused on the question of justice: according to which criteria should burdens and benefits of the provision of public goods be distributed to preserve conditions of justice (see e.g., Claassen, 2013; Miller, 2004; Murphy & Nagel, 2001)? This section puts forward two novel objections against the various benefit principles that have been proposed in response to this question. The objection from unequal access to club goods asserts that these benefit principles mandate unacceptable transfer payments to the privately wealthy. The objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods asserts that the benefit principles, unless qualified, mandate unacceptable transfer payments to people who disvalue their inclusive mode of provision. Both these objections draw on the case of contingently public goods: in each case, it is the possibility of providing the respective public goods as club goods that generates a problem. More specifically, these objections draw on a specific subset of contingently public goods: those whose provision is not directly required by justice (and which are therefore also discretionary in the sense further explored below).

The discussion of the demands of justice in the provision of public goods is motivated by two observations (see Miller & Taylor, 2018, esp. 562–64). On the one hand, there are some public goods that are required for justice. Consider the rule of law. Broadly understood as the effective restraint on arbitrary use of power through enforcement of legal rules and procedures, it qualifies as an (immaterial) public good. Moreover, it is presupposed by virtually all theories of justice: for what would be the point of allocating resources, if individuals were subject to the arbitrary exercise of power by others who could take them away (or impose physical harm)? On the other hand, there are goods whose provision is not required by justice, but generates a concern of justice: assuming an initially just society, how should the benefits and costs of their provision be allocated?10 Goods of the former type, “whose provision is itself a matter of justice”, are typically called “essential public goods” (Miller & Taylor, 2018, p. 564) or “necessary public goods” (Claassen, 2013, p. 273). Goods of the latter type, whose provision is not required by justice, are labeled “discretionary public goods” (Claassen, 2013, p. 273; Miller & Taylor, 2018, p. 564).11

Proponents of social theories of justice have not given much thought to discretionary public goods, and where they have considered them at all, they have typically endorsed procedural criteria.12 John Rawls, for instance, initially stipulated that the state may provide (discretionary) public goods only “when they satisfy Wicksell's unanimity criterion” (1999, p. 248), which makes their legitimate provision dependent on everyone's consent to a proposal specifying (i) the good to be provided and (ii) the tax schedule to pay for it (Wicksell, 1958). In his later work (Rawls, 2001), Rawls came to relax the unanimity condition, proposing instead a simple majority vote.13 As noted by Miller (2004), the problem with procedural approaches is that even if one thinks that they provide an account of legitimacy, they are silent on the question of distributive justice. But the surplus from the provision of discretionary public goods can be distributed in various ways—and not all appear (equally) just.

In light of the weaknesses of procedural accounts, some authors have advocated substantive criteria (Miller, 2004; Murphy & Nagel, 2001). They propose to address the question of justice in the provision of public goods in two steps. First, we identify the set of essential public goods, whose provision is required by justice; for these goods, the distribution of costs is determined by our theory of justice. In a second step, we consider discretionary public goods, and it is at this stage that we need an additional principle to determine the distribution of costs and benefits. The most basic such principle is the benefit principle, which requires the provision of discretionary public goods to benefit everyone. But this principle is highly permissive; assuming self-interested voting, even the unanimity condition implies that the benefit principle is met. Two more restrictive principles have been advanced. Murphy and Nagel (2001) propose14 that every person should contribute to the cost of providing discretionary public goods in proportion to the benefits she receives; call this the proportional benefit principle. Miller (2004) proposes that discretionary public goods should be provided so as to equalize the net benefits individuals receive; call this the equal benefit principle.

These principles have prompted objections. For example, Miller has criticized the proportional benefit principle as treating the state like an enterprise: insisting on contributions in proportion to benefits, he claims, contradicts the idea of a political community “whose foundational principle is that each member holds an equal stake” (2004, 144). Yet, Miller's equal benefit principle appears vulnerable to a related objection. In insisting on strictly equal benefits, one seems to adopt toward society the perspective of a jealous child. Among siblings, the equal benefit principle might have some bite: if one child does not like chocolate, but her brother does, she might insist that, if chocolates are the only sweets available, then, for reasons of justice, neither of them should get any. But at the level of society, insisting on a principle that prohibits the provision of public goods in circumstances where it would harm no one and benefit many seems to reveal a pathological insistence on an “equal share,” exposing a lack of generosity that can be expected toward fellow citizens. In addition, Miller and Taylor (2018, 568) have argued that the proportional benefit principle is incomplete. If two distinct sets of discretionary public goods satisfy the proportionality requirement, the principle does not tell us which one to choose.15 Assuming that we aim to maximize benefits, the equal benefit principle avoids this problem. But it is highly restrictive in other regards: unless benefits can be equalized, a good cannot be provided, even if everyone were to benefit from it. As Miller and Taylor note (2018, 569), this appears to render the equal benefit principle vulnerable to a leveling-down objection (though transfer schemes might help address this problem).16

Contingently public goods motivate two additional, and more fundamental objections, which apply to the various benefit principles simultaneously. First, there is the objection from unequal access to club goods: because contingently public goods are in principle exclusionary, they could be provided as club goods, but an unequal initial distribution of private resources implies unequal access to such club goods, which affects the distribution of benefits from their provision as public goods; as a result, the benefit principles mandate implausible transfers to the individually wealthy. This objection can be illustrated by reference to the case of a public swimming pool. A swimming pool that is accessible to everyone free of charge, or for a token fee, is an (impure) public good. We may initially think that all swimmers benefit from it. But suppose an individually wealthy swimmer argues that she does not benefit: because she is a member to a fitness club that offers pool access, she claims to gain nothing from a public pool. The proportional benefit principle, she holds, implies that she must contribute nothing, whereas the benefit principle and the equal benefit principle imply that she is even owed compensation.

Of course, how the public pool affects the wealthy swimmer depends on the exact specification of the case. If her sole motivation for purchasing membership to the club was to gain pool access, she can cancel her membership once the public pool has been built and her benefit is captured by the money saved on the club membership. As a result, she benefits from the public pool and has to contribute to its costs of provision. Even in this case, however, part of her benefit may escape accounting. For if she had been willing to pay more for the club membership than was required, she was able to secure a surplus benefit privately, and this surplus benefit does not count toward her benefit from access to the public pool. By contrast, the entire benefit from pool access is taken into account for those who initially lacked all pool access. But, one might argue, if the initial distribution was just, then this is fine: while part of the benefit the wealthy gain from public goods escapes accounting, it is the part they had already obtained from access to the club good—so, the provision of a public pool maintains but does not increase their advantage.

Next, however, consider a variation of the case. Suppose that the well-off swimmer decides not to use the public pool, but to keep her club membership. As she does not derive any benefit from the public pool, the equal benefit principle mandates a compensatory payment to the wealthy swimmer, provided there is a surplus benefit to building the public pool.17 The proportional benefit principle similarly justifies compensation if the public pool disbenefits the wealthy swimmer. Suppose that, once the public pool is built, some club members leave the fitness club, prompting a fee hike. If a wealthy swimmer decides to maintain her club membership, for example because she sufficiently values the other benefits of membership, then the provision of the public pool generates a disbenefit to her. Even according to the proportional benefit principle, she should thus make a negative contribution to the costs of providing the public pool, that is, she is owed compensation.

These implications of the benefit principles appear puzzling. If an initial distribution of private goods is just, one might grant the well-off any benefit they obtain from purchasing club goods that are unaffordable to others. One might perhaps even accept that, if they prefer their respective club goods, they do not need to contribute to the costs of providing public goods. But it does not seem plausible to assign them claims to compensation. If a group of people is willing to carry all costs of making some good freely available to everyone, can they really be required to fund transfer payments to wealthy people who prefer to consume an equivalent club good, yet are not made any worse off? Now, it is important to be cautious here. If we make a judgment on whether some person can reasonably claim compensation in a particular case, this judgment will ultimately rest in part on our intuitions about this case (as well as our intuitions about relevant other cases, to which the systematic account that underpins our judgment extends). Since the argument here proceeds at the level of ideal theory, we need to ensure that we are not led astray by intuitions about nonideal cases. Perhaps, one might worry, we deem the claim to compensation unreasonable simply because, in the world we inhabit, it would be absurd to compensate those who are wealthy and already have access to club goods. But assuming an initially just allocation of private goods, might it not simply be correct that we need to compensate those who receive less benefit, or even a disbenefit, because they already had access to the relevant goods in the form of club goods?

In my view, even under ideal circumstances, the demand for compensation is not plausible. The difference between cases where some are exempt from contributing and cases where they deserve compensation can be drawn by reference to the market as an alternative mode of provision. If those who favor a given public good could secure it by coordinating in a market, then they could provide it privately—in this case, the person with access to a corresponding club good would make no contribution, but they would also not be compensated. So, the outcome of the first type of case—no contribution by those with access to club goods—aligns with the market outcome, whereas the outcome of the second type of case—compensation to those with existing access to club goods—diverges from the market outcome. Of course, the mere fact that the hypothetical market outcome would involve no compensation does not imply that this is the correct view in a case where the state provides a good: the demands on the state differ from those on private market participants. But the divergence to the market-based outcome indicates that compensation is harder to justify than non-contribution, and especially where it is owed for a relative lack of benefit rather than for an indirect harm (due to costlier club goods). Note, moreover, that the state's involvement in the provision of the respective public goods may here be quite minimal—the state may simply provide an enforcement mechanism that allows those individuals who consent to chip in to collectively provide a public good that is then available to everyone. At least in such a case, even under initial conditions of justice, admitting the demand for compensation would effectively allow the better off to leverage their initial advantage to secure settlements from the worse off even though they already shoulder the entire cost of the state's provision of goods that are valuable and accessible to everyone. But this does not appear just—and even if the initial advantage attained through greater access to club goods was just.

But suppose one were to reject this argument and insist that, because the state always must treat everyone equally, as soon as it gets involved in the provision of discretionary public goods, compensation is indeed owed. In this case, the argument from unequal access to club goods points to a more fundamental concern: relative to which baseline is equal treatment to be ensured? In addressing this concern, it is helpful to first summarize an insight by Claassen (2013). Claassen argues that Miller's equal benefit principle disadvantages people whose conception of the good life relies heavily on the consumption of public goods relative to market goods (2013, pp. 278–81). In a pure market economy, he notes, those who favor public goods find themselves at a disadvantage relative to those who favor market goods—few public goods are provided. But this disadvantage is preserved, if we introduce public goods, yet require that everyone benefits equally from their provision: for while everyone will now be better off, everyone will be equally better off, so relative positions remain unchanged. This casts doubt on the justifiability of the benchmark of a pure market economy. The objection from unequal access to club goods casts further doubt on this benchmark, but on different grounds. For it shows that, with a pure market economy as our starting point, part of the benefit that wealthier people obtain from the provision of contingently public goods escapes accounting—namely the part they had managed to already secure in a private market for club goods that serve as substitutes. The benchmark used by the benefit principles thus not only disadvantages those who prefer public goods, but also the less wealthy.

The argument from unequal access to club goods reveals that regardless of people's conceptions of the good life (and whether preferences for public goods qualify as constitutive of such conceptions), the extent to which one stands to reap net benefits from access to contingently public goods will, ceteris paribus, correlate negatively with one's initial wealth. This reveals the benefit principles to be implausible, as it shows that they demand highly regressive compensation in the context of public good provision. This line of argument aligns with Claassen's in casting doubt on the starting point endorsed by the benefit principles, but is distinct in three ways. First, whereas Claassen focuses on preferences for public versus market goods, the concern here are wealth inequalities: my argument contends that the starting point of a pure market society disadvantages some people regardless of their preferences, simply because the less wealthy stand to gain more from the provision of contingently public goods relative to a pure market economy, and the assumption of such an economy as our reference point therefore relatively disadvantages these people. Second, the argument put forward here draws explicitly on the distinction between inherently and contingently public goods: contingently public goods are those that could alternatively have been provided in a more exclusionary form as club goods, and it is the unequal initial access to such club goods that generates the implausibly regressive distributive demands of the benefit principles. Finally, Claassen draws a more modest conclusion: instead of rejecting the benefit principles, he only maintains that one could reasonably take a different view, advocating for what one could call a position of “meta-neutrality”: he proposes to remain neutral as to whether one should remain neutral toward individuals' preferences (and distribute resources across all market and public goods to equalize welfare levels) or whether one should remain neutral toward individuals' preferences against the backdrop of a pure market society (and thus endorse the equal benefit principle).18 By contrast, my claim is stronger: it is that, at least given their benchmark of a pure market economy, the proposed benefit principles are implausible because they demand highly regressive compensation payments for the provision of contingently public goods.

In addition, there is an objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods: the benefit principles, implausibly, mandate compensation to people who disvalue the provision of contingently public goods merely because they disvalue their inclusive mode of provision. As Claassen's argument summarized above reveals, the assumption of neutrality toward individual preferences concerning the provision of discretionary public goods is not as innocent as is generally presumed. But while Claassen presents the question about the preference for market versus public goods as being primarily about which goods are provided, in the case of contingently public goods, we need to distinguish between the specific good provided (e.g., a park) and its mode of provision (as a public good or a club good). We need to draw this distinction because a market could provide such goods as club goods; and the distinction matters because people can value a good itself as well as its mode of provision. Ferdman (2018, pp. 666–67) notes this possibility of intrinsically valuing public goods: a person may value a good, like a public park, for its universal accessibility. The person who intrinsically values public parks would, ceteris paribus, prefer a public park to a private park to which she, but not everyone else, had access.19 But there is also the corresponding possibility of intrinsically disvaluing public goods: just as one can value public goods because of their mode of provision, so one can disvalue them due to their inclusive mode of provision. And this attitude is not just a theoretical possibility: in racist societies, people have historically objected to the provision of public goods, like beaches, public transportation, and libraries, on the ground that such goods should not be equally available to everyone.

The possibility of intrinsically disvaluing public goods gives rise to a challenge to the benefit principles, but its precise form depends on one's interpretation of the principle of neutrality that underpins them. The benefit principles are embedded in a liberal framework, which demands neutrality toward the preferences of citizens. The proponents of the benefit principles do not qualify, nor further discuss, the underlying notion of neutrality. According to a literal interpretation, (i) neutrality demands that one be neutral toward all preferences unless explicitly specified otherwise. On this interpretation, the possibility of an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods generates an objection. Consider person A, living in a class-based society, who deems herself a member of the upper class, and objects to the provision of public parks on the sole ground that their universal accessibility fails to respect a status distinction among members of different classes. Moreover, suppose that A is an indoors person, who enters neither public, nor private parks, and would never have learned of the public parks had she not read about it in her upper-class gazette. In this case, A's, preference against public provision contradicts the spirit of the political community, negating a basic understanding of others as equals. It is for this reason that I believe it would not warrant consideration: A could not reasonably demand compensation for the disbenefit the provision of public parks imposes on her. But this shows that the benefit principles must be qualified: their statement needs to expressly exclude some instances of intrinsic disvaluation of public goods.

However, at this point, one might interject that the principle of neutrality could also be interpreted differently. Indeed, its literal, unqualified interpretation may be deemed naïve: it requires remaining neutral regarding all preferences, including immoral ones. Although this is not explicitly stated, one might therefore insist, proponents of the benefit principles implicitly assume that at least some immoral preferences be excluded from consideration. But if one adopts this view, then one might respond that the above example is moralized and therefore needs to be rejected: A's preference not to have parks as public goods is immoral because it is based on immoral classist preferences; therefore, the principle of neutrality does not apply here, so A's preference does not warrant compensation, and no problem arises for the benefit principles. This response prompts the question: can we find a non-moralized example, which is not excluded by the principle of neutrality, but where a person's intrinsic disvaluation of a public good does not warrant compensation?

In addressing this question, note first that while the claim that the principle of neutrality should not include immoral preferences rules out its literal interpretation (i), it does not entail a specific alternative. Instead, it is consistent with at least three different interpretations of the principle: (ii) it demands neutrality toward all preferences except for a set implicitly put aside as immoral; (iii) it demands neutrality toward all preferences bar those that are in fact immoral; (iv) it stipulates that a preference is immoral if and only we need not remain neutral toward it. Now, on interpretation (iv), a non-moralized example is ruled out by definition. This is because (iv) stipulates that, whenever we should not remain neutral toward a preference, then this preference is to count as immoral. It follows, by definition, that when we should not compensate a person for intrinsically disvaluing a public good (i.e., should not be neutral), then this preference is immoral—so, there can be no non-moralized example. In this way, interpretation (iv) rules out any objection from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods. But this comes at a high cost. If interpreted in this way, the principle of neutrality makes a conceptual, rather than a substantial claim. This not only renders it uninformative: nothing is said about how extensive the set of immoral preferences is, nor why we should not be neutral toward them. More importantly, it turns the order of explanation upside down: the claim no longer is that we should not remain neutral toward a preference because it is immoral, but instead that a preference qualifies as immoral because we should not remain neutral toward it. In my view, this implication renders implausible the interpretation of the principle of neutrality as making a conceptual claim. But note that, even if one were to insist on interpretation (iv), the above argument about A's intrinsic disvaluation of public parks would be of some value: it would identify a specific type of preference with regard to which we should not remain neutral and provide reasons as why.

By contrast, interpretations (ii) and (iii), which make a substantial claim, allow for the possibility of a non-moralized example. I believe that such an example can be given. Consider B, who lives in an egalitarian republic. B, too, is an indoors person, who never uses parks. Still, she dislikes parks being provided as public goods because she dislikes universal accessibility. This is not due to classist or racist views; it just so happens that B prefers for goods to be privately rather than publicly available. B's case thus differs from A's: B's intrinsic disvaluation of public parks is not based on any other morally tainted preferences or beliefs. B does not object to the public provision because it would fail to respect a status difference; she simply has a preference for private goods. This preference on its own, I contend, is too innocent to qualify as immoral; it is a preference that does not express any disrespect toward, or repugnant views about, other people. But at the same time, and like in the case of A, B's intrinsic disvaluation of the public goods it is not a preference that warrants consideration when assessing the benefits and damages from the provision of public parks. This is because B's preference not to have parks as public goods is not well-motivated: by assumption, B does not intend to use the parks, so whether they are publicly accessible is of no relevance to B's ability to enjoy them (or any other goods), and B therefore suffers no meaningful harm from their provision as public goods. In assessing benefits, we need to take into consideration that, as an indoors person, B fails to benefit from the provision of public parks, but not that B disvalues their mode of provision.

If this line of argument is correct, then B's case qualifies as a non-moralized example, which shows that, according to the qualified interpretations (ii) and (iii) of the principle of neutrality, the benefit principles must be restricted: at least sometimes, disbenefits that result from the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods should be disregarded. Yet, even if one were to dispute this by insisting that B's preference is immoral or that B has a claim to compensation, my argument would still highlight the need for proponents of benefit principles to address the following question: under which conditions is an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods an immoral preference that may thus be ignored, and why? This is a serious question, because the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods does not always appear to be immoral: vulnerable groups and minorities for instance arguably have good reason to demand spaces which are not accessible to everyone. It is less evident whether an intrinsic disvaluation of public goods could be justified if one never intends to use the respective good, however, or would not notice its use by others: may a religious group justifiably object to some mountain's universal accessibility because they consider it sacred, even if they would never notice if anyone else were to go there?

If sound, then the two objections put forward in this section have two implications. At the substantial level, they show that the existing benefit principles, which have been proposed to complement existing theories of justice to account for discretionary public goods, are deficient in ways that have so far escaped notice. At the theoretical level, they reveal the importance of taking account of contingently public goods in examining the demands of justice in the provision of discretionary public goods. This is because neither of the objections put forward in this section could have been raised with equal effect by reference to inherently public goods. Inherently public goods could not alternatively have been provided as club goods (though imperfect substitutes might), so concerns about unequal access to these goods in a market do not arise in their case (or, at least, not in exactly the same way). And because these goods are, by definition, non-excludable, it would be incoherent to welcome the good itself, yet object to its inclusive mode of provision.

But the two objections also indicate a more constructive task, namely, to specify the benefit principle one should adopt instead.20 While the arguments put forward imply two conditions that an alternative benefit principle would have to meet, they do not yield comprehensive specification of such a principle. The two conditions they imply are as follows: first, the principle must be “club-good sensitive,” that is, it needs to specify under which conditions those who already had access to a club good that is then provided as a public good lack a claim to compensation; second, it must qualify the demand for neutrality, or more specifically, it needs to specify under which conditions preferences against public goods may or must be disregarded. But these two conditions can evidently be satisfied in numerous ways, and the above arguments do not yield any specific principle. Regarding club goods, for example, I have argued that those who had access to a club good cannot plausibly demand compensation for the provision of corresponding public good, if this provision does not make them worse off; but this leaves undetermined whether they can claim compensation if the provision in fact does make them worse off, and how much they must contribute if they benefit, but less so than everyone else. Meanwhile, regarding the intrinsic disvaluation of public goods, I have only argued that it sometimes cannot ground a claim to compensation, while admitting that it may in certain other contexts.

There are three reasons for which I refrain from attempting to defend any alternative principle here. First, I believe that good reasons can be put forward in favor of the equal as well as the proportional benefit principle (and perhaps also in favor of intermediary ones), so it is not evident which baseline to choose. But defending a specific view within this debate would divert from the article's argumentative trajectory. Second, I believe that one can reasonably disagree on how exactly the two conditions identified above should be met. In particular, as noted above, it does not appear obvious under exactly which conditions one may be justified in objecting to the inclusive mode of provision of contingently public goods. Finally, while relevant, the task of specifying an alternative is not critical to the aim of this article: it is not needed to show that contingently public goods are a neglected subset of public goods that is of relevance to the philosophical debate.

The preceding section has operated at the level of ideal theory, raising objections to principles that have been proposed to govern the provision of public goods in the context of an initially just society. In the actual world, circumstances are less favorable: we confront the provision of public goods against a background of numerous social injustices. In addition to injustices in the distribution of private resources, there are other types of social injustices, like unwarranted inequalities in opportunity and status. This section therefore moves on to discuss the provision of public goods under initially unjust or imperfectly just conditions. In so doing, part of its argument applies to public goods in general, while part of it applies specifically to contingently public goods. The central claim about public goods in general is that their provision holds the potential to render economic inequalities less relevant and to reduce inequalities in opportunity by reducing the importance of access to private resources, and that this can at times be an attractive alternative to other, transfer-based policies. Evidently, the provision of public goods will not always have this effect: it could instead even exacerbate existing injustices, as would happen, for instance, in an unjustly inegalitarian society where expensive, tax-funded public goods cater exclusively to the interests of the rich.21 With regard to contingently public goods more specifically, the section claims that they hold a distinctive, fourfold potential which arises from the fact that they in principle allow exclusion and could have been provided in the form of club goods. First, because it can be possible to provide a contingently public good simply by removing restrictions on access to an existing club good, it can be especially efficient at addressing injustices. Moreover, and relatedly, because their provision can at times be costless, contingently public goods can, at least under certain conditions, avoid the standard objection of involving a market interference. Third, because contingently public goods could have been provided as exclusionary club goods, their public mode of provision can be an especially powerful expression of a commitment to inclusiveness, which is critical where status inequalities are of concern. Finally, the provision of contingently public goods has a special potential to undermine the relevance of club goods, and to thereby remove a critical barrier to equality of opportunity.

In making the case that public goods have the potential to rectify injustices, I begin by considering injustices that are the result of economic inequality. Of course, not all economic inequalities are injustices; some reflect inequalities in desert or are otherwise justified (in fact, economic equality could reflect an injustice). The following arguments therefore apply only to inequalities that in fact amount to injustices. Economic inequality is typically measured by the inequality in personal income, or earning power, and wealth. Prominent measures, like the Gini coefficient, illustrate this. The Gini coefficient is an aggregate measure of the extent of economic inequality, and it is typically computed for the distribution of wealth and for the distribution of income. It can also be used to assess the extent to which redistributive measures like taxation and social subsidies affect income inequality. While important, measures like the Gini coefficient are in an important sense incomplete. They fail to capture how important ownership of private material resources is in the first place. But the importance of ownership of private resources may vary significantly. In a society where all lakeshores are privatized, individuals need private resources that enable them to purchase access if they want to swim in a lake. In a society where lakes are publicly accessible, private resources are not required for this purpose. This point generalizes: societies can be set up in ways that render the possession of private material resources more important or less. One critical factor determining the importance of ownership of private resources is the extent to which a society provides public goods. While there appears to be no straightforward way of quantifying, for a given society, the importance of ownership of private resources or the extent of the provision of public goods, both are significant concerns. Conceiving of economic inequality exclusively in terms of the distribution of private resources therefore ignores the extent to which ownership of such resources is necessary for access to valuable goods. But it appears sensible to be concerned with economic inequality not simply in the sense of being concerned about the distribution of income and wealth, but rather in the sense of being concerned about differences in what people are able to do, given the current distribution of income and wealth.

These considerations reveal that the provision of public goods can be a means to indirectly address inequalities in income and wealth—by reducing their relevance. But not merely can they be a means to do so: it appears plausible that their outright provision is, at least sometimes, more efficient, and politically more feasible, than the redistribution of private resources. There is an economic rationale for why it may be more efficient. In so far as public goods are non-rivalrous (or imperfectly rivalrous), their consumption by some does not (or does not significantly) diminish their availability for consumption by others. This means that providing a good as a contingently public good rather than as a club good typically comes with efficiency gains—it increases accessibility at no additional cost. If we are, concerned with economic inequality because of the resulting differences in what people can do given the economic resources they have, then the provision of public goods may thus be more effective: it may be possible to achieve greater progress toward economic equality for any given level of taxation. In addition, and relatedly, there is a political rationale for why addressing economic inequalities by providing public goods may be practically more feasible. In so far as the public good is available to all, and therefore potentially benefits everyone, the wealthy may be more willing to pay taxes for its direct provision than to finance targeted transfer payments to the less well-off. As Kohn notes, “[u]niversal benefits tend to have higher levels of political support than means-tested programs” (2020, p. 9).

While this argument holds for public goods quite generally, contingently public goods promise to be particularly efficient at achieving this. For because corresponding club goods may already exist, it may be possible to turn a club good into a contingently public good at effectively no cost, thereby increasing access without making anyone worse off. For the purpose of illustration, consider a company operating a pay-tv channel in a society experiencing high levels of economic inequality. Suppose that this company cannot use price discrimination, so it attempts to set its universal subscription rate at the profit-maximizing price. As a result, there will be some people who would value access to the channel, but do not subscribe, either because they do not value it sufficiently or because they simply lack the means to pay for the subscription.22 If the channel could be made accessible to everyone at no additional cost, then transforming it into a contingently public good promises efficiency gains. Moreover, if those willing to subscribe can be taxed at the current subscription rate, then doing so would not make anyone worse off. Now picture a society where economic inequality is of concern primarily because it results in unequal access to pay-tv. In this case, the best way for the state to address economic inequality may be to pay a lump sum subsidy to the tv-channel if it makes the program available to everyone. This ensures universal access and it may do so in a more efficient way than redistributive transfer payments could. Moreover, it may be more feasible as even existing subscribers may not object to being taxed at the current subscription rate to pay for universal access.

Of course, this scenario is schematic and avoids important complications. In all likelihood, it will not be possible to tax exactly those who would otherwise subscribe to a channel, so using general tax revenue may force some to contribute to goods they would prefer not to be provided. Moreover, subsidies eliminate the need for tv-channels to convince customers to subscribe by providing desired content. This highlights that, once we consider specific contingently public goods, we must weigh the benefits and disbenefits of providing these goods as public goods. The public provision of goods will be justifiable, on the basis of concerns about economic equality, only where access is sufficiently central to our concerns about economic inequality. In this regard, public libraries are arguably a more compelling case because economic inequalities are of greater concern if they limit access to education than if they limit access to pay-tv.23 At the same time, building libraries that offer free and universal access instead of relying on transfer payments to ensure that everyone is in a position to become a patron at a private library may well be the more economically efficient and the more feasible choice politically. But regardless of one's view about specific cases, the general point holds: sometimes, the provision of contingently public goods can help address economic inequalities in an effective and targeted (if perhaps partial) way.

Moreover, and this is a second feature that sets contingently public goods apart, they can at times escape the standard objection that the provision of public goods always needs justification because it requires taxation. Advocates and opponents of public goods alike typically suggest that unless we are in the fortunate position where their provision can be secured through assurance contracts or is financed by charities, it requires a state to tax firms or individuals to then use these funds to provide the goods (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Schmidtz, 1991). It is for this reason that it is typically the provision of public goods that is taken to require justification. Even those (see e.g., Ferdman, 2018; Kallhoff, 2014) who argue in favor of the provision of an extensive set of public goods implicitly accept that it is the provision of public goods that needs to be justified and offer such justifications. But there are at least two alternative ways in which a state can secure the provision of contingently public goods. First, where a non-rivalrous good already exists in the form of a club good, but some are excluded based on noneconomic criteria like gender, the state can issue regulations that prohibit such grounds of exclusion, thereby enlarging access and turning the good into a public good. Consider a privately run swimming pool, which is the only one far and near. If this pool excludes a specific group based on noneconomic criteria (e.g., men or persons of Asian descent), then we have a club good. Now, suppose the state introduces regulation prohibiting exclusion on such grounds and that the fee charged by the pool is small enough to effectively ensure universal access. In this case, the swimming pool (or, more precisely, pool access), has turned from a club good into a public good. Such a solution will not be available for all contingently public goods. Yet, it shows that at least sometimes, the state can ensure the provision of a public good without directly providing it, namely be prohibiting certain grounds of exclusion. Doing so does not require any state expenditure and consequently no taxation, though one might insist that issuing such regulation still amounst to a form of market interference.

In addition, whether certain contingently public goods are provided may directly depend on the initial allocation and specification of property rights. Public lands, such as woods, lakes, and plains, have a public good character: being accessible to everyone, they offer opportunities for recreation. But the decision to assign private property rights in these lands precedes the existence of a market, so it does not constitute a market interference. Moreover, a public good character can be preserved even for private goods if property rights are restricted in ways that grant everyone access. In the Nordic countries, the “right to roam” has existed for centuries, whereas private landowners in England and the United States have enjoyed much greater discretion in excluding others. Contingently public goods thus indicate that not all decisions on the provision of public goods amount to a market interference—some simply concern the market's set-up. Of course, this point holds most immediately at a rather abstract level: in the world we live in, property rights in most assets (though not in all, note for instance the oceans and outer space) have already been assigned, so any change to these property rights amounts to a form of market interference. Still, the fact that the initial decision to assign a particular set of property rights to specific assets affected the availability of contingently public goods provides at least a principled justification for such an interference: because the initial decision, which did not precede the market's existence, simultaneously determined the availability of public goods, amending existing property right claims is easier to justify (provided adequate compensation is offered where applicable).

While economic inequalities can constitute one sort of social injustice, social injustices can take other forms as well. In fact, the proposal to address economic inequalities through the provision of public goods presupposes that these inequalities are a concern primarily because they result in inequalities of opportunity and access: the provision of contingently public goods may leave existing inequalities in the ownership of private resources unchanged yet ensure greater equality of opportunity and access by offering an alternative to market consumption. And while inequalities in opportunity, access, and status may arise from economic ones, they need not. The case of a private country club illustrates this. Typically, such clubs charge hefty membership fees, which effectively exclude those who are not wealthy. But there can also be other grounds for exclusion. Historically, membership to country clubs has frequently been restricted on the basis of gender and race. Such restrictions are in one sense correlated with access money: if those excluded had the means to establish their own clubs, their lack of access could be alleviated. But at least from the perspective of the individual, it may well be the case that their exclusion is due to their gender or race rather than due to a lack of personal wealth.

This points to two additional ways in which contingently public goods hold a distinctive potential for addressing injustices. Where some members of society are deprived of access and thereby of opportunity and status on nonmaterial grounds, public goods can offer respite in two ways. First, in so far as public goods are freely available to all, they directly provide a shared realm of experience and social interaction and thereby constitute what Kallhoff calls “connectivity goods” (2014, pp. 642–44)—goods that not only enlarge access, but constitute a point of interaction and symbolize the commitment to shared space and equality. This is true not only, but especially of contingently public ones: because contingently public goods could have been provided in an exclusionary form, their public provision is a more decisive expression of this commitment to equality. In a society where status inequalities are a concern—think, for example, of a state with a strong divide among castes or ethnicities or religious groups—the provision of a contingently public good can be of great symbolic significance: due to the deliberate mode of its universally accessible mode of provision, it can be a powerful expression of a commitment to the equality of all citizens (and in a way not quite achievable with an inherently public good, which could not have been provided in a more exclusive form).

Second, and more indirectly, the provision of public goods tends to undermine the market's more exclusive modes of provision, and thereby the relevance of club goods in particular. Again, this is true of all public goods, but in particular of contingently public goods, because their provision can more directly diminish the attractiveness of the club goods to which they correspond. Our earlier example of the swimming pool illustrates this: once a public pool exists, people have less incentive to pay for access to private pools. In this sense, contingently public goods have the tendency to crowd out the corresponding club goods. This point is rarely highlighted, but important: the most promising long-term strategy for addressing inequalities of access that are the result of powerful structures of private clubs may consist in the provision of corresponding public goods that serve as substitutes. In this way, contingently public goods can gradually break the appeal and thereby the power of the more exclusive, private institutions, thereby reducing the inequality in access, and thus the inequalities in opportunity and perceived status it gives rise to.

If this examination is sound, then public goods—and contingently public goods in particular—constitute a natural, but underappreciated focal point for effectively rectifying existing injustices. Specifically, it appears plausible that the provision of contingently public good is a superior alternative to the introduction of a universal basic income (UBI) in at least certain contexts. Although a UBI has been advocated on various grounds, ranging from the justified claims of individuals to their share of the fruits of natural and social resources (see e.g., Van Parijs 1991, pp. 130–31) to its ability to address existing gender and racial injustices (see Bidadanure, 2019, pp. 492–95), it always aims to redistribute private resources relative to the status quo. There are, as indicated above, good reasons to believe that the provision of public goods can be the economically more efficient and politically more feasible policy. This will be the case, for instance, when non-rivalrous goods already exist in form of club goods and access can be universalized at little additional cost. It might also be the case where we can slightly amend private property rights, for instance in land, to ensure that some public good is provided. Moreover, where we confront injustices that are not due to inequalities in material resources, but rules and norms that exclude individuals from participating on equal terms, only the provision of contingently public goods, but not that of a UBI, may be able to rectify them—by effectively enlarging access and by creating a shared realm of interaction.24

This leaves us with a question: under what circumstances ought the state address injustices by providing public goods and when should it resort to other, redistributive measures? Or, more generally, which principles determine what sorts of public goods the state ought to provide? This article does not aim to provide any comprehensive answer to these questions, and for two reasons. On the one hand, the normative question whether a state ought to provide a particular public good must always be evaluated against the current social background conditions. For instance, whether a state ought to provide free sports grounds or ought to take redistributive measures to address an inequality in access to recreational facilities will depend on numerous factors, such as the costs of provision, the availability of information on individual preferences regarding types of sports grounds and the availability of alternative means of provision. So, in any particular case, a specific argument needs to be put forward in favor of the provision of contingently public goods. On the other hand, the account leaves open how different considerations are to be weighed: it remains silent, for instance, on how important economic efficiency is compared to equal access, and on how much weight attaches to the value of solidarity. Instead of providing a normative theory of public goods, this section primarily aims to highlight the potential of public goods to rectify existing injustices—and that this potential is especially pronounced in the case of contingently public goods. The account is thus open-ended, allowing proponents of specific views of the value of public goods and the criteria for injustice to draw on it in evaluating whether, according to them, a given public good ought to be provided.

The potential to rectify existing injustices provides at least a pro tanto justification for the provision of some contingently public goods—and it does so even if this provision is not currently favored by everyone or is not favored by the sum of individual preferences (regardless of how they are to be aggregated). This injustice-based justification of contingently public goods is distinct from the perfectionist justifications that have been advocated elsewhere. It has for instance been argued (compellingly in my view) that public goods can help create conditions of a good life by curbing harmful competition for scarce resources (Ferdman, 2018, p. 670; see also Hussain, 2018) and that they can contribute to a shared feeling of purpose, thereby strengthening “a sense of solidarity” (Kallhoff, 2014, p. 641), and that these benefits support an argument against state-neutrality and can justify the state provision of public goods. The argument put forward here is more modest: it claims that the provision of public goods may be justified by their ability to address existing social injustices, rather than by some independently valuable objective. This is not to say that there is no link: it seems reasonable, for example, to believe that a greater sense of solidarity will prevent certain social injustices from arising in the first place. But the focus differs: the pro tanto justification for public goods that has been proposed here appeals directly to their ability to rectify existing injustices. This, it seems reasonable to think, should make the argument less controversial because the existence of injustices provides a stronger case for action than more perfectionist proposals.

This article falls in line with several recent attempts (de Jongh, 2022; Ferdman & Kohn 2018; Judt, 2010; Kallhoff, 2014; Kohn, 2020) to reassess the role of public goods for a well-ordered society and to elevate them to a more prominent place in political thinking. In response to an ambiguity in how philosophers use the term “public good,” this article has proposed, in Section 2, to draw a distinction between inherently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and non-excludable, and contingently public goods, which are non-rivalrous and, as a matter of choice, provided in a non-exclusionary form. Sections 3 and 4 drew on this distinction to show how the category of contingently public goods is fruitful to philosophical debate. As Section 3 argued, contingently public goods pose a challenge to the various benefit principles that have been proposed to govern the distribution of costs and benefits in the provision of public goods. Because these goods could alternatively be provided in the form of exclusionary club goods, the proposed benefit principles mandate unreasonable transfer payments to the individually wealthy as well as to those who disvalue the public goods' inclusive mode of provision. As Section 4 argued, contingently public goods at the same time provide a natural, yet underappreciated focal point for addressing unwarranted economic inequalities, as well as inequalities in opportunity, access, and status, and thus for rectifying social injustices. Because public goods are equally accessible to everyone, they render the ownership of private resources less important, thereby diminishing the relevance of inequalities in income and wealth and broadening opportunity and access. Contingently public goods are special in four regards: their provision may be costless; it may not require any market interference; it holds the potential to be a particularly powerful expression of everyone's equal status; and it holds a particular potential to undermine the relevance of exclusionary club goods.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信