关于主权债务的叙述在意识形态上是否普遍可疑?拓宽意识形态批判范围的练习

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS
Ben Cross, Janosch Prinz
{"title":"关于主权债务的叙述在意识形态上是否普遍可疑?拓宽意识形态批判范围的练习","authors":"Ben Cross,&nbsp;Janosch Prinz","doi":"10.1111/josp.12511","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Our interest here is in the fourth of these theories. It strikes us as particularly interesting because it differs significantly from what are perhaps the most familiar notions of ideology. While the most familiar notions of ideology are arguably those which focus on the process of how a belief is generated, Prinz and Rossi (<span>2017</span>, p. 341) “focus not on the process of belief acquisition, but on the formation of the meaning of the relevant concept.” Furthermore, unlike the second type, it does not, strictly speaking, presuppose the existence of any particular distorting form of power, even if power asymmetries “are likely to be part of the picture” (Prinz &amp; Rossi, <span>2021</span>, p. 121).</p><p>However, we also think that the full potential of this novel theory of ideology has yet to be realized. As the theory currently stands, or at least, as we understand it, it focuses exclusively on how a narrative is <i>used by certain people in a particular instance</i>. If so, it does not rule out the possibility of addressing the disconnect by controlling or revising the way in which manifest and/or operative concepts are used. As a result, its conclusions are confined to a particular local case.</p><p>As an example of this, Prinz and Rossi (<span>2021</span>) criticize the use of technocratic and moralistic narratives in debates about sovereign debt during the post-2008 financial crises facing Greece and other European states. They argue that the use of these narratives during this period was ideological because there was a substantial difference between the appearance and the reality of their use. If their argument is sound, it tells us that technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt were used ideologically <i>in this particular context</i>. It allows for the possibility that the use of these narratives could be plausibly regarded as nonideological in other times and places.</p><p>Our interest, then, is in the extent to which it is possible to extend Prinz and Rossi's method of ideology critique, such that we can bridge the gap between: (i) P being used ideologically in a particular context and (ii) having reasons to regard P as in some sense pejoratively ideological across different contexts. Our main aim in this article is to show how it is possible to bridge this gap.</p><p>Our basic idea is this: we can bridge the gap between the fact that a narrative is ideological in a particular context and the claim that it is ideological across different contexts by showing that it is resistant to various mechanisms that might otherwise prevent it from functioning ideologically. The crucial step between (i) and (ii) is thus to find some way of showing that P is resistant to the kind of reform or oversight that would bring manifest and operative concepts more closely into line with each other.</p><p>Our idea might be best illustrated with a contrast case. Consider the medical profession. Let us grant, as seems plausible enough, that there are at least some medical doctors who are corrupt, incompetent, or in some other sense not what they purport to be. However, we might also think that there are various mechanisms—training, accountability, and so forth—that help ensure that such doctors are not the norm, and that the medical profession is on the whole reliable. To put it another way, the problem lies with bad doctors, rather than the profession itself. On our view, showing that a narrative is pejoratively ideological across different contexts amounts to showing that it is <i>not</i> like the medical profession. It means showing that there are no reliable mechanisms for keeping the narrative in check.<sup>2</sup></p><p>Our proposed extension of this theory of ideology critique makes three main contributions to existing literature. First, it extends the critical tools of ideology critique by showing how it can be used to anticipate ideologically suspicious narratives before they arise. It thus addresses a crucial realist desideratum, namely, that of providing action guidance to real-world political actors (Galston, <span>2010</span>; Horton, <span>2017</span>).</p><p>Second, we provide a short version of this kind of analysis for sovereign debt narratives. Extending the theory of ideology critique in this fashion would enable political actors in contexts other than that of post-2008 Europe to recognize that technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt would be ideologically suspicious <i>if</i> they were to be implemented in their own contexts.</p><p>Third, we show that radical realism's commitment to fidelity to the facts is not inconsistent with certain forms of abstraction and generalization. Our proposed method for showing how a given narrative can be ideologically suspicious across different contexts is rooted in empirical considerations, rather than a priori speculation. Our method may not be confined to a single context, but it is by no means context-free.</p><p>This essay proceeds as follows. In Section 2, we will examine Prinz and Rossi's discussion of ideology and sovereign debt more closely. We will try to show how their method of ideology critique effectively confines their criticism of sovereign debt narratives to their use in a particular context. In Section 3, we introduce a distinction between the <i>ideological use</i> of a narrative and its being <i>ideologically suspicious</i>. We explore the implications of this distinction and its relevance for broadening the scope of ideology critique. In Section 4, we outline our method for moving from a contextually specific theory of ideology critique to a broader theory that enables us to make claims about the epistemic status of a narrative across different contexts. In Section 5, we suggest some ways for applying this method to sovereign debt.</p><p>Public debates about sovereign debt come in a great variety of forms, often focusing on the extent to which the state might need to limit public spending in proportion to its revenue or on the status of creditor claims. Here, we set aside the details of such narratives and concentrate on their main framing. Prinz and Rossi (<span>2021</span>, pp. 118–125) criticize two framings of narratives often invoked in these debates: technocratic narratives, and moralist narratives. Technocratic narratives hold that expert knowledge of economics reveals what a sustainable approach to sovereign debt would look like, and that this expert knowledge should be heeded. Moralist narratives hold that the failure to pay sovereign debt is immoral in much the same way that it is immoral for a person to break a promise. Prinz and Rossi argue that both technocratic and moralist narratives were used ideologically during the post-2008 European financial crisis because these narratives were not what they seemed to be. In each case, there was a substantial disconnect between the narrative's appearance and its reality.</p><p>These disconnects enable Prinz and Rossi to conclude that the narratives were being used ideologically. However, there is a limitation to the scope of this conclusion. Prinz and Rossi's argument supports the claim that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are <i>contextually ideological</i>. That is, these narratives were used ideologically in a particular context (post-2008 Europe). However, this is not quite the same as demonstrating that the narratives are <i>generally ideological</i>, that is, pejoratively ideological across different contexts.</p><p>Let us refer to claims that a narrative is contextually ideological as CI-claims, and claims that a narrative is generally ideological as GI-claims. To clarify what is at stake in the distinction between CI-claims and GI-claims, suppose it turns out that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are contextually ideological but not generally ideological. One might then acknowledge that they functioned ideologically in post-2008 Europe, but nonetheless insist that these narratives might play non-ideological or perhaps even eminently epistemically valuable roles in other times and places. Perhaps there are other contexts in which we can be confident that the narratives could be invoked without either the epistemic certainty disconnect or the hypocrisy disconnect (or some other disconnect altogether) being present. This possibility could be ruled out only if we have good reasons to think that the narratives are generally ideological.</p><p>We want to emphasize that this is not necessarily a flaw in Prinz and Rossi's argument. Their argument that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are pejoratively ideological is substantial and important even if it is only advanced as a CI-claim. However, it has two significant limitations.</p><p>First, a GI-claim is evidently stronger, and in certain respects, more informative, than a CI-claim. It informs us about the status of the narrative in multiple contexts, as opposed to just one. Furthermore, showing that a narrative is generally ideological might tell us something more substantial about <i>why</i> it has been used ideologically in a particular context.</p><p>Second, and relatedly, a GI-claim provides clearer guidance for how the narrative in question should be approached and scrutinized <i>in the future</i>. This would strengthen the efforts of political theorists to provide practical, action-orienting guidance. Consider how Prinz and Rossi (<span>2021</span>, pp. 126–133) use their claim about the ideological character of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt to argue for a further claim: “to counter the danger of ideology, sovereign debt must be politicized all the way down” (2021, p. 116). That is, they recommend that debate about sovereign debt be confined to narratives that do not present themselves as “above the political fray.” Insofar as this is a proposal for depoliticizing debt in <i>all</i> contexts, it is also, in effect, a proposal for rejecting moralist and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt in all future contexts.</p><p>We think this proposal would receive stronger support from an argument making a GI-claim than one only making a CI-claim. Otherwise, one might argue that both the epistemic certainty disconnect and hypocrisy disconnect are no more than contingent features of moralist and technocratic narratives. Instead of proposing that the narratives are jettisoned altogether, one might instead propose that these two disconnects can be avoided. Why cannot we just recommend that the narratives be presented in a way that acknowledges uncertainty among experts? And why cannot we just recommend that proponents of the narratives employ them consistently? A stronger argument for jettisoning the narratives would require us to answer these questions. Doing so would amount to building a case for the claim that the narratives are generally ideological.</p><p>Our main interest here, then, is in exploring how we might move from a CI-claim to a GI-claim. Over the next two sections, we will try to explain how this is possible.</p><p>The first part of our strategy here is to make a distinction between the <i>ideological use</i> of a narrative and a narrative being <i>ideologically suspicious</i>. We have sufficient reasons to believe that a narrative is being used ideologically if we can conclusively demonstrate the existence of a disconnect between its appearance and its reality. In contrast, a narrative can still be ideologically suspicious even if the existence of this disconnect between the appearance and reality of its use cannot be conclusively demonstrated. In such cases, suspicion might arise because we have certain reasons for thinking that it is likely that a disconnect exists, even if we cannot conclusively verify it. It might also be because we have reasons for thinking that a disconnect would evade detection if it exists. If a narrative is ideologically suspicious, we cannot be confident that it is not being used ideologically, even though this is consistent with it not being so used.</p><p>There are two important points that need to be made in order to make sense of this distinction. The first concerns how it maps onto the contextually ideological/generally ideological distinction. CI-claims typically hold that a narrative is being used ideologically. This is because they are based on observations of various facts about how the narrative has functioned in this particular context. We think Prinz and Rossi give us good reasons to think that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt were used ideologically in the context of post-2008 Europe.</p><p>In contrast, if any GI-claims are plausible, they cannot consist of showing that a narrative is used ideologically. This is because GI-claims are made without access to information about how the narrative is used (or would be used) in all relevant contexts. However, this is not to say that GI-claims are necessarily made in ignorance of how the narrative happens to be operating in certain contexts. The claim that a narrative is contextually ideological in context C<sub>1</sub> might be an important premise in an argument for a GI—in fact, such claims do indeed form premises in the type of argument we will sketch in the next section. However, the argument for this GI-claim might not require awareness of how the narrative operates in C<sub>2</sub>, C<sub>3</sub>, C<sub>4</sub>, and so forth. Rather, it is meant to tell us something about how one might <i>suspect</i> that the narrative operates in other contexts, or would operate if it were to be used there. This points to a distinctive contribution of GI-claims: they can tell us something about the epistemic merits of the use of a narrative in a particular context even before it is used in this context.</p><p>A GI-claim can therefore only be a claim that a narrative is ideologically suspicious. There might also be certain circumstances where a CI-claim is only a claim that a narrative is ideologically suspicious. One possible reason for this might be that our information about the functioning of the narrative in this context is incomplete, but nonetheless adequate for generating reasons for suspicion. However, given that CI-claims draw heavily on facts within the relevant context, we would suggest that they will tend to be claims that a narrative is used ideologically. We can summarize this in Table 2.</p><p>The second point concerns the relation between the ideological use/ideologically suspicious distinction and the strength of the reason for rejecting the narrative. If X is known to be used ideologically, this provides the strongest reason for rejecting this use of X, since this entails that X has clear epistemic disvalue. In contrast, demonstrating that X is ideologically suspicious provides us with a reason that is not quite as strong, since it allows for the possibility that X is not actually being used ideologically. The fact that we might have good reasons to suspect X of being used ideologically does not necessarily entail that X is, in fact, used ideologically.</p><p>Now if GI-claims can never be claims that a narrative is used ideologically, we might think this difference in the strength of the reason for rejecting the narrative undermines the rationale for looking for a way of making plausible GI-claims in the first place. In the previous section, we noted that one of the limitations of CI-claims is that they might not provide a particularly strong reason for rejecting the use of the narrative in contexts other than the one in which it has been found to be used ideologically. But, if GI claims cannot provide a particularly strong reason either, what value do they have?</p><p>Our answer is that plausible GI-claims—that is, GI claims demonstrating that a particular narrative is ideologically suspicious—give us a stronger reason for rejecting the narrative across different contexts than any one CI claim. A CI claim gives us a very strong reason for rejecting the use of a narrative in a particular context, but a relatively weak reason for rejecting the use of the same narrative in other contexts. The latter reason would be no more than a weak form of induction: the fact that the narrative was used ideologically in one context gives us a reason to think that, if it is used elsewhere, it will also be used ideologically there. But as we saw in the previous section, this is because it might turn out that the features that cause a narrative to be used ideologically in a particular context do not obtain elsewhere. We can summarize this using Table 3.</p><p>The top-right box represents attempts to inductively extend CI-claims to the use of the narrative in other contexts. The reason why we think this provides a weaker reason for rejecting the narrative in those contexts than a GI-claim is this: to the extent that an argument for a GI-claim can be rendered plausible, it is less subject to the contingent factors of particular contexts than an inductive argument stemming from a single CI-claim. The strength of the latter can be diminished by differences between C<sub>1</sub> and other contexts, while the strength of the former cannot. Note, however, that this points to one of the challenges in making plausible GI-claims. It must be possible to show why a GI-claim is not vulnerable to differences in context.</p><p>At this point, it is worth considering two related objections, each of which is based on the view that the purposes of ideology critique are adequately serviced by making a multitude of CI-claims, without the need for a GI-claim. First, one might argue that if one wants to know about the status of the narrative in another context, one can simply examine that context. For example, if one wants to know about the status of sovereign debt narratives in, say, the aftermath of the 1970s oil crisis, one can simply study that context instead. Second, one might also argue that the strength of the reason in the top right box of Figure 3 can be increased if we can make multiple CI-claims about the use of the narrative, to a point where its strength might eventually exceed that of the GI-claim.</p><p>The problem with the first objection is that it renders ideology critique less capable of action guidance. This is because it is confined to the study of past contexts. It does not allow for claims to be made about the status of narratives that might be used again in the future. The second objection, meanwhile, has two problems. First, since there are usually limits to our access to information about different contexts, we cannot always rely on the availability of a multitude of CI-claims in order to strengthen an inductive argument. Second, even if a multitude of CI-claims were available, the GI-claim would still enjoy a distinct advantage over the inductive argument: it can tell us something more specific about the underlying reasons <i>why</i> a narrative has shown a tendency to be used ideologically.</p><p>With this in mind, our initial aim of extending Prinz and Rossi's theory of ideology critique beyond particular contexts can be reframed as an attempt to move from a CI-claim that a narrative is used ideologically to a GI-claim that the same narrative is ideologically suspicious. In the next section, we will try to show how this is possible.</p><p>Let us start by assuming that we have a plausible CI-claim: that X is used ideologically in C<sub>1</sub> in virtue of there being one or more disconnects between the reality and appearance of X in C<sub>1</sub>. Our aim here is to show how we can move from this claim to a plausible GI-claim: that X is ideologically suspicious across different contexts. Our strategy for doing this comes in two stages. First, we need to identify possible “deideologizing” mechanisms—that is, mechanisms that might be capable of overcoming these disconnects. Second, we need to show that these mechanisms are unlikely to succeed. If each of these two tasks can be accomplished, then we have shown that the possibility of differences in context does not prevent X from being regarded as ideologically suspicious. It would entail that any possible differences in context are not capable of generating effective mechanisms for overcoming these disconnects.</p><p>Our aim in this section is to help clarify this idea of a mechanism. We can divide mechanisms into two broad categories. The first category, which we will refer to as <i>safeguards</i>, contains what are generally the most likely candidates for overcoming disconnects. Safeguards are mechanisms for controlling the reality of the narrative in such a way that it does not stray from its appearance. The second, less common category, can be described as <i>narrative reform</i>. It seeks to revise the appearance of the narrative in order to bring it into line with reality. If an effective safeguard could be applied to moralistic narratives about sovereign debt, it would generally prevent these narratives from being invoked hypocritically. If an effective form of narrative reform could be applied to technocratic narratives, it would reconceptualize the claim that a particular policy is conclusively vindicated by expert analysis in such a way that renders it somehow compatible with the absence of any expert consensus.</p><p>We will first discuss two general problems when it comes to finding effective mechanisms. Following this, we will say a little more about safeguards and narrative reform respectively, and some of the more specific problems they may face.</p><p>Let us now see if we can apply this method to the question of sovereign debt. Prinz and Rossi, we believe, have already supplied us with a credible CI-claim about the use of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt in post-2008 Europe. In order to move from this to a credible GI-claim—that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are ideologically suspicious across contexts, we must carry out two tasks. First, we must identify what seem to be the most plausible candidate mechanisms for overcoming the disconnects between the appearance and reality of these narratives. Second, we must show that these mechanisms fail.</p><p>We sought to clarify the potential of the realist approach to ideology critique (Prinz &amp; Rossi, <span>2017</span>, <span>2021</span>) beyond contextual claims. We showed how we can bridge the gap between the fact that a narrative is ideological in a particular context and the claim that it is ideological across different contexts by showing that it is resistant to various mechanisms that might otherwise prevent it from functioning ideologically. We did so by focusing on the example of narratives about sovereign debt. We identified and reconstructed several promising mechanisms for countering the suspicion of ideology of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt. We have shown why none of these mechanisms are likely to be effective, certainly not reliably so. These steps vindicate the GI-claim, namely that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are prima facie ideologically suspicious at a general level.</p><p>We have said that our article offers three main contributions: a development of a method that enhances radical realism's capacity to provide action guidance; an application of this action guidance to sovereign debt narratives; and an illustration of how realism is compatible with certain forms of generalization and abstraction. We want to finish here by saying a little more about each of them.</p><p>First, political realists have often regarded the provision of action guidance as an essential desideratum for political philosophy, and have criticized moralists for failing to do this (Galston, <span>2010</span>; Horton, <span>2017</span>). However, it might be an open question whether realists have so far been any more successful than moralists in meeting this desideratum (Ulaş, <span>2020</span>). By showing how ideology critique can be used to anticipate future political debates, we hope to have shown how realism, at least in its radical form, can be genuinely action guiding.</p><p>Second, our argument contributes to the practical question of how to respond to future debates about sovereign debt. It shows a way for redirecting the constructive energies for dealing with sovereign debt towards political questions, which stand a better chance of leading to reliable orientation than ideologically suspicious technocratic and moralistic narratives. Such future debates are very likely to emerge in the aftermath of the coronavirus disease 2019 pandemic and the current return of high inflation. During the pandemic, many governments, in coordination with their central banks, increased deficit spending and issued the according amount of sovereign debt to levels which exceeded what was previously viewed as acceptable (Tooze, <span>2021</span>). In some countries, for example, Germany, debt brakes that are gradually becoming a regular feature of national law in the Eurozone, sometimes of constitutional rank, were temporarily suspended. While it might be tempting to suggest that the pandemic has taken us beyond technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt—even the Eurozone was willing to suspend the rules and create at least an indirect buyer of last resort for sovereign debt and collective sovereign bonds—the reemergence of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt is still very likely. The temporary exemptions from these debt brakes have been scheduled to run out, which would likely trigger the need for austerity, with the concomitant technocratic and moralistic narratives (Chappe &amp; Blyth, <span>2020</span>).</p><p>Our argument anticipates the return of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt to provide practical guidance in two ways. First, it provides those faced with such narratives with confidence for viewing them as generally ideologically suspicious. Second, by providing confidence for viewing these narratives as ideologically suspicious, our article contributes to a shift away from these narratives. Such a shift at least holds the possibility of the debates taking a more political turn, which would mean considering sovereign debt as a question structured by contingent power relations.</p><p>Third, our model of ideology critique may offer some insights regarding the extent to which political realism allows for abstraction and generalization. One might think that realism's emphasis on contextualism and fidelity to the facts might prevent it from making more generalizable claims that might go beyond a particular context (Lægaard, <span>2019</span>; for discussion, see Westphal, <span>2022</span>). However, the model of ideology critique we have outlined in this article does indeed show how realists can make claims that go beyond a particular context without forfeiting fidelity to the facts or contextualism. The kind of generalizable claims we have described here—what we have referred to as GI-claims—are responsive to facts and grounded in contextual interpretation in at least three ways. First, they draw on an accurate account of how a narrative functions in a particular context, as provided by the CI-claim. Second, the arguments about the effectiveness of safeguard and narrative reform mechanisms are also empirically informed. Third, the scope of the ideology critique mirrors the more general scope of the claims at the heart of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt, in as far as these narratives claim to be appropriate not just in the context at issue but more generally. Hence, we can see how fidelity to the facts and a commitment to contextual interpretation is compatible with certain modest forms of generalization. And, as we just noted, this generalization helps serve another important realist desideratum: resourcing real-world political thinking and activity.</p><p>Finally, it is also important to note what this model of ideology critique does <i>not</i> seek to do. It is not to be expected that it will tell us what the correct policy regarding sovereign debt is, if there is indeed such a thing. At most, it might point us towards one policy option by default if all its alternatives are revealed to depend on ideological narratives. In general, however, the purpose of ideology critique is to <i>resource</i> political decision-making, rather than determine it (Cross, <span>2022</span>, p. 1119; Kreutz &amp; Rossi, <span>2022</span>). It can do this by redirecting our attention away from narratives, which present a distorted version of reality.</p><p>This is not to say that our attention, once redirected, can be guaranteed to arrive at a more accurate version. It is entirely possible that casting away one ideologically suspicious narrative will result only in another ideologically suspicious narrative taking its place. And even if this does not occur, there is no guarantee that there is an “objective truth” waiting for us to discover once all ideological distortions have been cleared away. But as Rossi (<span>2019</span>, p. 647) points out, this is no reason not to seek for a less distorted picture of reality. The realist contention here is that our best hope for politics necessitates that ideological distortions are exposed for what they are. Ideology critique does not promise us a solution to all our political problems, but it helps remove some of the obstacles that stand in our way.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"56 1","pages":"116-132"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2023-02-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12511","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Can narratives about sovereign debt be generally ideologically suspicious? An exercise in broadening the scope of ideology critique\",\"authors\":\"Ben Cross,&nbsp;Janosch Prinz\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/josp.12511\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Our interest here is in the fourth of these theories. It strikes us as particularly interesting because it differs significantly from what are perhaps the most familiar notions of ideology. While the most familiar notions of ideology are arguably those which focus on the process of how a belief is generated, Prinz and Rossi (<span>2017</span>, p. 341) “focus not on the process of belief acquisition, but on the formation of the meaning of the relevant concept.” Furthermore, unlike the second type, it does not, strictly speaking, presuppose the existence of any particular distorting form of power, even if power asymmetries “are likely to be part of the picture” (Prinz &amp; Rossi, <span>2021</span>, p. 121).</p><p>However, we also think that the full potential of this novel theory of ideology has yet to be realized. As the theory currently stands, or at least, as we understand it, it focuses exclusively on how a narrative is <i>used by certain people in a particular instance</i>. If so, it does not rule out the possibility of addressing the disconnect by controlling or revising the way in which manifest and/or operative concepts are used. As a result, its conclusions are confined to a particular local case.</p><p>As an example of this, Prinz and Rossi (<span>2021</span>) criticize the use of technocratic and moralistic narratives in debates about sovereign debt during the post-2008 financial crises facing Greece and other European states. They argue that the use of these narratives during this period was ideological because there was a substantial difference between the appearance and the reality of their use. If their argument is sound, it tells us that technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt were used ideologically <i>in this particular context</i>. It allows for the possibility that the use of these narratives could be plausibly regarded as nonideological in other times and places.</p><p>Our interest, then, is in the extent to which it is possible to extend Prinz and Rossi's method of ideology critique, such that we can bridge the gap between: (i) P being used ideologically in a particular context and (ii) having reasons to regard P as in some sense pejoratively ideological across different contexts. Our main aim in this article is to show how it is possible to bridge this gap.</p><p>Our basic idea is this: we can bridge the gap between the fact that a narrative is ideological in a particular context and the claim that it is ideological across different contexts by showing that it is resistant to various mechanisms that might otherwise prevent it from functioning ideologically. The crucial step between (i) and (ii) is thus to find some way of showing that P is resistant to the kind of reform or oversight that would bring manifest and operative concepts more closely into line with each other.</p><p>Our idea might be best illustrated with a contrast case. Consider the medical profession. Let us grant, as seems plausible enough, that there are at least some medical doctors who are corrupt, incompetent, or in some other sense not what they purport to be. However, we might also think that there are various mechanisms—training, accountability, and so forth—that help ensure that such doctors are not the norm, and that the medical profession is on the whole reliable. To put it another way, the problem lies with bad doctors, rather than the profession itself. On our view, showing that a narrative is pejoratively ideological across different contexts amounts to showing that it is <i>not</i> like the medical profession. It means showing that there are no reliable mechanisms for keeping the narrative in check.<sup>2</sup></p><p>Our proposed extension of this theory of ideology critique makes three main contributions to existing literature. First, it extends the critical tools of ideology critique by showing how it can be used to anticipate ideologically suspicious narratives before they arise. It thus addresses a crucial realist desideratum, namely, that of providing action guidance to real-world political actors (Galston, <span>2010</span>; Horton, <span>2017</span>).</p><p>Second, we provide a short version of this kind of analysis for sovereign debt narratives. Extending the theory of ideology critique in this fashion would enable political actors in contexts other than that of post-2008 Europe to recognize that technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt would be ideologically suspicious <i>if</i> they were to be implemented in their own contexts.</p><p>Third, we show that radical realism's commitment to fidelity to the facts is not inconsistent with certain forms of abstraction and generalization. Our proposed method for showing how a given narrative can be ideologically suspicious across different contexts is rooted in empirical considerations, rather than a priori speculation. Our method may not be confined to a single context, but it is by no means context-free.</p><p>This essay proceeds as follows. In Section 2, we will examine Prinz and Rossi's discussion of ideology and sovereign debt more closely. We will try to show how their method of ideology critique effectively confines their criticism of sovereign debt narratives to their use in a particular context. In Section 3, we introduce a distinction between the <i>ideological use</i> of a narrative and its being <i>ideologically suspicious</i>. We explore the implications of this distinction and its relevance for broadening the scope of ideology critique. In Section 4, we outline our method for moving from a contextually specific theory of ideology critique to a broader theory that enables us to make claims about the epistemic status of a narrative across different contexts. In Section 5, we suggest some ways for applying this method to sovereign debt.</p><p>Public debates about sovereign debt come in a great variety of forms, often focusing on the extent to which the state might need to limit public spending in proportion to its revenue or on the status of creditor claims. Here, we set aside the details of such narratives and concentrate on their main framing. Prinz and Rossi (<span>2021</span>, pp. 118–125) criticize two framings of narratives often invoked in these debates: technocratic narratives, and moralist narratives. Technocratic narratives hold that expert knowledge of economics reveals what a sustainable approach to sovereign debt would look like, and that this expert knowledge should be heeded. Moralist narratives hold that the failure to pay sovereign debt is immoral in much the same way that it is immoral for a person to break a promise. Prinz and Rossi argue that both technocratic and moralist narratives were used ideologically during the post-2008 European financial crisis because these narratives were not what they seemed to be. In each case, there was a substantial disconnect between the narrative's appearance and its reality.</p><p>These disconnects enable Prinz and Rossi to conclude that the narratives were being used ideologically. However, there is a limitation to the scope of this conclusion. Prinz and Rossi's argument supports the claim that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are <i>contextually ideological</i>. That is, these narratives were used ideologically in a particular context (post-2008 Europe). However, this is not quite the same as demonstrating that the narratives are <i>generally ideological</i>, that is, pejoratively ideological across different contexts.</p><p>Let us refer to claims that a narrative is contextually ideological as CI-claims, and claims that a narrative is generally ideological as GI-claims. To clarify what is at stake in the distinction between CI-claims and GI-claims, suppose it turns out that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are contextually ideological but not generally ideological. One might then acknowledge that they functioned ideologically in post-2008 Europe, but nonetheless insist that these narratives might play non-ideological or perhaps even eminently epistemically valuable roles in other times and places. Perhaps there are other contexts in which we can be confident that the narratives could be invoked without either the epistemic certainty disconnect or the hypocrisy disconnect (or some other disconnect altogether) being present. This possibility could be ruled out only if we have good reasons to think that the narratives are generally ideological.</p><p>We want to emphasize that this is not necessarily a flaw in Prinz and Rossi's argument. Their argument that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are pejoratively ideological is substantial and important even if it is only advanced as a CI-claim. However, it has two significant limitations.</p><p>First, a GI-claim is evidently stronger, and in certain respects, more informative, than a CI-claim. It informs us about the status of the narrative in multiple contexts, as opposed to just one. Furthermore, showing that a narrative is generally ideological might tell us something more substantial about <i>why</i> it has been used ideologically in a particular context.</p><p>Second, and relatedly, a GI-claim provides clearer guidance for how the narrative in question should be approached and scrutinized <i>in the future</i>. This would strengthen the efforts of political theorists to provide practical, action-orienting guidance. Consider how Prinz and Rossi (<span>2021</span>, pp. 126–133) use their claim about the ideological character of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt to argue for a further claim: “to counter the danger of ideology, sovereign debt must be politicized all the way down” (2021, p. 116). That is, they recommend that debate about sovereign debt be confined to narratives that do not present themselves as “above the political fray.” Insofar as this is a proposal for depoliticizing debt in <i>all</i> contexts, it is also, in effect, a proposal for rejecting moralist and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt in all future contexts.</p><p>We think this proposal would receive stronger support from an argument making a GI-claim than one only making a CI-claim. Otherwise, one might argue that both the epistemic certainty disconnect and hypocrisy disconnect are no more than contingent features of moralist and technocratic narratives. Instead of proposing that the narratives are jettisoned altogether, one might instead propose that these two disconnects can be avoided. Why cannot we just recommend that the narratives be presented in a way that acknowledges uncertainty among experts? And why cannot we just recommend that proponents of the narratives employ them consistently? A stronger argument for jettisoning the narratives would require us to answer these questions. Doing so would amount to building a case for the claim that the narratives are generally ideological.</p><p>Our main interest here, then, is in exploring how we might move from a CI-claim to a GI-claim. Over the next two sections, we will try to explain how this is possible.</p><p>The first part of our strategy here is to make a distinction between the <i>ideological use</i> of a narrative and a narrative being <i>ideologically suspicious</i>. We have sufficient reasons to believe that a narrative is being used ideologically if we can conclusively demonstrate the existence of a disconnect between its appearance and its reality. In contrast, a narrative can still be ideologically suspicious even if the existence of this disconnect between the appearance and reality of its use cannot be conclusively demonstrated. In such cases, suspicion might arise because we have certain reasons for thinking that it is likely that a disconnect exists, even if we cannot conclusively verify it. It might also be because we have reasons for thinking that a disconnect would evade detection if it exists. If a narrative is ideologically suspicious, we cannot be confident that it is not being used ideologically, even though this is consistent with it not being so used.</p><p>There are two important points that need to be made in order to make sense of this distinction. The first concerns how it maps onto the contextually ideological/generally ideological distinction. CI-claims typically hold that a narrative is being used ideologically. This is because they are based on observations of various facts about how the narrative has functioned in this particular context. We think Prinz and Rossi give us good reasons to think that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt were used ideologically in the context of post-2008 Europe.</p><p>In contrast, if any GI-claims are plausible, they cannot consist of showing that a narrative is used ideologically. This is because GI-claims are made without access to information about how the narrative is used (or would be used) in all relevant contexts. However, this is not to say that GI-claims are necessarily made in ignorance of how the narrative happens to be operating in certain contexts. The claim that a narrative is contextually ideological in context C<sub>1</sub> might be an important premise in an argument for a GI—in fact, such claims do indeed form premises in the type of argument we will sketch in the next section. However, the argument for this GI-claim might not require awareness of how the narrative operates in C<sub>2</sub>, C<sub>3</sub>, C<sub>4</sub>, and so forth. Rather, it is meant to tell us something about how one might <i>suspect</i> that the narrative operates in other contexts, or would operate if it were to be used there. This points to a distinctive contribution of GI-claims: they can tell us something about the epistemic merits of the use of a narrative in a particular context even before it is used in this context.</p><p>A GI-claim can therefore only be a claim that a narrative is ideologically suspicious. There might also be certain circumstances where a CI-claim is only a claim that a narrative is ideologically suspicious. One possible reason for this might be that our information about the functioning of the narrative in this context is incomplete, but nonetheless adequate for generating reasons for suspicion. However, given that CI-claims draw heavily on facts within the relevant context, we would suggest that they will tend to be claims that a narrative is used ideologically. We can summarize this in Table 2.</p><p>The second point concerns the relation between the ideological use/ideologically suspicious distinction and the strength of the reason for rejecting the narrative. If X is known to be used ideologically, this provides the strongest reason for rejecting this use of X, since this entails that X has clear epistemic disvalue. In contrast, demonstrating that X is ideologically suspicious provides us with a reason that is not quite as strong, since it allows for the possibility that X is not actually being used ideologically. The fact that we might have good reasons to suspect X of being used ideologically does not necessarily entail that X is, in fact, used ideologically.</p><p>Now if GI-claims can never be claims that a narrative is used ideologically, we might think this difference in the strength of the reason for rejecting the narrative undermines the rationale for looking for a way of making plausible GI-claims in the first place. In the previous section, we noted that one of the limitations of CI-claims is that they might not provide a particularly strong reason for rejecting the use of the narrative in contexts other than the one in which it has been found to be used ideologically. But, if GI claims cannot provide a particularly strong reason either, what value do they have?</p><p>Our answer is that plausible GI-claims—that is, GI claims demonstrating that a particular narrative is ideologically suspicious—give us a stronger reason for rejecting the narrative across different contexts than any one CI claim. A CI claim gives us a very strong reason for rejecting the use of a narrative in a particular context, but a relatively weak reason for rejecting the use of the same narrative in other contexts. The latter reason would be no more than a weak form of induction: the fact that the narrative was used ideologically in one context gives us a reason to think that, if it is used elsewhere, it will also be used ideologically there. But as we saw in the previous section, this is because it might turn out that the features that cause a narrative to be used ideologically in a particular context do not obtain elsewhere. We can summarize this using Table 3.</p><p>The top-right box represents attempts to inductively extend CI-claims to the use of the narrative in other contexts. The reason why we think this provides a weaker reason for rejecting the narrative in those contexts than a GI-claim is this: to the extent that an argument for a GI-claim can be rendered plausible, it is less subject to the contingent factors of particular contexts than an inductive argument stemming from a single CI-claim. The strength of the latter can be diminished by differences between C<sub>1</sub> and other contexts, while the strength of the former cannot. Note, however, that this points to one of the challenges in making plausible GI-claims. It must be possible to show why a GI-claim is not vulnerable to differences in context.</p><p>At this point, it is worth considering two related objections, each of which is based on the view that the purposes of ideology critique are adequately serviced by making a multitude of CI-claims, without the need for a GI-claim. First, one might argue that if one wants to know about the status of the narrative in another context, one can simply examine that context. For example, if one wants to know about the status of sovereign debt narratives in, say, the aftermath of the 1970s oil crisis, one can simply study that context instead. Second, one might also argue that the strength of the reason in the top right box of Figure 3 can be increased if we can make multiple CI-claims about the use of the narrative, to a point where its strength might eventually exceed that of the GI-claim.</p><p>The problem with the first objection is that it renders ideology critique less capable of action guidance. This is because it is confined to the study of past contexts. It does not allow for claims to be made about the status of narratives that might be used again in the future. The second objection, meanwhile, has two problems. First, since there are usually limits to our access to information about different contexts, we cannot always rely on the availability of a multitude of CI-claims in order to strengthen an inductive argument. Second, even if a multitude of CI-claims were available, the GI-claim would still enjoy a distinct advantage over the inductive argument: it can tell us something more specific about the underlying reasons <i>why</i> a narrative has shown a tendency to be used ideologically.</p><p>With this in mind, our initial aim of extending Prinz and Rossi's theory of ideology critique beyond particular contexts can be reframed as an attempt to move from a CI-claim that a narrative is used ideologically to a GI-claim that the same narrative is ideologically suspicious. In the next section, we will try to show how this is possible.</p><p>Let us start by assuming that we have a plausible CI-claim: that X is used ideologically in C<sub>1</sub> in virtue of there being one or more disconnects between the reality and appearance of X in C<sub>1</sub>. Our aim here is to show how we can move from this claim to a plausible GI-claim: that X is ideologically suspicious across different contexts. Our strategy for doing this comes in two stages. First, we need to identify possible “deideologizing” mechanisms—that is, mechanisms that might be capable of overcoming these disconnects. Second, we need to show that these mechanisms are unlikely to succeed. If each of these two tasks can be accomplished, then we have shown that the possibility of differences in context does not prevent X from being regarded as ideologically suspicious. It would entail that any possible differences in context are not capable of generating effective mechanisms for overcoming these disconnects.</p><p>Our aim in this section is to help clarify this idea of a mechanism. We can divide mechanisms into two broad categories. The first category, which we will refer to as <i>safeguards</i>, contains what are generally the most likely candidates for overcoming disconnects. Safeguards are mechanisms for controlling the reality of the narrative in such a way that it does not stray from its appearance. The second, less common category, can be described as <i>narrative reform</i>. It seeks to revise the appearance of the narrative in order to bring it into line with reality. If an effective safeguard could be applied to moralistic narratives about sovereign debt, it would generally prevent these narratives from being invoked hypocritically. If an effective form of narrative reform could be applied to technocratic narratives, it would reconceptualize the claim that a particular policy is conclusively vindicated by expert analysis in such a way that renders it somehow compatible with the absence of any expert consensus.</p><p>We will first discuss two general problems when it comes to finding effective mechanisms. Following this, we will say a little more about safeguards and narrative reform respectively, and some of the more specific problems they may face.</p><p>Let us now see if we can apply this method to the question of sovereign debt. Prinz and Rossi, we believe, have already supplied us with a credible CI-claim about the use of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt in post-2008 Europe. In order to move from this to a credible GI-claim—that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are ideologically suspicious across contexts, we must carry out two tasks. First, we must identify what seem to be the most plausible candidate mechanisms for overcoming the disconnects between the appearance and reality of these narratives. Second, we must show that these mechanisms fail.</p><p>We sought to clarify the potential of the realist approach to ideology critique (Prinz &amp; Rossi, <span>2017</span>, <span>2021</span>) beyond contextual claims. We showed how we can bridge the gap between the fact that a narrative is ideological in a particular context and the claim that it is ideological across different contexts by showing that it is resistant to various mechanisms that might otherwise prevent it from functioning ideologically. We did so by focusing on the example of narratives about sovereign debt. We identified and reconstructed several promising mechanisms for countering the suspicion of ideology of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt. We have shown why none of these mechanisms are likely to be effective, certainly not reliably so. These steps vindicate the GI-claim, namely that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are prima facie ideologically suspicious at a general level.</p><p>We have said that our article offers three main contributions: a development of a method that enhances radical realism's capacity to provide action guidance; an application of this action guidance to sovereign debt narratives; and an illustration of how realism is compatible with certain forms of generalization and abstraction. We want to finish here by saying a little more about each of them.</p><p>First, political realists have often regarded the provision of action guidance as an essential desideratum for political philosophy, and have criticized moralists for failing to do this (Galston, <span>2010</span>; Horton, <span>2017</span>). However, it might be an open question whether realists have so far been any more successful than moralists in meeting this desideratum (Ulaş, <span>2020</span>). By showing how ideology critique can be used to anticipate future political debates, we hope to have shown how realism, at least in its radical form, can be genuinely action guiding.</p><p>Second, our argument contributes to the practical question of how to respond to future debates about sovereign debt. It shows a way for redirecting the constructive energies for dealing with sovereign debt towards political questions, which stand a better chance of leading to reliable orientation than ideologically suspicious technocratic and moralistic narratives. Such future debates are very likely to emerge in the aftermath of the coronavirus disease 2019 pandemic and the current return of high inflation. During the pandemic, many governments, in coordination with their central banks, increased deficit spending and issued the according amount of sovereign debt to levels which exceeded what was previously viewed as acceptable (Tooze, <span>2021</span>). In some countries, for example, Germany, debt brakes that are gradually becoming a regular feature of national law in the Eurozone, sometimes of constitutional rank, were temporarily suspended. While it might be tempting to suggest that the pandemic has taken us beyond technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt—even the Eurozone was willing to suspend the rules and create at least an indirect buyer of last resort for sovereign debt and collective sovereign bonds—the reemergence of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt is still very likely. The temporary exemptions from these debt brakes have been scheduled to run out, which would likely trigger the need for austerity, with the concomitant technocratic and moralistic narratives (Chappe &amp; Blyth, <span>2020</span>).</p><p>Our argument anticipates the return of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt to provide practical guidance in two ways. First, it provides those faced with such narratives with confidence for viewing them as generally ideologically suspicious. Second, by providing confidence for viewing these narratives as ideologically suspicious, our article contributes to a shift away from these narratives. Such a shift at least holds the possibility of the debates taking a more political turn, which would mean considering sovereign debt as a question structured by contingent power relations.</p><p>Third, our model of ideology critique may offer some insights regarding the extent to which political realism allows for abstraction and generalization. One might think that realism's emphasis on contextualism and fidelity to the facts might prevent it from making more generalizable claims that might go beyond a particular context (Lægaard, <span>2019</span>; for discussion, see Westphal, <span>2022</span>). However, the model of ideology critique we have outlined in this article does indeed show how realists can make claims that go beyond a particular context without forfeiting fidelity to the facts or contextualism. The kind of generalizable claims we have described here—what we have referred to as GI-claims—are responsive to facts and grounded in contextual interpretation in at least three ways. First, they draw on an accurate account of how a narrative functions in a particular context, as provided by the CI-claim. Second, the arguments about the effectiveness of safeguard and narrative reform mechanisms are also empirically informed. Third, the scope of the ideology critique mirrors the more general scope of the claims at the heart of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt, in as far as these narratives claim to be appropriate not just in the context at issue but more generally. Hence, we can see how fidelity to the facts and a commitment to contextual interpretation is compatible with certain modest forms of generalization. And, as we just noted, this generalization helps serve another important realist desideratum: resourcing real-world political thinking and activity.</p><p>Finally, it is also important to note what this model of ideology critique does <i>not</i> seek to do. It is not to be expected that it will tell us what the correct policy regarding sovereign debt is, if there is indeed such a thing. At most, it might point us towards one policy option by default if all its alternatives are revealed to depend on ideological narratives. In general, however, the purpose of ideology critique is to <i>resource</i> political decision-making, rather than determine it (Cross, <span>2022</span>, p. 1119; Kreutz &amp; Rossi, <span>2022</span>). It can do this by redirecting our attention away from narratives, which present a distorted version of reality.</p><p>This is not to say that our attention, once redirected, can be guaranteed to arrive at a more accurate version. It is entirely possible that casting away one ideologically suspicious narrative will result only in another ideologically suspicious narrative taking its place. And even if this does not occur, there is no guarantee that there is an “objective truth” waiting for us to discover once all ideological distortions have been cleared away. But as Rossi (<span>2019</span>, p. 647) points out, this is no reason not to seek for a less distorted picture of reality. The realist contention here is that our best hope for politics necessitates that ideological distortions are exposed for what they are. Ideology critique does not promise us a solution to all our political problems, but it helps remove some of the obstacles that stand in our way.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46756,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"volume\":\"56 1\",\"pages\":\"116-132\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-02-12\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12511\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12511\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12511","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

我们感兴趣的是第四种理论。它让我们感到特别有趣,因为它与我们最熟悉的意识形态概念有很大的不同。虽然最熟悉的意识形态概念可以说是那些关注信念如何产生过程的概念,但Prinz和Rossi (2017, p. 341)“不关注信念获得的过程,而是关注相关概念意义的形成。”此外,与第二种类型不同的是,严格来说,它并没有预设任何特定的扭曲形式的权力的存在,即使权力不对称“很可能是画面的一部分”(Prinz &amp;Rossi, 2021,第121页)。然而,我们也认为,这一新颖的意识形态理论的潜力尚未充分发挥出来。根据该理论目前的立场,或者至少在我们的理解中,它只关注特定情况下某些人如何使用叙述。如果是这样,则不排除通过控制或修改使用显示和/或操作概念的方式来解决这种脱节的可能性。因此,其结论仅限于一个特定的当地案例。作为这方面的一个例子,Prinz和Rossi(2021)批评在2008年后希腊和其他欧洲国家面临的金融危机期间,在关于主权债务的辩论中使用技术官僚和道德主义叙事。他们认为,在这一时期,这些叙事的使用是意识形态的,因为它们的使用在表象和现实之间存在着巨大的差异。如果他们的论点是合理的,那么它告诉我们,在这种特殊背景下,有关主权债务的技术官僚主义和道德主义叙事在意识形态上被使用了。它允许这样一种可能性,即在其他时间和地点,这些叙事的使用可能被合理地视为非意识形态。因此,我们的兴趣在于,在多大程度上可以扩展Prinz和Rossi的意识形态批判方法,这样我们就可以弥合以下两者之间的差距:(i) P在特定背景下被意识形态地使用,以及(ii)有理由在不同背景下将P视为某种意义上贬义的意识形态。本文的主要目的是展示如何弥合这一差距。我们的基本思想是这样的:我们可以通过展示它对各种可能阻止它在意识形态上发挥作用的机制的抵抗,来弥合叙述在特定语境中是意识形态的这一事实与在不同语境中是意识形态的这一说法之间的差距。因此,在(i)和(ii)之间的关键步骤是找到某种方法来表明P抗拒那种能使明显的和可操作的概念更紧密地彼此一致的改革或监督。我们的想法可以用一个对比的例子来最好地说明。以医疗行业为例。让我们承认,至少有一些医生是腐败的、无能的,或者在某种意义上不是他们所声称的那样,这似乎是合理的。然而,我们可能也会认为,有各种各样的机制——培训、问责等等——有助于确保这样的医生不是常态,并且医疗行业总体上是可靠的。换句话说,问题出在坏医生身上,而不是这个职业本身。在我们看来,表明一种叙述在不同的背景下带有贬义的意识形态,就等于表明它不像医学专业。这意味着没有可靠的机制来控制叙事。我们对这一意识形态批判理论的延伸提出了对现有文献的三个主要贡献。首先,它扩展了意识形态批判的批判工具,展示了如何在意识形态可疑的叙事出现之前使用它来预测它们。因此,它解决了一个关键的现实主义愿望,即为现实世界的政治行动者提供行动指导(Galston, 2010;霍顿,2017)。其次,我们为主权债务叙事提供了这种分析的简短版本。以这种方式扩展意识形态批判理论,将使2008年后欧洲以外的背景下的政治行动者认识到,如果在自己的背景下实施有关主权债务的技术官僚和道德主义叙事,将在意识形态上令人怀疑。第三,我们表明激进现实主义忠于事实的承诺与某些形式的抽象和概括并不矛盾。我们提出的方法是基于经验的考虑,而不是先验的推测,来显示给定的叙述如何在不同的背景下在意识形态上是可疑的。我们的方法可能不局限于单个上下文,但它绝不是与上下文无关的。这篇文章是这样进行的。在第2节中,我们将更仔细地研究Prinz和Rossi对意识形态和主权债务的讨论。 现在,如果gi的主张永远不能成为叙事被意识形态使用的主张,我们可能会认为,这种拒绝叙事的理由强度的差异破坏了寻找一种合理的gi主张的方法的基本原理。在前一节中,我们注意到,ci声明的局限性之一是,它们可能不能提供一个特别有力的理由来拒绝在除了被发现在意识形态上被使用的情况下使用叙事的情况下使用叙事。但是,如果地理标志索赔也不能提供一个特别有力的理由,那么它们还有什么价值呢?我们的答案是,可信的CI主张——也就是说,GI主张表明一个特定的叙述在意识形态上是可疑的——给了我们一个更有力的理由来拒绝不同背景下的叙述,而不是任何一个CI主张。CI主张为我们提供了一个非常有力的理由来拒绝在特定语境中使用叙述,但却提供了一个相对薄弱的理由来拒绝在其他语境中使用同一叙述。后一种理由只不过是一种弱形式的归纳法:叙述在一种语境中被意识形态地使用,这一事实使我们有理由认为,如果它在其他地方被使用,它也会在那里被意识形态地使用。但正如我们在前一节所看到的,这是因为在特定的语境中,导致叙事在意识形态上被使用的特征可能不会在其他地方出现。我们可以用表3总结这一点。右上方的方框表示尝试归纳地将ci声明扩展到在其他上下文中使用叙述。我们之所以认为这比GI-claim提供了一个更弱的理由来拒绝那些上下文中的叙述,是因为:在某种程度上,GI-claim的论点可以被认为是合理的,它比源自单个CI-claim的归纳论点更少受到特定上下文的偶然因素的影响。后者的强度可能会因C1和其他上下文之间的差异而减弱,而前者的强度则不会。然而,请注意,这指出了提出合理的gi声明的挑战之一。必须能够说明为什么gi声明不容易受到上下文差异的影响。在这一点上,值得考虑两种相关的反对意见,每一种反对意见都基于这样一种观点,即意识形态批判的目的可以通过提出大量的gi声明来充分满足,而不需要gi声明。首先,有人可能会说,如果一个人想知道叙事在另一个语境中的地位,他可以简单地检查那个语境。例如,如果你想知道主权债务叙事在上世纪70年代石油危机之后的地位,你可以简单地研究那个背景。其次,有人可能还会争辩说,如果我们可以对叙述的使用做出多个ci声明,那么图3右上方框中的理由的强度可以增加,直到它的强度最终可能超过gi声明的强度。第一个反对意见的问题在于,它削弱了意识形态批判指导行动的能力。这是因为它仅限于对过去语境的研究。它不允许对将来可能再次使用的叙述的状态作出声明。与此同时,第二个反对意见有两个问题。首先,由于我们对不同语境信息的获取通常是有限的,我们不能总是依靠大量ci声明的可用性来加强归纳论证。其次,即使有大量的ci -claim可用,GI-claim仍然比归纳论点有明显的优势:它可以告诉我们一些更具体的关于为什么一个叙述显示出被意识形态使用的倾向的潜在原因。考虑到这一点,我们将Prinz和Rossi的意识形态批判理论扩展到特定语境之外的最初目标可以被重新定义为一种尝试,即从gi的主张——一种叙事被意识形态地使用——转向gi的主张——同样的叙事在意识形态上是可疑的。在下一节中,我们将尝试说明这是如何实现的。让我们先假设我们有一个貌似合理的ci命题:X在C1中被意识形态地使用是因为在C1中X的现实与表象之间存在一个或多个脱节。我们在这里的目的是展示我们如何从这个论断转向一个合理的gi论断:X在不同的语境中在意识形态上是可疑的。我们的策略分为两个阶段。首先,我们需要确定可能的“去意识形态化”机制——也就是说,可能能够克服这些脱节的机制。其次,我们需要证明这些机制不太可能成功。如果这两项任务都能完成,那么我们已经表明,上下文差异的可能性并不能阻止X被视为意识形态可疑。 这将导致任何可能的背景差异都无法产生克服这些脱节的有效机制。本节的目的是帮助阐明机制的这个概念。我们可以将机制分为两大类。第一类,我们将其称为保障措施,包含通常最有可能克服断开的候选对象。保障措施是一种控制叙事现实的机制,使其不会偏离表象。第二种,不太常见的类型,可以被描述为叙事改革。它试图修改叙事的外观,以使其符合现实。如果一种有效的保护措施能够适用于有关主权债务的道德叙事,它通常会防止这些叙事被伪善地援引。如果能够将一种有效的叙述改革形式应用于技术官僚的叙述,它将重新定义下述说法,即专家分析最终证明某项政策是正确的,从而使其在某种程度上与缺乏任何专家共识相一致。在寻找有效机制方面,我们将首先讨论两个一般性问题。在此之后,我们将分别谈谈保障和叙事改革,以及它们可能面临的一些更具体的问题。现在让我们看看能否将这种方法应用于主权债务问题。我们认为,普林茨和罗西已经为我们提供了一个可信的ci主张,即在2008年后的欧洲主权债务问题上使用道德主义和技术官僚主义的叙述。为了从这一点转向可信的gi主张——关于主权债务的道德主义和技术官僚叙事在意识形态上是可疑的,我们必须完成两项任务。首先,我们必须确定似乎最合理的候选机制,以克服这些叙事的表象与现实之间的脱节。其次,我们必须证明这些机制是失败的。我们试图澄清现实主义方法对意识形态批判的潜力(Prinz &amp;Rossi, 2017,2021)超越上下文主张。我们展示了如何弥合叙述在特定语境中是意识形态的这一事实与在不同语境中是意识形态的这一说法之间的差距,方法是展示它对各种可能阻止它在意识形态上发挥作用的机制的抵抗力。我们通过关注主权债务叙事的例子来做到这一点。我们确定并重建了几个有希望的机制,以对抗对主权债务的道德主义和技术官僚叙事的意识形态的怀疑。我们已经说明了为什么这些机制都不可能有效,当然也不可靠。这些步骤证明了gi的说法是正确的,即关于主权债务的道德主义和技术官僚叙事在总体层面上在意识形态上是初步可疑的。我们已经说过,我们的文章提供了三个主要贡献:发展了一种方法,增强了激进现实主义提供行动指导的能力;将这一行动指南应用于主权债务叙述;这也说明了现实主义是如何与某些形式的概括和抽象相容的。我们想在这里多说一点关于他们每一个。首先,政治现实主义者经常将提供行动指导视为政治哲学的基本要求,并批评道德主义者未能做到这一点(Galston, 2010;霍顿,2017)。然而,到目前为止,现实主义者是否比道德家更成功地满足了这一愿望,这可能是一个悬而未决的问题(ulaku, 2020)。通过展示如何使用意识形态批判来预测未来的政治辩论,我们希望展示现实主义,至少在其激进形式下,如何能够真正指导行动。其次,我们的论点有助于解决一个实际问题,即如何应对未来有关主权债务的辩论。它显示了一种将处理主权债务的建设性精力转向政治问题的方法,政治问题比意识形态上可疑的技术官僚主义和道德主义叙事更有可能导向可靠的方向。在2019年冠状病毒大流行和当前高通胀回归之后,未来很可能出现这样的辩论。在疫情期间,许多政府与其中央银行协调,增加了赤字支出,并发行了相应数量的主权债务,超过了以前认为可接受的水平(Tooze, 2021年)。在德国等一些国家,债务刹车机制已被暂时搁置。债务刹车机制正逐渐成为欧元区国家法律的常规特征,有时还具有宪法级别。 尽管人们可能很容易认为,这场大流行已经让我们超越了关于主权债务的技术官僚主义和道德主义叙事——即使欧元区愿意暂停这些规则,至少为主权债务和集体主权债券创造一个间接的最后买家——但关于主权债务的技术官僚主义和道德主义叙事仍然很有可能重新出现。这些债务刹车的临时豁免计划即将到期,这可能会引发紧缩的需要,并伴随着技术官僚和道德主义的叙述。切,2020)。我们的论点预计,有关主权债务的技术官僚主义和道德主义叙事将在两个方面提供实际指导。首先,它让那些面对此类叙事的人有信心将其视为意识形态上的可疑。其次,通过提供将这些叙事视为意识形态可疑的信心,我们的文章有助于摆脱这些叙事。这种转变至少有可能使辩论转向更政治化的方向,这将意味着将主权债务视为一个由偶然性权力关系构成的问题。第三,我们的意识形态批判模型可以提供一些关于政治现实主义允许抽象和概括的程度的见解。有人可能会认为,现实主义对情境主义和对事实的忠诚的强调可能会阻止它提出可能超出特定背景的更概括的主张(Lægaard, 2019;有关讨论,请参见Westphal, 2022)。然而,我们在本文中概述的意识形态批判模型确实表明,现实主义者如何能够在不丧失对事实或情境主义的忠诚的情况下,提出超越特定背景的主张。我们在这里描述的那种可概括的主张——我们称之为gi主张——是对事实的回应,并且至少以三种方式建立在上下文解释的基础上。首先,他们利用了一种准确的描述,即一种叙述在特定语境中是如何发挥作用的,就像ci声明所提供的那样。其次,关于保障机制和叙事改革机制有效性的论证也有实证依据。第三,意识形态批判的范围反映了技术官僚和道德主义关于主权债务的叙述的核心主张的更普遍的范围,因为这些叙述声称不仅在争论的背景下,而且在更普遍的情况下是合适的。因此,我们可以看到对事实的忠实和对上下文解释的承诺是如何与某些适度形式的概括相兼容的。而且,正如我们刚才提到的,这种概括有助于满足现实主义者的另一个重要愿望:为现实世界的政治思想和活动提供资源。最后,同样重要的是要注意到这种意识形态批判模式并没有寻求做什么。我们不能指望它会告诉我们,关于主权债务的正确政策是什么——如果真有这样的政策的话。至多,如果所有的备选方案都暴露出依赖于意识形态叙事,它可能会让我们默认选择一种政策。然而,一般来说,意识形态批判的目的是为政治决策提供资源,而不是决定它(Cross, 2022,第1119页;克鲁兹,罗西,2022)。它可以通过将我们的注意力从呈现扭曲现实的叙事中转移开来来做到这一点。这并不是说,我们的注意力一旦被重新定向,就能保证到达一个更准确的版本。抛弃一种意识形态上可疑的叙事,只会导致另一种意识形态上可疑的叙事取而代之,这是完全可能的。即使不发生这种情况,也不能保证一旦所有意识形态的扭曲都被清除,就会有“客观真理”等着我们去发现。但正如罗西(2019年,第647页)指出的那样,没有理由不去寻求一幅不那么扭曲的现实图景。现实主义的论点是,我们对政治的最大希望是意识形态扭曲被暴露出来。意识形态批判并不能解决我们所有的政治问题,但它有助于消除我们前进道路上的一些障碍。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Can narratives about sovereign debt be generally ideologically suspicious? An exercise in broadening the scope of ideology critique

Our interest here is in the fourth of these theories. It strikes us as particularly interesting because it differs significantly from what are perhaps the most familiar notions of ideology. While the most familiar notions of ideology are arguably those which focus on the process of how a belief is generated, Prinz and Rossi (2017, p. 341) “focus not on the process of belief acquisition, but on the formation of the meaning of the relevant concept.” Furthermore, unlike the second type, it does not, strictly speaking, presuppose the existence of any particular distorting form of power, even if power asymmetries “are likely to be part of the picture” (Prinz & Rossi, 2021, p. 121).

However, we also think that the full potential of this novel theory of ideology has yet to be realized. As the theory currently stands, or at least, as we understand it, it focuses exclusively on how a narrative is used by certain people in a particular instance. If so, it does not rule out the possibility of addressing the disconnect by controlling or revising the way in which manifest and/or operative concepts are used. As a result, its conclusions are confined to a particular local case.

As an example of this, Prinz and Rossi (2021) criticize the use of technocratic and moralistic narratives in debates about sovereign debt during the post-2008 financial crises facing Greece and other European states. They argue that the use of these narratives during this period was ideological because there was a substantial difference between the appearance and the reality of their use. If their argument is sound, it tells us that technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt were used ideologically in this particular context. It allows for the possibility that the use of these narratives could be plausibly regarded as nonideological in other times and places.

Our interest, then, is in the extent to which it is possible to extend Prinz and Rossi's method of ideology critique, such that we can bridge the gap between: (i) P being used ideologically in a particular context and (ii) having reasons to regard P as in some sense pejoratively ideological across different contexts. Our main aim in this article is to show how it is possible to bridge this gap.

Our basic idea is this: we can bridge the gap between the fact that a narrative is ideological in a particular context and the claim that it is ideological across different contexts by showing that it is resistant to various mechanisms that might otherwise prevent it from functioning ideologically. The crucial step between (i) and (ii) is thus to find some way of showing that P is resistant to the kind of reform or oversight that would bring manifest and operative concepts more closely into line with each other.

Our idea might be best illustrated with a contrast case. Consider the medical profession. Let us grant, as seems plausible enough, that there are at least some medical doctors who are corrupt, incompetent, or in some other sense not what they purport to be. However, we might also think that there are various mechanisms—training, accountability, and so forth—that help ensure that such doctors are not the norm, and that the medical profession is on the whole reliable. To put it another way, the problem lies with bad doctors, rather than the profession itself. On our view, showing that a narrative is pejoratively ideological across different contexts amounts to showing that it is not like the medical profession. It means showing that there are no reliable mechanisms for keeping the narrative in check.2

Our proposed extension of this theory of ideology critique makes three main contributions to existing literature. First, it extends the critical tools of ideology critique by showing how it can be used to anticipate ideologically suspicious narratives before they arise. It thus addresses a crucial realist desideratum, namely, that of providing action guidance to real-world political actors (Galston, 2010; Horton, 2017).

Second, we provide a short version of this kind of analysis for sovereign debt narratives. Extending the theory of ideology critique in this fashion would enable political actors in contexts other than that of post-2008 Europe to recognize that technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt would be ideologically suspicious if they were to be implemented in their own contexts.

Third, we show that radical realism's commitment to fidelity to the facts is not inconsistent with certain forms of abstraction and generalization. Our proposed method for showing how a given narrative can be ideologically suspicious across different contexts is rooted in empirical considerations, rather than a priori speculation. Our method may not be confined to a single context, but it is by no means context-free.

This essay proceeds as follows. In Section 2, we will examine Prinz and Rossi's discussion of ideology and sovereign debt more closely. We will try to show how their method of ideology critique effectively confines their criticism of sovereign debt narratives to their use in a particular context. In Section 3, we introduce a distinction between the ideological use of a narrative and its being ideologically suspicious. We explore the implications of this distinction and its relevance for broadening the scope of ideology critique. In Section 4, we outline our method for moving from a contextually specific theory of ideology critique to a broader theory that enables us to make claims about the epistemic status of a narrative across different contexts. In Section 5, we suggest some ways for applying this method to sovereign debt.

Public debates about sovereign debt come in a great variety of forms, often focusing on the extent to which the state might need to limit public spending in proportion to its revenue or on the status of creditor claims. Here, we set aside the details of such narratives and concentrate on their main framing. Prinz and Rossi (2021, pp. 118–125) criticize two framings of narratives often invoked in these debates: technocratic narratives, and moralist narratives. Technocratic narratives hold that expert knowledge of economics reveals what a sustainable approach to sovereign debt would look like, and that this expert knowledge should be heeded. Moralist narratives hold that the failure to pay sovereign debt is immoral in much the same way that it is immoral for a person to break a promise. Prinz and Rossi argue that both technocratic and moralist narratives were used ideologically during the post-2008 European financial crisis because these narratives were not what they seemed to be. In each case, there was a substantial disconnect between the narrative's appearance and its reality.

These disconnects enable Prinz and Rossi to conclude that the narratives were being used ideologically. However, there is a limitation to the scope of this conclusion. Prinz and Rossi's argument supports the claim that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are contextually ideological. That is, these narratives were used ideologically in a particular context (post-2008 Europe). However, this is not quite the same as demonstrating that the narratives are generally ideological, that is, pejoratively ideological across different contexts.

Let us refer to claims that a narrative is contextually ideological as CI-claims, and claims that a narrative is generally ideological as GI-claims. To clarify what is at stake in the distinction between CI-claims and GI-claims, suppose it turns out that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are contextually ideological but not generally ideological. One might then acknowledge that they functioned ideologically in post-2008 Europe, but nonetheless insist that these narratives might play non-ideological or perhaps even eminently epistemically valuable roles in other times and places. Perhaps there are other contexts in which we can be confident that the narratives could be invoked without either the epistemic certainty disconnect or the hypocrisy disconnect (or some other disconnect altogether) being present. This possibility could be ruled out only if we have good reasons to think that the narratives are generally ideological.

We want to emphasize that this is not necessarily a flaw in Prinz and Rossi's argument. Their argument that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are pejoratively ideological is substantial and important even if it is only advanced as a CI-claim. However, it has two significant limitations.

First, a GI-claim is evidently stronger, and in certain respects, more informative, than a CI-claim. It informs us about the status of the narrative in multiple contexts, as opposed to just one. Furthermore, showing that a narrative is generally ideological might tell us something more substantial about why it has been used ideologically in a particular context.

Second, and relatedly, a GI-claim provides clearer guidance for how the narrative in question should be approached and scrutinized in the future. This would strengthen the efforts of political theorists to provide practical, action-orienting guidance. Consider how Prinz and Rossi (2021, pp. 126–133) use their claim about the ideological character of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt to argue for a further claim: “to counter the danger of ideology, sovereign debt must be politicized all the way down” (2021, p. 116). That is, they recommend that debate about sovereign debt be confined to narratives that do not present themselves as “above the political fray.” Insofar as this is a proposal for depoliticizing debt in all contexts, it is also, in effect, a proposal for rejecting moralist and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt in all future contexts.

We think this proposal would receive stronger support from an argument making a GI-claim than one only making a CI-claim. Otherwise, one might argue that both the epistemic certainty disconnect and hypocrisy disconnect are no more than contingent features of moralist and technocratic narratives. Instead of proposing that the narratives are jettisoned altogether, one might instead propose that these two disconnects can be avoided. Why cannot we just recommend that the narratives be presented in a way that acknowledges uncertainty among experts? And why cannot we just recommend that proponents of the narratives employ them consistently? A stronger argument for jettisoning the narratives would require us to answer these questions. Doing so would amount to building a case for the claim that the narratives are generally ideological.

Our main interest here, then, is in exploring how we might move from a CI-claim to a GI-claim. Over the next two sections, we will try to explain how this is possible.

The first part of our strategy here is to make a distinction between the ideological use of a narrative and a narrative being ideologically suspicious. We have sufficient reasons to believe that a narrative is being used ideologically if we can conclusively demonstrate the existence of a disconnect between its appearance and its reality. In contrast, a narrative can still be ideologically suspicious even if the existence of this disconnect between the appearance and reality of its use cannot be conclusively demonstrated. In such cases, suspicion might arise because we have certain reasons for thinking that it is likely that a disconnect exists, even if we cannot conclusively verify it. It might also be because we have reasons for thinking that a disconnect would evade detection if it exists. If a narrative is ideologically suspicious, we cannot be confident that it is not being used ideologically, even though this is consistent with it not being so used.

There are two important points that need to be made in order to make sense of this distinction. The first concerns how it maps onto the contextually ideological/generally ideological distinction. CI-claims typically hold that a narrative is being used ideologically. This is because they are based on observations of various facts about how the narrative has functioned in this particular context. We think Prinz and Rossi give us good reasons to think that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt were used ideologically in the context of post-2008 Europe.

In contrast, if any GI-claims are plausible, they cannot consist of showing that a narrative is used ideologically. This is because GI-claims are made without access to information about how the narrative is used (or would be used) in all relevant contexts. However, this is not to say that GI-claims are necessarily made in ignorance of how the narrative happens to be operating in certain contexts. The claim that a narrative is contextually ideological in context C1 might be an important premise in an argument for a GI—in fact, such claims do indeed form premises in the type of argument we will sketch in the next section. However, the argument for this GI-claim might not require awareness of how the narrative operates in C2, C3, C4, and so forth. Rather, it is meant to tell us something about how one might suspect that the narrative operates in other contexts, or would operate if it were to be used there. This points to a distinctive contribution of GI-claims: they can tell us something about the epistemic merits of the use of a narrative in a particular context even before it is used in this context.

A GI-claim can therefore only be a claim that a narrative is ideologically suspicious. There might also be certain circumstances where a CI-claim is only a claim that a narrative is ideologically suspicious. One possible reason for this might be that our information about the functioning of the narrative in this context is incomplete, but nonetheless adequate for generating reasons for suspicion. However, given that CI-claims draw heavily on facts within the relevant context, we would suggest that they will tend to be claims that a narrative is used ideologically. We can summarize this in Table 2.

The second point concerns the relation between the ideological use/ideologically suspicious distinction and the strength of the reason for rejecting the narrative. If X is known to be used ideologically, this provides the strongest reason for rejecting this use of X, since this entails that X has clear epistemic disvalue. In contrast, demonstrating that X is ideologically suspicious provides us with a reason that is not quite as strong, since it allows for the possibility that X is not actually being used ideologically. The fact that we might have good reasons to suspect X of being used ideologically does not necessarily entail that X is, in fact, used ideologically.

Now if GI-claims can never be claims that a narrative is used ideologically, we might think this difference in the strength of the reason for rejecting the narrative undermines the rationale for looking for a way of making plausible GI-claims in the first place. In the previous section, we noted that one of the limitations of CI-claims is that they might not provide a particularly strong reason for rejecting the use of the narrative in contexts other than the one in which it has been found to be used ideologically. But, if GI claims cannot provide a particularly strong reason either, what value do they have?

Our answer is that plausible GI-claims—that is, GI claims demonstrating that a particular narrative is ideologically suspicious—give us a stronger reason for rejecting the narrative across different contexts than any one CI claim. A CI claim gives us a very strong reason for rejecting the use of a narrative in a particular context, but a relatively weak reason for rejecting the use of the same narrative in other contexts. The latter reason would be no more than a weak form of induction: the fact that the narrative was used ideologically in one context gives us a reason to think that, if it is used elsewhere, it will also be used ideologically there. But as we saw in the previous section, this is because it might turn out that the features that cause a narrative to be used ideologically in a particular context do not obtain elsewhere. We can summarize this using Table 3.

The top-right box represents attempts to inductively extend CI-claims to the use of the narrative in other contexts. The reason why we think this provides a weaker reason for rejecting the narrative in those contexts than a GI-claim is this: to the extent that an argument for a GI-claim can be rendered plausible, it is less subject to the contingent factors of particular contexts than an inductive argument stemming from a single CI-claim. The strength of the latter can be diminished by differences between C1 and other contexts, while the strength of the former cannot. Note, however, that this points to one of the challenges in making plausible GI-claims. It must be possible to show why a GI-claim is not vulnerable to differences in context.

At this point, it is worth considering two related objections, each of which is based on the view that the purposes of ideology critique are adequately serviced by making a multitude of CI-claims, without the need for a GI-claim. First, one might argue that if one wants to know about the status of the narrative in another context, one can simply examine that context. For example, if one wants to know about the status of sovereign debt narratives in, say, the aftermath of the 1970s oil crisis, one can simply study that context instead. Second, one might also argue that the strength of the reason in the top right box of Figure 3 can be increased if we can make multiple CI-claims about the use of the narrative, to a point where its strength might eventually exceed that of the GI-claim.

The problem with the first objection is that it renders ideology critique less capable of action guidance. This is because it is confined to the study of past contexts. It does not allow for claims to be made about the status of narratives that might be used again in the future. The second objection, meanwhile, has two problems. First, since there are usually limits to our access to information about different contexts, we cannot always rely on the availability of a multitude of CI-claims in order to strengthen an inductive argument. Second, even if a multitude of CI-claims were available, the GI-claim would still enjoy a distinct advantage over the inductive argument: it can tell us something more specific about the underlying reasons why a narrative has shown a tendency to be used ideologically.

With this in mind, our initial aim of extending Prinz and Rossi's theory of ideology critique beyond particular contexts can be reframed as an attempt to move from a CI-claim that a narrative is used ideologically to a GI-claim that the same narrative is ideologically suspicious. In the next section, we will try to show how this is possible.

Let us start by assuming that we have a plausible CI-claim: that X is used ideologically in C1 in virtue of there being one or more disconnects between the reality and appearance of X in C1. Our aim here is to show how we can move from this claim to a plausible GI-claim: that X is ideologically suspicious across different contexts. Our strategy for doing this comes in two stages. First, we need to identify possible “deideologizing” mechanisms—that is, mechanisms that might be capable of overcoming these disconnects. Second, we need to show that these mechanisms are unlikely to succeed. If each of these two tasks can be accomplished, then we have shown that the possibility of differences in context does not prevent X from being regarded as ideologically suspicious. It would entail that any possible differences in context are not capable of generating effective mechanisms for overcoming these disconnects.

Our aim in this section is to help clarify this idea of a mechanism. We can divide mechanisms into two broad categories. The first category, which we will refer to as safeguards, contains what are generally the most likely candidates for overcoming disconnects. Safeguards are mechanisms for controlling the reality of the narrative in such a way that it does not stray from its appearance. The second, less common category, can be described as narrative reform. It seeks to revise the appearance of the narrative in order to bring it into line with reality. If an effective safeguard could be applied to moralistic narratives about sovereign debt, it would generally prevent these narratives from being invoked hypocritically. If an effective form of narrative reform could be applied to technocratic narratives, it would reconceptualize the claim that a particular policy is conclusively vindicated by expert analysis in such a way that renders it somehow compatible with the absence of any expert consensus.

We will first discuss two general problems when it comes to finding effective mechanisms. Following this, we will say a little more about safeguards and narrative reform respectively, and some of the more specific problems they may face.

Let us now see if we can apply this method to the question of sovereign debt. Prinz and Rossi, we believe, have already supplied us with a credible CI-claim about the use of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt in post-2008 Europe. In order to move from this to a credible GI-claim—that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are ideologically suspicious across contexts, we must carry out two tasks. First, we must identify what seem to be the most plausible candidate mechanisms for overcoming the disconnects between the appearance and reality of these narratives. Second, we must show that these mechanisms fail.

We sought to clarify the potential of the realist approach to ideology critique (Prinz & Rossi, 2017, 2021) beyond contextual claims. We showed how we can bridge the gap between the fact that a narrative is ideological in a particular context and the claim that it is ideological across different contexts by showing that it is resistant to various mechanisms that might otherwise prevent it from functioning ideologically. We did so by focusing on the example of narratives about sovereign debt. We identified and reconstructed several promising mechanisms for countering the suspicion of ideology of moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt. We have shown why none of these mechanisms are likely to be effective, certainly not reliably so. These steps vindicate the GI-claim, namely that moralistic and technocratic narratives about sovereign debt are prima facie ideologically suspicious at a general level.

We have said that our article offers three main contributions: a development of a method that enhances radical realism's capacity to provide action guidance; an application of this action guidance to sovereign debt narratives; and an illustration of how realism is compatible with certain forms of generalization and abstraction. We want to finish here by saying a little more about each of them.

First, political realists have often regarded the provision of action guidance as an essential desideratum for political philosophy, and have criticized moralists for failing to do this (Galston, 2010; Horton, 2017). However, it might be an open question whether realists have so far been any more successful than moralists in meeting this desideratum (Ulaş, 2020). By showing how ideology critique can be used to anticipate future political debates, we hope to have shown how realism, at least in its radical form, can be genuinely action guiding.

Second, our argument contributes to the practical question of how to respond to future debates about sovereign debt. It shows a way for redirecting the constructive energies for dealing with sovereign debt towards political questions, which stand a better chance of leading to reliable orientation than ideologically suspicious technocratic and moralistic narratives. Such future debates are very likely to emerge in the aftermath of the coronavirus disease 2019 pandemic and the current return of high inflation. During the pandemic, many governments, in coordination with their central banks, increased deficit spending and issued the according amount of sovereign debt to levels which exceeded what was previously viewed as acceptable (Tooze, 2021). In some countries, for example, Germany, debt brakes that are gradually becoming a regular feature of national law in the Eurozone, sometimes of constitutional rank, were temporarily suspended. While it might be tempting to suggest that the pandemic has taken us beyond technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt—even the Eurozone was willing to suspend the rules and create at least an indirect buyer of last resort for sovereign debt and collective sovereign bonds—the reemergence of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt is still very likely. The temporary exemptions from these debt brakes have been scheduled to run out, which would likely trigger the need for austerity, with the concomitant technocratic and moralistic narratives (Chappe & Blyth, 2020).

Our argument anticipates the return of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt to provide practical guidance in two ways. First, it provides those faced with such narratives with confidence for viewing them as generally ideologically suspicious. Second, by providing confidence for viewing these narratives as ideologically suspicious, our article contributes to a shift away from these narratives. Such a shift at least holds the possibility of the debates taking a more political turn, which would mean considering sovereign debt as a question structured by contingent power relations.

Third, our model of ideology critique may offer some insights regarding the extent to which political realism allows for abstraction and generalization. One might think that realism's emphasis on contextualism and fidelity to the facts might prevent it from making more generalizable claims that might go beyond a particular context (Lægaard, 2019; for discussion, see Westphal, 2022). However, the model of ideology critique we have outlined in this article does indeed show how realists can make claims that go beyond a particular context without forfeiting fidelity to the facts or contextualism. The kind of generalizable claims we have described here—what we have referred to as GI-claims—are responsive to facts and grounded in contextual interpretation in at least three ways. First, they draw on an accurate account of how a narrative functions in a particular context, as provided by the CI-claim. Second, the arguments about the effectiveness of safeguard and narrative reform mechanisms are also empirically informed. Third, the scope of the ideology critique mirrors the more general scope of the claims at the heart of technocratic and moralistic narratives about sovereign debt, in as far as these narratives claim to be appropriate not just in the context at issue but more generally. Hence, we can see how fidelity to the facts and a commitment to contextual interpretation is compatible with certain modest forms of generalization. And, as we just noted, this generalization helps serve another important realist desideratum: resourcing real-world political thinking and activity.

Finally, it is also important to note what this model of ideology critique does not seek to do. It is not to be expected that it will tell us what the correct policy regarding sovereign debt is, if there is indeed such a thing. At most, it might point us towards one policy option by default if all its alternatives are revealed to depend on ideological narratives. In general, however, the purpose of ideology critique is to resource political decision-making, rather than determine it (Cross, 2022, p. 1119; Kreutz & Rossi, 2022). It can do this by redirecting our attention away from narratives, which present a distorted version of reality.

This is not to say that our attention, once redirected, can be guaranteed to arrive at a more accurate version. It is entirely possible that casting away one ideologically suspicious narrative will result only in another ideologically suspicious narrative taking its place. And even if this does not occur, there is no guarantee that there is an “objective truth” waiting for us to discover once all ideological distortions have been cleared away. But as Rossi (2019, p. 647) points out, this is no reason not to seek for a less distorted picture of reality. The realist contention here is that our best hope for politics necessitates that ideological distortions are exposed for what they are. Ideology critique does not promise us a solution to all our political problems, but it helps remove some of the obstacles that stand in our way.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信