一个民主,如果我们能保持的话。哈贝马斯公共领域的新结构转型述评

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Cristina Lafont
{"title":"一个民主,如果我们能保持的话。哈贝马斯公共领域的新结构转型述评","authors":"Cristina Lafont","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12663","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Habermas's new book, <i>A New Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere</i>,<sup>1</sup> offers a timely and insightful analysis of the threats that online communication poses to the maintenance of an inclusive public sphere in democratic societies. Amid growing discontent with democracy, there are plenty of reasons to be worried about the increasing deterioration of the political public sphere. In addition to long-standing threats such as the excessive influence of money in political discourse, the potential for manipulation by powerful social groups, and the exclusion of marginalized voices from public discourse, technological innovations such as social media platforms and big data collection are generating new types of threats.</p><p>These threats are being generated more quickly than society's ability to cope with them. The business model of social media platforms is based on maximizing user engagement through data harvesting and algorithmic personalization. The preselection of content for users based on data about their past preferences facilitates the creation of filter bubbles and echo chambers with the consequence that those who rely mainly on social media almost never receive information, news, or opinions that they do not already agree with. These features of social media not only increase group isolation, fragmentation, and polarization but also facilitate the dissemination of misinformation, fake news, conspiracy theories, and the micro-targeted manipulation of voters.</p><p>Amid these threatening developments, we are seeing a decline in traditional media outlets that operate under journalistic norms of impartiality, accuracy, accountability, and so on. Consequently, it is unclear how citizens can stay sufficiently politically informed to engage in meaningful debate with their fellow citizens, even on the most fundamental political problems facing them. At this historical juncture, the danger that a shared sense of community among the citizenry disappears seems alarmingly real. Yet, democratic self-government is only possible if citizens can forge a collective political will by changing one another's hearts and minds in public debate. Without an inclusive public sphere, citizens cannot keep the democracies they have got.<sup>2</sup></p><p>This concern is at the core of Habermas's analysis of the role of social media communication in bringing about a new structural transformation of the public sphere. Indeed, Habermas identifies the <i>inclusive</i> character of the public sphere as the feature that is most in danger of “disappearing” due to the centrifugal forces of social media communication which yield increased fragmentation, polarization, misinformation, and so on.<sup>3</sup> I share Habermas's concern. I am convinced by his analysis of the distinctive threats that social media communication poses to the maintenance of an inclusive public sphere. I also agree with the two main mechanisms that he identifies as most promising for minimizing such threats over the long term: regulations and learning processes. However, I fear that there are some limits to the effectiveness of these mechanisms that Habermas does not discuss.</p><p>In what follows, I offer a brief overview of Habermas's analysis in order to highlight some of these limits. Although I agree with Habermas that a better distribution of responsibilities between social media platforms and users is urgently needed, I argue that it may nonetheless be insufficient for preventing an increased fragmentation of the public sphere (1). This raises the question of whether there are any alternative developments that can help counteract the negative effects of fragmentation and polarization on the political public sphere in democratic societies. As a tentative answer, I briefly explore the potential contribution that citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics may make to the maintenance of an inclusive political public sphere (2).</p><p>Habermas is certainly right to suggest that it is going to take a long time for Internet users to acquire the skills and the media literacy required to properly participate in digitized communication as authors. This hope about learning processes may partly explain why he takes a less skeptical attitude toward this new structural transformation of the public sphere than he did toward the previous one in his groundbreaking 1962 work, <i>The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere</i>.<sup>4</sup> I agree that we should have a hopeful attitude and avoid misplaced nostalgia for the pre-digital era of traditional media outlets. Yet, there is a worrisome dis-analogy between the two technological revolutions that is relevant in our context. Whereas the bulk of the population simply could not participate in mass communication before learning how to read, Internet users were turned into authors overnight. They are participating in mass communication as authors <i>before</i> acquiring any of the requisite media literacy and without any proper regulations. A better analogy would be letting everyone drive on the highway <i>before</i> passing a driving test and without any traffic regulations. We may not have 300 years to fix the ensuing mess!</p><p>Leaving this issue aside, I am also not sure that the main threats to the political public sphere derive from the transformation of readers into authors. In fact, the <i>flipside</i> of this phenomenon seems to be much more salient. The most significant threats are posed by the fact that the new social media operators <i>are no longer authors</i>. As Habermas recognizes, social media platforms “neither produce, nor edit nor select.” They thereby disclaim any responsibility for the consequences of the spread of content that is “unregulated because professional filters are lacking” (p. 159). This is a problematic feature that social media operators share with the gig economy generally. In the same way that social media platforms are “empowering all potential users in principle to become independent and equally entitled authors” (Habermas, <span>2022b</span>, p. 159), platforms like Uber or Lift are “empowering” gig workers to become independent contractors. The flipside of that “empowerment” is that these platforms are no longer “employers” and can therefore relinquish any responsibility for providing labor protections to gig workers, although the latter cannot secure those protections on their own.<sup>5</sup> The main problem with making social media users “authors” or gig workers “independent contractors” is that responsibilities are offloaded onto them <i>under conditions in which they cannot properly discharge them</i>.</p><p>In the case of social media, the problem is not simply that platform users do not have the professional skills and media literacy to properly fulfill the various authorship roles involved in online communication (from editors to reporters, journalists, witnesses, whistleblowers, and so on). This is certainly a problem. But no matter how much social media users improve their authorship skills, there is a clear structural limit. Social media users are also always at the same time passive recipients. Yet, because of the current business model, content spreads across social media according to algorithms that maximize user engagement rather than accuracy. Consequently, targeted recipients often have no way to discern whether the content that appears in their “feeds” is accurate or false, whether it represents the views of fellow citizens or foreign trolls, whether it is generated by a reliable source or by an online bot using a fake account, and so on.<sup>6</sup> To the extent that this is the case, platform users cannot be held responsible for preventing the negative consequences of the spread of misinformation and disinformation, although they certainly contribute to it by sharing, liking, commenting, and so on. Since ought implies can, it is not surprising that online platforms’ creative attempts to relinquish any responsibility are meeting strong resistance. This fight is ongoing. Yet, whereas labor protections for gig workers are still being fought about intensely, content moderation by social media platforms is already here to stay.<sup>7</sup> Devastating incidents like Facebook's role in inciting genocidal violence against Rohingya Muslims in Myanmar have brought social media companies under increasing public pressure. Consequently, these companies have not been able to simply declare themselves “platforms” and their users “authors” as a way of relinquishing their obligation to act as responsible editors and remove harmful content and misinformation from their sites.<sup>8</sup></p><p>Now, I do not mean to suggest that leaving content moderation in the hands of private businesses is an optimal solution to the problem. Far from it. But state regulation of content has problems of its own. In addition to the well-known dangers of state censorship, state agencies or courts could hardly adjudicate the tremendous amount of content that platforms remove each day while also maintaining due process guarantees of legal recourse for users.<sup>9</sup> A third alternative (with its own set of problems) would be enabling users themselves to control the content that appears in their “feeds.” This would require the development of technical means (so-called “middleware”) to restrict access to unwanted content (Keller, <span>2022</span>). Currently, it is unclear what the best solutions might be. The problems are complex and constantly evolving due to technological innovations. Each regulatory option carries the risk of having severe negative effects on the quality of the public sphere. Precisely because of this, it is clear that what citizens need to learn about online communication is not so much how to behave <i>as authors</i> but, above all, how to behave <i>as citizens</i>.</p><p>In democratic societies, citizens are ultimately responsible for demanding adequate regulation of any new technologies and practices that threaten the equal protection of everyone's fundamental rights and freedoms. This does not mean, however, that at this historical juncture, the responsibilities of citizenship vis-à-vis the social media are any easier to discharge than those of online authorship. To the contrary, Habermas’ observation is correct here too. It is likely to take a long time for citizens to learn how to best regulate the communicative practices enabled by new forms of social media so that their beneficial features are enhanced while their disruptive potential is neutralized. However, in this context, it is also important to note that a lot of the threats that Habermas rightly highlights are <i>neither exclusive nor distinctive</i> of social media. Citizens must demand that any media (whether traditional or digitized) is responsible for not spreading disinformation and misinformation. This is not only happening with respect to social media platforms. It is also happening with respect to TV news channels and other outlets. To take just one salient example: TV news was the main source of early Covid-19 misinformation in the United States. Facebook ranked second.<sup>10</sup></p><p>Contrary to Habermas's diagnosis, my fear is that although these problems are certainly exacerbated by social media, they are not a product of the unskilled behavior of Internet users bumbling about in the role of authors. In fact, the polarized and self-segregating mentality that Habermas refers to does not seem to be limited to Internet users at all. The question at stake here is whether online communication is generating these problems or whether users are reproducing online what they do (and always already did) offline.<sup>11</sup> This is an important question. If the social and political fragmentation that takes place in online networks simply <i>reflects</i> the fragmentation of social networks that results from citizens’ free choices in their offline lives (e.g., where people prefer to live, who they like to talk to and engage with, which news channels they prefer to watch, etc.), it is far from clear that regulations on social media or increased media literacy can address such problems. To once again take an example from the United States: recent studies show that a much higher percentage of Americans are politically segregated through television news channels than through online platforms. Television is indeed the top driver of partisan audience segregation among Americans.<sup>12</sup> Moreover, even if it turns out that social media <i>decisively</i> exacerbates the problem, it is also not clear that there is a regulatory mechanism that is compatible with citizens’ freedoms which can impede voluntary online self-segregation (and the ensuing fragmentation, polarization, etc.) any more than there is a mechanism to impede voluntary self-segregation offline (e.g., to regulate citizens’ choices of traditional media outlets, neighborhoods, and schools).</p><p>The concerning levels of fragmentation and polarization in most democratic societies may be caused by a variety of concurrent factors: a sharp increase in social inequality produced by decades of neoliberal capitalism, a corresponding erosion of solidarity, and the emergence of social media. Whatever the ultimate causes of social fragmentation and polarization are far from clear that increasing media literacy or regulating social media platforms can <i>suffice</i> to address the tendencies of an increasing portion of the citizenry to self-segregate both online and offline. This is not to deny that we need to regulate social media in order to counteract the role that algorithm personalization plays in facilitating the creation of filter bubbles and echo chambers. Nor do I mean to suggest that increasing media literacy and providing Internet users with suitable tools to control the content they are exposed to is not urgently needed. However, to the extent that fragmentation and polarization are <i>not a uniquely online phenomena</i> but something that permeates all aspects of society both online and offline, improving online communication will not be enough to maintain an inclusive public sphere.<sup>13</sup> We need additional tools to counteract the negative effects that fragmentation and polarization exert upon the political public sphere.</p><p>In this context, the increasing popularity of citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics such as citizens’ juries and Deliberative Polls is not surprising.<sup>14</sup> Indeed, the <i>inclusiveness</i> that is characteristic of these deliberative fora provides participants with the exact opposite experience of an echo chamber or a polarized political debate. Without suggesting that these institutional innovations could be a panacea, I would like to briefly indicate some specific contributions that they could make toward maintaining an inclusive political public sphere if they were properly institutionalized.</p><p>Political debates in the public sphere tend to be dominated by powerful political actors whose interests often deviate from those of the general public. As mentioned, this has only gotten worse with the spread of social media that facilitates the formation of filter bubbles and echo chambers. In the current media environment, citizens have a hard time not only getting themselves informed (as opposed to being bombarded with fake news, misinformation, conspiracy theories, etc.) but, even more importantly, figuring out the considered opinions of their fellow citizens on important political questions—especially those of citizens with whom they disagree. Citizens frequently cannot tell if the views they are exposed to reflect the genuine oppositional opinions of fellow citizens who disagree with them or whether they reflect the manipulated opinions of powerful actors with particular interests that in no way resonate with the citizenry (e.g., lobbyists, hackers, Internet bots, and foreign governments trolls).</p><p>In such a context, it is not surprising that scholars and practitioners who are familiar with the workings of citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics are enthusiastic about the quality of political deliberation that they facilitate for participants both online and offline. Minipublics facilitate well-informed, high-quality deliberation on important political decisions among a randomly selected sample of citizens that is descriptively representative of the constituency which will be subject to that decision. Indeed, across all relevant dimensions—inclusion, diversity, access to reliable and balanced information, independence, impartiality, orientation toward the public interest, and so on—the deliberative conditions available to minipublics’ participants are the exact opposite of those that prevail in most social forums currently available to citizens. Thus, it does not seem far-fetched to imagine that as more and more citizens become familiar with the workings of minipublics, they would become increasingly enthusiastic about them. Indeed, if deliberative minipublics were institutionalized for a variety of purposes at the local, national, and even transnational levels, they could become an extremely valuable <i>resource</i> to the citizenry precisely at a time when reliable sources of inclusive, well-informed, impartial political deliberation are getting harder and harder to come by.<sup>15</sup> How could minipublics help improve the inclusiveness and the quality of deliberation in the public sphere?</p><p>To begin with, minipublics could serve some important functions that are not very different from those that traditional media outlets (used to) fulfill. As with the latter, their contribution as a resource for the citizenry would not consist of doing the thinking or deciding for them.<sup>16</sup> Rather, it would consist of making the most relevant arguments for and against policies under discussion readily available to citizens.<sup>17</sup> Minipublics can do so by filtering out irrelevant or patently manipulative considerations that cannot survive public scrutiny while highlighting the key information, potential trade-offs, and long-term consequences of the available alternatives as evaluated from the diverse political perspectives that resonate with the citizenry of a political community at a given time.</p><p>Minipublics are particularly well suited to serve this function. Precisely to the extent that their randomly selected participants are a mirror of the whole citizenry, the reasons and considerations that lead them to form their considered judgments are likely to be those that resonate with the rest of the citizenry (Fishkin, <span>2018</span>, p. 72). Moreover, by highlighting the considerations that are most relevant for reaching a considered judgment on the political issue in question, minipublics would not only serve the function of reducing the costs of acquiring that type of information to the public. They would also serve the crucial function of sorting out the “wheat from the chaff,” that is, the information that reflects the considered views of some citizens as opposed to the many distorting claims that are strategically deployed to subvert rather than inform and which are therefore unsustainable in the face of deliberative scrutiny (Niemeyer, <span>2014</span>, p. 14). By testing the available arguments and providing their considered judgments to their fellow citizens, minipublics could play a constructive role in <i>structuring public discourses</i>. Minipublics could act as a regulator of information in the public sphere by doing the hard work of sorting through arguments and providing reasons for the resulting positions to the remainder of the public. Moreover, due to their inclusiveness, minipublics are not only able to identify acceptable public arguments, but they can also help publicize the concerns of marginalized groups that hardly ever find a voice among the most influential political actors.</p><p>Here, it is important to highlight that minipublics’ participants are as diverse as the citizenry itself and are therefore as likely to disagree in their considered opinions on contested political issues as the rest of the citizenry does. However, this does not make minipublics useless. On the contrary, they can provide <i>crucial</i> information to the citizenry if their reasoning and recommendations are made widely available. Knowing the interests, values, and lines of reasoning that resonate with our fellow citizens with respect to contentious political issues is essential precisely in cases when we disagree. For knowing the genuine sources of contention and disagreement on specific political issues—as opposed to the manipulative claims and pseudo-arguments that constantly circulate in the public sphere—would enable citizens to figure out the kind of information, evidence, arguments, or counterarguments that they would need to provide to their fellow citizens in order to move the public debate on these issues forward. This is precisely what citizens can no longer do in an increasingly fragmented and polarized public sphere.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"30 1","pages":"77-83"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12663","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"A democracy, if we can keep it. Remarks on J. Habermas’ a new structural transformation of the public sphere\",\"authors\":\"Cristina Lafont\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12663\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Habermas's new book, <i>A New Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere</i>,<sup>1</sup> offers a timely and insightful analysis of the threats that online communication poses to the maintenance of an inclusive public sphere in democratic societies. Amid growing discontent with democracy, there are plenty of reasons to be worried about the increasing deterioration of the political public sphere. In addition to long-standing threats such as the excessive influence of money in political discourse, the potential for manipulation by powerful social groups, and the exclusion of marginalized voices from public discourse, technological innovations such as social media platforms and big data collection are generating new types of threats.</p><p>These threats are being generated more quickly than society's ability to cope with them. The business model of social media platforms is based on maximizing user engagement through data harvesting and algorithmic personalization. The preselection of content for users based on data about their past preferences facilitates the creation of filter bubbles and echo chambers with the consequence that those who rely mainly on social media almost never receive information, news, or opinions that they do not already agree with. These features of social media not only increase group isolation, fragmentation, and polarization but also facilitate the dissemination of misinformation, fake news, conspiracy theories, and the micro-targeted manipulation of voters.</p><p>Amid these threatening developments, we are seeing a decline in traditional media outlets that operate under journalistic norms of impartiality, accuracy, accountability, and so on. Consequently, it is unclear how citizens can stay sufficiently politically informed to engage in meaningful debate with their fellow citizens, even on the most fundamental political problems facing them. At this historical juncture, the danger that a shared sense of community among the citizenry disappears seems alarmingly real. Yet, democratic self-government is only possible if citizens can forge a collective political will by changing one another's hearts and minds in public debate. Without an inclusive public sphere, citizens cannot keep the democracies they have got.<sup>2</sup></p><p>This concern is at the core of Habermas's analysis of the role of social media communication in bringing about a new structural transformation of the public sphere. Indeed, Habermas identifies the <i>inclusive</i> character of the public sphere as the feature that is most in danger of “disappearing” due to the centrifugal forces of social media communication which yield increased fragmentation, polarization, misinformation, and so on.<sup>3</sup> I share Habermas's concern. I am convinced by his analysis of the distinctive threats that social media communication poses to the maintenance of an inclusive public sphere. I also agree with the two main mechanisms that he identifies as most promising for minimizing such threats over the long term: regulations and learning processes. However, I fear that there are some limits to the effectiveness of these mechanisms that Habermas does not discuss.</p><p>In what follows, I offer a brief overview of Habermas's analysis in order to highlight some of these limits. Although I agree with Habermas that a better distribution of responsibilities between social media platforms and users is urgently needed, I argue that it may nonetheless be insufficient for preventing an increased fragmentation of the public sphere (1). This raises the question of whether there are any alternative developments that can help counteract the negative effects of fragmentation and polarization on the political public sphere in democratic societies. As a tentative answer, I briefly explore the potential contribution that citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics may make to the maintenance of an inclusive political public sphere (2).</p><p>Habermas is certainly right to suggest that it is going to take a long time for Internet users to acquire the skills and the media literacy required to properly participate in digitized communication as authors. This hope about learning processes may partly explain why he takes a less skeptical attitude toward this new structural transformation of the public sphere than he did toward the previous one in his groundbreaking 1962 work, <i>The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere</i>.<sup>4</sup> I agree that we should have a hopeful attitude and avoid misplaced nostalgia for the pre-digital era of traditional media outlets. Yet, there is a worrisome dis-analogy between the two technological revolutions that is relevant in our context. Whereas the bulk of the population simply could not participate in mass communication before learning how to read, Internet users were turned into authors overnight. They are participating in mass communication as authors <i>before</i> acquiring any of the requisite media literacy and without any proper regulations. A better analogy would be letting everyone drive on the highway <i>before</i> passing a driving test and without any traffic regulations. We may not have 300 years to fix the ensuing mess!</p><p>Leaving this issue aside, I am also not sure that the main threats to the political public sphere derive from the transformation of readers into authors. In fact, the <i>flipside</i> of this phenomenon seems to be much more salient. The most significant threats are posed by the fact that the new social media operators <i>are no longer authors</i>. As Habermas recognizes, social media platforms “neither produce, nor edit nor select.” They thereby disclaim any responsibility for the consequences of the spread of content that is “unregulated because professional filters are lacking” (p. 159). This is a problematic feature that social media operators share with the gig economy generally. In the same way that social media platforms are “empowering all potential users in principle to become independent and equally entitled authors” (Habermas, <span>2022b</span>, p. 159), platforms like Uber or Lift are “empowering” gig workers to become independent contractors. The flipside of that “empowerment” is that these platforms are no longer “employers” and can therefore relinquish any responsibility for providing labor protections to gig workers, although the latter cannot secure those protections on their own.<sup>5</sup> The main problem with making social media users “authors” or gig workers “independent contractors” is that responsibilities are offloaded onto them <i>under conditions in which they cannot properly discharge them</i>.</p><p>In the case of social media, the problem is not simply that platform users do not have the professional skills and media literacy to properly fulfill the various authorship roles involved in online communication (from editors to reporters, journalists, witnesses, whistleblowers, and so on). This is certainly a problem. But no matter how much social media users improve their authorship skills, there is a clear structural limit. Social media users are also always at the same time passive recipients. Yet, because of the current business model, content spreads across social media according to algorithms that maximize user engagement rather than accuracy. Consequently, targeted recipients often have no way to discern whether the content that appears in their “feeds” is accurate or false, whether it represents the views of fellow citizens or foreign trolls, whether it is generated by a reliable source or by an online bot using a fake account, and so on.<sup>6</sup> To the extent that this is the case, platform users cannot be held responsible for preventing the negative consequences of the spread of misinformation and disinformation, although they certainly contribute to it by sharing, liking, commenting, and so on. Since ought implies can, it is not surprising that online platforms’ creative attempts to relinquish any responsibility are meeting strong resistance. This fight is ongoing. Yet, whereas labor protections for gig workers are still being fought about intensely, content moderation by social media platforms is already here to stay.<sup>7</sup> Devastating incidents like Facebook's role in inciting genocidal violence against Rohingya Muslims in Myanmar have brought social media companies under increasing public pressure. Consequently, these companies have not been able to simply declare themselves “platforms” and their users “authors” as a way of relinquishing their obligation to act as responsible editors and remove harmful content and misinformation from their sites.<sup>8</sup></p><p>Now, I do not mean to suggest that leaving content moderation in the hands of private businesses is an optimal solution to the problem. Far from it. But state regulation of content has problems of its own. In addition to the well-known dangers of state censorship, state agencies or courts could hardly adjudicate the tremendous amount of content that platforms remove each day while also maintaining due process guarantees of legal recourse for users.<sup>9</sup> A third alternative (with its own set of problems) would be enabling users themselves to control the content that appears in their “feeds.” This would require the development of technical means (so-called “middleware”) to restrict access to unwanted content (Keller, <span>2022</span>). Currently, it is unclear what the best solutions might be. The problems are complex and constantly evolving due to technological innovations. Each regulatory option carries the risk of having severe negative effects on the quality of the public sphere. Precisely because of this, it is clear that what citizens need to learn about online communication is not so much how to behave <i>as authors</i> but, above all, how to behave <i>as citizens</i>.</p><p>In democratic societies, citizens are ultimately responsible for demanding adequate regulation of any new technologies and practices that threaten the equal protection of everyone's fundamental rights and freedoms. This does not mean, however, that at this historical juncture, the responsibilities of citizenship vis-à-vis the social media are any easier to discharge than those of online authorship. To the contrary, Habermas’ observation is correct here too. It is likely to take a long time for citizens to learn how to best regulate the communicative practices enabled by new forms of social media so that their beneficial features are enhanced while their disruptive potential is neutralized. However, in this context, it is also important to note that a lot of the threats that Habermas rightly highlights are <i>neither exclusive nor distinctive</i> of social media. Citizens must demand that any media (whether traditional or digitized) is responsible for not spreading disinformation and misinformation. This is not only happening with respect to social media platforms. It is also happening with respect to TV news channels and other outlets. To take just one salient example: TV news was the main source of early Covid-19 misinformation in the United States. Facebook ranked second.<sup>10</sup></p><p>Contrary to Habermas's diagnosis, my fear is that although these problems are certainly exacerbated by social media, they are not a product of the unskilled behavior of Internet users bumbling about in the role of authors. In fact, the polarized and self-segregating mentality that Habermas refers to does not seem to be limited to Internet users at all. The question at stake here is whether online communication is generating these problems or whether users are reproducing online what they do (and always already did) offline.<sup>11</sup> This is an important question. If the social and political fragmentation that takes place in online networks simply <i>reflects</i> the fragmentation of social networks that results from citizens’ free choices in their offline lives (e.g., where people prefer to live, who they like to talk to and engage with, which news channels they prefer to watch, etc.), it is far from clear that regulations on social media or increased media literacy can address such problems. To once again take an example from the United States: recent studies show that a much higher percentage of Americans are politically segregated through television news channels than through online platforms. Television is indeed the top driver of partisan audience segregation among Americans.<sup>12</sup> Moreover, even if it turns out that social media <i>decisively</i> exacerbates the problem, it is also not clear that there is a regulatory mechanism that is compatible with citizens’ freedoms which can impede voluntary online self-segregation (and the ensuing fragmentation, polarization, etc.) any more than there is a mechanism to impede voluntary self-segregation offline (e.g., to regulate citizens’ choices of traditional media outlets, neighborhoods, and schools).</p><p>The concerning levels of fragmentation and polarization in most democratic societies may be caused by a variety of concurrent factors: a sharp increase in social inequality produced by decades of neoliberal capitalism, a corresponding erosion of solidarity, and the emergence of social media. Whatever the ultimate causes of social fragmentation and polarization are far from clear that increasing media literacy or regulating social media platforms can <i>suffice</i> to address the tendencies of an increasing portion of the citizenry to self-segregate both online and offline. This is not to deny that we need to regulate social media in order to counteract the role that algorithm personalization plays in facilitating the creation of filter bubbles and echo chambers. Nor do I mean to suggest that increasing media literacy and providing Internet users with suitable tools to control the content they are exposed to is not urgently needed. However, to the extent that fragmentation and polarization are <i>not a uniquely online phenomena</i> but something that permeates all aspects of society both online and offline, improving online communication will not be enough to maintain an inclusive public sphere.<sup>13</sup> We need additional tools to counteract the negative effects that fragmentation and polarization exert upon the political public sphere.</p><p>In this context, the increasing popularity of citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics such as citizens’ juries and Deliberative Polls is not surprising.<sup>14</sup> Indeed, the <i>inclusiveness</i> that is characteristic of these deliberative fora provides participants with the exact opposite experience of an echo chamber or a polarized political debate. Without suggesting that these institutional innovations could be a panacea, I would like to briefly indicate some specific contributions that they could make toward maintaining an inclusive political public sphere if they were properly institutionalized.</p><p>Political debates in the public sphere tend to be dominated by powerful political actors whose interests often deviate from those of the general public. As mentioned, this has only gotten worse with the spread of social media that facilitates the formation of filter bubbles and echo chambers. In the current media environment, citizens have a hard time not only getting themselves informed (as opposed to being bombarded with fake news, misinformation, conspiracy theories, etc.) but, even more importantly, figuring out the considered opinions of their fellow citizens on important political questions—especially those of citizens with whom they disagree. Citizens frequently cannot tell if the views they are exposed to reflect the genuine oppositional opinions of fellow citizens who disagree with them or whether they reflect the manipulated opinions of powerful actors with particular interests that in no way resonate with the citizenry (e.g., lobbyists, hackers, Internet bots, and foreign governments trolls).</p><p>In such a context, it is not surprising that scholars and practitioners who are familiar with the workings of citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics are enthusiastic about the quality of political deliberation that they facilitate for participants both online and offline. Minipublics facilitate well-informed, high-quality deliberation on important political decisions among a randomly selected sample of citizens that is descriptively representative of the constituency which will be subject to that decision. Indeed, across all relevant dimensions—inclusion, diversity, access to reliable and balanced information, independence, impartiality, orientation toward the public interest, and so on—the deliberative conditions available to minipublics’ participants are the exact opposite of those that prevail in most social forums currently available to citizens. Thus, it does not seem far-fetched to imagine that as more and more citizens become familiar with the workings of minipublics, they would become increasingly enthusiastic about them. Indeed, if deliberative minipublics were institutionalized for a variety of purposes at the local, national, and even transnational levels, they could become an extremely valuable <i>resource</i> to the citizenry precisely at a time when reliable sources of inclusive, well-informed, impartial political deliberation are getting harder and harder to come by.<sup>15</sup> How could minipublics help improve the inclusiveness and the quality of deliberation in the public sphere?</p><p>To begin with, minipublics could serve some important functions that are not very different from those that traditional media outlets (used to) fulfill. As with the latter, their contribution as a resource for the citizenry would not consist of doing the thinking or deciding for them.<sup>16</sup> Rather, it would consist of making the most relevant arguments for and against policies under discussion readily available to citizens.<sup>17</sup> Minipublics can do so by filtering out irrelevant or patently manipulative considerations that cannot survive public scrutiny while highlighting the key information, potential trade-offs, and long-term consequences of the available alternatives as evaluated from the diverse political perspectives that resonate with the citizenry of a political community at a given time.</p><p>Minipublics are particularly well suited to serve this function. Precisely to the extent that their randomly selected participants are a mirror of the whole citizenry, the reasons and considerations that lead them to form their considered judgments are likely to be those that resonate with the rest of the citizenry (Fishkin, <span>2018</span>, p. 72). Moreover, by highlighting the considerations that are most relevant for reaching a considered judgment on the political issue in question, minipublics would not only serve the function of reducing the costs of acquiring that type of information to the public. They would also serve the crucial function of sorting out the “wheat from the chaff,” that is, the information that reflects the considered views of some citizens as opposed to the many distorting claims that are strategically deployed to subvert rather than inform and which are therefore unsustainable in the face of deliberative scrutiny (Niemeyer, <span>2014</span>, p. 14). By testing the available arguments and providing their considered judgments to their fellow citizens, minipublics could play a constructive role in <i>structuring public discourses</i>. Minipublics could act as a regulator of information in the public sphere by doing the hard work of sorting through arguments and providing reasons for the resulting positions to the remainder of the public. Moreover, due to their inclusiveness, minipublics are not only able to identify acceptable public arguments, but they can also help publicize the concerns of marginalized groups that hardly ever find a voice among the most influential political actors.</p><p>Here, it is important to highlight that minipublics’ participants are as diverse as the citizenry itself and are therefore as likely to disagree in their considered opinions on contested political issues as the rest of the citizenry does. However, this does not make minipublics useless. On the contrary, they can provide <i>crucial</i> information to the citizenry if their reasoning and recommendations are made widely available. Knowing the interests, values, and lines of reasoning that resonate with our fellow citizens with respect to contentious political issues is essential precisely in cases when we disagree. For knowing the genuine sources of contention and disagreement on specific political issues—as opposed to the manipulative claims and pseudo-arguments that constantly circulate in the public sphere—would enable citizens to figure out the kind of information, evidence, arguments, or counterarguments that they would need to provide to their fellow citizens in order to move the public debate on these issues forward. This is precisely what citizens can no longer do in an increasingly fragmented and polarized public sphere.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"30 1\",\"pages\":\"77-83\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-03-30\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12663\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12663\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12663","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

摘要

一个更好的比喻是,让每个人在没有通过驾驶考试、没有任何交通规则的情况下在高速公路上开车。我们可能没有300年的时间来解决随之而来的混乱!撇开这个问题不谈,我也不确定对政治公共领域的主要威胁是否来自读者向作者的转变。事实上,这种现象的另一面似乎更为突出。最严重的威胁来自于新的社交媒体运营商不再是作者这一事实。正如哈贝马斯所认识到的,社交媒体平台“既不生产,也不编辑,也不选择”。因此,他们拒绝对“由于缺乏专业过滤器而不受管制”的内容传播的后果承担任何责任(第159页)。这是社交媒体运营商与零工经济普遍存在的一个问题。就像社交媒体平台“原则上授权所有潜在用户成为独立的、同样有资格的作者”一样(Habermas, 2022b,第159页),Uber或Lift等平台也在“授权”临时工成为独立的承包商。这种“授权”的另一面是,这些平台不再是“雇主”,因此可以放弃为零工工人提供劳动保护的任何责任,尽管后者无法自己获得这些保护把社交媒体用户变成“作者”或把零工工人变成“独立合同工”的主要问题是,在他们无法适当履行责任的情况下,责任被转嫁给了他们。就社交媒体而言,问题不仅仅在于平台用户不具备专业技能和媒体素养,无法恰当地履行在线交流中涉及的各种作者角色(从编辑到记者、记者、证人、举报人等等)。这当然是个问题。但无论社交媒体用户如何提高他们的写作技能,都有一个明显的结构性限制。社交媒体用户同时也是被动的接受者。然而,由于目前的商业模式,内容在社交媒体上的传播依据的是最大化用户参与度的算法,而不是准确性。因此,目标接受者往往无法辨别出现在他们“feed”中的内容是准确的还是虚假的,它代表的是同胞的观点还是外国喷子的观点,它是由可靠的来源生成的还是由使用虚假账户的在线机器人生成的,等等在这种情况下,平台用户不能对防止错误信息和虚假信息传播的负面后果负责,尽管他们肯定会通过分享、点赞、评论等方式做出贡献。既然“应该”意味着“可以”,那么网络平台放弃任何责任的创造性尝试遭遇强烈抵制也就不足为奇了。这场斗争仍在继续。然而,尽管针对零工工人的劳动保护仍在激烈争论,但社交媒体平台的内容审核已经存在Facebook在煽动针对缅甸罗兴亚穆斯林的种族灭绝暴力中扮演的角色等毁灭性事件,让社交媒体公司面临越来越大的公众压力。因此,这些公司不能简单地宣称自己是“平台”,他们的用户是“作者”,作为一种放弃他们作为负责任的编辑,从他们的网站上删除有害内容和错误信息的义务的方式。现在,我并不是说把内容审核交给私营企业是解决问题的最佳办法。远非如此。但国家对内容的监管也有其自身的问题。除了众所周知的国家审查的危险之外,国家机构或法院很难对平台每天删除的大量内容进行裁决,同时还要为用户提供法律追索权的正当程序保证第三种选择(有其自身的问题)是允许用户自己控制出现在他们的“提要”中的内容。这将需要开发技术手段(所谓的“中间件”)来限制对不需要的内容的访问(Keller, 2022)。目前,还不清楚最好的解决方案是什么。由于技术创新,这些问题很复杂,而且不断演变。每一种监管选择都有可能对公共领域的质量产生严重的负面影响。正因为如此,很明显,公民在网络交流方面需要学习的,与其说是如何作为作者行事,不如说是如何作为公民行事。在民主社会中,公民最终有责任要求对任何威胁平等保护每个人的基本权利和自由的新技术和做法进行充分监管。 然而,这并不意味着,在这个历史关头,公民对-à-vis社交媒体的责任比网络作者的责任更容易履行。相反,哈贝马斯的观察在这里也是正确的。公民可能需要很长时间才能学会如何最好地规范新形式的社交媒体所带来的交流实践,从而增强其有益的特征,同时消除其破坏性的潜力。然而,在这种背景下,同样重要的是要注意到,哈贝马斯正确强调的许多威胁既不是社交媒体独有的,也不是独特的。公民必须要求任何媒体(无论是传统的还是数字化的)都有责任不传播虚假信息和错误信息。这不仅仅发生在社交媒体平台上。这种情况也发生在电视新闻频道和其他媒体上。举一个突出的例子:电视新闻是美国早期新冠肺炎错误信息的主要来源。Facebook排名第二。与哈贝马斯的诊断相反,我担心的是,尽管社交媒体肯定加剧了这些问题,但它们并不是互联网用户以作者的身份笨拙行为的产物。事实上,哈贝马斯所说的两极分化和自我隔离的心态,似乎根本不局限于互联网用户。这里的关键问题是,在线交流是否正在产生这些问题,或者用户是否正在在线上复制他们在线下所做的(并且总是已经做过的)这是一个重要的问题。如果在线网络中发生的社会和政治碎片化仅仅反映了公民在线下生活中自由选择所导致的社交网络碎片化(例如,人们喜欢住在哪里,他们喜欢与谁交谈和互动,他们喜欢看哪些新闻频道,等等),那么对社交媒体的监管或提高媒体素养能否解决这些问题还远不清楚。再次以美国为例:最近的研究表明,通过电视新闻频道进行政治隔离的美国人比通过网络平台进行政治隔离的美国人比例高得多。此外,即使事实证明社交媒体决定性地加剧了这一问题,也不清楚是否存在一种与公民自由相容的监管机制,这种机制可以阻碍自愿的在线自我隔离(以及随之而来的分裂、两极分化等),就像没有一种机制可以阻碍自愿的线下自我隔离一样(例如,规范公民对传统媒体、社区和学校的选择)。在大多数民主社会中,令人担忧的分裂和两极分化可能是由多种同时发生的因素造成的:几十年的新自由主义资本主义造成的社会不平等急剧加剧,对团结的相应侵蚀,以及社交媒体的出现。无论社会分裂和两极分化的最终原因是什么,我们都远不清楚,提高媒体素养或规范社交媒体平台是否足以解决越来越多的公民在线上和线下自我隔离的趋势。这并不否认我们需要监管社交媒体,以抵消算法个性化在促进过滤气泡和回音室产生方面所起的作用。我的意思也不是说,提高媒体素养和为互联网用户提供合适的工具来控制他们接触到的内容不是迫切需要的。然而,从某种程度上说,分裂和两极分化不是网络上独有的现象,而是渗透到社会的各个方面,包括线上和线下,改善在线交流将不足以维持一个包容性的公共领域我们需要更多的工具来抵消分裂和两极分化对政治公共领域造成的负面影响。在这方面,公民大会和诸如公民陪审团和协商民意调查等其他协商小公众日益普及并不令人惊讶事实上,作为这些审议论坛特征的包容性为参与者提供了与回音室或两极分化的政治辩论完全相反的体验。我并不是说这些制度创新可以是万灵药,我想简要地指出,如果它们得到适当的制度化,它们可以为维持一个包容性的政治公共领域作出一些具体贡献。公共领域的政治辩论往往由强大的政治行动者主导,他们的利益往往偏离公众的利益。 如前所述,随着社交媒体的传播,这种情况只会变得更糟,社交媒体助长了过滤气泡和回音室的形成。在当前的媒体环境中,公民不仅很难获得自己的信息(而不是被假新闻,错误信息,阴谋论等轰炸),而且更重要的是,弄清楚他们的同胞对重要政治问题的考虑意见-特别是那些与他们不同意的公民。公民经常无法判断他们所接触到的观点是否反映了与他们持不同意见的同胞的真正反对意见,还是反映了具有特殊利益的强大行动者(例如游说者、黑客、互联网机器人和外国政府巨魔)操纵的意见,这些意见不会引起公民的共鸣。在这样的背景下,熟悉公民大会和其他协商小公众运作的学者和实践者对他们为在线和离线参与者提供的政治审议质量充满热情也就不足为奇了。小型公众有助于在随机选择的公民样本中就重要的政治决定进行知情和高质量的审议,这些样本在一定程度上代表了将受该决定约束的选民。事实上,在所有相关的维度上——包括包容性、多样性、获得可靠和平衡的信息、独立性、公正性、面向公共利益等等——小公众的参与者所能获得的审议条件,与目前大多数面向公民的社会论坛所能获得的审议条件完全相反。因此,设想随着越来越多的公民熟悉微型公共机构的运作,他们对它们的热情会越来越高,这似乎并不牵强。事实上,如果在地方、国家甚至跨国层面上,为了各种目的而将审议型微型公众制度化,它们就可能成为公民极其宝贵的资源,而此时,包容性、消息灵通、公正的政治审议的可靠来源正变得越来越难以获得微型公众如何帮助提高公共领域的包容性和审议质量?首先,微型公众可以提供一些重要的功能,这些功能与传统媒体所履行的功能没有太大的不同。与后者一样,他们作为公民资源的贡献并不包括为他们思考或做决定相反,它将包括为公民提供支持和反对正在讨论的政策的最相关的论据微型公众可以通过过滤掉不相关的或明显的操纵因素来做到这一点,这些因素无法在公众监督下生存,同时突出关键信息、潜在的权衡和现有替代方案的长期后果,这些替代方案是在给定时间内与政治社区公民产生共鸣的不同政治观点进行评估的。小型公共机构特别适合履行这一职能。确切地说,他们随机选择的参与者是整个公民的镜子,导致他们形成深思熟虑的判断的原因和考虑因素很可能与其他公民产生共鸣(Fishkin, 2018,第72页)。此外,通过强调对所涉政治问题作出经过深思熟虑的判断最有关的考虑因素,小型公众不仅可以起到减少向公众获取这类信息的费用的作用。它们还将起到“从谷壳中挑出小麦”的关键作用,即反映一些公民经过深思熟虑的观点的信息,而不是许多扭曲的主张,这些主张被战略性地部署以颠覆而不是告知,因此在审议审查面前是不可持续的(Niemeyer, 2014,第14页)。通过检验现有的论点,并向同胞提供他们经过深思熟虑的判断,微型公众可以在构建公共话语方面发挥建设性作用。“小公众”可以充当公共领域信息的监管者,通过对各种观点进行分类,并向其余公众提供各种立场的理由。此外,由于其包容性,微型公众不仅能够确定可接受的公共论点,而且还可以帮助宣传边缘化群体的关切,这些群体在最有影响力的政治行动者中几乎找不到发言权。 在这里,重要的是要强调,微型公众的参与者与公民本身一样多样化,因此,在有争议的政治问题上,他们的意见可能与其他公民一样不一致。然而,这并不是说迷你公共毫无用处。相反,如果他们的推理和建议广为流传,他们可以向公民提供关键信息。在有争议的政治问题上,了解与我们的同胞产生共鸣的利益、价值观和推理思路,正是在我们意见不一致的情况下至关重要。因为了解在特定政治问题上争论和分歧的真正来源——而不是在公共领域中不断流传的操纵主张和伪论点——将使公民能够弄清楚他们需要向同胞提供的信息、证据、论点或反论点,以便推动这些问题的公共辩论向前发展。在一个日益分裂和两极化的公共领域,公民们再也无法做到这一点。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
A democracy, if we can keep it. Remarks on J. Habermas’ a new structural transformation of the public sphere

Habermas's new book, A New Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere,1 offers a timely and insightful analysis of the threats that online communication poses to the maintenance of an inclusive public sphere in democratic societies. Amid growing discontent with democracy, there are plenty of reasons to be worried about the increasing deterioration of the political public sphere. In addition to long-standing threats such as the excessive influence of money in political discourse, the potential for manipulation by powerful social groups, and the exclusion of marginalized voices from public discourse, technological innovations such as social media platforms and big data collection are generating new types of threats.

These threats are being generated more quickly than society's ability to cope with them. The business model of social media platforms is based on maximizing user engagement through data harvesting and algorithmic personalization. The preselection of content for users based on data about their past preferences facilitates the creation of filter bubbles and echo chambers with the consequence that those who rely mainly on social media almost never receive information, news, or opinions that they do not already agree with. These features of social media not only increase group isolation, fragmentation, and polarization but also facilitate the dissemination of misinformation, fake news, conspiracy theories, and the micro-targeted manipulation of voters.

Amid these threatening developments, we are seeing a decline in traditional media outlets that operate under journalistic norms of impartiality, accuracy, accountability, and so on. Consequently, it is unclear how citizens can stay sufficiently politically informed to engage in meaningful debate with their fellow citizens, even on the most fundamental political problems facing them. At this historical juncture, the danger that a shared sense of community among the citizenry disappears seems alarmingly real. Yet, democratic self-government is only possible if citizens can forge a collective political will by changing one another's hearts and minds in public debate. Without an inclusive public sphere, citizens cannot keep the democracies they have got.2

This concern is at the core of Habermas's analysis of the role of social media communication in bringing about a new structural transformation of the public sphere. Indeed, Habermas identifies the inclusive character of the public sphere as the feature that is most in danger of “disappearing” due to the centrifugal forces of social media communication which yield increased fragmentation, polarization, misinformation, and so on.3 I share Habermas's concern. I am convinced by his analysis of the distinctive threats that social media communication poses to the maintenance of an inclusive public sphere. I also agree with the two main mechanisms that he identifies as most promising for minimizing such threats over the long term: regulations and learning processes. However, I fear that there are some limits to the effectiveness of these mechanisms that Habermas does not discuss.

In what follows, I offer a brief overview of Habermas's analysis in order to highlight some of these limits. Although I agree with Habermas that a better distribution of responsibilities between social media platforms and users is urgently needed, I argue that it may nonetheless be insufficient for preventing an increased fragmentation of the public sphere (1). This raises the question of whether there are any alternative developments that can help counteract the negative effects of fragmentation and polarization on the political public sphere in democratic societies. As a tentative answer, I briefly explore the potential contribution that citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics may make to the maintenance of an inclusive political public sphere (2).

Habermas is certainly right to suggest that it is going to take a long time for Internet users to acquire the skills and the media literacy required to properly participate in digitized communication as authors. This hope about learning processes may partly explain why he takes a less skeptical attitude toward this new structural transformation of the public sphere than he did toward the previous one in his groundbreaking 1962 work, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere.4 I agree that we should have a hopeful attitude and avoid misplaced nostalgia for the pre-digital era of traditional media outlets. Yet, there is a worrisome dis-analogy between the two technological revolutions that is relevant in our context. Whereas the bulk of the population simply could not participate in mass communication before learning how to read, Internet users were turned into authors overnight. They are participating in mass communication as authors before acquiring any of the requisite media literacy and without any proper regulations. A better analogy would be letting everyone drive on the highway before passing a driving test and without any traffic regulations. We may not have 300 years to fix the ensuing mess!

Leaving this issue aside, I am also not sure that the main threats to the political public sphere derive from the transformation of readers into authors. In fact, the flipside of this phenomenon seems to be much more salient. The most significant threats are posed by the fact that the new social media operators are no longer authors. As Habermas recognizes, social media platforms “neither produce, nor edit nor select.” They thereby disclaim any responsibility for the consequences of the spread of content that is “unregulated because professional filters are lacking” (p. 159). This is a problematic feature that social media operators share with the gig economy generally. In the same way that social media platforms are “empowering all potential users in principle to become independent and equally entitled authors” (Habermas, 2022b, p. 159), platforms like Uber or Lift are “empowering” gig workers to become independent contractors. The flipside of that “empowerment” is that these platforms are no longer “employers” and can therefore relinquish any responsibility for providing labor protections to gig workers, although the latter cannot secure those protections on their own.5 The main problem with making social media users “authors” or gig workers “independent contractors” is that responsibilities are offloaded onto them under conditions in which they cannot properly discharge them.

In the case of social media, the problem is not simply that platform users do not have the professional skills and media literacy to properly fulfill the various authorship roles involved in online communication (from editors to reporters, journalists, witnesses, whistleblowers, and so on). This is certainly a problem. But no matter how much social media users improve their authorship skills, there is a clear structural limit. Social media users are also always at the same time passive recipients. Yet, because of the current business model, content spreads across social media according to algorithms that maximize user engagement rather than accuracy. Consequently, targeted recipients often have no way to discern whether the content that appears in their “feeds” is accurate or false, whether it represents the views of fellow citizens or foreign trolls, whether it is generated by a reliable source or by an online bot using a fake account, and so on.6 To the extent that this is the case, platform users cannot be held responsible for preventing the negative consequences of the spread of misinformation and disinformation, although they certainly contribute to it by sharing, liking, commenting, and so on. Since ought implies can, it is not surprising that online platforms’ creative attempts to relinquish any responsibility are meeting strong resistance. This fight is ongoing. Yet, whereas labor protections for gig workers are still being fought about intensely, content moderation by social media platforms is already here to stay.7 Devastating incidents like Facebook's role in inciting genocidal violence against Rohingya Muslims in Myanmar have brought social media companies under increasing public pressure. Consequently, these companies have not been able to simply declare themselves “platforms” and their users “authors” as a way of relinquishing their obligation to act as responsible editors and remove harmful content and misinformation from their sites.8

Now, I do not mean to suggest that leaving content moderation in the hands of private businesses is an optimal solution to the problem. Far from it. But state regulation of content has problems of its own. In addition to the well-known dangers of state censorship, state agencies or courts could hardly adjudicate the tremendous amount of content that platforms remove each day while also maintaining due process guarantees of legal recourse for users.9 A third alternative (with its own set of problems) would be enabling users themselves to control the content that appears in their “feeds.” This would require the development of technical means (so-called “middleware”) to restrict access to unwanted content (Keller, 2022). Currently, it is unclear what the best solutions might be. The problems are complex and constantly evolving due to technological innovations. Each regulatory option carries the risk of having severe negative effects on the quality of the public sphere. Precisely because of this, it is clear that what citizens need to learn about online communication is not so much how to behave as authors but, above all, how to behave as citizens.

In democratic societies, citizens are ultimately responsible for demanding adequate regulation of any new technologies and practices that threaten the equal protection of everyone's fundamental rights and freedoms. This does not mean, however, that at this historical juncture, the responsibilities of citizenship vis-à-vis the social media are any easier to discharge than those of online authorship. To the contrary, Habermas’ observation is correct here too. It is likely to take a long time for citizens to learn how to best regulate the communicative practices enabled by new forms of social media so that their beneficial features are enhanced while their disruptive potential is neutralized. However, in this context, it is also important to note that a lot of the threats that Habermas rightly highlights are neither exclusive nor distinctive of social media. Citizens must demand that any media (whether traditional or digitized) is responsible for not spreading disinformation and misinformation. This is not only happening with respect to social media platforms. It is also happening with respect to TV news channels and other outlets. To take just one salient example: TV news was the main source of early Covid-19 misinformation in the United States. Facebook ranked second.10

Contrary to Habermas's diagnosis, my fear is that although these problems are certainly exacerbated by social media, they are not a product of the unskilled behavior of Internet users bumbling about in the role of authors. In fact, the polarized and self-segregating mentality that Habermas refers to does not seem to be limited to Internet users at all. The question at stake here is whether online communication is generating these problems or whether users are reproducing online what they do (and always already did) offline.11 This is an important question. If the social and political fragmentation that takes place in online networks simply reflects the fragmentation of social networks that results from citizens’ free choices in their offline lives (e.g., where people prefer to live, who they like to talk to and engage with, which news channels they prefer to watch, etc.), it is far from clear that regulations on social media or increased media literacy can address such problems. To once again take an example from the United States: recent studies show that a much higher percentage of Americans are politically segregated through television news channels than through online platforms. Television is indeed the top driver of partisan audience segregation among Americans.12 Moreover, even if it turns out that social media decisively exacerbates the problem, it is also not clear that there is a regulatory mechanism that is compatible with citizens’ freedoms which can impede voluntary online self-segregation (and the ensuing fragmentation, polarization, etc.) any more than there is a mechanism to impede voluntary self-segregation offline (e.g., to regulate citizens’ choices of traditional media outlets, neighborhoods, and schools).

The concerning levels of fragmentation and polarization in most democratic societies may be caused by a variety of concurrent factors: a sharp increase in social inequality produced by decades of neoliberal capitalism, a corresponding erosion of solidarity, and the emergence of social media. Whatever the ultimate causes of social fragmentation and polarization are far from clear that increasing media literacy or regulating social media platforms can suffice to address the tendencies of an increasing portion of the citizenry to self-segregate both online and offline. This is not to deny that we need to regulate social media in order to counteract the role that algorithm personalization plays in facilitating the creation of filter bubbles and echo chambers. Nor do I mean to suggest that increasing media literacy and providing Internet users with suitable tools to control the content they are exposed to is not urgently needed. However, to the extent that fragmentation and polarization are not a uniquely online phenomena but something that permeates all aspects of society both online and offline, improving online communication will not be enough to maintain an inclusive public sphere.13 We need additional tools to counteract the negative effects that fragmentation and polarization exert upon the political public sphere.

In this context, the increasing popularity of citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics such as citizens’ juries and Deliberative Polls is not surprising.14 Indeed, the inclusiveness that is characteristic of these deliberative fora provides participants with the exact opposite experience of an echo chamber or a polarized political debate. Without suggesting that these institutional innovations could be a panacea, I would like to briefly indicate some specific contributions that they could make toward maintaining an inclusive political public sphere if they were properly institutionalized.

Political debates in the public sphere tend to be dominated by powerful political actors whose interests often deviate from those of the general public. As mentioned, this has only gotten worse with the spread of social media that facilitates the formation of filter bubbles and echo chambers. In the current media environment, citizens have a hard time not only getting themselves informed (as opposed to being bombarded with fake news, misinformation, conspiracy theories, etc.) but, even more importantly, figuring out the considered opinions of their fellow citizens on important political questions—especially those of citizens with whom they disagree. Citizens frequently cannot tell if the views they are exposed to reflect the genuine oppositional opinions of fellow citizens who disagree with them or whether they reflect the manipulated opinions of powerful actors with particular interests that in no way resonate with the citizenry (e.g., lobbyists, hackers, Internet bots, and foreign governments trolls).

In such a context, it is not surprising that scholars and practitioners who are familiar with the workings of citizens’ assemblies and other deliberative minipublics are enthusiastic about the quality of political deliberation that they facilitate for participants both online and offline. Minipublics facilitate well-informed, high-quality deliberation on important political decisions among a randomly selected sample of citizens that is descriptively representative of the constituency which will be subject to that decision. Indeed, across all relevant dimensions—inclusion, diversity, access to reliable and balanced information, independence, impartiality, orientation toward the public interest, and so on—the deliberative conditions available to minipublics’ participants are the exact opposite of those that prevail in most social forums currently available to citizens. Thus, it does not seem far-fetched to imagine that as more and more citizens become familiar with the workings of minipublics, they would become increasingly enthusiastic about them. Indeed, if deliberative minipublics were institutionalized for a variety of purposes at the local, national, and even transnational levels, they could become an extremely valuable resource to the citizenry precisely at a time when reliable sources of inclusive, well-informed, impartial political deliberation are getting harder and harder to come by.15 How could minipublics help improve the inclusiveness and the quality of deliberation in the public sphere?

To begin with, minipublics could serve some important functions that are not very different from those that traditional media outlets (used to) fulfill. As with the latter, their contribution as a resource for the citizenry would not consist of doing the thinking or deciding for them.16 Rather, it would consist of making the most relevant arguments for and against policies under discussion readily available to citizens.17 Minipublics can do so by filtering out irrelevant or patently manipulative considerations that cannot survive public scrutiny while highlighting the key information, potential trade-offs, and long-term consequences of the available alternatives as evaluated from the diverse political perspectives that resonate with the citizenry of a political community at a given time.

Minipublics are particularly well suited to serve this function. Precisely to the extent that their randomly selected participants are a mirror of the whole citizenry, the reasons and considerations that lead them to form their considered judgments are likely to be those that resonate with the rest of the citizenry (Fishkin, 2018, p. 72). Moreover, by highlighting the considerations that are most relevant for reaching a considered judgment on the political issue in question, minipublics would not only serve the function of reducing the costs of acquiring that type of information to the public. They would also serve the crucial function of sorting out the “wheat from the chaff,” that is, the information that reflects the considered views of some citizens as opposed to the many distorting claims that are strategically deployed to subvert rather than inform and which are therefore unsustainable in the face of deliberative scrutiny (Niemeyer, 2014, p. 14). By testing the available arguments and providing their considered judgments to their fellow citizens, minipublics could play a constructive role in structuring public discourses. Minipublics could act as a regulator of information in the public sphere by doing the hard work of sorting through arguments and providing reasons for the resulting positions to the remainder of the public. Moreover, due to their inclusiveness, minipublics are not only able to identify acceptable public arguments, but they can also help publicize the concerns of marginalized groups that hardly ever find a voice among the most influential political actors.

Here, it is important to highlight that minipublics’ participants are as diverse as the citizenry itself and are therefore as likely to disagree in their considered opinions on contested political issues as the rest of the citizenry does. However, this does not make minipublics useless. On the contrary, they can provide crucial information to the citizenry if their reasoning and recommendations are made widely available. Knowing the interests, values, and lines of reasoning that resonate with our fellow citizens with respect to contentious political issues is essential precisely in cases when we disagree. For knowing the genuine sources of contention and disagreement on specific political issues—as opposed to the manipulative claims and pseudo-arguments that constantly circulate in the public sphere—would enable citizens to figure out the kind of information, evidence, arguments, or counterarguments that they would need to provide to their fellow citizens in order to move the public debate on these issues forward. This is precisely what citizens can no longer do in an increasingly fragmented and polarized public sphere.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信