拜物教的市场意识形态概念:解读与辩护

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS
Antoine Louette
{"title":"拜物教的市场意识形态概念:解读与辩护","authors":"Antoine Louette","doi":"10.1111/josp.12497","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>When Charles de Brosses first coined the term ‘fetishism’ in <i>On the Worship of Fetish Gods</i> (1760), it was in a rather misled attempt to demonstrate the immaturity of ‘primitive’ religious cults (de Brosses, <span>1760</span>; see Iacono, <span>1992</span>, 51). Yet a little more than a hundred years later, Marx had turned the concept into one of the most deep-probing tools which social philosophy can bring to the study of capitalism.</p><p>The German philosopher-cum-economist had noticed the way in which his European contemporaries would still sneer at the West African religious habit of treating social objects as ‘independent figures endowed with a life of their own’, and he realized he could turn the joke on them: they themselves did the same with their own ‘immense collection of commodities’ (Capital I, 165 and 125; see also Iacono, <span>1992</span>, 79–80, Heinrich, <span>2012</span>, 179–81 and Graeber, <span>2005</span>).</p><p>The ‘joke’, importantly, was a rather pointed one, and has remained so to this day. Just as Marx hoped to spur his contemporaries out of capitalism, the contemporary literature uses the concept of commodity fetishism to mount a radical critique of the capitalist market. Two main conceptions can be distinguished. According to the first conception, the concept of commodity fetishism alerts us to a form of market ideology that plays a crucial role in the reproduction of market domination (Cohen, <span>2000</span>; Elster, <span>1986</span>). On the second conception, by contrast, commodity fetishism refers to market domination itself, understood as a form of structural domination with a specific profit-maximizing logic (Roberts, <span>2017</span>, Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>, Ripstein, <span>1987</span>).</p><p>In recent years, mainly thanks to the efforts of Roberts (<span>2017</span>), drawing on Arthur Ripstein (<span>1987</span>), the market domination conception seems to have taken precedence. This is unfortunate, I believe. Granted, the market domination conception has the undeniable benefit of emphasizing the profit-maximizing logic that distinguishes market domination from other forms of structural domination. But at a time when the detrimental effects of this logic have become well-known, the concept can provide a better ‘basis for resistance’, as Sally Haslanger would put it (cf. <span>2020</span>, 36), by focusing less on market domination itself than on the exact workings of its ideological reproduction.</p><p>In this paper, therefore, I attempt to go against the grain. As we will see, this requires developing an innovative theoretical framework for understanding ideology—one which not only adapts to the market the influential account which Haslanger and others have offered in relation to racism and sexism (<span>2012</span>, <span>2017c</span>; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>, Einspahr, <span>2010</span>), but which also refines this account by showing how acknowledging the influence which structural domination may have on ideology helps it solve an important problem.</p><p>The proponents of the market domination conception ground their claim that fetishism is not market ideology in two main objections. First, that while fetishism may involve certain representations, these are not ideological since they are not epistemically deficient, at least not by inclusion of falsehoods (Roberts, <span>2017</span>). Second, that anyway we should understand fetishism as concerning activity in the market, not representations of the market, lest we lose sight of its practical significance (Ripstein, <span>1987</span>).</p><p>My first step is to argue that the market ideology view can escape both, provided it departs from the ‘theoretical’ interpretation of the analytic Marxists (Cohen, <span>2000</span>; Elster, <span>1986</span>) and favors instead the more ‘practical’ understanding of ideology that we can find most prominently in Halslanger's work (<span>2017c</span>). On this understanding, ideology refers to cultural schemas which are liable to epistemic deficiency by omission of truths, rather than by inclusion of falsehood, because they are involved in, indeed, crucial to, social activity and its practical failings. The first feature rescues the market ideology conception from the first objection, and the second from the second.</p><p>In my view, however, the real problem with the market ideology conception lies elsewhere: that is, in its apparent inability to explain how market ideology can play its central role, namely contributing to the reproduction of market domination. This is because it is unclear why, unlike other forms of ideology, it should be expected to be widespread enough across social milieux to impair agents' ability to break free from it. Ideology, after all, is never total (Haslanger, <span>2017b</span>; see also Geuss, <span>1981</span>).</p><p>To solve this problem, I draw on the market domination conception of fetishism, and specifically on its analysis of the profit-maximizing logic of market domination (Ripstein, <span>1987</span>, Roberts, <span>2017</span>, Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). I argue that this logic makes market ideology pervasive (see Sewell, <span>1992</span>), which deprives agents of the symbolic-material discrepancies between social milieux that would help them break free from market ideology.</p><p>Thus, on the interpretation I offer, fetishism should be understood as the <i>pervasive</i> ideology of the market, where its pervasiveness is due to what can be called <i>the standardizing influence of market domination across social milieux</i>.</p><p>This new interpretation clarifies one of the central mechanisms—indeed, perhaps the most fundamental mechanism—of the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market. As such, it provides a better basis for resistance to structural domination in the market than the market domination conception of fetishism, the analytic Marxists' interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism, and the influential conception of ideology we owe to Haslanger and others.</p><p>In the first section below, I focus on the market ideology conception, its analytic Marxist interpretation, and the two objections leveled against it by the proponents of the alternative, market domination conception. In Section 2, I build on Haslanger's influential account of ideology to offer a more ‘practical’ interpretation of the market ideology conception that escapes both objections. In Section 3, I turn to what I believe is the central problem with the market ideology conception of fetishism. Finally, in Section 4, I draw on the market domination conception to suggest a way to rescue the market ideology conception from this problem.</p><p>To set the scene, I begin with the relation between class domination, the market, and commodification. Then, I focus on the market ideology conception, its analytic Marxist interpretation, and the two objections.</p><p>Class domination refers to the situation of the worker who, forced to sell her labour power to some member of the capitalist class to make a living, finds herself unable to exit a relationship in which the relevant capitalist can get her to do more or less what she wants her to do for as long as she has bought her ability to work (see, for example, Gourevitch, <span>2018</span>). Importantly, class domination depends on the market, which organizes the systematic transfer of resources from workers to capitalists that impairs the ability of the former not to work for some capitalist or other. As such, the market explains why there can be class domination without any legally or normatively sanctioned class distinctions (see, for example, Young, <span>1990</span>, 47).</p><p>The market is a social practice of commodity production and exchange, that is, a collective solution to a coordination problem: the problem is for private producers to make a living in the absence of some form of central planning, and the solution the commodification process which generates market exchange and competition (Cohen, <span>2000</span>; Roberts, <span>2017</span>, for example, 78n97; Sewell, <span>1992</span>; Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). Those who enact the market participate in commodifying things—from means of production to products to their own ability to produce—by repeatedly reducing them, by means of money and other measuring devices, to units which can be counted, added, compared, and converted into one another. This in turn enables and encourages them to produce and exchange things not as favors or as gifts, but as commodities, viz. in such a way that no one gives more than <i>exactly</i> what she gets (Graeber, <span>2001</span>, 55–56 and <span>2011</span>, 103–05, Sewell, <span>1992</span>, 25–26, and Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 416–23; see Ripstein, <span>1987</span>, 736, Heinrich, <span>2012</span>, chapter 3, and Marx, <i>Capital I</i> [<span>1976</span>], chapter 1).</p><p>Crucially, from the fact that things are commodities, not naturally, but because those who enact the market participate in commodifying them, we should not conclude that it is entirely up to those who enact the market whether to commodify or not: as Marx suggested, the commodification process tends to occur ‘behind their backs’, as an unintended result of their actions (Marx, <span>1976</span>, chapter 1; see Sewell, <span>1992</span>, 22 and 25). How exactly does this work? This, and its consequences for the entrenchment of structural domination in the market, is the focus of the market ideology conception of fetishism.</p><p>Ideology, on a broadly Marxist conception, has three related features: first, it entrenches structural domination, second, it is epistemically deficient, and third, it has a ‘tainted origin’ in structural domination (Geuss, <span>1981</span>, 21; see Shelby, <span>2003</span>, and Celikates, <span>2016</span>). Indeed, ideology is often said to entrench structural domination <i>because</i> it is epistemically deficient, and to be epistemically deficient <i>because</i> agents learn it from dominating practices (see, for example, Haslanger, <span>2017a</span>, Einspahr, <span>2010</span>, Celikates, <span>2016</span>). In line with this account, the market ideology conception of fetishism defines fetishism as an epistemically deficient view of the market, which agents infer from the way things appear to them, and which leads them to reproduce the market and entrench class domination (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 115, Geras, <span>1971</span>, 78–79, Celikates, <span>2016</span>, 14; see also Haslanger, for example, <span>2017c</span>).<sup>1</sup></p><p>The view in question is epistemically deficient insofar as it does not alert agents to the fact that the things they exchange with their employers and clients are commodities because they themselves participate in commodifying them (see Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 116, Elster, <span>1986</span>, 57; cf. Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 165 and 112–20). This epistemically deficient view, however, is not like a ‘hallucination’ attributable entirely to a failure of perspicacity on the part of agents, but is rather ‘like a mirage’, insofar as the external world itself is misleading (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 115; see also Elster, <span>1986</span>, 56 and 177, Geras, <span>1971</span>, 78–9). In particular, the ‘foundation’ of exchange-value ‘in labouring activity is not [visible]’ (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 116). This epistemically deficient view, finally, explains why commodification occurs ‘behind the backs’ of agents, as an unintended results of their actions, and so why they fail to change the market for the better and entrench class domination as a result: agents will not even think of organizing production and exchange differently if they fail to realize that things are commodities because they themselves participate in commodifying them. Thus, as Cohen puts it, ‘[f]etishism protects capitalism’ (<span>2000</span>, 129).</p><p>This is the core of the market ideology conception of fetishism, and as such it is common to the two main interpretations of this conception: the dominant, analytic Marxists's interpretation put forward most famously by Gerald Cohen (<span>2000</span>) and Jon Elster (<span>1986</span>), and the socialization-based account which I will adapt from feminist and antiracist political theory in the next section (Haslanger, <span>2012</span>, <span>2017c</span>; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>, Einspahr, <span>2010</span>). The difference between the two interpretations lies in the exact way in which the ideological view in question is epistemically deficient.</p><p>According to the analytic Marxists, this view is not epistemically deficient merely by omission of part of what commodities are, viz. their being commodities because agents participate in commodifying them, as it will be on my alternative interpretation. Rather, it is epistemically deficient by inclusion of something which commodities are not, viz. their being commodities ‘as an inherent property’, as a matter of ‘substance’, or, more generally, ‘naturally and inevitably’ (Elster, <span>1986</span>, 57 and Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 116 and 127, respectively). Thus on the analytic Marxist view, and in Cohen's words, there are ‘two phases in commodity fetishism: (1) separation of exchange-value from its material basis; (2) attachment of exchange-value to the substance of the commodity’ (<span>2000</span>, 117; cf. 116). On my alternative interpretation, by contrast, only the first phase obtains.</p><p>Insofar as including such ontological precisions as an account of the substance of commodities is the mark of a theoretical attitude, one on which agents flesh out their view of things beyond what is ‘practically necessary’ (Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 48), we may say that for the analytic Marxists, the ideological view in question is a theoretical view. 2 On such a view, commodities are endowed with a natural dimension, where this means not only that their social dimension is stripped out from the way they appear, as it is on my alternative interpretation, but also that their appearance is more elaborate than it is on my alternative interpretation: to those who hold this view, commodities appear not just as things whose exact value must be paid if they are to change hands, but also as things which possess value by virtue of their physical properties, ‘just as they have weight’ (Elster, <span>1986</span>, 57).<sup>3</sup></p><p>This interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism has recently come under sustained pressure from the proponents of the market domination view of fetishism. William Roberts (<span>2017</span>), in particular, has built on Arthur Ripstein (<span>1987</span>) to argue that ‘[f]etishism ought to be understood as a form of domination rather than a form of false consciousness’ (<span>2017</span>, 85). I will describe the form of domination they have in mind in Section 4. Here, I focus on their central objections.</p><p>The first is Roberts's. As we saw above, to define fetishism as market ideology involves claiming that the view which agents infer from the way the things they exchange appear to them is epistemically deficient. But this view is not epistemically deficient, Roberts argues, since things appear as what they are to those who hold this view. As he puts it, the market ideology conception of fetishism ‘trips over Marx's explicit claim that, in fetishism, “the social relations between [the producers’] private labours appear <i>as what they are</i>”. Where social relations are mediated by commodities, exchanges <i>are</i> the real relations between the producers of commodities' (Roberts, <span>2017</span>, 86–87, quoting Marx, <i>Capital</i> 1, <span>1976</span>, 166, to which he adds the emphasis).</p><p>For those of us less interested in exegesis than Roberts, the fact that this was ‘Marx's explicit claim’ may not carry additional weight. Yet Roberts is also interested in theorizing fetishism further, and he makes it clear that he considers Marx to be right on this point: fetishism concerns social reality as it is constructed by ‘the social practice of exchange’ (<span>2017</span>, 88n133). I agree, as suggested above. In fact, this point is widely accepted in the literature on fetishism. The analytic Marxists themselves concur, insisting, as we saw above, that fetishism is ‘like a mirage’, insofar as the external world itself is misleading (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 115; see also Elster, <span>1986</span>, 56 and 177, Geras, <span>1971</span>, 78–9).</p><p>This, however, makes the analytic Marxists's interpretation vulnerable to Roberts's objection. On their ‘theoretical’ reading, recall, the ideological view at the heart of fetishism fails to alert agents to part of what commodities are (viz. their social aspect) not just by omission of it, but by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz. their purported natural aspect). To those who hold this view, therefore, commodities do <i>not</i> appear as what they are: they appear to be naturally commodities while, really, they are commodities by social construction. Thus the analytic Marxists' theoretical reading of the market ideology conception is vulnerable to the first objection.</p><p>The same goes for the second objection, viz. that the ideological view at issue is irrelevant since fetishism is best understood as concerning social activity rather than theoretical understanding. This objection is raised by Ripstein, who insists, against Cohen and the classical proponents of the market ideology conception, that fetishism ‘is the failing associated with practical involvement in the world’, not with ‘the virtue of knowledge’, because activity and understanding are distinct modes of engagement with the world, and fetishism is about activity, not understanding (Ripstein, <span>1987</span>, 743).</p><p>Like Roberts above, not only does Ripstein take this to be Marx's claim, but he also insists that Marx was right. For to focus primarily on theoretical understanding rather than social activity, he suggests, is to risk concentrating on ‘how knowledgeable or error prone’ people are in the market, to the detriment of the fact that ‘[t]o have one's activities entirely shaped by [the market] is to be enslaved […]’ (<span>1987</span>, 743 and 747).</p><p>I agree that Ripstein's—and Marx's—primarily practical orientation is crucial. The concept of fetishism should help us focus on structural domination in the market, be it to draw our attention to the phenomenon itself, as Ripstein believes, or to alert us to the exact workings of its ideological reproduction, as I think would be more useful at this stage. I also agree that the risk of losing sight of this practical predicament is real on a ‘theoretical’ interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism. The analytic Marxists testify to this. Elster, for instance, concludes that ‘[fetishism] is a cognitive illusion arising from market transactions, <i>not a morally deplorable feature of markets</i>’ (<span>1986</span>, 58, my emphasis). Likewise, Cohen, mired in theoretical debates about the labour theory of value, offers only an ‘<i>explanation without defence</i> of Marx's views [on fetishism]’ (<span>2000</span>, xii, his emphasis). For fear of losing sight of social activity and its current predicament, therefore, we should not take fetishism to concern theoretical understanding. This is to say that the analytic Marxists' conception of fetishism falls prey to the second objection, as it did to the first.</p><p>I conclude, with Roberts and Ripstein, that fetishism should not be conceived as the ideology of the market if ideology is understood as the analytic Marxists understand it, that is, theoretically. Things are different if ideology is understood practically, as I argue in the next section.</p><p>The ‘practical’ understanding of ideology has recently become influential in feminist and antiracist studies, largely thanks to the efforts of Sally Haslanger (e.g. <span>2017c</span>). In this section, I adapt it to the market, in order to offer an interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism which escapes the two objections encountered in the previous section.</p><p>We saw above that, according to the analytic Marxists, the ideological view at the heart of fetishism is epistemically deficient not merely by omission of part of what commodities are (viz., their social aspect), but also by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz., their purported natural aspect), which I suggested was the mark of a theoretical mode of engagement with the world.</p><p>By contrast, on the conception of ideology put forward by Haslanger and others, ideology is much more ‘practical’. Developed as part of a critico-theoretical, socio-constructivist account of gender and race (see, for example, Haslanger, <span>2012</span>), this conception offers an account of ideology as the schemas of dominating practices insofar as agents are socialized into them, where socialization is understood as the process through which agents learn from the milieux they frequent the schemas of the practices enacted in these milieux (Haslanger, <span>2017b</span>; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>).</p><p>While Haslanger does not apply this account to specifically capitalist and classist issues, it can be fruitfully put to the service of the market ideology conception of fetishism. Seen in this light, commodity fetishism can be understood as a schema of the market insofar as agents are socialized into it. According to the broadly Bourdieusian account of socialization Haslanger relies on, this suggests that to fetishise the market is to keep applying the commodity schema to things, because in this milieu things ‘actualise’ or ‘incorporate’ this schema, and so ‘teach’ or ‘inculcate’ it in turn (Sewell, <span>1992</span>, 12–13, quoted in Haslanger, <span>2017c</span>, 22; see also Einspahr, <span>2010</span>, and Bourdieu, <span>1977</span>).<sup>4</sup></p><p>Importantly, socialization is, on this account, oriented to helping agents enact social practices, understood as ‘collective solutions to coordination or access problems’ (Haslanger, <span>2016</span>, 126). This means that the schemas of these practices, being geared primarily to helping agents solve collective problems, often focus on those aspects of things which are useful in this respect, to the detriment of other, less immediately relevant aspects (cf. Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 45–47). Given this, the commodity schema can be understood as the schema that things are commodities <i>full stop</i>, not that they are commodities <i>naturally</i> (<i>or not</i>), this latter aspect falling outside the immediate concern of agents aiming to make a living.<sup>5</sup></p><p>In other words, on the interpretation we can build from Haslanger's account of ideology, the commodity schema is epistemically mistaken not by inclusion of something which commodities are not, as it is for the analytic Marxists, but instead by omission of part of what commodities are. As Haslanger would put it, it only ‘leave[s] out’ the fact that commodities are such because we participate in commodifying them, and this is how it ‘obscure[s] [their] social dimension’ (Haslanger, <span>2012</span>, 18 and 467; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>). In other words, it does not give them a more elaborate appearance by representing their (mistaken) ontological status, as it does on the analytic Marxists' interpretation: here, commodities only appear as things whose exact value must be paid if they are to change hands, not as things which, in addition, have their value in this way or that.</p><p>This point is crucial, because it enables this alternative interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism to escape the two objections from the previous section.</p><p>The first objection, recall, was that the commodity schema is not epistemically deficient, since things appear as what they are to those who hold it (Roberts, <span>2017</span>). As noted above, I agree with Roberts—and Marx—that fetishism is about the social construction of reality by the market: as we may now say with Haslanger, things on the market ‘actualise’ or ‘incorporate’ the commodity schema, and to this extent appear as what they are to those who hold this schema.</p><p>But from this, crucially, we should not conclude that the commodity schema cannot be epistemically deficient <i>as well</i>, and, therefore, ideological <i>as well</i>. From the fact that commodities do appear as what they are to those who hold the commodity schema, it does not follow that they appear as <i>everything</i> that they are. It may well be the case that everything that commodities appear to be (viz., commodities) is true of them, but that the schema still leaves out some crucial fact about them (viz., their social dimension).</p><p>In other words, Roberts's objection applies to the analytic-Marxist view, as we saw above, but not to the alternative interpretation I just offered. To agents whose ‘theoretical’ view of commodities fails to alert them to part of what commodities are (viz. their social dimension) <i>by inclusion</i> of something which commodities are not (viz. their alleged natural dimension), commodities do <i>not</i> appear as what they are. But to agents whose ‘practical’ schema of commodities is epistemically mistaken only <i>by omission</i> of part of what commodities are (viz. their social dimension), commodities <i>do</i> appear as what they are (viz. as commodities), if not as everything that they are. Therefore, the alternative interpretation, unlike the analytic Marxist view, escapes the first objection.</p><p>The same goes for Roberts's objection, viz. that the commodity schema is irrelevant since fetishism should concern market activity rather than theoretical understanding, on pain of neglecting the structurally dominated character of this activity. As I wrote above, I agree with Ripstein that a focus on structural domination in the market is crucial. But I also hold that, unlike the analytic Marxists' interpretation, my alternative interpretation can focus on understanding without running the risk of losing sight of this practical failing.</p><p>Indeed, from the fact that fetishism should not concern theoretical understanding, it does not follow that fetishism cannot be about understanding <i>at all</i>. For even if fetishism is not about the kind of theoretical understanding the analytic Marxists focus on, it can be about the kind of practical understanding on which the alternative interpretation insists. Ripstein's distinction between activity and understanding is too stark: it misses the fact that activity involves understanding in the form of the schemas (e.g., the commodity schema) which enable agents to enact their various social practices (e.g., the market).</p><p>Put differently, from the fact that ‘all social life is essentially <i>practical</i>’ (Marx, <i>Eighth Thesis on Feuerbach</i>, quoted in Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 45, original emphasis), we should not conclude with Ripstein that fetishism ‘is the failing associated with practical involvement in the world’ rather than with any kind of understanding (1987, 743). Instead, we should conclude with Torrance that ‘what people observe and how they experience and describe their surroundings depends on their purposes and the problems they face’ (Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 45)—that is, more precisely, on the schemas which help them enact the social practices in which they participate and which, geared as they are to helping them solve collective problems, may fail to alert them to more than they strictly need to understand in order to do so (cf. Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 47).<sup>6</sup> The commodity schema is a case in point: as we saw above, it leaves out the social dimension of commodities, this otherwise crucial fact being of little immediate interest to agents focused on making a living. Thus, while it would indeed be a mistake to take fetishism to concern the kind of theoretical understanding which the analytic Marxists have in mind, the concept can be about the kind of practical understanding involved in social activity on which the alternative interpretation operates. Therefore, this interpretation escapes the second objection, as it escaped the first.</p><p>I conclude, <i>contra</i> Roberts and Ripstein, that fetishism can be understood as the ideology of the market, provided that ideology is understood practically rather than theoretically. The main problem with the market ideology conception of fetishism lies elsewhere, as I argue now.</p><p>The problem is the following: the market ideology conception of fetishism seems unable to explain how the commodity schema can play the central role which it is meant to play, viz. contributing to the reproduction of market domination. This is because it is unclear why it should be expected to be widespread enough across social milieux to impair agents' ability to break free from it, when, in general, ideologies should not be expected to be so widespread.</p><p>On the practical interpretation I offered above, it is agents' socialization into ideology, understood as the process through which they learn ideology from the social milieux in which it is embodied, that explains ideology's domination-reproducing effect. But as is widely recognized, including by Haslanger herself (2017b; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span> and Geuss, <span>1981</span>), ideology is never total. In the case at hand, things should be expected to embody and teach the commodity schema with employers and clients, but the gift schema with friends or family, and the favor schema with neighbors. Given this fragmentation, it is unclear how agents can fail to correct their schema of commodities by learning that things are commodities at work because they are treated as such in this milieu but not in others—and, therefore, how they can find themselves in the grip of anything like an ideology of the market that has them participate in commodification ‘behind their back’ and so contribute to the reproduction of market domination.<sup>7</sup></p><p>To make this argument in more detail, the first thing to emphasize is that agents are socialized into a multiplicity of social practices, some of which are not capitalist. As Haslanger insists, ‘[t]here are multiple reasons to avoid the idea that ideology [e.g., capitalist schemas] functions as a total system governing society as a whole’ (2017b, 161). Indeed, Robin Celikates emphasizes, we should bear in mind Raymond Geuss's famous claim that ‘a society of happy slaves, content with their chains […] is a nightmare, not a realistic view of a state of society which is at present possible’ (<span>1981</span>, 83–84, quoted in Celikates, <span>2016</span>). In other words, we should expect ideological schemas to be actualised in things in some of the milieux which agents navigate, <i>but not in others</i>.</p><p>Yet if so, crucially, we should also expect agents to learn that things actualise a schema because they themselves incorporate it in things in some milieux but not in others. Agents are ‘knowledgeable’, after all (Giddens, <span>1979</span>, 5; see also Celikates, <span>2006</span>, Boltanski &amp; Thévenot, <span>2006</span>), and should be expected to realize that if things actualise different schemas in different milieux, it is largely because they themselves apply different schemas to them. Indeed, it is ‘a leading theorem’ of Anthony Giddens that ‘every social actor knows a great deal about the conditions of reproduction of the society of which he or she is a member’ (<span>1979</span>, 5, emphasis removed; see also Scott, <span>1985</span>, 319).</p><p>This is particularly clear with the commodity schema. If socialization is fragmented in this way, we should expect the commodity schema to be incorporated in things when people exchange them with their employers or clients, but not when they exchange them with their neighbors, friends, or family. As Graeber (<span>2011</span>) and Cohen (<span>2009</span>) insist, commodity exchange is very different from the kind of exchange that in principle occurs between neighbors, friends, or family. The schema of commodity exchange is not just ‘give as good as you get’, as in neighborly exchange, but rather ‘give <i>exactly</i> as good as you get’, the price being the expression of this mathematical equivalence made possible by the reduction of things to countable units (Graeber, <span>2011</span>, chapter 5). The discrepancy is even more striking with close friends and family. There, the schema is the ‘baseline communist’ one, ‘to each according to their needs and from each according to their means’ (Graeber, ibid.; cf. Cohen, <span>2009</span>, 39–45). Thus, in principle, the things which agents exchange with neighbors, friends, or family do not actualise the commodity schema, but the favor schema or the gift schema (as the case may be). When plumbers fix the bathrooms of their relatives for free, for example, their ability to work does not incorporate the commodity schema. It is not standardized but personalized, and the plumbers' relatives are not presented with a bill.<sup>8</sup></p><p>Yet, crucially, if, as I just argued, the things which agents exchange with their neighbors, friends, and family do <i>not</i> incorporate the commodity schema in the way that the things which they exchange with their employers and clients do, then it is unclear how the commodity schema can leave out the fact that these things are commodities largely because people participate in commodifying them. People, again, are not ‘judgmental dopes’, in Garfinkel's famous phrase (<span>1984</span>, 75; see also Celikates, <span>2006</span>, 30 and Roberts, <span>2017</span>, 95), and if things incorporate different schemas in different milieux, the discrepancies between things or milieux should help them realize that they themselves participate in the incorporating. When a plumber fixes her neighbor's kitchen sink because he previously babysat her children and she owes him one, or repairs her parents' bathroom for free, she can hardly fail to infer that <i>if her ability to work is a commodity at work, it is partly because she participates in commodifying it by selling it to her employer or clients for an hourly wage</i>.<sup>9</sup> In other words, we should expect her commodity schema to include the fact that her ability to work is a commodity at work in part because of herself and her employer, just like we should expect her gift schema and her favor schema to include, respectively, the facts that her ability to work is a gift in family milieux partly because it has been made so by herself and her parents, or that its being exchanged as a favor in neighborly spheres is due, to a significant extent, to her and her neighbors' making it so. To expect any less of them would fail to do justice to what we can call, with Giddens, their ‘penetration’ (<span>1979</span>, 71–72).</p><p>If socialization works in this fragmented way, then, we should expect things to actualise the commodity schema with employers and clients, but the gift schema with family and friends and the favor schema with neighbors. But this suggests in turn that we should not expect agents' commodity schema to limit itself to the fact that at work things are commodities, omitting the further fact that, if they are so, it is largely because agents themselves participate in commodifying them in this milieu. If so, however, then it is unclear how the commodity schema can explain how commodification may ‘work “behind the backs” of the social actors who produce and reproduce [it]’, as Giddens would put it (<span>1979</span>, 71), and thus prevent them from changing the market for the better and from entrenching class domination as a result.<sup>10</sup></p><p>Put differently, the market ideology conception of fetishism fails to adequately explain the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market.</p><p>To rescue the market ideology conception, I draw on the market domination conception: specifically, on its analysis of the profit-maximizing logic of market domination (Ripstein 1986, Roberts, <span>2017</span>, Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). I argue that this logic makes market ideology pervasive (see Sewell, <span>1992</span>), which deprives agents of the epistemic discrepancies between milieux that would help them break free from it and, therefore, explains why commodification may occur ‘behind their backs’. On this modified interpretation, fetishism should be understood as the <i>pervasive</i> ideology of the market, where its pervasiveness is due to what can be called <i>the standardizing effect of market domination across social milieux</i>.</p><p>As we saw above, the ideology conception of fetishism has recently come under pressure from Roberts (<span>2017</span>), building on previous work from Ripstein (<span>1987</span>). I have already pushed back against their objections above. Now I want to focus on what I take to be the central insight of the market domination conception of fetishism they offer. This is not meant to constitute an endorsement of their view, however, but merely an acknowledgement that the phenomenon they focus on is of the greatest importance in the analysis of fetishism, if not what fetishism is.</p><p>On the market domination conception, fetishism is a form of domination that is distinct from, even as it influences, class domination: it is the impersonal domination suffered by both workers and capitalists because of market competition (see Roberts, <span>2017</span>, 88 and Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>, 379). As Roberts insists, ‘the dominant class in modernity, the class of capitalists, is as subject to impersonal domination as are the laboring classes’ (<span>2017</span>, 102). Vrousalis agrees: Roberts, he writes, is right that ‘capitalist [or impersonal] domination is not equivalent to class domination’ (<span>2017</span>, 379). Ripstein concurs: according to him, the central feature of this domination is that ‘the options of all are limited by the market’, not merely those of workers relative to capitalists (<span>1987</span>, 747).</p><p>The complete definition of this impersonal domination is the object of some debate between Roberts and Vrousalis, who disagree as to who is to be held responsible for it, and whether it is arbitrary in some sense (see Roberts, <span>2017</span>; Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). But let me bypass these disagreements to focus on what both Roberts and Vrousalis agree on, and Ripstein as well. This is that both workers and capitalists are dominated into maximizing profit. As Vrousalis insists, market competition affects radically the power of the capitalist class over the working class. Without competition, each capitalist can act as an ‘absolute monarch’ over their workers, unconstrained in the wage they offer and in what they ask them to do. But as soon as they face (perfect-enough) competition, they can no longer determine wages arbitrarily, or have workers do whatever takes their fancy: at this point ‘[each] is constrained, on pain of competitive disadvantage, to maximise profit, which in turn requires paying [workers] a market-clearing wage’ and exploiting them (<span>2017</span>, 380–81). Roberts concurs, writing for instance that ‘[t]he capitalist, dominated by market imperatives, is compelled thereby to exploit labor’, which by definition entails making a profit (<span>2017</span>, 102). Ripstein agrees as well, emphasizing both that the worker ‘must make himself marketable and once sold, direct his activity to whatever his employer demands’, and that ‘[t]he employer's options are broader but still limited: On pain of bankruptcy, this demand can only take a single form: produce what is profitable’ (<span>1987</span>, 748).</p><p>In other words, all the proponents of the domination conception of fetishism agree that in an important respect the domination at issue is ‘non-arbitrary’ in the sense of ‘regulated’—indeed, regulated by one key rule: ‘maximize profit’ (Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>, 381).<sup>11</sup> If Roberts downplays this aspect, it is only to emphasize that this domination is in another sense arbitrary, viz. whimsical. For the two aspects seem to clash, and it is on this apparent clash that Vrousalis insists when he characterizes this domination as ‘non-arbitrary’. But the clash is only apparent, as it is quite compatible for the domination that on each view constitutes fetishism to be both arbitrary and non-arbitrary in these senses. The market may have movements that are quite difficult to anticipate and, at the same time, still channel capitalists (and workers in their wake) in one definite direction: that of making profit. As Sewell emphasizes, what characterizes capitalism is precisely both a ‘chronic instability or unpredictability’ and ‘a continuous dynamic of capital accumulation […]’ (<span>1992</span>, 25–26).<sup>12</sup></p><p>Now, Vrousalis also insists, against Roberts, that the agents of this domination are not ‘markets or market imperatives’, but ‘[c]apitalists who dominate each other by jointly constituting the ‘external coercive necessities confronting the individual capitalist’ (<span>2017</span>, 3, quoting Marx, <span>1976</span>, 381). Here, I do not engage in this debate, however, for it would take us too far afield. Instead, I focus on the profit-maximizing logic that they all agree on. For it offers a solution to the problem identified in the previous section.</p><p>The reasoning is this: if capitalists and workers are dominated into maximizing profit, then they are dominated into incorporating the commodity schema beyond the workplace, in as many milieux as competition requires. This in turns deprives them of the discrepancies between milieux that could help them realize that they themselves are incorporating the commodity schema in things, which explains how this schema can fail to include this fact.</p><p>As Sewell emphasizes, ‘the commodification of things’ is at the core of the ‘continuous dynamic of capital accumulation’ and profit maximization we saw him mention earlier (<span>1992</span>, 25). Capitalists, on pain of competitive disadvantage, have a strong incentive to ensure that as many things are commodified as possible, and so, therefore, do their workers. Only commodities are ‘opportunities for profit’ after all, and competition requires capitalists to maximize profit. This is why, in Sewell's words again, ‘the commodification of things’ is now ‘pervasive’, that is, ‘present in a relatively wide range of institutional spheres, practices, and discourses’ (ibid., 25 and 22): the ‘chain of commodity exchange’ is ‘vast’, as ‘the commodity form […] organizes a virtually universal intersection of resources’ (ibid., 26). In this respect, it is no surprise that Marx's first description of capitalism in <i>Capital</i> is as ‘an immense collection of commodities’ (<span>1976</span>, chapter 1). The domination identified above turns commodity exchange into a practice that is pervasive in a way few practices are.<sup>13</sup></p><p>Now, Sewell seems to take such pervasiveness to result from the fact that the commodity schema is ‘exceptionally transposable’ (<span>1992</span>, 25), rather than from the profit-maximizing logic of the domination which Ripstein, Roberts, and Vrousalis insist on. Sewell nowhere mentions domination, but instead insists that the commodity schema itself ‘knows no natural limits’ as ‘it can be applied not only to cloth, tobacco, or cooking pans, but to land, housework, bread, sex, advertising, emotions, or knowledge […]’ (ibid., 25–26). But this seems to me mistaken. Exceptional <i>transposability</i> is not exceptional <i>transposition</i>, and a motivating force—‘a force that requires it’, as MacKinnon puts it (<span>1982</span>, 540)—is crucial for the <i>actual</i> rather than merely <i>virtual</i> pervasiveness of the chain of commodity exchange. This motivating force is the domination with a profit-maximizing logic that affects both capitalists and their workers in the market.</p><p>Thus, while capitalists and workers might try to keep the things they exchange with their family largely uncommodified, they will often expand the commodity schema to the things they exchange with friends and neighbors. The magazine <i>Plumbing Connection</i> provides a telling example of this phenomenon in an article entitled ‘The Deal with Mates Rates’, by Brad Fallon (<span>2014</span>). Fallon begins by noting that ‘people with trade skills are always faced with the old ‘mates rates' dilemma’. He frames the dilemma as follows: ‘with a client […] I just roll off the invoice – job well done’; ‘however, add a stressed friend, relative or neighbour into the scenario – someone who I see all the time, whether in my street, at school, or socially – and suddenly, I have this overwhelming need to become the not-for-profit, happy to spend my weekend plumbing “for free” emergency plumber’. And so he goes on to offer ‘some of [his] most helpful tips for ensuring that [people with trade skills] are adequately paid for the work [they] do’. The tips can be grouped in two categories: making excuses, and commodifying, the only exception being the family (‘Obviously […], if it is your Mother-In-Law knocking on the door, throw all the rules out and do the job straight away for free’). One good tip, in particular, consists in ‘booking the job in during standard work hours with one of [your] staff members'. As Fallon emphasizes, this ‘change[s] the dynamic of the relationship back from a personal favour to a professional plumbing service’. Other tips go in the same direction.<sup>14</sup> As this example illustrates, capitalists and their staff members are dominated into extending the commodity schema beyond the workplace to as many milieux as competition requires – even with their friends, if not with their mother-in-law.<sup>15</sup></p><p>But this standardizing influence of structural domination on socialization, crucially, offers a solution to the problem affecting the market ideology conception of fetishism. The problem, recall, was that if things incorporate different schemas in different milieux, which they should do if socialization works in the fragmented way it is widely recognized to work in, then the discrepancies between these milieux should prompt agents to realize that they themselves participate in the incorporating, and to include this fact in their commodity schema. If our plumber fixes her neighbor's kitchen sink because the neighbor previously babysat her children and she owes him one, or her parents' bathroom for free, we should expect her schema of her ability to work in the workplace to tell her that it is partly commodified by herself and her employer. Brad Fallon is a case in point: he complains that ‘because I like to “help” my friends’, […] it feels wrong to charge them’ (<span>2014</span>). But the standardizing influence of structural domination offers a solution to this problem. For if the plumber, or any other market agent, is dominated in such a way that, with her neighbors or friends, she does not exchange her ability to work as a favor or as a gift but as a commodity, in just the same way as she does with her employer and customers, then the move from one milieu to the next will be so natural that it will blunt her critical consciousness: specifically, she will not realize that she herself is playing an important part in actualising the commodity schema in her ability to work, and her version of the schema will not include this fact. Fallon's version of the schema, because he has reflected on it, may be sufficiently critical, but he is an exception. Indeed, he insists, ‘most friends, neighbours and relatives […] don't actually want a discount or preferential treatment’. In fact, usually they do not even ask him ‘to discount [his] prices' (ibid.). Unlike him, they may well fetishise commodities.</p><p>More generally, I want to suggest the following explanation of the mirage at the heart of fetishism. If the commodity schema is incorporated not just in the things agents exchange with their employers and customers, but also in the things they exchange with their ‘friends, relatives or neighbours’, as Fallon puts it, then the schema they infer from the commodities they exchange with their employers and customers will leave out the fact that they themselves are partly responsible for the commodification of commodities. For when a schema is pervasive in this way, there are no hitches between the spheres of activity agents navigate, and they stop noticing that they are applying it themselves: as Sewell puts it, schemas that are incorporated in a relatively wide range of milieux tend to become ‘relatively unconscious, in the sense that they are taken-for-granted mental assumptions or modes of procedures that actors normally apply without being aware that they are applying them’ (<span>1992</span>, 22; see also 24 ff.). Agents in such a standardized environment are deprived of the prompts that could have helped them realize that they are following the standard, and end up doing so without thinking (cf. Graeber, <span>2005</span>, 431).<sup>16</sup> One might say that the commodity schema, in particular, is reflected back to them by so many things that they become ‘naturals’ relative to it, applying it ‘naturally’ to the things that reflect it, aware only that they are exchanging them as commodities, not that they are contributing to commodifying them as they do. Their critical consciousness is blunted, and this is why the commodification process occurs ‘behind their backs’, as an unintended result of their actions.</p><p>The commodity schema does not alert capitalists and workers to the fact that it is because they participate in commodifying them that the things they exchange are commodities, and it does not alert them to this fact because they participate in the incorporation of this schema in things without thinking. They do this, in turn, because they are dominated into incorporating this schema in things, not just in the workplace, but pervasively, for instance in friendly reunions and neighborly encounters, if not in family settings. In other words, the impersonal domination at issue deprives them of the standpoints from which to realize that they are participating in the construction of social reality in such a way that they entrench, in a vicious circle, their own domination (see Lahire, <span>2001</span>; MacKinnon, <span>1982</span>).<sup>17</sup></p><p>Thus fetishism, or the ideology of the market understood in terms of socialization into the market, entrenches structural domination because structural domination, in the form of the impersonal domination Vrousalis, Roberts and Ripstein emphasize and of the class domination it affects, has a standardizing influence on agents' socialization.</p><p>Put differently, if the ideology of the market is understood to be both practical (against the theoretical interpretation of the market ideology conception) and rendered pervasive across social milieux by what I have called the standardizing influence of market domination (against the current interpretation of the practical conception of ideology), then the market ideology conception of fetishism can shed some new light on one of the key mechanisms of the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market. This, I conclude, would provide us with a better ‘basis of resistance’, in Haslanger's phrase (<span>2020</span>, 36), than the market domination conception of fetishism, the analytic Marxist interpretation of the market ideology conception, and the influential account of ideology developed by Haslanger herself.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"54 4","pages":"548-564"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2022-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12497","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The market ideology conception of fetishism: An interpretation and defense\",\"authors\":\"Antoine Louette\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/josp.12497\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>When Charles de Brosses first coined the term ‘fetishism’ in <i>On the Worship of Fetish Gods</i> (1760), it was in a rather misled attempt to demonstrate the immaturity of ‘primitive’ religious cults (de Brosses, <span>1760</span>; see Iacono, <span>1992</span>, 51). Yet a little more than a hundred years later, Marx had turned the concept into one of the most deep-probing tools which social philosophy can bring to the study of capitalism.</p><p>The German philosopher-cum-economist had noticed the way in which his European contemporaries would still sneer at the West African religious habit of treating social objects as ‘independent figures endowed with a life of their own’, and he realized he could turn the joke on them: they themselves did the same with their own ‘immense collection of commodities’ (Capital I, 165 and 125; see also Iacono, <span>1992</span>, 79–80, Heinrich, <span>2012</span>, 179–81 and Graeber, <span>2005</span>).</p><p>The ‘joke’, importantly, was a rather pointed one, and has remained so to this day. Just as Marx hoped to spur his contemporaries out of capitalism, the contemporary literature uses the concept of commodity fetishism to mount a radical critique of the capitalist market. Two main conceptions can be distinguished. According to the first conception, the concept of commodity fetishism alerts us to a form of market ideology that plays a crucial role in the reproduction of market domination (Cohen, <span>2000</span>; Elster, <span>1986</span>). On the second conception, by contrast, commodity fetishism refers to market domination itself, understood as a form of structural domination with a specific profit-maximizing logic (Roberts, <span>2017</span>, Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>, Ripstein, <span>1987</span>).</p><p>In recent years, mainly thanks to the efforts of Roberts (<span>2017</span>), drawing on Arthur Ripstein (<span>1987</span>), the market domination conception seems to have taken precedence. This is unfortunate, I believe. Granted, the market domination conception has the undeniable benefit of emphasizing the profit-maximizing logic that distinguishes market domination from other forms of structural domination. But at a time when the detrimental effects of this logic have become well-known, the concept can provide a better ‘basis for resistance’, as Sally Haslanger would put it (cf. <span>2020</span>, 36), by focusing less on market domination itself than on the exact workings of its ideological reproduction.</p><p>In this paper, therefore, I attempt to go against the grain. As we will see, this requires developing an innovative theoretical framework for understanding ideology—one which not only adapts to the market the influential account which Haslanger and others have offered in relation to racism and sexism (<span>2012</span>, <span>2017c</span>; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>, Einspahr, <span>2010</span>), but which also refines this account by showing how acknowledging the influence which structural domination may have on ideology helps it solve an important problem.</p><p>The proponents of the market domination conception ground their claim that fetishism is not market ideology in two main objections. First, that while fetishism may involve certain representations, these are not ideological since they are not epistemically deficient, at least not by inclusion of falsehoods (Roberts, <span>2017</span>). Second, that anyway we should understand fetishism as concerning activity in the market, not representations of the market, lest we lose sight of its practical significance (Ripstein, <span>1987</span>).</p><p>My first step is to argue that the market ideology view can escape both, provided it departs from the ‘theoretical’ interpretation of the analytic Marxists (Cohen, <span>2000</span>; Elster, <span>1986</span>) and favors instead the more ‘practical’ understanding of ideology that we can find most prominently in Halslanger's work (<span>2017c</span>). On this understanding, ideology refers to cultural schemas which are liable to epistemic deficiency by omission of truths, rather than by inclusion of falsehood, because they are involved in, indeed, crucial to, social activity and its practical failings. The first feature rescues the market ideology conception from the first objection, and the second from the second.</p><p>In my view, however, the real problem with the market ideology conception lies elsewhere: that is, in its apparent inability to explain how market ideology can play its central role, namely contributing to the reproduction of market domination. This is because it is unclear why, unlike other forms of ideology, it should be expected to be widespread enough across social milieux to impair agents' ability to break free from it. Ideology, after all, is never total (Haslanger, <span>2017b</span>; see also Geuss, <span>1981</span>).</p><p>To solve this problem, I draw on the market domination conception of fetishism, and specifically on its analysis of the profit-maximizing logic of market domination (Ripstein, <span>1987</span>, Roberts, <span>2017</span>, Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). I argue that this logic makes market ideology pervasive (see Sewell, <span>1992</span>), which deprives agents of the symbolic-material discrepancies between social milieux that would help them break free from market ideology.</p><p>Thus, on the interpretation I offer, fetishism should be understood as the <i>pervasive</i> ideology of the market, where its pervasiveness is due to what can be called <i>the standardizing influence of market domination across social milieux</i>.</p><p>This new interpretation clarifies one of the central mechanisms—indeed, perhaps the most fundamental mechanism—of the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market. As such, it provides a better basis for resistance to structural domination in the market than the market domination conception of fetishism, the analytic Marxists' interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism, and the influential conception of ideology we owe to Haslanger and others.</p><p>In the first section below, I focus on the market ideology conception, its analytic Marxist interpretation, and the two objections leveled against it by the proponents of the alternative, market domination conception. In Section 2, I build on Haslanger's influential account of ideology to offer a more ‘practical’ interpretation of the market ideology conception that escapes both objections. In Section 3, I turn to what I believe is the central problem with the market ideology conception of fetishism. Finally, in Section 4, I draw on the market domination conception to suggest a way to rescue the market ideology conception from this problem.</p><p>To set the scene, I begin with the relation between class domination, the market, and commodification. Then, I focus on the market ideology conception, its analytic Marxist interpretation, and the two objections.</p><p>Class domination refers to the situation of the worker who, forced to sell her labour power to some member of the capitalist class to make a living, finds herself unable to exit a relationship in which the relevant capitalist can get her to do more or less what she wants her to do for as long as she has bought her ability to work (see, for example, Gourevitch, <span>2018</span>). Importantly, class domination depends on the market, which organizes the systematic transfer of resources from workers to capitalists that impairs the ability of the former not to work for some capitalist or other. As such, the market explains why there can be class domination without any legally or normatively sanctioned class distinctions (see, for example, Young, <span>1990</span>, 47).</p><p>The market is a social practice of commodity production and exchange, that is, a collective solution to a coordination problem: the problem is for private producers to make a living in the absence of some form of central planning, and the solution the commodification process which generates market exchange and competition (Cohen, <span>2000</span>; Roberts, <span>2017</span>, for example, 78n97; Sewell, <span>1992</span>; Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). Those who enact the market participate in commodifying things—from means of production to products to their own ability to produce—by repeatedly reducing them, by means of money and other measuring devices, to units which can be counted, added, compared, and converted into one another. This in turn enables and encourages them to produce and exchange things not as favors or as gifts, but as commodities, viz. in such a way that no one gives more than <i>exactly</i> what she gets (Graeber, <span>2001</span>, 55–56 and <span>2011</span>, 103–05, Sewell, <span>1992</span>, 25–26, and Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 416–23; see Ripstein, <span>1987</span>, 736, Heinrich, <span>2012</span>, chapter 3, and Marx, <i>Capital I</i> [<span>1976</span>], chapter 1).</p><p>Crucially, from the fact that things are commodities, not naturally, but because those who enact the market participate in commodifying them, we should not conclude that it is entirely up to those who enact the market whether to commodify or not: as Marx suggested, the commodification process tends to occur ‘behind their backs’, as an unintended result of their actions (Marx, <span>1976</span>, chapter 1; see Sewell, <span>1992</span>, 22 and 25). How exactly does this work? This, and its consequences for the entrenchment of structural domination in the market, is the focus of the market ideology conception of fetishism.</p><p>Ideology, on a broadly Marxist conception, has three related features: first, it entrenches structural domination, second, it is epistemically deficient, and third, it has a ‘tainted origin’ in structural domination (Geuss, <span>1981</span>, 21; see Shelby, <span>2003</span>, and Celikates, <span>2016</span>). Indeed, ideology is often said to entrench structural domination <i>because</i> it is epistemically deficient, and to be epistemically deficient <i>because</i> agents learn it from dominating practices (see, for example, Haslanger, <span>2017a</span>, Einspahr, <span>2010</span>, Celikates, <span>2016</span>). In line with this account, the market ideology conception of fetishism defines fetishism as an epistemically deficient view of the market, which agents infer from the way things appear to them, and which leads them to reproduce the market and entrench class domination (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 115, Geras, <span>1971</span>, 78–79, Celikates, <span>2016</span>, 14; see also Haslanger, for example, <span>2017c</span>).<sup>1</sup></p><p>The view in question is epistemically deficient insofar as it does not alert agents to the fact that the things they exchange with their employers and clients are commodities because they themselves participate in commodifying them (see Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 116, Elster, <span>1986</span>, 57; cf. Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 165 and 112–20). This epistemically deficient view, however, is not like a ‘hallucination’ attributable entirely to a failure of perspicacity on the part of agents, but is rather ‘like a mirage’, insofar as the external world itself is misleading (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 115; see also Elster, <span>1986</span>, 56 and 177, Geras, <span>1971</span>, 78–9). In particular, the ‘foundation’ of exchange-value ‘in labouring activity is not [visible]’ (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 116). This epistemically deficient view, finally, explains why commodification occurs ‘behind the backs’ of agents, as an unintended results of their actions, and so why they fail to change the market for the better and entrench class domination as a result: agents will not even think of organizing production and exchange differently if they fail to realize that things are commodities because they themselves participate in commodifying them. Thus, as Cohen puts it, ‘[f]etishism protects capitalism’ (<span>2000</span>, 129).</p><p>This is the core of the market ideology conception of fetishism, and as such it is common to the two main interpretations of this conception: the dominant, analytic Marxists's interpretation put forward most famously by Gerald Cohen (<span>2000</span>) and Jon Elster (<span>1986</span>), and the socialization-based account which I will adapt from feminist and antiracist political theory in the next section (Haslanger, <span>2012</span>, <span>2017c</span>; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>, Einspahr, <span>2010</span>). The difference between the two interpretations lies in the exact way in which the ideological view in question is epistemically deficient.</p><p>According to the analytic Marxists, this view is not epistemically deficient merely by omission of part of what commodities are, viz. their being commodities because agents participate in commodifying them, as it will be on my alternative interpretation. Rather, it is epistemically deficient by inclusion of something which commodities are not, viz. their being commodities ‘as an inherent property’, as a matter of ‘substance’, or, more generally, ‘naturally and inevitably’ (Elster, <span>1986</span>, 57 and Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 116 and 127, respectively). Thus on the analytic Marxist view, and in Cohen's words, there are ‘two phases in commodity fetishism: (1) separation of exchange-value from its material basis; (2) attachment of exchange-value to the substance of the commodity’ (<span>2000</span>, 117; cf. 116). On my alternative interpretation, by contrast, only the first phase obtains.</p><p>Insofar as including such ontological precisions as an account of the substance of commodities is the mark of a theoretical attitude, one on which agents flesh out their view of things beyond what is ‘practically necessary’ (Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 48), we may say that for the analytic Marxists, the ideological view in question is a theoretical view. 2 On such a view, commodities are endowed with a natural dimension, where this means not only that their social dimension is stripped out from the way they appear, as it is on my alternative interpretation, but also that their appearance is more elaborate than it is on my alternative interpretation: to those who hold this view, commodities appear not just as things whose exact value must be paid if they are to change hands, but also as things which possess value by virtue of their physical properties, ‘just as they have weight’ (Elster, <span>1986</span>, 57).<sup>3</sup></p><p>This interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism has recently come under sustained pressure from the proponents of the market domination view of fetishism. William Roberts (<span>2017</span>), in particular, has built on Arthur Ripstein (<span>1987</span>) to argue that ‘[f]etishism ought to be understood as a form of domination rather than a form of false consciousness’ (<span>2017</span>, 85). I will describe the form of domination they have in mind in Section 4. Here, I focus on their central objections.</p><p>The first is Roberts's. As we saw above, to define fetishism as market ideology involves claiming that the view which agents infer from the way the things they exchange appear to them is epistemically deficient. But this view is not epistemically deficient, Roberts argues, since things appear as what they are to those who hold this view. As he puts it, the market ideology conception of fetishism ‘trips over Marx's explicit claim that, in fetishism, “the social relations between [the producers’] private labours appear <i>as what they are</i>”. Where social relations are mediated by commodities, exchanges <i>are</i> the real relations between the producers of commodities' (Roberts, <span>2017</span>, 86–87, quoting Marx, <i>Capital</i> 1, <span>1976</span>, 166, to which he adds the emphasis).</p><p>For those of us less interested in exegesis than Roberts, the fact that this was ‘Marx's explicit claim’ may not carry additional weight. Yet Roberts is also interested in theorizing fetishism further, and he makes it clear that he considers Marx to be right on this point: fetishism concerns social reality as it is constructed by ‘the social practice of exchange’ (<span>2017</span>, 88n133). I agree, as suggested above. In fact, this point is widely accepted in the literature on fetishism. The analytic Marxists themselves concur, insisting, as we saw above, that fetishism is ‘like a mirage’, insofar as the external world itself is misleading (Cohen, <span>2000</span>, 115; see also Elster, <span>1986</span>, 56 and 177, Geras, <span>1971</span>, 78–9).</p><p>This, however, makes the analytic Marxists's interpretation vulnerable to Roberts's objection. On their ‘theoretical’ reading, recall, the ideological view at the heart of fetishism fails to alert agents to part of what commodities are (viz. their social aspect) not just by omission of it, but by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz. their purported natural aspect). To those who hold this view, therefore, commodities do <i>not</i> appear as what they are: they appear to be naturally commodities while, really, they are commodities by social construction. Thus the analytic Marxists' theoretical reading of the market ideology conception is vulnerable to the first objection.</p><p>The same goes for the second objection, viz. that the ideological view at issue is irrelevant since fetishism is best understood as concerning social activity rather than theoretical understanding. This objection is raised by Ripstein, who insists, against Cohen and the classical proponents of the market ideology conception, that fetishism ‘is the failing associated with practical involvement in the world’, not with ‘the virtue of knowledge’, because activity and understanding are distinct modes of engagement with the world, and fetishism is about activity, not understanding (Ripstein, <span>1987</span>, 743).</p><p>Like Roberts above, not only does Ripstein take this to be Marx's claim, but he also insists that Marx was right. For to focus primarily on theoretical understanding rather than social activity, he suggests, is to risk concentrating on ‘how knowledgeable or error prone’ people are in the market, to the detriment of the fact that ‘[t]o have one's activities entirely shaped by [the market] is to be enslaved […]’ (<span>1987</span>, 743 and 747).</p><p>I agree that Ripstein's—and Marx's—primarily practical orientation is crucial. The concept of fetishism should help us focus on structural domination in the market, be it to draw our attention to the phenomenon itself, as Ripstein believes, or to alert us to the exact workings of its ideological reproduction, as I think would be more useful at this stage. I also agree that the risk of losing sight of this practical predicament is real on a ‘theoretical’ interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism. The analytic Marxists testify to this. Elster, for instance, concludes that ‘[fetishism] is a cognitive illusion arising from market transactions, <i>not a morally deplorable feature of markets</i>’ (<span>1986</span>, 58, my emphasis). Likewise, Cohen, mired in theoretical debates about the labour theory of value, offers only an ‘<i>explanation without defence</i> of Marx's views [on fetishism]’ (<span>2000</span>, xii, his emphasis). For fear of losing sight of social activity and its current predicament, therefore, we should not take fetishism to concern theoretical understanding. This is to say that the analytic Marxists' conception of fetishism falls prey to the second objection, as it did to the first.</p><p>I conclude, with Roberts and Ripstein, that fetishism should not be conceived as the ideology of the market if ideology is understood as the analytic Marxists understand it, that is, theoretically. Things are different if ideology is understood practically, as I argue in the next section.</p><p>The ‘practical’ understanding of ideology has recently become influential in feminist and antiracist studies, largely thanks to the efforts of Sally Haslanger (e.g. <span>2017c</span>). In this section, I adapt it to the market, in order to offer an interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism which escapes the two objections encountered in the previous section.</p><p>We saw above that, according to the analytic Marxists, the ideological view at the heart of fetishism is epistemically deficient not merely by omission of part of what commodities are (viz., their social aspect), but also by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz., their purported natural aspect), which I suggested was the mark of a theoretical mode of engagement with the world.</p><p>By contrast, on the conception of ideology put forward by Haslanger and others, ideology is much more ‘practical’. Developed as part of a critico-theoretical, socio-constructivist account of gender and race (see, for example, Haslanger, <span>2012</span>), this conception offers an account of ideology as the schemas of dominating practices insofar as agents are socialized into them, where socialization is understood as the process through which agents learn from the milieux they frequent the schemas of the practices enacted in these milieux (Haslanger, <span>2017b</span>; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>).</p><p>While Haslanger does not apply this account to specifically capitalist and classist issues, it can be fruitfully put to the service of the market ideology conception of fetishism. Seen in this light, commodity fetishism can be understood as a schema of the market insofar as agents are socialized into it. According to the broadly Bourdieusian account of socialization Haslanger relies on, this suggests that to fetishise the market is to keep applying the commodity schema to things, because in this milieu things ‘actualise’ or ‘incorporate’ this schema, and so ‘teach’ or ‘inculcate’ it in turn (Sewell, <span>1992</span>, 12–13, quoted in Haslanger, <span>2017c</span>, 22; see also Einspahr, <span>2010</span>, and Bourdieu, <span>1977</span>).<sup>4</sup></p><p>Importantly, socialization is, on this account, oriented to helping agents enact social practices, understood as ‘collective solutions to coordination or access problems’ (Haslanger, <span>2016</span>, 126). This means that the schemas of these practices, being geared primarily to helping agents solve collective problems, often focus on those aspects of things which are useful in this respect, to the detriment of other, less immediately relevant aspects (cf. Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 45–47). Given this, the commodity schema can be understood as the schema that things are commodities <i>full stop</i>, not that they are commodities <i>naturally</i> (<i>or not</i>), this latter aspect falling outside the immediate concern of agents aiming to make a living.<sup>5</sup></p><p>In other words, on the interpretation we can build from Haslanger's account of ideology, the commodity schema is epistemically mistaken not by inclusion of something which commodities are not, as it is for the analytic Marxists, but instead by omission of part of what commodities are. As Haslanger would put it, it only ‘leave[s] out’ the fact that commodities are such because we participate in commodifying them, and this is how it ‘obscure[s] [their] social dimension’ (Haslanger, <span>2012</span>, 18 and 467; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span>). In other words, it does not give them a more elaborate appearance by representing their (mistaken) ontological status, as it does on the analytic Marxists' interpretation: here, commodities only appear as things whose exact value must be paid if they are to change hands, not as things which, in addition, have their value in this way or that.</p><p>This point is crucial, because it enables this alternative interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism to escape the two objections from the previous section.</p><p>The first objection, recall, was that the commodity schema is not epistemically deficient, since things appear as what they are to those who hold it (Roberts, <span>2017</span>). As noted above, I agree with Roberts—and Marx—that fetishism is about the social construction of reality by the market: as we may now say with Haslanger, things on the market ‘actualise’ or ‘incorporate’ the commodity schema, and to this extent appear as what they are to those who hold this schema.</p><p>But from this, crucially, we should not conclude that the commodity schema cannot be epistemically deficient <i>as well</i>, and, therefore, ideological <i>as well</i>. From the fact that commodities do appear as what they are to those who hold the commodity schema, it does not follow that they appear as <i>everything</i> that they are. It may well be the case that everything that commodities appear to be (viz., commodities) is true of them, but that the schema still leaves out some crucial fact about them (viz., their social dimension).</p><p>In other words, Roberts's objection applies to the analytic-Marxist view, as we saw above, but not to the alternative interpretation I just offered. To agents whose ‘theoretical’ view of commodities fails to alert them to part of what commodities are (viz. their social dimension) <i>by inclusion</i> of something which commodities are not (viz. their alleged natural dimension), commodities do <i>not</i> appear as what they are. But to agents whose ‘practical’ schema of commodities is epistemically mistaken only <i>by omission</i> of part of what commodities are (viz. their social dimension), commodities <i>do</i> appear as what they are (viz. as commodities), if not as everything that they are. Therefore, the alternative interpretation, unlike the analytic Marxist view, escapes the first objection.</p><p>The same goes for Roberts's objection, viz. that the commodity schema is irrelevant since fetishism should concern market activity rather than theoretical understanding, on pain of neglecting the structurally dominated character of this activity. As I wrote above, I agree with Ripstein that a focus on structural domination in the market is crucial. But I also hold that, unlike the analytic Marxists' interpretation, my alternative interpretation can focus on understanding without running the risk of losing sight of this practical failing.</p><p>Indeed, from the fact that fetishism should not concern theoretical understanding, it does not follow that fetishism cannot be about understanding <i>at all</i>. For even if fetishism is not about the kind of theoretical understanding the analytic Marxists focus on, it can be about the kind of practical understanding on which the alternative interpretation insists. Ripstein's distinction between activity and understanding is too stark: it misses the fact that activity involves understanding in the form of the schemas (e.g., the commodity schema) which enable agents to enact their various social practices (e.g., the market).</p><p>Put differently, from the fact that ‘all social life is essentially <i>practical</i>’ (Marx, <i>Eighth Thesis on Feuerbach</i>, quoted in Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 45, original emphasis), we should not conclude with Ripstein that fetishism ‘is the failing associated with practical involvement in the world’ rather than with any kind of understanding (1987, 743). Instead, we should conclude with Torrance that ‘what people observe and how they experience and describe their surroundings depends on their purposes and the problems they face’ (Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 45)—that is, more precisely, on the schemas which help them enact the social practices in which they participate and which, geared as they are to helping them solve collective problems, may fail to alert them to more than they strictly need to understand in order to do so (cf. Torrance, <span>1995</span>, 47).<sup>6</sup> The commodity schema is a case in point: as we saw above, it leaves out the social dimension of commodities, this otherwise crucial fact being of little immediate interest to agents focused on making a living. Thus, while it would indeed be a mistake to take fetishism to concern the kind of theoretical understanding which the analytic Marxists have in mind, the concept can be about the kind of practical understanding involved in social activity on which the alternative interpretation operates. Therefore, this interpretation escapes the second objection, as it escaped the first.</p><p>I conclude, <i>contra</i> Roberts and Ripstein, that fetishism can be understood as the ideology of the market, provided that ideology is understood practically rather than theoretically. The main problem with the market ideology conception of fetishism lies elsewhere, as I argue now.</p><p>The problem is the following: the market ideology conception of fetishism seems unable to explain how the commodity schema can play the central role which it is meant to play, viz. contributing to the reproduction of market domination. This is because it is unclear why it should be expected to be widespread enough across social milieux to impair agents' ability to break free from it, when, in general, ideologies should not be expected to be so widespread.</p><p>On the practical interpretation I offered above, it is agents' socialization into ideology, understood as the process through which they learn ideology from the social milieux in which it is embodied, that explains ideology's domination-reproducing effect. But as is widely recognized, including by Haslanger herself (2017b; see also Celikates, <span>2016</span> and Geuss, <span>1981</span>), ideology is never total. In the case at hand, things should be expected to embody and teach the commodity schema with employers and clients, but the gift schema with friends or family, and the favor schema with neighbors. Given this fragmentation, it is unclear how agents can fail to correct their schema of commodities by learning that things are commodities at work because they are treated as such in this milieu but not in others—and, therefore, how they can find themselves in the grip of anything like an ideology of the market that has them participate in commodification ‘behind their back’ and so contribute to the reproduction of market domination.<sup>7</sup></p><p>To make this argument in more detail, the first thing to emphasize is that agents are socialized into a multiplicity of social practices, some of which are not capitalist. As Haslanger insists, ‘[t]here are multiple reasons to avoid the idea that ideology [e.g., capitalist schemas] functions as a total system governing society as a whole’ (2017b, 161). Indeed, Robin Celikates emphasizes, we should bear in mind Raymond Geuss's famous claim that ‘a society of happy slaves, content with their chains […] is a nightmare, not a realistic view of a state of society which is at present possible’ (<span>1981</span>, 83–84, quoted in Celikates, <span>2016</span>). In other words, we should expect ideological schemas to be actualised in things in some of the milieux which agents navigate, <i>but not in others</i>.</p><p>Yet if so, crucially, we should also expect agents to learn that things actualise a schema because they themselves incorporate it in things in some milieux but not in others. Agents are ‘knowledgeable’, after all (Giddens, <span>1979</span>, 5; see also Celikates, <span>2006</span>, Boltanski &amp; Thévenot, <span>2006</span>), and should be expected to realize that if things actualise different schemas in different milieux, it is largely because they themselves apply different schemas to them. Indeed, it is ‘a leading theorem’ of Anthony Giddens that ‘every social actor knows a great deal about the conditions of reproduction of the society of which he or she is a member’ (<span>1979</span>, 5, emphasis removed; see also Scott, <span>1985</span>, 319).</p><p>This is particularly clear with the commodity schema. If socialization is fragmented in this way, we should expect the commodity schema to be incorporated in things when people exchange them with their employers or clients, but not when they exchange them with their neighbors, friends, or family. As Graeber (<span>2011</span>) and Cohen (<span>2009</span>) insist, commodity exchange is very different from the kind of exchange that in principle occurs between neighbors, friends, or family. The schema of commodity exchange is not just ‘give as good as you get’, as in neighborly exchange, but rather ‘give <i>exactly</i> as good as you get’, the price being the expression of this mathematical equivalence made possible by the reduction of things to countable units (Graeber, <span>2011</span>, chapter 5). The discrepancy is even more striking with close friends and family. There, the schema is the ‘baseline communist’ one, ‘to each according to their needs and from each according to their means’ (Graeber, ibid.; cf. Cohen, <span>2009</span>, 39–45). Thus, in principle, the things which agents exchange with neighbors, friends, or family do not actualise the commodity schema, but the favor schema or the gift schema (as the case may be). When plumbers fix the bathrooms of their relatives for free, for example, their ability to work does not incorporate the commodity schema. It is not standardized but personalized, and the plumbers' relatives are not presented with a bill.<sup>8</sup></p><p>Yet, crucially, if, as I just argued, the things which agents exchange with their neighbors, friends, and family do <i>not</i> incorporate the commodity schema in the way that the things which they exchange with their employers and clients do, then it is unclear how the commodity schema can leave out the fact that these things are commodities largely because people participate in commodifying them. People, again, are not ‘judgmental dopes’, in Garfinkel's famous phrase (<span>1984</span>, 75; see also Celikates, <span>2006</span>, 30 and Roberts, <span>2017</span>, 95), and if things incorporate different schemas in different milieux, the discrepancies between things or milieux should help them realize that they themselves participate in the incorporating. When a plumber fixes her neighbor's kitchen sink because he previously babysat her children and she owes him one, or repairs her parents' bathroom for free, she can hardly fail to infer that <i>if her ability to work is a commodity at work, it is partly because she participates in commodifying it by selling it to her employer or clients for an hourly wage</i>.<sup>9</sup> In other words, we should expect her commodity schema to include the fact that her ability to work is a commodity at work in part because of herself and her employer, just like we should expect her gift schema and her favor schema to include, respectively, the facts that her ability to work is a gift in family milieux partly because it has been made so by herself and her parents, or that its being exchanged as a favor in neighborly spheres is due, to a significant extent, to her and her neighbors' making it so. To expect any less of them would fail to do justice to what we can call, with Giddens, their ‘penetration’ (<span>1979</span>, 71–72).</p><p>If socialization works in this fragmented way, then, we should expect things to actualise the commodity schema with employers and clients, but the gift schema with family and friends and the favor schema with neighbors. But this suggests in turn that we should not expect agents' commodity schema to limit itself to the fact that at work things are commodities, omitting the further fact that, if they are so, it is largely because agents themselves participate in commodifying them in this milieu. If so, however, then it is unclear how the commodity schema can explain how commodification may ‘work “behind the backs” of the social actors who produce and reproduce [it]’, as Giddens would put it (<span>1979</span>, 71), and thus prevent them from changing the market for the better and from entrenching class domination as a result.<sup>10</sup></p><p>Put differently, the market ideology conception of fetishism fails to adequately explain the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market.</p><p>To rescue the market ideology conception, I draw on the market domination conception: specifically, on its analysis of the profit-maximizing logic of market domination (Ripstein 1986, Roberts, <span>2017</span>, Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). I argue that this logic makes market ideology pervasive (see Sewell, <span>1992</span>), which deprives agents of the epistemic discrepancies between milieux that would help them break free from it and, therefore, explains why commodification may occur ‘behind their backs’. On this modified interpretation, fetishism should be understood as the <i>pervasive</i> ideology of the market, where its pervasiveness is due to what can be called <i>the standardizing effect of market domination across social milieux</i>.</p><p>As we saw above, the ideology conception of fetishism has recently come under pressure from Roberts (<span>2017</span>), building on previous work from Ripstein (<span>1987</span>). I have already pushed back against their objections above. Now I want to focus on what I take to be the central insight of the market domination conception of fetishism they offer. This is not meant to constitute an endorsement of their view, however, but merely an acknowledgement that the phenomenon they focus on is of the greatest importance in the analysis of fetishism, if not what fetishism is.</p><p>On the market domination conception, fetishism is a form of domination that is distinct from, even as it influences, class domination: it is the impersonal domination suffered by both workers and capitalists because of market competition (see Roberts, <span>2017</span>, 88 and Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>, 379). As Roberts insists, ‘the dominant class in modernity, the class of capitalists, is as subject to impersonal domination as are the laboring classes’ (<span>2017</span>, 102). Vrousalis agrees: Roberts, he writes, is right that ‘capitalist [or impersonal] domination is not equivalent to class domination’ (<span>2017</span>, 379). Ripstein concurs: according to him, the central feature of this domination is that ‘the options of all are limited by the market’, not merely those of workers relative to capitalists (<span>1987</span>, 747).</p><p>The complete definition of this impersonal domination is the object of some debate between Roberts and Vrousalis, who disagree as to who is to be held responsible for it, and whether it is arbitrary in some sense (see Roberts, <span>2017</span>; Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>). But let me bypass these disagreements to focus on what both Roberts and Vrousalis agree on, and Ripstein as well. This is that both workers and capitalists are dominated into maximizing profit. As Vrousalis insists, market competition affects radically the power of the capitalist class over the working class. Without competition, each capitalist can act as an ‘absolute monarch’ over their workers, unconstrained in the wage they offer and in what they ask them to do. But as soon as they face (perfect-enough) competition, they can no longer determine wages arbitrarily, or have workers do whatever takes their fancy: at this point ‘[each] is constrained, on pain of competitive disadvantage, to maximise profit, which in turn requires paying [workers] a market-clearing wage’ and exploiting them (<span>2017</span>, 380–81). Roberts concurs, writing for instance that ‘[t]he capitalist, dominated by market imperatives, is compelled thereby to exploit labor’, which by definition entails making a profit (<span>2017</span>, 102). Ripstein agrees as well, emphasizing both that the worker ‘must make himself marketable and once sold, direct his activity to whatever his employer demands’, and that ‘[t]he employer's options are broader but still limited: On pain of bankruptcy, this demand can only take a single form: produce what is profitable’ (<span>1987</span>, 748).</p><p>In other words, all the proponents of the domination conception of fetishism agree that in an important respect the domination at issue is ‘non-arbitrary’ in the sense of ‘regulated’—indeed, regulated by one key rule: ‘maximize profit’ (Vrousalis, <span>2017</span>, 381).<sup>11</sup> If Roberts downplays this aspect, it is only to emphasize that this domination is in another sense arbitrary, viz. whimsical. For the two aspects seem to clash, and it is on this apparent clash that Vrousalis insists when he characterizes this domination as ‘non-arbitrary’. But the clash is only apparent, as it is quite compatible for the domination that on each view constitutes fetishism to be both arbitrary and non-arbitrary in these senses. The market may have movements that are quite difficult to anticipate and, at the same time, still channel capitalists (and workers in their wake) in one definite direction: that of making profit. As Sewell emphasizes, what characterizes capitalism is precisely both a ‘chronic instability or unpredictability’ and ‘a continuous dynamic of capital accumulation […]’ (<span>1992</span>, 25–26).<sup>12</sup></p><p>Now, Vrousalis also insists, against Roberts, that the agents of this domination are not ‘markets or market imperatives’, but ‘[c]apitalists who dominate each other by jointly constituting the ‘external coercive necessities confronting the individual capitalist’ (<span>2017</span>, 3, quoting Marx, <span>1976</span>, 381). Here, I do not engage in this debate, however, for it would take us too far afield. Instead, I focus on the profit-maximizing logic that they all agree on. For it offers a solution to the problem identified in the previous section.</p><p>The reasoning is this: if capitalists and workers are dominated into maximizing profit, then they are dominated into incorporating the commodity schema beyond the workplace, in as many milieux as competition requires. This in turns deprives them of the discrepancies between milieux that could help them realize that they themselves are incorporating the commodity schema in things, which explains how this schema can fail to include this fact.</p><p>As Sewell emphasizes, ‘the commodification of things’ is at the core of the ‘continuous dynamic of capital accumulation’ and profit maximization we saw him mention earlier (<span>1992</span>, 25). Capitalists, on pain of competitive disadvantage, have a strong incentive to ensure that as many things are commodified as possible, and so, therefore, do their workers. Only commodities are ‘opportunities for profit’ after all, and competition requires capitalists to maximize profit. This is why, in Sewell's words again, ‘the commodification of things’ is now ‘pervasive’, that is, ‘present in a relatively wide range of institutional spheres, practices, and discourses’ (ibid., 25 and 22): the ‘chain of commodity exchange’ is ‘vast’, as ‘the commodity form […] organizes a virtually universal intersection of resources’ (ibid., 26). In this respect, it is no surprise that Marx's first description of capitalism in <i>Capital</i> is as ‘an immense collection of commodities’ (<span>1976</span>, chapter 1). The domination identified above turns commodity exchange into a practice that is pervasive in a way few practices are.<sup>13</sup></p><p>Now, Sewell seems to take such pervasiveness to result from the fact that the commodity schema is ‘exceptionally transposable’ (<span>1992</span>, 25), rather than from the profit-maximizing logic of the domination which Ripstein, Roberts, and Vrousalis insist on. Sewell nowhere mentions domination, but instead insists that the commodity schema itself ‘knows no natural limits’ as ‘it can be applied not only to cloth, tobacco, or cooking pans, but to land, housework, bread, sex, advertising, emotions, or knowledge […]’ (ibid., 25–26). But this seems to me mistaken. Exceptional <i>transposability</i> is not exceptional <i>transposition</i>, and a motivating force—‘a force that requires it’, as MacKinnon puts it (<span>1982</span>, 540)—is crucial for the <i>actual</i> rather than merely <i>virtual</i> pervasiveness of the chain of commodity exchange. This motivating force is the domination with a profit-maximizing logic that affects both capitalists and their workers in the market.</p><p>Thus, while capitalists and workers might try to keep the things they exchange with their family largely uncommodified, they will often expand the commodity schema to the things they exchange with friends and neighbors. The magazine <i>Plumbing Connection</i> provides a telling example of this phenomenon in an article entitled ‘The Deal with Mates Rates’, by Brad Fallon (<span>2014</span>). Fallon begins by noting that ‘people with trade skills are always faced with the old ‘mates rates' dilemma’. He frames the dilemma as follows: ‘with a client […] I just roll off the invoice – job well done’; ‘however, add a stressed friend, relative or neighbour into the scenario – someone who I see all the time, whether in my street, at school, or socially – and suddenly, I have this overwhelming need to become the not-for-profit, happy to spend my weekend plumbing “for free” emergency plumber’. And so he goes on to offer ‘some of [his] most helpful tips for ensuring that [people with trade skills] are adequately paid for the work [they] do’. The tips can be grouped in two categories: making excuses, and commodifying, the only exception being the family (‘Obviously […], if it is your Mother-In-Law knocking on the door, throw all the rules out and do the job straight away for free’). One good tip, in particular, consists in ‘booking the job in during standard work hours with one of [your] staff members'. As Fallon emphasizes, this ‘change[s] the dynamic of the relationship back from a personal favour to a professional plumbing service’. Other tips go in the same direction.<sup>14</sup> As this example illustrates, capitalists and their staff members are dominated into extending the commodity schema beyond the workplace to as many milieux as competition requires – even with their friends, if not with their mother-in-law.<sup>15</sup></p><p>But this standardizing influence of structural domination on socialization, crucially, offers a solution to the problem affecting the market ideology conception of fetishism. The problem, recall, was that if things incorporate different schemas in different milieux, which they should do if socialization works in the fragmented way it is widely recognized to work in, then the discrepancies between these milieux should prompt agents to realize that they themselves participate in the incorporating, and to include this fact in their commodity schema. If our plumber fixes her neighbor's kitchen sink because the neighbor previously babysat her children and she owes him one, or her parents' bathroom for free, we should expect her schema of her ability to work in the workplace to tell her that it is partly commodified by herself and her employer. Brad Fallon is a case in point: he complains that ‘because I like to “help” my friends’, […] it feels wrong to charge them’ (<span>2014</span>). But the standardizing influence of structural domination offers a solution to this problem. For if the plumber, or any other market agent, is dominated in such a way that, with her neighbors or friends, she does not exchange her ability to work as a favor or as a gift but as a commodity, in just the same way as she does with her employer and customers, then the move from one milieu to the next will be so natural that it will blunt her critical consciousness: specifically, she will not realize that she herself is playing an important part in actualising the commodity schema in her ability to work, and her version of the schema will not include this fact. Fallon's version of the schema, because he has reflected on it, may be sufficiently critical, but he is an exception. Indeed, he insists, ‘most friends, neighbours and relatives […] don't actually want a discount or preferential treatment’. In fact, usually they do not even ask him ‘to discount [his] prices' (ibid.). Unlike him, they may well fetishise commodities.</p><p>More generally, I want to suggest the following explanation of the mirage at the heart of fetishism. If the commodity schema is incorporated not just in the things agents exchange with their employers and customers, but also in the things they exchange with their ‘friends, relatives or neighbours’, as Fallon puts it, then the schema they infer from the commodities they exchange with their employers and customers will leave out the fact that they themselves are partly responsible for the commodification of commodities. For when a schema is pervasive in this way, there are no hitches between the spheres of activity agents navigate, and they stop noticing that they are applying it themselves: as Sewell puts it, schemas that are incorporated in a relatively wide range of milieux tend to become ‘relatively unconscious, in the sense that they are taken-for-granted mental assumptions or modes of procedures that actors normally apply without being aware that they are applying them’ (<span>1992</span>, 22; see also 24 ff.). Agents in such a standardized environment are deprived of the prompts that could have helped them realize that they are following the standard, and end up doing so without thinking (cf. Graeber, <span>2005</span>, 431).<sup>16</sup> One might say that the commodity schema, in particular, is reflected back to them by so many things that they become ‘naturals’ relative to it, applying it ‘naturally’ to the things that reflect it, aware only that they are exchanging them as commodities, not that they are contributing to commodifying them as they do. Their critical consciousness is blunted, and this is why the commodification process occurs ‘behind their backs’, as an unintended result of their actions.</p><p>The commodity schema does not alert capitalists and workers to the fact that it is because they participate in commodifying them that the things they exchange are commodities, and it does not alert them to this fact because they participate in the incorporation of this schema in things without thinking. They do this, in turn, because they are dominated into incorporating this schema in things, not just in the workplace, but pervasively, for instance in friendly reunions and neighborly encounters, if not in family settings. In other words, the impersonal domination at issue deprives them of the standpoints from which to realize that they are participating in the construction of social reality in such a way that they entrench, in a vicious circle, their own domination (see Lahire, <span>2001</span>; MacKinnon, <span>1982</span>).<sup>17</sup></p><p>Thus fetishism, or the ideology of the market understood in terms of socialization into the market, entrenches structural domination because structural domination, in the form of the impersonal domination Vrousalis, Roberts and Ripstein emphasize and of the class domination it affects, has a standardizing influence on agents' socialization.</p><p>Put differently, if the ideology of the market is understood to be both practical (against the theoretical interpretation of the market ideology conception) and rendered pervasive across social milieux by what I have called the standardizing influence of market domination (against the current interpretation of the practical conception of ideology), then the market ideology conception of fetishism can shed some new light on one of the key mechanisms of the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market. This, I conclude, would provide us with a better ‘basis of resistance’, in Haslanger's phrase (<span>2020</span>, 36), than the market domination conception of fetishism, the analytic Marxist interpretation of the market ideology conception, and the influential account of ideology developed by Haslanger herself.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46756,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"volume\":\"54 4\",\"pages\":\"548-564\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-11-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12497\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Social Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12497\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12497","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

回想一下,问题是,如果事物在不同的环境中整合了不同的图式,如果社会化以碎片化的方式运作,那么这些环境之间的差异应该促使行动者意识到他们自己也参与了整合,并将这一事实包含在他们的商品图式中。如果我们的水管工修理了邻居的厨房水槽,因为邻居以前照看过她的孩子,她欠他一个,或者她父母的浴室是免费的,我们应该期待她在工作场所工作能力的图式告诉她,这在一定程度上是由她自己和她的雇主商业化的。布拉德·法伦(Brad Fallon)就是一个很好的例子:他抱怨说,“因为我喜欢‘帮助’我的朋友,所以向他们收费感觉不对”(2014年)。而结构性支配的规范化影响为这一问题提供了解决方案。因为,如果水管工或任何其他市场代理人被这样一种方式所支配:她与邻居或朋友之间,不把自己的工作能力作为一种恩惠或礼物,而是作为一种商品进行交换,就像她与雇主和顾客之间的交换一样,那么,从一个环境转移到另一个环境将是如此自然,以至于会削弱她的批判意识。具体来说,她不会意识到她自己在实现她的工作能力中的商品图式中扮演着重要的角色,她的图式版本不会包括这个事实。法伦的图式版本,因为他对它进行了反思,可能是足够批判的,但他是一个例外。事实上,他坚持认为,“大多数朋友、邻居和亲戚……实际上并不想要折扣或优惠待遇”。事实上,通常他们甚至不会要求他“打折”(同上)。与他不同的是,他们很可能迷恋商品。更一般地说,我想对拜物教核心的海市蜃楼提出以下解释。如果商品图式不仅包括代理人与雇主和顾客交换的东西,也包括他们与“朋友、亲戚或邻居”交换的东西,如法伦所说,那么他们从与雇主和顾客交换的商品中推断出的图式将忽略他们自己对商品商品化负有部分责任这一事实。因为当一个图式以这种方式普遍存在时,行为主体所导航的活动领域之间就不会有任何障碍,他们也不会注意到自己在应用它:正如休厄尔所说,在相对广泛的环境中被纳入的图式往往会变得“相对无意识,从某种意义上说,它们被视为理所当然的心理假设或程序模式,行为主体通常不会意识到他们在应用它们”(1992,22;参见24 ff.)。在这样一个标准化的环境中,代理被剥夺了可以帮助他们意识到他们正在遵循标准的提示,并且最终不经思考就这样做了(cf. Graeber, 2005,431)有人可能会说,特别是商品图式,被如此多的事物反射到他们身上,以至于他们相对于它变得“自然”,“自然”地将它应用于反映它的事物,只意识到他们将它们作为商品交换,而不是像他们所做的那样为商品化做出贡献。他们的批判意识被削弱了,这就是为什么商品化过程“在他们背后”发生,作为他们行为的意外结果。商品图式并没有提醒资本家和工人,因为他们参与了商品交易,所以他们交换的东西就是商品,商品图式并没有提醒他们注意这个事实,因为他们不假思索地参与了商品图式的整合。他们这样做,反过来,因为他们被支配着,把这种图式融入到事物中,不仅在工作场所,而且无处不在,例如在友好的聚会和邻居的相遇中,如果不是在家庭环境中。换句话说,问题中的非个人统治剥夺了他们的立场,使他们意识到他们以这样一种方式参与社会现实的建设,在一个恶性循环中,他们巩固了自己的统治(见Lahire, 2001;麦金农,1982)。因此,拜物教,或者从社会化进入市场的角度理解的市场意识形态,巩固了结构性统治,因为结构性统治,以弗罗萨里斯、罗伯茨和里普斯坦强调的非个人统治的形式,以及它所影响的阶级统治的形式,对代理人的社会化有一种标准化的影响。 换句话说,如果市场意识形态被理解为既实用(与市场意识形态概念的理论解释相反),又通过我所说的市场支配的标准化影响(与当前对意识形态实践概念的解释相反)在社会环境中普遍存在,那么,拜物教的市场意识形态概念可以为结构性支配在市场中意识形态再生产的关键机制之一提供新的视角。我的结论是,这将为我们提供一个更好的“抵抗基础”,用哈斯兰格的话说(2020,36),而不是拜物教的市场支配概念,分析马克思主义对市场意识形态概念的解释,以及哈斯兰格本人对意识形态的有影响力的解释。 因此,根据我提供的解释,拜物教应该被理解为市场的普遍意识形态,它的普遍存在是由于市场支配在社会环境中的标准化影响。这种新的解释阐明了市场中结构性支配的意识形态再生产的核心机制之一——实际上,也许是最基本的机制。因此,它比拜物教的市场支配概念、分析马克思主义者对拜物教的市场意识形态概念的解释,以及我们归功于哈斯兰格等人的有影响力的意识形态概念,为抵制市场中的结构性支配提供了更好的基础。在下面的第一部分中,我将重点关注市场意识形态概念,它的分析马克思主义解释,以及另一种选择——市场支配概念的支持者对它提出的两种反对意见。在第2节中,我以哈斯兰格对意识形态的有影响力的描述为基础,对市场意识形态概念提供了一个更“实用”的解释,避免了这两种反对意见。在第3节,我转向我认为是拜物教的市场意识形态概念的核心问题。最后,在第四节中,我借鉴了市场支配概念,提出了一种将市场意识形态概念从这个问题中拯救出来的方法。为了设置场景,我从阶级统治、市场和商品化之间的关系开始。然后,我专注于市场意识形态概念,分析马克思主义的解释,和两个objections.Class统治指工人的情况,她被迫出售劳动力的一些成员资产阶级谋生,发现自己无法退出的关系相关的资本主义或多或少可以让她做她想要做什么只要她买了工作能力(见,例如,Gourevitch, 2018)。重要的是,阶级统治依赖于市场,它组织了资源从工人到资本家的系统转移,从而削弱了前者不为某个资本家或其他资本家工作的能力。因此,市场解释了为什么在没有任何法律或规范认可的阶级区分的情况下可以存在阶级统治(例如,参见Young, 1990,47)。市场是商品生产和交换的社会实践,也就是说,是对协调问题的集体解决方案:问题是私人生产者在缺乏某种形式的中央计划的情况下谋生,解决方案是产生市场交换和竞争的商品化过程(Cohen, 2000;例如,罗伯茨,2017年,78n97;西维尔,1992;Vrousalis, 2017)。那些制定市场的人参与了商品的商品化——从生产资料到产品,再到他们自己的生产能力——通过货币和其他计量工具,反复地将它们减少到可以计数、增加、比较和相互转换的单位。这反过来又使他们能够并鼓励他们生产和交换东西,而不是作为恩惠或礼物,而是作为商品,也就是说,在这样一种方式下,没有人付出比她得到的更多(格雷伯,2001年,55-56;2011年,103-05;休厄尔,1992年,25-26;科恩,2000年,416-23;见里普斯坦,1987年,第736页;海因里希,2012年,第3章;马克思,《资本论1》[1976],第1章)。至关重要的是,从事物是商品这一事实出发,不是自然地,而是因为那些制定市场的人参与了它们的商品化,我们不应该得出结论,认为是否商品化完全取决于那些制定市场的人:正如马克思所建议的那样,商品化过程往往是“在他们背后”发生的,作为他们行动的意外结果(马克思,1976年,第1章;参见Sewell, 1992,22和25)。这究竟是如何工作的呢?这一点,以及它对市场中结构性支配的巩固的后果,是拜物教的市场意识形态概念的焦点。从广义的马克思主义概念来看,意识形态有三个相关特征:第一,它巩固了结构性支配;第二,它在认识论上有缺陷;第三,它在结构性支配中有一个“污染的起源”(Geuss, 1981,21;参见Shelby, 2003年和Celikates, 2016年)。事实上,意识形态通常被认为巩固了结构性统治,因为它在认知上有缺陷,而且在认知上有缺陷,因为主体从支配实践中学习到它(例如,见Haslanger, 2017a, espinahr, 2010, Celikates, 2016)。根据这一说法,拜物教的市场意识形态概念将拜物教定义为一种认识论缺陷的市场观点,代理人从事物对他们的表现方式中推断,并导致他们复制市场并巩固阶级统治(Cohen, 2000, 115, Geras, 1971, 78-79, Celikates, 2016, 14;另见Haslanger,例如,2017c)。 然而,罗伯茨也对进一步理论化拜物教感兴趣,他明确表示,他认为马克思在这一点上是正确的:拜物教关注社会现实,因为它是由“交换的社会实践”构建的(2017,88n133)。我同意上面的建议。事实上,这一点在有关拜物教的文献中被广泛接受。分析马克思主义者自己也同意,坚持认为,正如我们上面看到的,拜物教是“像海市蜃楼”,因为外部世界本身是误导的(Cohen, 2000, 115;另见Elster, 1986, 56和177;Geras, 1971, 78-9)。然而,这使得分析马克思主义者的解释容易受到罗伯茨的反对。回想一下,在他们的“理论”阅读中,拜物教核心的意识形态观点未能提醒代理人注意商品的一部分(即它们的社会方面),这不仅仅是由于忽略了它,而是由于包含了商品所不是的东西(即它们所谓的自然方面)。因此,对持这种观点的人来说,商品并不表现为它们的本来面目:它们表现为自然的商品,而实际上,它们是通过社会建构而成为商品的。因此,分析马克思主义者对市场意识形态概念的理论解读容易受到第一种反对意见的影响。第二个反对意见也是如此,即争论中的意识形态观点是无关紧要的,因为拜物教最好被理解为与社会活动有关,而不是理论理解。这个反对意见是由里普斯坦提出的,他坚持反对科恩和市场意识形态概念的古典支持者,他认为拜物教“是与实际参与世界有关的失败”,而不是与“知识的美德”有关,因为活动和理解是与世界接触的不同模式,拜物教是关于活动,而不是理解(里普斯坦,1987,743)。和上面的罗伯茨一样,里普斯坦不仅认为这是马克思的主张,而且还坚持认为马克思是正确的。因为他认为,主要关注理论理解而不是社会活动,是在冒险关注人们在市场中的“知识有多渊博或容易出错”,而损害了这样一个事实:“一个人的活动完全由(市场)塑造,就会被(市场)奴役……”(1987,743和747)。我同意里普斯坦和马克思的主要实践取向是至关重要的。拜物教的概念应该帮助我们关注市场中的结构性支配,正如里普斯坦所相信的那样,它可以将我们的注意力吸引到现象本身,或者提醒我们注意其意识形态再生产的确切运作,我认为在这个阶段会更有用。我也同意,在对拜物教的市场意识形态概念进行“理论”解释时,忽视这种实际困境的风险是真实存在的。分析马克思主义者证明了这一点。例如,埃尔斯特总结道,“[拜物教]是一种来自市场交易的认知错觉,而不是市场的道德可悲特征”(1986,58,我的重点)。同样地,科恩陷入了关于劳动价值论的理论争论中,他只提供了一个“对马克思(关于拜物教)观点的解释而不辩护”(2000年,第十二章,他的重点)。因此,我们不应该以拜物教来关注理论认识,以免忽视社会活动及其当前的困境。这就是说,分析马克思主义者关于拜物教的概念受到第二个反对意见的影响,正如它受到第一个反对意见的影响一样。我与罗伯茨和里普斯坦的结论是,拜物教不应该被视为市场的意识形态,如果意识形态被理解为分析马克思主义者的理解,也就是说,理论上的理解。如果意识形态被实际地理解,事情就不同了,正如我在下一节所论证的那样。对意识形态的“实践”理解最近在女权主义和反种族主义研究中变得有影响力,这在很大程度上要归功于Sally Haslanger (e.g. 2017c)的努力。在本节中,我将其与市场相适应,以提供对拜物教的市场意识形态概念的解释,从而避免在前一节中遇到的两个反对意见。我们在上面看到,根据分析马克思主义者的观点,拜物教核心的意识形态观点在认识论上是有缺陷的,不仅因为遗漏了商品的一部分(即它们的社会方面),而且还因为包含了商品不是的东西(即它们所谓的自然方面),我认为这是一种与世界接触的理论模式的标志。相比之下,在哈斯兰格等人提出的意识形态概念中,意识形态更具有“实践性”。 作为对性别和种族的批判理论和社会建构主义解释的一部分(例如,见Haslanger, 2012),这一概念提供了一种意识形态的解释,即在主体被社会化的情况下,意识形态是主导实践的模式,其中社会化被理解为主体从环境中学习的过程,他们经常使用这些环境中制定的实践模式(Haslanger, 2017b;参见Celikates, 2016)。虽然哈斯兰格并没有将这种解释具体应用于资本主义和阶级主义问题,但它可以有效地为拜物教的市场意识形态概念服务。从这个角度来看,商品拜物教可以被理解为一种市场模式,只要代理人被社会化了。根据哈斯兰格所依赖的广义的布尔迪厄社会化解释,这表明,迷恋市场就是不断地将商品图式应用于事物,因为在这种环境中,事物“实现”或“融入”了这种图式,因此反过来“教导”或“灌输”了这种图式(Sewell, 1992,12 - 13,引用于哈斯兰格,2017c, 22;参见Einspahr, 2010和Bourdieu, 1977)。4 .重要的是,在这方面,社会化旨在帮助代理人制定社会实践,被理解为“协调或访问问题的集体解决方案”(Haslanger, 2016, 126)。这意味着,这些实践的模式主要是为了帮助代理人解决集体问题,往往侧重于在这方面有用的方面,而损害其他不太直接相关的方面(参见Torrance, 1995,45 - 47)。鉴于此,商品图式可以被理解为事物完全是商品的图式,而不是它们自然是(或不是)商品的图式,后者不在以谋生为目标的行动者的直接关注范围之内。换句话说,根据哈斯兰格对意识形态的解释,商品图式在认识论上是错误的,不是因为它包含了商品所不包含的东西,就像分析马克思主义者认为的那样,而是因为遗漏了商品是什么。正如哈斯兰格所说,它只是“忽略了”这样一个事实,即商品之所以如此,是因为我们参与了商品的商品化,这就是它如何“模糊了[s][它们]的社会维度”(哈斯兰格,2012,18和467;参见Celikates, 2016)。换句话说,它并没有像分析马克思主义者的解释那样,通过表现它们的(错误的)本体论地位,给它们一个更精致的外观:在这里,商品只是表现为,如果要转手,就必须支付其确切价值的东西,而不是表现为另外以这种或那种方式具有价值的东西。这一点是至关重要的,因为它使这种对拜物教的市场意识形态概念的替代解释能够逃避前一节的两个反对意见。回想一下,第一个反对意见是,商品图式在认识论上并不缺乏,因为事物对持有它的人来说是什么样子的(罗伯茨,2017)。如上所述,我同意罗伯茨和马克思的观点,即拜物教是关于市场对现实的社会建构:正如我们现在可以用哈斯兰格的话来说,市场上的事物“实现”或“整合”了商品图式,在这种程度上,对于持有这种图式的人来说,它们是什么样子的。但至关重要的是,我们不应该由此得出结论,商品图式不可能在认知上也有缺陷,因此也不可能在意识形态上有缺陷。在持有商品图式的人看来,商品确实是按其本来面目出现的,但这并不能由此得出商品是按其本来面目出现的。很可能的情况是,商品所表现出来的一切(即商品)对它们来说都是真实的,但这个图式仍然遗漏了一些关于它们的关键事实(即它们的社会维度)。换句话说,罗伯茨的反对意见适用于分析马克思主义的观点,正如我们上面看到的,但不适用于我刚才提供的另一种解释。对于那些对商品的“理论”观点未能通过包含商品所不存在的东西(即所谓的自然维度)来提醒他们商品是什么(即商品的社会维度)的代理人来说,商品并没有表现出它们的样子。但是,对于那些商品的“实践”图式在认识论上只是由于遗漏了商品的一部分(即它们的社会维度)而出现错误的代理人来说,商品确实表现为它们是什么(即作为商品),如果不是它们的一切。因此,与分析马克思主义的观点不同,另一种解释避开了第一个反对意见。罗伯茨的反对意见也是如此,即商品图式是无关紧要的,因为拜物教应该关注市场活动,而不是理论理解,否则就会忽视这种活动的结构主导特征。 然而,如果是这样的话,至关重要的是,我们还应该期望代理了解到,事物实现了一个图式,因为它们自己将图式融入了某些环境中的事物中,而不是其他环境中的事物中。毕竟,代理人是“有知识的”(Giddens, 1979,5;参见Celikates, 2006, Boltanski &amp;thsamuvenot, 2006),并且应该期望认识到,如果事物在不同的环境中实现不同的模式,这在很大程度上是因为它们自己对它们应用不同的模式。事实上,安东尼·吉登斯(Anthony Giddens)的“一个主要定理”是,“每个社会行动者都非常了解他或她所处的社会的再生产条件”(1979,5,重点移去;另见Scott, 1985, 319)。这一点在商品模式中表现得尤为明显。如果社会化是以这种方式分裂的,那么我们应该期望商品图式在人们与雇主或客户交换时被纳入到物品中,而不是在他们与邻居、朋友或家人交换时。正如格雷伯(2011)和科恩(2009)所坚持的那样,商品交换与原则上发生在邻居、朋友或家庭之间的那种交换有很大的不同。商品交换的模式不只是像邻居交换那样“得到多少就给多少”,而是“得到多少就给多少”,价格是这种数学等价的表达,通过将事物简化为可计数的单位而成为可能(格雷伯,2011,第5章)。这种差异在亲密的朋友和家人中更加明显。在那里,模式是“基本的共产主义”模式,“按需分配,按需分配”(格雷伯,同上;参见Cohen, 2009, 39-45)。因此,原则上,代理人与邻居、朋友或家人交换的东西并没有实现商品图式,而是实现了恩惠图式或礼物图式(视情况而定)。例如,当水管工免费修理亲戚的浴室时,他们的工作能力就不包含商品图式。它不是标准化的,而是个性化的,水管工的亲属不会收到账单。然而,至关重要的是,如果像我刚才所说的那样,代理人与邻居、朋友和家人交换的东西不像他们与雇主和客户交换的东西那样包含在商品图式中,那么,商品图式如何能忽略这样一个事实,即这些东西之所以是商品,主要是因为人们参与了它们的商品化,这就不清楚了。加芬克尔(Garfinkel)的名言(1984,75;另见Celikates, 2006, 30和Roberts, 2017, 95),如果事物在不同的环境中包含不同的模式,事物或环境之间的差异应该帮助他们意识到他们自己参与了合并。当一个水管工修理她邻居的厨房水槽,因为他以前照看过她的孩子,而她欠他一个,或者免费修理她父母的浴室时,她几乎不能不推断,如果她的工作能力在工作中是一种商品,那么部分原因是她通过将工作能力卖给雇主或客户以获得小时工资,从而参与了将其商品化的过程换句话说,我们应该期待她的商品模式包括这样一个事实,她的工作能力是一种商品在工作部分是因为自己和雇主,就像我们应该期待她的礼物包括模式和她的支持模式,分别的事实,她的工作能力是一个礼物在家庭milieux部分原因是因为它已经取得了她自己和她的父母,或它的交换作为友好的球体是由于一个忙,在很大程度上,感谢她和她的邻居们的努力。期望他们少一点,就不能公正地对待我们可以用吉登斯的话说,他们的“渗透”(1979,71 - 72)。如果社会化以这种碎片化的方式运作,那么,我们应该期待事物在雇主和客户之间实现商品图式,而在家人和朋友之间实现礼物图式,在邻居之间实现恩惠图式。但这反过来又表明,我们不应该期望代理人的商品图式局限于工作中事物是商品的事实,而忽略了一个进一步的事实:如果它们是商品,那主要是因为代理人自己在这种环境中参与了将它们商品化的过程。然而,如果是这样的话,那么就不清楚商品图式如何解释商品化如何在“生产和再生产[它]的社会行动者”背后“运作”,正如吉登斯所说(1979,71),从而阻止他们向更好的方向改变市场,从而巩固阶级统治。换句话说,拜物教的市场意识形态概念未能充分解释结构性支配在市场中的意识形态再生产。 为了挽救市场意识形态概念,我借鉴了市场支配概念:具体来说,是对市场支配的利润最大化逻辑的分析(Ripstein 1986, Roberts, 2017, Vrousalis, 2017)。我认为,这种逻辑使市场意识形态无处不在(见Sewell, 1992),它剥夺了代理人在环境之间的认知差异,这将帮助他们摆脱它,因此,解释了为什么商品化可能“在他们背后”发生。根据这种修正的解释,拜物教应该被理解为市场的普遍意识形态,它的普遍存在是由于所谓的市场统治在社会环境中的标准化效应。正如我们在上面看到的,拜物教的意识形态概念最近受到了罗伯茨(2017)的压力,这是基于里普斯坦(1987)之前的工作。我已经反驳了他们的上述反对意见。现在我想把重点放在我认为是他们提出的拜物教的市场支配概念的核心见解上。然而,这并不意味着对他们观点的认可,而仅仅是承认他们所关注的现象在分析拜物教中是最重要的,如果不是拜物教是什么的话。在市场统治概念上,拜物教是一种统治形式,它不同于阶级统治,即使它影响着阶级统治:它是工人和资本家由于市场竞争而遭受的非个人统治(见Roberts, 2017,88和Vrousalis, 2017,379)。正如罗伯茨所坚持的那样,“现代性的统治阶级,资本家阶级,和劳动阶级一样受制于非个人的统治”(2017,102)。Vrousalis同意这一观点:他写道,罗伯茨“资本主义(或非个人)统治不等同于阶级统治”是正确的(2017,379)。里普斯坦对此表示赞同:根据他的观点,这种统治的核心特征是“所有人的选择都受到市场的限制”,而不仅仅是工人相对于资本家的选择(1987,747)。这种非人格支配的完整定义是Roberts和Vrousalis之间一些争论的对象,他们不同意谁应该对它负责,以及它是否在某种意义上是任意的(见Roberts, 2017;Vrousalis, 2017)。但让我绕开这些分歧,把重点放在罗伯茨和弗鲁萨利斯以及里普斯坦都同意的事情上。这就是工人和资本家都受到利润最大化的支配。正如Vrousalis所坚持的那样,市场竞争从根本上影响了资产阶级对工人阶级的权力。没有竞争,每个资本家都可以充当工人的“绝对君主”,在他们提供的工资和要求他们做的事情上不受约束。但一旦他们面临(足够完美的)竞争,他们就不能再武断地决定工资,也不能再让工人随心所欲:在这一点上,“[每个]都受到限制,在竞争劣势的痛苦下,利润最大化,这反过来又需要支付[工人]市场清算工资”并剥削他们(2017,380 - 81)。罗伯茨对此表示赞同,他写道,例如,“受市场需求支配的资本家被迫剥削劳动力”,从定义上讲,剥削劳动力意味着赚取利润(2017,102)。里普斯坦也同意这一点,他强调工人“必须使自己具有市场价值,一旦被出卖,他的活动就必须满足雇主的任何要求”,并且“雇主的选择范围更广,但仍然有限:在破产的痛苦中,这种要求只能采取一种形式:生产有利可图的东西”(1987,748)。换句话说,所有恋物主义统治概念的支持者都同意,在一个重要方面,所讨论的统治在“受管制”的意义上是“非任意的”——实际上,受一条关键规则的管制:“利润最大化”(Vrousalis, 2017, 381)如果罗伯茨淡化了这方面,那只是为了强调这种支配在另一种意义上是武断的,即异想天开。因为这两个方面似乎是冲突的,正是在这种明显的冲突上,弗鲁萨里斯坚持,当他把这种统治定性为“非任意的”时。但这种冲突只是表面上的,因为它与统治是完全相容的,在这些意义上,每种观点都构成了拜物教,既任意又非任意。市场的走势可能很难预测,但与此同时,它仍然引导资本家(以及紧跟其后的工人)朝着一个明确的方向前进:即盈利。正如休厄尔所强调的,资本主义的特征恰恰是“长期的不稳定性或不可预测性”和“资本积累的持续动态[…]”(1992,25-26)。 现在,Vrousalis还坚持认为,与罗伯茨相反,这种统治的代理人不是“市场或市场命令”,而是“通过共同构成“个体资本家面临的外部强制性必需品”来相互统治的资本家”(2017,3,引用马克思,1976,381)。然而,在这里,我不进行这种辩论,因为它会使我们离题太远。相反,我关注的是他们都认同的利润最大化逻辑。因为它为前一节中确定的问题提供了解决方案。理由是这样的:如果资本家和工人被控制以实现利润最大化,那么他们就会被控制在工作场所之外,在竞争所需的许多环境中融入商品模式。这反过来又剥夺了他们对环境差异的认识,而环境差异可以帮助他们意识到,他们自己正在将商品图式融入到事物中,这就解释了为什么这个图式不能包括这个事实。正如休厄尔所强调的,“事物的商品化”是他之前提到的“资本积累的持续动态”和利润最大化的核心(1992,25)。在竞争劣势的痛苦下,资本家有强烈的动机确保尽可能多的商品商品化,因此,他们的工人也是如此。毕竟,只有商品才是“获利的机会”,而竞争要求资本家最大化利润。这就是为什么,用休厄尔的话来说,“事物的商品化”现在是“普遍的”,也就是说,“出现在相对广泛的制度领域、实践和话语中”(同上,25和22):“商品交换链”是“巨大的”,因为“商品形式[…]组织了一个几乎普遍的资源交集”(同上,26)。在这方面,马克思在《资本论》中对资本主义的第一次描述是“一个巨大的商品集合”(1976年,第1章),这并不奇怪。上面确定的统治将商品交换变成了一种实践,这种实践在某种程度上是普遍存在的。现在,休厄尔似乎把这种普遍性看作是商品模式是“异常可转位的”(1992,25)这一事实的结果,而不是里普斯坦、罗伯茨和弗鲁萨利斯所坚持的统治的利润最大化逻辑的结果。休厄尔没有提到统治,而是坚持认为商品图式本身“没有自然限制”,因为“它不仅可以应用于布料、烟草或烹饪锅,还可以应用于土地、家务、面包、性、广告、情感或知识[…]”(同上,25-26)。但在我看来,这似乎是错误的。特殊的可转置性并不是特殊的转置,一种推动力——正如麦金农所说(1982,540),“一种需要它的力量”——对于商品交换链的实际而不仅仅是虚拟的普遍性至关重要。这种驱动力是利润最大化逻辑的支配,它影响着市场上的资本家和他们的工人。因此,虽然资本家和工人可能试图保持他们与家人交换的东西基本上不商品化,但他们往往会将商品图式扩展到他们与朋友和邻居交换的东西。《管道连接》杂志在布拉德·法伦(2014)的一篇题为《与伴侣的交易费率》的文章中提供了一个很好的例子。法伦首先指出,“拥有贸易技能的人总是面临着老的‘配偶比率’困境”。他将这种两难处境描述为:“与客户在一起……我只需开出发票——干得好”;“然而,如果有一个压力很大的朋友、亲戚或邻居——无论是在街上、在学校还是在社交场合,我都经常见到的人——加入到这个场景中,我突然有了一种强烈的需求,想要成为一个非盈利的人,乐意把周末的时间花在‘免费’的紧急管道工上。”因此,他继续提供了“一些(他的)最有用的建议,以确保(拥有贸易技能的人)得到(他们)所做的工作应有的报酬”。这些建议可以分为两类:找借口和商品化,唯一的例外是家庭(“很明显,如果是你的岳母来敲门,把所有的规则都扔出去,直接免费做这件事”)。一个特别好的建议是,“在标准工作时间与(你的)一位员工预约这项工作”。正如法伦所强调的,这“改变了关系的动态,从个人的帮助回到了专业的管道服务”。其他的建议也是如此正如这个例子所表明的那样,资本家和他们的员工受到支配,将商品模式从工作场所扩展到竞争所需的尽可能多的环境——即使是与他们的朋友,如果不是与他们的岳母。15但这种结构性支配对社会化的标准化影响,至关重要的是,为影响拜物教的市场意识形态概念的问题提供了一个解决方案。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The market ideology conception of fetishism: An interpretation and defense

When Charles de Brosses first coined the term ‘fetishism’ in On the Worship of Fetish Gods (1760), it was in a rather misled attempt to demonstrate the immaturity of ‘primitive’ religious cults (de Brosses, 1760; see Iacono, 1992, 51). Yet a little more than a hundred years later, Marx had turned the concept into one of the most deep-probing tools which social philosophy can bring to the study of capitalism.

The German philosopher-cum-economist had noticed the way in which his European contemporaries would still sneer at the West African religious habit of treating social objects as ‘independent figures endowed with a life of their own’, and he realized he could turn the joke on them: they themselves did the same with their own ‘immense collection of commodities’ (Capital I, 165 and 125; see also Iacono, 1992, 79–80, Heinrich, 2012, 179–81 and Graeber, 2005).

The ‘joke’, importantly, was a rather pointed one, and has remained so to this day. Just as Marx hoped to spur his contemporaries out of capitalism, the contemporary literature uses the concept of commodity fetishism to mount a radical critique of the capitalist market. Two main conceptions can be distinguished. According to the first conception, the concept of commodity fetishism alerts us to a form of market ideology that plays a crucial role in the reproduction of market domination (Cohen, 2000; Elster, 1986). On the second conception, by contrast, commodity fetishism refers to market domination itself, understood as a form of structural domination with a specific profit-maximizing logic (Roberts, 2017, Vrousalis, 2017, Ripstein, 1987).

In recent years, mainly thanks to the efforts of Roberts (2017), drawing on Arthur Ripstein (1987), the market domination conception seems to have taken precedence. This is unfortunate, I believe. Granted, the market domination conception has the undeniable benefit of emphasizing the profit-maximizing logic that distinguishes market domination from other forms of structural domination. But at a time when the detrimental effects of this logic have become well-known, the concept can provide a better ‘basis for resistance’, as Sally Haslanger would put it (cf. 2020, 36), by focusing less on market domination itself than on the exact workings of its ideological reproduction.

In this paper, therefore, I attempt to go against the grain. As we will see, this requires developing an innovative theoretical framework for understanding ideology—one which not only adapts to the market the influential account which Haslanger and others have offered in relation to racism and sexism (2012, 2017c; see also Celikates, 2016, Einspahr, 2010), but which also refines this account by showing how acknowledging the influence which structural domination may have on ideology helps it solve an important problem.

The proponents of the market domination conception ground their claim that fetishism is not market ideology in two main objections. First, that while fetishism may involve certain representations, these are not ideological since they are not epistemically deficient, at least not by inclusion of falsehoods (Roberts, 2017). Second, that anyway we should understand fetishism as concerning activity in the market, not representations of the market, lest we lose sight of its practical significance (Ripstein, 1987).

My first step is to argue that the market ideology view can escape both, provided it departs from the ‘theoretical’ interpretation of the analytic Marxists (Cohen, 2000; Elster, 1986) and favors instead the more ‘practical’ understanding of ideology that we can find most prominently in Halslanger's work (2017c). On this understanding, ideology refers to cultural schemas which are liable to epistemic deficiency by omission of truths, rather than by inclusion of falsehood, because they are involved in, indeed, crucial to, social activity and its practical failings. The first feature rescues the market ideology conception from the first objection, and the second from the second.

In my view, however, the real problem with the market ideology conception lies elsewhere: that is, in its apparent inability to explain how market ideology can play its central role, namely contributing to the reproduction of market domination. This is because it is unclear why, unlike other forms of ideology, it should be expected to be widespread enough across social milieux to impair agents' ability to break free from it. Ideology, after all, is never total (Haslanger, 2017b; see also Geuss, 1981).

To solve this problem, I draw on the market domination conception of fetishism, and specifically on its analysis of the profit-maximizing logic of market domination (Ripstein, 1987, Roberts, 2017, Vrousalis, 2017). I argue that this logic makes market ideology pervasive (see Sewell, 1992), which deprives agents of the symbolic-material discrepancies between social milieux that would help them break free from market ideology.

Thus, on the interpretation I offer, fetishism should be understood as the pervasive ideology of the market, where its pervasiveness is due to what can be called the standardizing influence of market domination across social milieux.

This new interpretation clarifies one of the central mechanisms—indeed, perhaps the most fundamental mechanism—of the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market. As such, it provides a better basis for resistance to structural domination in the market than the market domination conception of fetishism, the analytic Marxists' interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism, and the influential conception of ideology we owe to Haslanger and others.

In the first section below, I focus on the market ideology conception, its analytic Marxist interpretation, and the two objections leveled against it by the proponents of the alternative, market domination conception. In Section 2, I build on Haslanger's influential account of ideology to offer a more ‘practical’ interpretation of the market ideology conception that escapes both objections. In Section 3, I turn to what I believe is the central problem with the market ideology conception of fetishism. Finally, in Section 4, I draw on the market domination conception to suggest a way to rescue the market ideology conception from this problem.

To set the scene, I begin with the relation between class domination, the market, and commodification. Then, I focus on the market ideology conception, its analytic Marxist interpretation, and the two objections.

Class domination refers to the situation of the worker who, forced to sell her labour power to some member of the capitalist class to make a living, finds herself unable to exit a relationship in which the relevant capitalist can get her to do more or less what she wants her to do for as long as she has bought her ability to work (see, for example, Gourevitch, 2018). Importantly, class domination depends on the market, which organizes the systematic transfer of resources from workers to capitalists that impairs the ability of the former not to work for some capitalist or other. As such, the market explains why there can be class domination without any legally or normatively sanctioned class distinctions (see, for example, Young, 1990, 47).

The market is a social practice of commodity production and exchange, that is, a collective solution to a coordination problem: the problem is for private producers to make a living in the absence of some form of central planning, and the solution the commodification process which generates market exchange and competition (Cohen, 2000; Roberts, 2017, for example, 78n97; Sewell, 1992; Vrousalis, 2017). Those who enact the market participate in commodifying things—from means of production to products to their own ability to produce—by repeatedly reducing them, by means of money and other measuring devices, to units which can be counted, added, compared, and converted into one another. This in turn enables and encourages them to produce and exchange things not as favors or as gifts, but as commodities, viz. in such a way that no one gives more than exactly what she gets (Graeber, 2001, 55–56 and 2011, 103–05, Sewell, 1992, 25–26, and Cohen, 2000, 416–23; see Ripstein, 1987, 736, Heinrich, 2012, chapter 3, and Marx, Capital I [1976], chapter 1).

Crucially, from the fact that things are commodities, not naturally, but because those who enact the market participate in commodifying them, we should not conclude that it is entirely up to those who enact the market whether to commodify or not: as Marx suggested, the commodification process tends to occur ‘behind their backs’, as an unintended result of their actions (Marx, 1976, chapter 1; see Sewell, 1992, 22 and 25). How exactly does this work? This, and its consequences for the entrenchment of structural domination in the market, is the focus of the market ideology conception of fetishism.

Ideology, on a broadly Marxist conception, has three related features: first, it entrenches structural domination, second, it is epistemically deficient, and third, it has a ‘tainted origin’ in structural domination (Geuss, 1981, 21; see Shelby, 2003, and Celikates, 2016). Indeed, ideology is often said to entrench structural domination because it is epistemically deficient, and to be epistemically deficient because agents learn it from dominating practices (see, for example, Haslanger, 2017a, Einspahr, 2010, Celikates, 2016). In line with this account, the market ideology conception of fetishism defines fetishism as an epistemically deficient view of the market, which agents infer from the way things appear to them, and which leads them to reproduce the market and entrench class domination (Cohen, 2000, 115, Geras, 1971, 78–79, Celikates, 2016, 14; see also Haslanger, for example, 2017c).1

The view in question is epistemically deficient insofar as it does not alert agents to the fact that the things they exchange with their employers and clients are commodities because they themselves participate in commodifying them (see Cohen, 2000, 116, Elster, 1986, 57; cf. Torrance, 1995, 165 and 112–20). This epistemically deficient view, however, is not like a ‘hallucination’ attributable entirely to a failure of perspicacity on the part of agents, but is rather ‘like a mirage’, insofar as the external world itself is misleading (Cohen, 2000, 115; see also Elster, 1986, 56 and 177, Geras, 1971, 78–9). In particular, the ‘foundation’ of exchange-value ‘in labouring activity is not [visible]’ (Cohen, 2000, 116). This epistemically deficient view, finally, explains why commodification occurs ‘behind the backs’ of agents, as an unintended results of their actions, and so why they fail to change the market for the better and entrench class domination as a result: agents will not even think of organizing production and exchange differently if they fail to realize that things are commodities because they themselves participate in commodifying them. Thus, as Cohen puts it, ‘[f]etishism protects capitalism’ (2000, 129).

This is the core of the market ideology conception of fetishism, and as such it is common to the two main interpretations of this conception: the dominant, analytic Marxists's interpretation put forward most famously by Gerald Cohen (2000) and Jon Elster (1986), and the socialization-based account which I will adapt from feminist and antiracist political theory in the next section (Haslanger, 2012, 2017c; see also Celikates, 2016, Einspahr, 2010). The difference between the two interpretations lies in the exact way in which the ideological view in question is epistemically deficient.

According to the analytic Marxists, this view is not epistemically deficient merely by omission of part of what commodities are, viz. their being commodities because agents participate in commodifying them, as it will be on my alternative interpretation. Rather, it is epistemically deficient by inclusion of something which commodities are not, viz. their being commodities ‘as an inherent property’, as a matter of ‘substance’, or, more generally, ‘naturally and inevitably’ (Elster, 1986, 57 and Cohen, 2000, 116 and 127, respectively). Thus on the analytic Marxist view, and in Cohen's words, there are ‘two phases in commodity fetishism: (1) separation of exchange-value from its material basis; (2) attachment of exchange-value to the substance of the commodity’ (2000, 117; cf. 116). On my alternative interpretation, by contrast, only the first phase obtains.

Insofar as including such ontological precisions as an account of the substance of commodities is the mark of a theoretical attitude, one on which agents flesh out their view of things beyond what is ‘practically necessary’ (Torrance, 1995, 48), we may say that for the analytic Marxists, the ideological view in question is a theoretical view. 2 On such a view, commodities are endowed with a natural dimension, where this means not only that their social dimension is stripped out from the way they appear, as it is on my alternative interpretation, but also that their appearance is more elaborate than it is on my alternative interpretation: to those who hold this view, commodities appear not just as things whose exact value must be paid if they are to change hands, but also as things which possess value by virtue of their physical properties, ‘just as they have weight’ (Elster, 1986, 57).3

This interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism has recently come under sustained pressure from the proponents of the market domination view of fetishism. William Roberts (2017), in particular, has built on Arthur Ripstein (1987) to argue that ‘[f]etishism ought to be understood as a form of domination rather than a form of false consciousness’ (2017, 85). I will describe the form of domination they have in mind in Section 4. Here, I focus on their central objections.

The first is Roberts's. As we saw above, to define fetishism as market ideology involves claiming that the view which agents infer from the way the things they exchange appear to them is epistemically deficient. But this view is not epistemically deficient, Roberts argues, since things appear as what they are to those who hold this view. As he puts it, the market ideology conception of fetishism ‘trips over Marx's explicit claim that, in fetishism, “the social relations between [the producers’] private labours appear as what they are”. Where social relations are mediated by commodities, exchanges are the real relations between the producers of commodities' (Roberts, 2017, 86–87, quoting Marx, Capital 1, 1976, 166, to which he adds the emphasis).

For those of us less interested in exegesis than Roberts, the fact that this was ‘Marx's explicit claim’ may not carry additional weight. Yet Roberts is also interested in theorizing fetishism further, and he makes it clear that he considers Marx to be right on this point: fetishism concerns social reality as it is constructed by ‘the social practice of exchange’ (2017, 88n133). I agree, as suggested above. In fact, this point is widely accepted in the literature on fetishism. The analytic Marxists themselves concur, insisting, as we saw above, that fetishism is ‘like a mirage’, insofar as the external world itself is misleading (Cohen, 2000, 115; see also Elster, 1986, 56 and 177, Geras, 1971, 78–9).

This, however, makes the analytic Marxists's interpretation vulnerable to Roberts's objection. On their ‘theoretical’ reading, recall, the ideological view at the heart of fetishism fails to alert agents to part of what commodities are (viz. their social aspect) not just by omission of it, but by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz. their purported natural aspect). To those who hold this view, therefore, commodities do not appear as what they are: they appear to be naturally commodities while, really, they are commodities by social construction. Thus the analytic Marxists' theoretical reading of the market ideology conception is vulnerable to the first objection.

The same goes for the second objection, viz. that the ideological view at issue is irrelevant since fetishism is best understood as concerning social activity rather than theoretical understanding. This objection is raised by Ripstein, who insists, against Cohen and the classical proponents of the market ideology conception, that fetishism ‘is the failing associated with practical involvement in the world’, not with ‘the virtue of knowledge’, because activity and understanding are distinct modes of engagement with the world, and fetishism is about activity, not understanding (Ripstein, 1987, 743).

Like Roberts above, not only does Ripstein take this to be Marx's claim, but he also insists that Marx was right. For to focus primarily on theoretical understanding rather than social activity, he suggests, is to risk concentrating on ‘how knowledgeable or error prone’ people are in the market, to the detriment of the fact that ‘[t]o have one's activities entirely shaped by [the market] is to be enslaved […]’ (1987, 743 and 747).

I agree that Ripstein's—and Marx's—primarily practical orientation is crucial. The concept of fetishism should help us focus on structural domination in the market, be it to draw our attention to the phenomenon itself, as Ripstein believes, or to alert us to the exact workings of its ideological reproduction, as I think would be more useful at this stage. I also agree that the risk of losing sight of this practical predicament is real on a ‘theoretical’ interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism. The analytic Marxists testify to this. Elster, for instance, concludes that ‘[fetishism] is a cognitive illusion arising from market transactions, not a morally deplorable feature of markets’ (1986, 58, my emphasis). Likewise, Cohen, mired in theoretical debates about the labour theory of value, offers only an ‘explanation without defence of Marx's views [on fetishism]’ (2000, xii, his emphasis). For fear of losing sight of social activity and its current predicament, therefore, we should not take fetishism to concern theoretical understanding. This is to say that the analytic Marxists' conception of fetishism falls prey to the second objection, as it did to the first.

I conclude, with Roberts and Ripstein, that fetishism should not be conceived as the ideology of the market if ideology is understood as the analytic Marxists understand it, that is, theoretically. Things are different if ideology is understood practically, as I argue in the next section.

The ‘practical’ understanding of ideology has recently become influential in feminist and antiracist studies, largely thanks to the efforts of Sally Haslanger (e.g. 2017c). In this section, I adapt it to the market, in order to offer an interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism which escapes the two objections encountered in the previous section.

We saw above that, according to the analytic Marxists, the ideological view at the heart of fetishism is epistemically deficient not merely by omission of part of what commodities are (viz., their social aspect), but also by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz., their purported natural aspect), which I suggested was the mark of a theoretical mode of engagement with the world.

By contrast, on the conception of ideology put forward by Haslanger and others, ideology is much more ‘practical’. Developed as part of a critico-theoretical, socio-constructivist account of gender and race (see, for example, Haslanger, 2012), this conception offers an account of ideology as the schemas of dominating practices insofar as agents are socialized into them, where socialization is understood as the process through which agents learn from the milieux they frequent the schemas of the practices enacted in these milieux (Haslanger, 2017b; see also Celikates, 2016).

While Haslanger does not apply this account to specifically capitalist and classist issues, it can be fruitfully put to the service of the market ideology conception of fetishism. Seen in this light, commodity fetishism can be understood as a schema of the market insofar as agents are socialized into it. According to the broadly Bourdieusian account of socialization Haslanger relies on, this suggests that to fetishise the market is to keep applying the commodity schema to things, because in this milieu things ‘actualise’ or ‘incorporate’ this schema, and so ‘teach’ or ‘inculcate’ it in turn (Sewell, 1992, 12–13, quoted in Haslanger, 2017c, 22; see also Einspahr, 2010, and Bourdieu, 1977).4

Importantly, socialization is, on this account, oriented to helping agents enact social practices, understood as ‘collective solutions to coordination or access problems’ (Haslanger, 2016, 126). This means that the schemas of these practices, being geared primarily to helping agents solve collective problems, often focus on those aspects of things which are useful in this respect, to the detriment of other, less immediately relevant aspects (cf. Torrance, 1995, 45–47). Given this, the commodity schema can be understood as the schema that things are commodities full stop, not that they are commodities naturally (or not), this latter aspect falling outside the immediate concern of agents aiming to make a living.5

In other words, on the interpretation we can build from Haslanger's account of ideology, the commodity schema is epistemically mistaken not by inclusion of something which commodities are not, as it is for the analytic Marxists, but instead by omission of part of what commodities are. As Haslanger would put it, it only ‘leave[s] out’ the fact that commodities are such because we participate in commodifying them, and this is how it ‘obscure[s] [their] social dimension’ (Haslanger, 2012, 18 and 467; see also Celikates, 2016). In other words, it does not give them a more elaborate appearance by representing their (mistaken) ontological status, as it does on the analytic Marxists' interpretation: here, commodities only appear as things whose exact value must be paid if they are to change hands, not as things which, in addition, have their value in this way or that.

This point is crucial, because it enables this alternative interpretation of the market ideology conception of fetishism to escape the two objections from the previous section.

The first objection, recall, was that the commodity schema is not epistemically deficient, since things appear as what they are to those who hold it (Roberts, 2017). As noted above, I agree with Roberts—and Marx—that fetishism is about the social construction of reality by the market: as we may now say with Haslanger, things on the market ‘actualise’ or ‘incorporate’ the commodity schema, and to this extent appear as what they are to those who hold this schema.

But from this, crucially, we should not conclude that the commodity schema cannot be epistemically deficient as well, and, therefore, ideological as well. From the fact that commodities do appear as what they are to those who hold the commodity schema, it does not follow that they appear as everything that they are. It may well be the case that everything that commodities appear to be (viz., commodities) is true of them, but that the schema still leaves out some crucial fact about them (viz., their social dimension).

In other words, Roberts's objection applies to the analytic-Marxist view, as we saw above, but not to the alternative interpretation I just offered. To agents whose ‘theoretical’ view of commodities fails to alert them to part of what commodities are (viz. their social dimension) by inclusion of something which commodities are not (viz. their alleged natural dimension), commodities do not appear as what they are. But to agents whose ‘practical’ schema of commodities is epistemically mistaken only by omission of part of what commodities are (viz. their social dimension), commodities do appear as what they are (viz. as commodities), if not as everything that they are. Therefore, the alternative interpretation, unlike the analytic Marxist view, escapes the first objection.

The same goes for Roberts's objection, viz. that the commodity schema is irrelevant since fetishism should concern market activity rather than theoretical understanding, on pain of neglecting the structurally dominated character of this activity. As I wrote above, I agree with Ripstein that a focus on structural domination in the market is crucial. But I also hold that, unlike the analytic Marxists' interpretation, my alternative interpretation can focus on understanding without running the risk of losing sight of this practical failing.

Indeed, from the fact that fetishism should not concern theoretical understanding, it does not follow that fetishism cannot be about understanding at all. For even if fetishism is not about the kind of theoretical understanding the analytic Marxists focus on, it can be about the kind of practical understanding on which the alternative interpretation insists. Ripstein's distinction between activity and understanding is too stark: it misses the fact that activity involves understanding in the form of the schemas (e.g., the commodity schema) which enable agents to enact their various social practices (e.g., the market).

Put differently, from the fact that ‘all social life is essentially practical’ (Marx, Eighth Thesis on Feuerbach, quoted in Torrance, 1995, 45, original emphasis), we should not conclude with Ripstein that fetishism ‘is the failing associated with practical involvement in the world’ rather than with any kind of understanding (1987, 743). Instead, we should conclude with Torrance that ‘what people observe and how they experience and describe their surroundings depends on their purposes and the problems they face’ (Torrance, 1995, 45)—that is, more precisely, on the schemas which help them enact the social practices in which they participate and which, geared as they are to helping them solve collective problems, may fail to alert them to more than they strictly need to understand in order to do so (cf. Torrance, 1995, 47).6 The commodity schema is a case in point: as we saw above, it leaves out the social dimension of commodities, this otherwise crucial fact being of little immediate interest to agents focused on making a living. Thus, while it would indeed be a mistake to take fetishism to concern the kind of theoretical understanding which the analytic Marxists have in mind, the concept can be about the kind of practical understanding involved in social activity on which the alternative interpretation operates. Therefore, this interpretation escapes the second objection, as it escaped the first.

I conclude, contra Roberts and Ripstein, that fetishism can be understood as the ideology of the market, provided that ideology is understood practically rather than theoretically. The main problem with the market ideology conception of fetishism lies elsewhere, as I argue now.

The problem is the following: the market ideology conception of fetishism seems unable to explain how the commodity schema can play the central role which it is meant to play, viz. contributing to the reproduction of market domination. This is because it is unclear why it should be expected to be widespread enough across social milieux to impair agents' ability to break free from it, when, in general, ideologies should not be expected to be so widespread.

On the practical interpretation I offered above, it is agents' socialization into ideology, understood as the process through which they learn ideology from the social milieux in which it is embodied, that explains ideology's domination-reproducing effect. But as is widely recognized, including by Haslanger herself (2017b; see also Celikates, 2016 and Geuss, 1981), ideology is never total. In the case at hand, things should be expected to embody and teach the commodity schema with employers and clients, but the gift schema with friends or family, and the favor schema with neighbors. Given this fragmentation, it is unclear how agents can fail to correct their schema of commodities by learning that things are commodities at work because they are treated as such in this milieu but not in others—and, therefore, how they can find themselves in the grip of anything like an ideology of the market that has them participate in commodification ‘behind their back’ and so contribute to the reproduction of market domination.7

To make this argument in more detail, the first thing to emphasize is that agents are socialized into a multiplicity of social practices, some of which are not capitalist. As Haslanger insists, ‘[t]here are multiple reasons to avoid the idea that ideology [e.g., capitalist schemas] functions as a total system governing society as a whole’ (2017b, 161). Indeed, Robin Celikates emphasizes, we should bear in mind Raymond Geuss's famous claim that ‘a society of happy slaves, content with their chains […] is a nightmare, not a realistic view of a state of society which is at present possible’ (1981, 83–84, quoted in Celikates, 2016). In other words, we should expect ideological schemas to be actualised in things in some of the milieux which agents navigate, but not in others.

Yet if so, crucially, we should also expect agents to learn that things actualise a schema because they themselves incorporate it in things in some milieux but not in others. Agents are ‘knowledgeable’, after all (Giddens, 1979, 5; see also Celikates, 2006, Boltanski & Thévenot, 2006), and should be expected to realize that if things actualise different schemas in different milieux, it is largely because they themselves apply different schemas to them. Indeed, it is ‘a leading theorem’ of Anthony Giddens that ‘every social actor knows a great deal about the conditions of reproduction of the society of which he or she is a member’ (1979, 5, emphasis removed; see also Scott, 1985, 319).

This is particularly clear with the commodity schema. If socialization is fragmented in this way, we should expect the commodity schema to be incorporated in things when people exchange them with their employers or clients, but not when they exchange them with their neighbors, friends, or family. As Graeber (2011) and Cohen (2009) insist, commodity exchange is very different from the kind of exchange that in principle occurs between neighbors, friends, or family. The schema of commodity exchange is not just ‘give as good as you get’, as in neighborly exchange, but rather ‘give exactly as good as you get’, the price being the expression of this mathematical equivalence made possible by the reduction of things to countable units (Graeber, 2011, chapter 5). The discrepancy is even more striking with close friends and family. There, the schema is the ‘baseline communist’ one, ‘to each according to their needs and from each according to their means’ (Graeber, ibid.; cf. Cohen, 2009, 39–45). Thus, in principle, the things which agents exchange with neighbors, friends, or family do not actualise the commodity schema, but the favor schema or the gift schema (as the case may be). When plumbers fix the bathrooms of their relatives for free, for example, their ability to work does not incorporate the commodity schema. It is not standardized but personalized, and the plumbers' relatives are not presented with a bill.8

Yet, crucially, if, as I just argued, the things which agents exchange with their neighbors, friends, and family do not incorporate the commodity schema in the way that the things which they exchange with their employers and clients do, then it is unclear how the commodity schema can leave out the fact that these things are commodities largely because people participate in commodifying them. People, again, are not ‘judgmental dopes’, in Garfinkel's famous phrase (1984, 75; see also Celikates, 2006, 30 and Roberts, 2017, 95), and if things incorporate different schemas in different milieux, the discrepancies between things or milieux should help them realize that they themselves participate in the incorporating. When a plumber fixes her neighbor's kitchen sink because he previously babysat her children and she owes him one, or repairs her parents' bathroom for free, she can hardly fail to infer that if her ability to work is a commodity at work, it is partly because she participates in commodifying it by selling it to her employer or clients for an hourly wage.9 In other words, we should expect her commodity schema to include the fact that her ability to work is a commodity at work in part because of herself and her employer, just like we should expect her gift schema and her favor schema to include, respectively, the facts that her ability to work is a gift in family milieux partly because it has been made so by herself and her parents, or that its being exchanged as a favor in neighborly spheres is due, to a significant extent, to her and her neighbors' making it so. To expect any less of them would fail to do justice to what we can call, with Giddens, their ‘penetration’ (1979, 71–72).

If socialization works in this fragmented way, then, we should expect things to actualise the commodity schema with employers and clients, but the gift schema with family and friends and the favor schema with neighbors. But this suggests in turn that we should not expect agents' commodity schema to limit itself to the fact that at work things are commodities, omitting the further fact that, if they are so, it is largely because agents themselves participate in commodifying them in this milieu. If so, however, then it is unclear how the commodity schema can explain how commodification may ‘work “behind the backs” of the social actors who produce and reproduce [it]’, as Giddens would put it (1979, 71), and thus prevent them from changing the market for the better and from entrenching class domination as a result.10

Put differently, the market ideology conception of fetishism fails to adequately explain the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market.

To rescue the market ideology conception, I draw on the market domination conception: specifically, on its analysis of the profit-maximizing logic of market domination (Ripstein 1986, Roberts, 2017, Vrousalis, 2017). I argue that this logic makes market ideology pervasive (see Sewell, 1992), which deprives agents of the epistemic discrepancies between milieux that would help them break free from it and, therefore, explains why commodification may occur ‘behind their backs’. On this modified interpretation, fetishism should be understood as the pervasive ideology of the market, where its pervasiveness is due to what can be called the standardizing effect of market domination across social milieux.

As we saw above, the ideology conception of fetishism has recently come under pressure from Roberts (2017), building on previous work from Ripstein (1987). I have already pushed back against their objections above. Now I want to focus on what I take to be the central insight of the market domination conception of fetishism they offer. This is not meant to constitute an endorsement of their view, however, but merely an acknowledgement that the phenomenon they focus on is of the greatest importance in the analysis of fetishism, if not what fetishism is.

On the market domination conception, fetishism is a form of domination that is distinct from, even as it influences, class domination: it is the impersonal domination suffered by both workers and capitalists because of market competition (see Roberts, 2017, 88 and Vrousalis, 2017, 379). As Roberts insists, ‘the dominant class in modernity, the class of capitalists, is as subject to impersonal domination as are the laboring classes’ (2017, 102). Vrousalis agrees: Roberts, he writes, is right that ‘capitalist [or impersonal] domination is not equivalent to class domination’ (2017, 379). Ripstein concurs: according to him, the central feature of this domination is that ‘the options of all are limited by the market’, not merely those of workers relative to capitalists (1987, 747).

The complete definition of this impersonal domination is the object of some debate between Roberts and Vrousalis, who disagree as to who is to be held responsible for it, and whether it is arbitrary in some sense (see Roberts, 2017; Vrousalis, 2017). But let me bypass these disagreements to focus on what both Roberts and Vrousalis agree on, and Ripstein as well. This is that both workers and capitalists are dominated into maximizing profit. As Vrousalis insists, market competition affects radically the power of the capitalist class over the working class. Without competition, each capitalist can act as an ‘absolute monarch’ over their workers, unconstrained in the wage they offer and in what they ask them to do. But as soon as they face (perfect-enough) competition, they can no longer determine wages arbitrarily, or have workers do whatever takes their fancy: at this point ‘[each] is constrained, on pain of competitive disadvantage, to maximise profit, which in turn requires paying [workers] a market-clearing wage’ and exploiting them (2017, 380–81). Roberts concurs, writing for instance that ‘[t]he capitalist, dominated by market imperatives, is compelled thereby to exploit labor’, which by definition entails making a profit (2017, 102). Ripstein agrees as well, emphasizing both that the worker ‘must make himself marketable and once sold, direct his activity to whatever his employer demands’, and that ‘[t]he employer's options are broader but still limited: On pain of bankruptcy, this demand can only take a single form: produce what is profitable’ (1987, 748).

In other words, all the proponents of the domination conception of fetishism agree that in an important respect the domination at issue is ‘non-arbitrary’ in the sense of ‘regulated’—indeed, regulated by one key rule: ‘maximize profit’ (Vrousalis, 2017, 381).11 If Roberts downplays this aspect, it is only to emphasize that this domination is in another sense arbitrary, viz. whimsical. For the two aspects seem to clash, and it is on this apparent clash that Vrousalis insists when he characterizes this domination as ‘non-arbitrary’. But the clash is only apparent, as it is quite compatible for the domination that on each view constitutes fetishism to be both arbitrary and non-arbitrary in these senses. The market may have movements that are quite difficult to anticipate and, at the same time, still channel capitalists (and workers in their wake) in one definite direction: that of making profit. As Sewell emphasizes, what characterizes capitalism is precisely both a ‘chronic instability or unpredictability’ and ‘a continuous dynamic of capital accumulation […]’ (1992, 25–26).12

Now, Vrousalis also insists, against Roberts, that the agents of this domination are not ‘markets or market imperatives’, but ‘[c]apitalists who dominate each other by jointly constituting the ‘external coercive necessities confronting the individual capitalist’ (2017, 3, quoting Marx, 1976, 381). Here, I do not engage in this debate, however, for it would take us too far afield. Instead, I focus on the profit-maximizing logic that they all agree on. For it offers a solution to the problem identified in the previous section.

The reasoning is this: if capitalists and workers are dominated into maximizing profit, then they are dominated into incorporating the commodity schema beyond the workplace, in as many milieux as competition requires. This in turns deprives them of the discrepancies between milieux that could help them realize that they themselves are incorporating the commodity schema in things, which explains how this schema can fail to include this fact.

As Sewell emphasizes, ‘the commodification of things’ is at the core of the ‘continuous dynamic of capital accumulation’ and profit maximization we saw him mention earlier (1992, 25). Capitalists, on pain of competitive disadvantage, have a strong incentive to ensure that as many things are commodified as possible, and so, therefore, do their workers. Only commodities are ‘opportunities for profit’ after all, and competition requires capitalists to maximize profit. This is why, in Sewell's words again, ‘the commodification of things’ is now ‘pervasive’, that is, ‘present in a relatively wide range of institutional spheres, practices, and discourses’ (ibid., 25 and 22): the ‘chain of commodity exchange’ is ‘vast’, as ‘the commodity form […] organizes a virtually universal intersection of resources’ (ibid., 26). In this respect, it is no surprise that Marx's first description of capitalism in Capital is as ‘an immense collection of commodities’ (1976, chapter 1). The domination identified above turns commodity exchange into a practice that is pervasive in a way few practices are.13

Now, Sewell seems to take such pervasiveness to result from the fact that the commodity schema is ‘exceptionally transposable’ (1992, 25), rather than from the profit-maximizing logic of the domination which Ripstein, Roberts, and Vrousalis insist on. Sewell nowhere mentions domination, but instead insists that the commodity schema itself ‘knows no natural limits’ as ‘it can be applied not only to cloth, tobacco, or cooking pans, but to land, housework, bread, sex, advertising, emotions, or knowledge […]’ (ibid., 25–26). But this seems to me mistaken. Exceptional transposability is not exceptional transposition, and a motivating force—‘a force that requires it’, as MacKinnon puts it (1982, 540)—is crucial for the actual rather than merely virtual pervasiveness of the chain of commodity exchange. This motivating force is the domination with a profit-maximizing logic that affects both capitalists and their workers in the market.

Thus, while capitalists and workers might try to keep the things they exchange with their family largely uncommodified, they will often expand the commodity schema to the things they exchange with friends and neighbors. The magazine Plumbing Connection provides a telling example of this phenomenon in an article entitled ‘The Deal with Mates Rates’, by Brad Fallon (2014). Fallon begins by noting that ‘people with trade skills are always faced with the old ‘mates rates' dilemma’. He frames the dilemma as follows: ‘with a client […] I just roll off the invoice – job well done’; ‘however, add a stressed friend, relative or neighbour into the scenario – someone who I see all the time, whether in my street, at school, or socially – and suddenly, I have this overwhelming need to become the not-for-profit, happy to spend my weekend plumbing “for free” emergency plumber’. And so he goes on to offer ‘some of [his] most helpful tips for ensuring that [people with trade skills] are adequately paid for the work [they] do’. The tips can be grouped in two categories: making excuses, and commodifying, the only exception being the family (‘Obviously […], if it is your Mother-In-Law knocking on the door, throw all the rules out and do the job straight away for free’). One good tip, in particular, consists in ‘booking the job in during standard work hours with one of [your] staff members'. As Fallon emphasizes, this ‘change[s] the dynamic of the relationship back from a personal favour to a professional plumbing service’. Other tips go in the same direction.14 As this example illustrates, capitalists and their staff members are dominated into extending the commodity schema beyond the workplace to as many milieux as competition requires – even with their friends, if not with their mother-in-law.15

But this standardizing influence of structural domination on socialization, crucially, offers a solution to the problem affecting the market ideology conception of fetishism. The problem, recall, was that if things incorporate different schemas in different milieux, which they should do if socialization works in the fragmented way it is widely recognized to work in, then the discrepancies between these milieux should prompt agents to realize that they themselves participate in the incorporating, and to include this fact in their commodity schema. If our plumber fixes her neighbor's kitchen sink because the neighbor previously babysat her children and she owes him one, or her parents' bathroom for free, we should expect her schema of her ability to work in the workplace to tell her that it is partly commodified by herself and her employer. Brad Fallon is a case in point: he complains that ‘because I like to “help” my friends’, […] it feels wrong to charge them’ (2014). But the standardizing influence of structural domination offers a solution to this problem. For if the plumber, or any other market agent, is dominated in such a way that, with her neighbors or friends, she does not exchange her ability to work as a favor or as a gift but as a commodity, in just the same way as she does with her employer and customers, then the move from one milieu to the next will be so natural that it will blunt her critical consciousness: specifically, she will not realize that she herself is playing an important part in actualising the commodity schema in her ability to work, and her version of the schema will not include this fact. Fallon's version of the schema, because he has reflected on it, may be sufficiently critical, but he is an exception. Indeed, he insists, ‘most friends, neighbours and relatives […] don't actually want a discount or preferential treatment’. In fact, usually they do not even ask him ‘to discount [his] prices' (ibid.). Unlike him, they may well fetishise commodities.

More generally, I want to suggest the following explanation of the mirage at the heart of fetishism. If the commodity schema is incorporated not just in the things agents exchange with their employers and customers, but also in the things they exchange with their ‘friends, relatives or neighbours’, as Fallon puts it, then the schema they infer from the commodities they exchange with their employers and customers will leave out the fact that they themselves are partly responsible for the commodification of commodities. For when a schema is pervasive in this way, there are no hitches between the spheres of activity agents navigate, and they stop noticing that they are applying it themselves: as Sewell puts it, schemas that are incorporated in a relatively wide range of milieux tend to become ‘relatively unconscious, in the sense that they are taken-for-granted mental assumptions or modes of procedures that actors normally apply without being aware that they are applying them’ (1992, 22; see also 24 ff.). Agents in such a standardized environment are deprived of the prompts that could have helped them realize that they are following the standard, and end up doing so without thinking (cf. Graeber, 2005, 431).16 One might say that the commodity schema, in particular, is reflected back to them by so many things that they become ‘naturals’ relative to it, applying it ‘naturally’ to the things that reflect it, aware only that they are exchanging them as commodities, not that they are contributing to commodifying them as they do. Their critical consciousness is blunted, and this is why the commodification process occurs ‘behind their backs’, as an unintended result of their actions.

The commodity schema does not alert capitalists and workers to the fact that it is because they participate in commodifying them that the things they exchange are commodities, and it does not alert them to this fact because they participate in the incorporation of this schema in things without thinking. They do this, in turn, because they are dominated into incorporating this schema in things, not just in the workplace, but pervasively, for instance in friendly reunions and neighborly encounters, if not in family settings. In other words, the impersonal domination at issue deprives them of the standpoints from which to realize that they are participating in the construction of social reality in such a way that they entrench, in a vicious circle, their own domination (see Lahire, 2001; MacKinnon, 1982).17

Thus fetishism, or the ideology of the market understood in terms of socialization into the market, entrenches structural domination because structural domination, in the form of the impersonal domination Vrousalis, Roberts and Ripstein emphasize and of the class domination it affects, has a standardizing influence on agents' socialization.

Put differently, if the ideology of the market is understood to be both practical (against the theoretical interpretation of the market ideology conception) and rendered pervasive across social milieux by what I have called the standardizing influence of market domination (against the current interpretation of the practical conception of ideology), then the market ideology conception of fetishism can shed some new light on one of the key mechanisms of the ideological reproduction of structural domination in the market. This, I conclude, would provide us with a better ‘basis of resistance’, in Haslanger's phrase (2020, 36), than the market domination conception of fetishism, the analytic Marxist interpretation of the market ideology conception, and the influential account of ideology developed by Haslanger herself.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信