{"title":"捍卫民主:民主自卫的战斗性和普及性模式","authors":"Rune Møller Stahl, Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12639","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>With the electoral victories of authoritarian populists in a range of parliamentary democracies in recent years, there has been a growing unease with the ability of existing democratic institutions to keep such authoritarian threats under control. The election of authoritarian leaning figures in countries such as Hungary, Poland, Philippines, Brazil, Russia, and the United States has led many to doubt the capacity of the institutions of parliamentary democracy to protect themselves against democratic backsliding. This perceived inability for democratic self-defense has led to a resurgence of academic interest in the idea of <i>militant democracy</i> in recent years (Abts & Rummens, <span>2010</span>; Cappocia, <span>2013</span>; Kaltwasser, <span>2019</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Malkopoulou & Kirshner, <span>2019</span>; Müller, <span>2012</span>; Sajo, <span>2012</span>).</p><p>The concept of militant democracy was originally coined by the German-Jewish émigré and constitutional scholar Karl Loewenstein, who in two articles in <i>APSR</i> in 1937 sought to develop ways in which representative democracies could respond to the emergence of fascism. Loewenstein's argument was that free and equal political elections could open the path for a fascist dismantling of representative democracy via democratic means. Consequently, democracy had to become <i>militant</i> and safeguard itself by compromising with its foundational principles of freedom and equality by prohibiting extreme political parties and by curtailing the political rights of extremists (Loewenstein, <span>1937a, 1937b</span>). As such, it is not difficult to see why contemporary scholars want to revive Loewenstein's idea of militant democracy as a response to populism. The main threat to present-day democracies, many argue, does not stem from revolutionary movements, which seek to subvert democracy through insurrection (Runciman, <span>2018</span>, pp. 2–3; Levitsky & Ziblatt, <span>2018</span>, pp. 5–6), but rather from the gradual erosion of democratic norms and institutions by elected political leaders.</p><p>Contemporary political leaders such as Donald Trump in the United States, Victor Orban in Hungary, Silvio Berlusconi in Italy, Nicolás Maduro in Venezuela, Jaroslaw Kaczynski in Poland, Recep Erdogan in Turkey, and Vladimir Putin in Russia have all ascended to power via more or less legitimate electoral channels and have—to a varying degree—centralized power, dissolved institutional checks and balances, and rolled back political rights. Moreover, contemporary populists display an antipluralist, anti-institutional, and authoritarian interpretation of popular sovereignty, insofar as many populist leaders claim to be the true representative of the people, denying the political legitimacy of political opposition and constitutional limits to the executive (Finchelstein, <span>2017</span>; Müller, <span>2016a</span>; Rummens, 2017)<sup>1</sup>. Although militant democratic measures were developed to combat fascism in the 1930s, neo-militant models try to contain contemporary right-wing populism and prevent further democratic backsliding. Consequently, neo-militant democrats have developed institutional and juridical ways of limiting the political influence of elected populists and populist movements (Abts & Rummens, <span>2010</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Müller, <span>2012</span>; Tyulkina, <span>2015</span>). The remedy to right-wing populism from such neo-militant democrats often involves restricted access to the political sphere either in the form of party bans (Bourne, <span>2012</span>), restrictions on individual and political rights (Abts & Rummens, <span>2010</span>), increased electoral threshold, or the strengthening of independent institutions like constitutional courts (Mounk, <span>2018</span>, p. 257). In <i>How Democracies Die</i>, for example, Steven Levitsky and Daniel Ziblatt argue that the central historical and institutional precondition for the election of a populist such as Donald Trump was the demise of antimajoritarian, gatekeeping institutions and the removal of the “filtering role” of political parties in presidential nominations after the McGovern-Fraser Commission in 1971 recommended binding primary elections (Levitsky & Ziblatt, <span>2018</span>, pp. 48–52). Implied in their argument is that without the gatekeeping, antimajoritarian functions performed by the “smoke-filled room” (Levitsky & Ziblatt, <span>2018</span>, p. 41) of nonelected, unaccountable, elite officials, “the people” are free to, and will eventually, elect a demagogue like Trump. For Yascha Mounk (<span>2018</span>, pp. 257–259), the best way to contain a populist in office is to rely on constitutional courts as guardians of the constitution—a core feature of militant democracy.</p><p>In addition to his work on populism and the intellectual history of 20th century democratic ideas, Jan-Werner Müller has also been an important analyst of the nuances and problems of the militant democracy strategy in the postwar era (Müller, <span>2012, 2016b</span>). Faced with the recent rise of populism, Müller identifies a form of “soft militant democracy” as a response to the present authoritarian danger. He contrasts such “soft” version with “the ultimate ‘hard’ measure of banning a party or restricting rights to certain kinds of speech,” as the “soft” version merely “leaves a party in existence – but officially limit its possibilities for political participation, or de facto make life for the party difficult” (Müller, <span>2016b</span>, p. 259). As such, many intellectuals, who worry about the fate of liberal democracy, conceptualize one important source of liberal democracy's crisis as residing in extreme popular movements and populist parties, as an unreasoned and dissatisfied population, attracted to the dangerous political ideologies of right-wing populists, who promise the unrealistic restoration of an unbridled national sovereignty. The crisis of liberal democracy, in this line of thinking, emerges through choices and actions of an unbridled majority, and as such the remedy is to limit the popular access to the political sphere and count on antimajoritarian institutions like constitutional courts or legal obstacles like new party legislation to curb populist forces. These measures resemble the original militant democratic strategies developed by Loewenstein (<span>1937a, 1977b</span>). As such, to save liberal democracy, some critics of populism argue, the values of freedom and equality on which this regime is founded must be temporary suspended for certain political groups and demands (Abt & Rummens, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>This way of countering the potential authoritarian threats to democracy has some limitations. As such, we argue that the policy prescriptions and modes of analysis associated with both hard and soft versions of militant democracy can productively be supplemented with other, less antimajoritarian and elite-driven approaches to democratic self-defense. The problem with the modes of democratic self-defense inspired by militant democracy is twofold.</p><p>First, on a normative level, we will argue that the idea of defending democratic institutions by limiting popular participation and expression is questionable as its rests on a depoliticizing, elitist, and exclusionary understanding of politics, relying on handing power to unelected and potentially unaccountable technocrats or jurists. Second, on an empirical level, we will argue that a militant approach to democratic self-defense risks, on its own terms, being counterproductive, as the exclusion of certain popular demands by the political elites might only intensify the political narrative on which populists are already harvesting votes. Insofar as the militant model of democratic self-defense depends on creating a conflict between a popular majority and political elites such as representatives, judges, or other unelected magistrates, it risks backfiring by politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive.</p><p>To remedy these shortcomings, we propose a supplement to the militant democratic approach. Recognizing, as militant democrats point out, that existing institutions of parliamentary democracy have trouble dealing with authoritarian threats from within, we propose amending the militant model with a <i>popular</i> model of democratic self-defense. This popular understanding of democratic self-defense, drawing from both popular republican and socialist imaginaries, relies on institutional ways of <i>deepening</i>, rather than <i>restricting</i> democratic participation. Such a popular understanding of democratic self-defense involves not only an awareness of the dangers to democracy stemming from potentially authoritarian demagogues, but also to threats stemming from unaccountable economic elites, and to the inadequacy of liberal democracy to resist the translation of economic wealth into political power (McCormick, <span>2007</span>). Instead of relying predominantly on the potentially depoliticizing and exclusionary strategy of militant democracy as a remedy to the contemporary crisis of democracy, we propose an “anti-oligarchic” strategy, which reintroduces the idea of institutions of collective power in order to combat excessive elite domination. It is important to stress that actually existing political systems might utilize both militant and popular instruments in defense of their democratic constitution. Hence, a democratic polity might strengthen its constitutional court (a militant instrument) while simultaneously establishing a second chamber of “ordinary” citizens with certain veto powers (a popular instrument). In this article, though, we are mainly interested in the conceptual, normative, and political differences between militant and popular models of democratic self-defense <i>as models</i>, that is, the ways in which the different models rely on either restricting or increasing popular participation as a means to defend the democratic constitution.</p><p>In order to advance this argument, the article is structured the following way: We begin, first, by revisiting the classical and contemporary arguments for militant democracy as democratic self-defense. Second, by reconstructing the genealogy of liberal democracy, we argue that the depoliticizing strategy of militant democracy is not a last resort of a liberal democracy in crisis; instead, depoliticizing and exclusionary strategies are integral to liberal democracy, and as such, militant democracy does not represent a <i>perversion</i> of liberal democracy, but rather a <i>radicalization</i> of tendencies already rooted in the liberal tradition. Third, we outline the historical trajectories of an alternative mode of democratic self-defense through a historical engagement with institutional solutions in the republican and socialist tradition. Lastly, we argue how these insights might form the basis of a supplementary, popular model for the defense of democracy that in contrast to the militant model does not seek to restrict but rather expand popular participation in democratic processes.</p><p>Militant democracy is a broad term for different legal and political mechanisms employed to prevent political extremism to emerge in a constitutional state with a representative government. The core idea of militant democracy is that democracies, in order to protect themselves, might under certain circumstances restrict the rights and access to the political system for those who seek to undermine democracy (Müller, <span>2012, 2016b</span>). As noted above, some who deem populism an undemocratic, quasi-authoritarian political phenomena have turned to some version of militant democracy in order to contain the threat of populism (Müller, <span>2016b</span>; Abt & Rummens, 2010).</p><p>Loewenstein's classic account of militant democracy was formulated in two articles from 1937 in which he analyzes how democratic systems can counter the threat posed by fascist movements. As such, militant democracy is an attempt to counter a specific political problem that emerges in the 20th century along with the spread of representative government, mass politics, and universal suffrage: If democracy essentially consists of free elections, universal suffrage, and majoritarianism along with the freedom of speech, assembly, and press, then antidemocratic movements can use the democratic process to subdue democracy itself. As Nazi minister of propaganda Joseph Goebbels once observed, “it will always be one of the best jokes of democracy that it gives its deadly enemies the means to destroy it” (Goebbels in Fox & Nolte [<span>1995</span>, p. 1]). By upholding a naïve loyalty to the democratic principles of free and equal access to the political sphere, Loewenstein argues, “fascist exponents systematically discredit the democratic order and make it unworkable by paralyzing its functions until chaos reigns” (Loewenstein, <span>1937a</span>, p. 424). Through such “democratic fundamentalism,” democratic systems are effectively tolerating the “Trojan horse” of authoritarian movements using the democratic process of elections to subdue democracy (Loewenstein, <span>1937a</span>, p. 424). In order to fight fascism, democracy itself must instead become militant, meaning that “if democracy believes in the superiority of its absolute values over the opportunistic platitudes of fascism, it must live up to the demands of the hour, and every possible effort must be made to rescue it, even at the risk and cost of violating fundamental principles” (Loewenstein, <span>1937a</span>, p. 432). Such “every possible effort” involves a general constraining of democracy by banning subversive parties, heightening the electoral threshold, restricting freedom of the press in the form of criminalization of editorial subversive propaganda, restricting freedom of speech by prohibiting incitement to violence and hatred against particular groups of the population as well as prohibiting derogatory statements against democratic institutions, republican symbols, and high officials of the state (Loewenstein, <span>1937b</span>, pp. 651–652). As such, by applying this militant democratic legislation, democratic states have begun the “deliberate transformation of obsolete forms and rigid concepts into the instrumentalities of ‘disciplined’, or even—let us not shy away from the word—<i>‘authoritarian’ democracy</i>” (Loewenstein, <span>1937b</span>, p. 657, italics added). In short, militant democracy as a strategy of democratic self-defense involves—in classic formulation by Loewenstein—the transformation of the democratic ideal itself into a kind of political rule, which draws extensively upon the exclusionary strategies of the authoritarian ideologies, is to combat.</p><p>Contemporary neo-militant democrats have certainly moderated Loewenstein's original framework and shy away from authoritarian measures in order to make the restrictions on basic rights of political participation compatible with the fundamental principles of liberal democracy (Capoccia, <span>2013</span>, p. 219). Some neo-militant democrats distinguish between antidemocratic actions and antidemocratic ideas, and limit militant measures to the former and not latter (Bourne, <span>2012</span>, p. 209; Capoccia, <span>2005</span>, p. 57). Others argue that antidemocrats have other legitimate political interests, which make exclusion illegitimate as long as they do not violate the right to participation of other citizens (Kirshner, <span>2014</span>, pp. 40–41); yet others argue for a two-track strategy, where the threat of political exclusion increases as antidemocrats move closer to public offices and political power (Abt & Rummens, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>Militant democracy has to a large extent set the parameters of the debates around countering populism today. As such, we argue that normatively militant democracy is elitist in its conceptualization of the political <i>problem</i> it seeks to remedy—insofar as the major threat to the democratic order primarily, though not exclusively, emanates from the dissatisfaction of ordinary people—potentially exclusionary, and depoliticizing in its <i>responses</i> to this problem and potentially ineffective, if not counterproductive in its <i>results</i>. The last issue concerning the effectiveness of militant democratic instruments is indeed an empirical question, one that we cannot do full justice to in this article, although we will provide some exemplary discussion.</p><p>First, militant democracy is an elitist strategy, as the task of combating political extremism is assigned to elected politicians, bureaucrats, or unelected, antimajoritarian institutions. The problem is most often associated with mass politics, which is deemed potentially volatile and violent. As Malkopoulou and Norman (<span>2018</span>) have recently argued, militant democracy is “a fundamentally anti-participatory and elitist logic … of anti-extremist politics” (p. 444), which regards mass participation as a potential threat that political elites are to counter by restricting the public sphere, constraining the democratic system and disciplining its culture. As highlighted in an overview article by Jan-Werner Müller (<span>2016b</span>, p. 254), while some understand militant democracy as part of a “transitional constitutionalism,” where the new elites are normatively justified in using strong juridical measures to defend the new democratic constitution against its enemies, others argue for a more fundamental normative justification by which a political system, and its governing elite, can never allow antidemocratic forces to come to power. Whether one operates with context-specific or fundamental justifications of militant democracy, the heart of the matter is that democratic self-defense in the militant register is the task of political elites.</p><p>Second, militant democratic strategies of self-defense are exclusionary, and potentially depoliticizing. Instead of facing political opponents in open political struggle, hereby emphasizing the pluralistic, conflictual, and agonistic nature of democracy (Lefort, <span>1988</span>; Mouffe, <span>2013</span>), militant democracy depoliticizes conflict and transposes it from the realm of politics into the legal realm, where exclusionary means like party bans and restrictions on rights of speech and assembly are used in order to stifle political conflict. In short, although the alternative model of democratic self-defense that we develop below encourages political conflict by empowering the citizenry through different institutional means, the militant model discourages political conflict by complicating the access to the public sphere for certain groups.</p><p>Third, the strategy of militant democracy is not only elitist, and depoliticizing, but also potentially ineffective and counterproductive. Many commentators on contemporary populism argue that the primary rhetorical strategy of populists is to highlight a conflict between the “pure” and “uncorrupted” people and the “self-interested” and “deeply corrupted” elites (Finchelstein, <span>2017</span>; Mounk, <span>2018</span>, pp. 41–46; Müller, <span>2016a</span>, pp. 2–3, 103–104). By excluding certain parties from the political process as well as certain opinions from public debate, political elites might give further credibility to the “elite-versus-people”—narrative on which contemporary critics of liberal democracy are already mobilizing. It is obviously an empirical claim whether the use of militant democratic measures is responsible for creating political dissatisfaction. But, we argue, militant modes of self-defense posit a conflict between a popular majority against political elites, hereby potentially politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive.</p><p>Based on these arguments, we find there are good reasons to supplement militant democracy with different modalities of democratic self-defense, which avoids some of the pitfalls of militant democracy. Such supplements entail procedures that are citizen driven as well as open to legitimate contestation and political struggle. One might object that militant democracy is only an <i>extraordinary</i> mechanism and that the moment democracy's enemies are defeated, the <i>ordinary</i> politics of liberal democracy will continue with its non-exclusionary, open, and egalitarian political processes. This is, for example, the argument of Ruti Teitel (<span>2007</span>, p. 49), who argues that “militant constitutional democracy ought to be understood as belonging to transitional constitutionalism, associated with periods of political transformation that often demand closer judicial vigilance in the presence of fledging and often fragile democratic institutions; it may not be appropriate for mature liberal democracies.” Here, we disagree. As we shall argue below, we regard the elitist, exclusionary, and depoliticizing elements of militant democracy as a <i>radicalization</i> of already existing tenets of liberal democracy, not the temporary suspension of liberal democracy's core ideals. Hence, we agree with Jan-Werner Müller (<span>2011</span>) that democracy as it has been institutionalized in the postwar constitutional settlements is indeed a “constrained democracy,” hereby making postwar liberal democracy and militant democracy members of the same species rather than fundamentally different.</p><p>In order to demonstrate how militant democracy is not a deviation, but rather a radicalization of tendencies in the liberal tradition, we revisit below the historical origins of liberal democracy. While proponents of “liberal democracy” like to trace its roots back to John Locke and the early modern period, the concept is of a relative recent pedigree. Duncan Bell has recently shown how the term “liberal democracy” did not come into regular use until the interwar years in conjunction with an understanding of a growing threat to the liberal order and a dichotomy between liberalism and totalitarianism (Bell, <span>2014</span>). In this context, liberalism and democracy was increasingly tied together as not only connected, but mutually constitutive. This idea of liberal democracy, however, obfuscates the real political history, where liberalism and democracy, understood as broad-based popular sovereignty, have distinct histories, and have in most historical periods been in conflict.</p><p>Before the modern period, the term “democracy” was not principally used to specify a set of political institutions. Rather, democracy was defined as a type of social class rule, namely, the rule by the popular class—the poor—as opposed to the nobles or the propertied classes. In Aristotle's famous typology of state forms, “democracy” was defined by social class, rather than in institutional terms, as government in the interest of the poor (Aristotle, <span>1995</span>, III, v. 4 [1279B]). Indirectly, as the poor constituted a majority, democracy involved majority rule, but the social definition was nevertheless central. This equation of democracy as majority rule with the political power of the “Party of the Poor,” and hence with egalitarian policies, can be seen through Western history. Andreas Kalyvas describes how democracy until the 19th century was seen as the “politics of the assembled poor” (Kalyvas, <span>2019</span>, p. 539), finding the equation of democracy and the political power of the poor in figures from Xenophon to Thomas Aquinas, and Marsilius de Padua. This identification of democracy with the power of the poor reappears both with opponents of popular rule, such as the aristocratic republican Cicero (Wood, <span>2008</span>, p. 143), and with the early modern proponents of democratic constitutions, such as popular republicans in the North Italian City States (McCormick, <span>2011</span>) or the Levellers and Diggers of the English Civil War (Robertson, <span>2007</span>; Rees, <span>2016</span>).</p><p>The term “liberalism,” instead, was coined in the early 1800s, designating an ideologically centrist position on the constitutional question, in the spectrum between radical republican democrats and conservatives who defended absolutist monarchy: Liberals favored keeping monarchs, but curtailing their arbitrary power through constitutions (Fawcett, <span>2015</span>). The new ideology of liberalism is built on a century-old tradition of liberal thought, represented by thinkers such as Locke and Montesquieu who voiced a critique of monarchy without demanding a fully democratic-republican constitution (Domènech & Raventós, <span>2008</span>; Wood, <span>2008</span>). Liberal political thought of course changed in the course of the 19th and 20th century, with classical liberals being pressured into accepting universal suffrage by movements of workers, women, and other excluded groups (Therborn, <span>1977</span>). This gradual democratization of liberalism ended in the situation, where in the first decades of the 20th century it was possible to construct the idea of the eternal connection between liberalism and democracy that emerged in the interwar years. Despite this, however, some of liberalism's skepticism toward popular power remains. Paradoxically this can be seen in the liberal response to threats against liberal democracy itself. Here, defenders of liberal democracy, both in its militant and nonmilitant forms, have inherited a skepticism toward the popular masses that have survived the “democratization” of the liberal tradition.</p><p>The main problem of liberal theory, from this perspective, is that it has traditionally primarily been able to imagine threats against democracy as coming from either the state or the mob. David Held, for example, describes classical liberal democracy as essentially a form of “protective democracy” (Held, <span>2006</span>, p. 99). This protection means on the one hand using the state to protect life and property against the mob, and on the other hand using the division of power, rule of law, and (limited) representation to protect the individual against the state. Of special concern was what Alexis de Tocqueville called the “tyranny of the majority” (De Tocqueville, <span>2003</span>, p. 286), which followed from the introduction of representative government in the 18th and 19th century. This fear of the “tyranny of the majority” as a result of representative government is, as we have argued in the above, similar to the problem Loewenstein's militant democracy set out to solve a century later. With elected governments, the two dangers of the state and the mob could be combined by a poor majority using the power granted by general suffrage to confiscate property or tax away the wealth of the rich minority. When early advocates of what would become the liberal tradition like Madison or Montesquieu advocated for a mixed constitution, and opposed the notion of democracy, it was precisely in order to make sure that popular power was balanced with elements of elite rule. As Madison famously argued in federalist paper no. 10, “democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and contention; have ever been incompatible with personal security or the rights of property; and have in general been as short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths” (Madison et al., <span>1961</span>, p. 76). In short, Madison forcefully condenses the liberal fear of the people, insofar as he regards popular rule as volatile, unruly, and insecure as well as threatening to private property. For that reason, Madison argued in paper no. 63 that the defining characteristic of the American Constitution “lies <i>in the total exclusion of the people in their collective capacity</i>” (Madon et al., <span>1961</span>, p. 385). Instead, liberals like Madison proposed representative government and division of power as <i>explicitly</i> nondemocratic means of governing the polity and preventing “the tyranny of the majority.” John Stuart Mill, arguably one of the greatest proponents of inclusive government within 19th century liberalism, also used the term widely and advocated for limiting the democratic elements of the constitution and create institutions that should be “protecting minorities by admitting them to a substantial participation in political power” (Mill, <span>2008</span>, p. 302). In this way, proponents of liberalism envisioned protective institutions as necessary in order to protect individuals against the state, and protect executive state power against democracy, that is, the political power of the poor. This resulted in a set of antimajoritarian institutions, such as powerful political courts with appointed (elite) officers and constitutional limits to democracy.</p><p>One way to further demonstrate the relation between the elitist and depoliticizing strategy of militant democracy specifically and liberal democracy more generally is to note how liberal democrats interpreted the rise of the fascism in the first half of the 20th century. This gives us a good indicator of how liberal and militant democrats understand political problems and potential remedies alike. Interestingly, when liberal democracy was reinvented in the wake of the Second World War and the experiences of fascism, it was comparable forms of antimajoritarian institutions that were set up, as when liberals in the 18th and 19th centuries were trying to diminish the direct popular influence on their newly established constitutional states. The experiences of fascism were largely interpreted as a case of the excess of popular majority power, and the need was therefore to rein in democracy, creating a “disciplined democracy” (Müller, <span>2011</span>, p. 39). This development was especially prominent in the European context. Michael Wilkinson describes how in the postwar era “European elites attributed the collapse of interwar liberal democracy to over-politicization” and that the relationship between state and mass democracy therefore had to be “reconstituted through a process of internal depoliticization” (Wilkinson, <span>2021</span>, p. 74). What was different in the postwar period was that instead of conceptualizing these antimajoritarian institutions as limits to a popular majority appropriating private property, they were now construed as necessary safeguards for protecting democratic majorities against their own antidemocratic proclivities. Parallelly, even though the issue of minority protection was now cast in terms of protections for ethnic and minority rights, the type of institutional setup proposed to remedy these threats was to large extent similar to the antimajoritarian institutions that 19th-century liberals had envisioned for protection of the wealthy minorities (Moyn, <span>2018</span>).</p><p>This is interesting, because the interpretation that interwar fascism sprang from an excess of popular power hardly seems the only explanation—or even, as shall argue below, an especially convincing explanation. Similarly, although some commentators link the electoral success of contemporary populism to various pathologies within the citizenry (i.e., the emotional, short-sighted, and irrational nature of the “the people”), other researchers show how populism is essentially an elite phenomenon (Herman & Muldoon, <span>2018</span>; Mondon & Winter, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>If we trace Mussolini's rise as a political figure, we see a situation where elite actors play a far more central role than electoral victories. The emergence of the fascists as a political force merged out of the political and economic turbulence after WWI. Here, economic elites, especially landowners in the Po Valley, turned toward protofascists organizations for protection against a wave of labor organizing and unrest (Paxton, <span>2007</span>, pp. 73–86). When Mussolini was eventually appointed to prime minister, it was not as a product of a sweeping electoral victory, or the forceful seizure of power through the “march on Rome” as implied by fascist mythology, but rather through a series of deals with central actors in the economic and political establishment (Lyttelton, <span>2004</span>, p. 94). Figures such as Franco in Spain or Horthy in Hungary likewise emerged against, or in spite of, electoral majorities and popular power. The best case for the rise of a fascist leader through the ballot box is of course Hitler. But here as well, his actual ascension to state power was not a product of an outright electoral victory, but rather by backroom dealings with representatives of factions of the traditional elite, notably the military, landowners, and sections of industry (Kershaw, <span>2014</span>; Paxton, <span>2007</span>). As Levitsky and Ziblatt (<span>2018</span>, p. 15) argue, historically, political elites have often helped fascists and semi-authoritarians into power by striking a “devil's bargain,” thinking they could control such political actors while simultaneously achieving short-term electoral gains. Given these examples, one could as reasonably have drawn very different lessons from the rise of fascism than the ones prevalent among constitutional architects of the postwar era. Instead of “disciplining” the popular masses, and creating a set of expert-run, antimajoritarian institutions, one could as reasonably have argued for expanding democracy and creating a set of institutions to “discipline” economic and political elites. When this did not happen, we argue that it is because in the liberal imaginary, threats to constitutional governments primarily stem from an excess of popular power.</p><p>What happens if we assume that the liberal approach to protecting democracy is really elitist and potentially antidemocratic? Does it necessarily follow that these protections are dangerous and unwanted? Might it not be the case that in order for democracy to function, it needs non- or even antidemocratic protections? Must democracies turn militant or die?</p><p>We will argue that this is not the case. Rather there are alternative, prodemocratic, or popular ways of conceptualizing the defense against authoritarian threats that potentially avoid some of the shortcomings associated with militant democracy. Hence we want to offer a perspective that can supplement to the militant model. But this requires a change of perspective. The liberal perspective, as we have argued above, primarily sees threats as stemming from either the state or the mob, leading to solutions involving divisions of power and antimajoritarian (often elite-led) institutions. But historically, other political traditions have conceptualized the problem differently. We argue that we can find the intellectual resources for a democratic notion of political self-defense in the popular republican and the socialist tradition.<sup>3</sup> These traditions share the liberal skepticism toward state power and traditional hierarchies. But in contrast to liberalism, they identify the main threats to democracy as stemming from societal elites, rather than the masses. These perspectives on democratic self-defense can properly be understood as “anti-oligarchic” in nature, meaning that their main concern is defending democracy from being taken over by elites from within or outside of the state. This anti-oligarchic perspective aims to defend democracy in both direct and indirect ways. Directly, a popular, anti-oligarchic perspective aims to avoid unaccountable elites making devil's bargain with undemocratic forces in order to overturn democracy (as seen in Italy and Germany). Indirectly, a popular, anti-oligarchic perspective aims to drain away popular support for antidemocratic movements by keeping democracy more responsive to popular demands, less prone to elite takeover, and thus avoiding the sort of discontent that leads large numbers of people to turn toward antidemocratic movements. As Hannah Arendt argued already in <i>The Origins of Totalitarianism</i> (1951), a central precondition for tyrannical and totalitarian government is isolation and loneliness of individuals, as—in her vocabulary—these sentiments destroy the public realm of appearances and the distinctly political opportunity of acting in concert (Arendt, <span>1968</span>, pp. 474–475). For our purposes, Arendt's argument points to the dangers of the depoliticizing effects of militant democratic and antimajoritarian models of democratic self-defense. By restricting the political realm and excluding groups or questions from the political process, these attempts risk further strengthening the sort of political isolation and alienation that draw people to authoritarian movements. Instead, the popular model of democratic self-defense developed below relies on the institutionalization of collective power as the principal mechanism of self-defense—that is, to counter individual isolation by creating public spaces, where acting in concert becomes politically possible. In short, if contemporary antidemocratic sentiments gain support from a critique of liberal democracy as elitist and exclusionary, it might be counterproductive to confront such antidemocratic sentiments with further depoliticization, as entailed in the militant model. What we lay out below are not institutional blueprints for a popular model self-defense but attempts at drawing alternative theoretical groundings for democratic self-defense from two political traditions, which allow for a shift in perspective from the liberal understandings of democratic self-defense.</p><p>It is one thing to argue that different traditions of democratic self-defense exist, it is another, more demanding task to argue that republican and socialist models of self-defense—what we group together as <i>popular</i> models of self-defense—can offer a viable supplement to militant democratic instruments given the contemporary crisis of democracy and rising right-wing authoritarianism.</p><p>Table 1 summarizes the analysis by distinguishing between two ideal typical models of democratic self-defense—the liberal and popular model. We are well-aware that real-world polities might productively combine instruments from the two models, and that upholding a democratic constitution might require attention to antidemocratic movements <i>as well as</i> to oligarchic elites. What we are interested in here is the difference between the models <i>as models</i>, that is, at the general and abstract level. Other interventions in this debate could productively explore specific, combined approaches to context-specific situations. While the main ambitions and primary instruments of each of the three strategies of democratic self-defense are explained in our analysis above, we want to highlight in Table 2 how each strategy of self-defense confronts three major problems intimately related to the defense of democracy, namely: (1) the election of a dictator, (2) the defense of minority rights, and (3) corruption of the state by elected politicians and bureaucrats.</p><p>In order to exemplify the popular defenses against the different threats outlined here, we have in addition to the theoretical discussion below also added some reflections on the contrasting practical implementation of the models.</p><p>First, the three strategies differ in their approach to the potential threat of an election of a dictator. All three approaches agree on the possibility of such an election, as the free, equal, and open nature of the democratic system makes possible the election of a dictator or a “would-be autocrat” as Levitsky and Ziblatt coin the term. The liberal approach of militant democracy is predominantly <i>preemptive</i> in its approach, insofar as militant democrats seek to counter “would-be autocrats” by restricting political rights and liberties in order to repress potentially subversive movements <i>before</i> they gain widespread popular support. Contemporary critics of populism often combine this approach with a call for stronger courts and softer instruments such as increased civic education in order to curb the extremist inclinations of ordinary voters. As such, such strategies somewhat shy away from political conflict by employing preemptive instruments of restriction and education. In contrast, the popular models are more <i>reactive</i> in their responses to the potential election of a dictator. Popular republicanism has employed political trails and ostracism and the socialist tradition has developed electoral recall as mechanisms of superseding dictators, hence relying on institutions of collective power in which a political conflict can take place rather than suppressing conflict and transposing it into the realm of law like militant democrats propose.</p><p>Our claim when it comes to preventing the election of a dictator is not that popular instruments of democratic self-defense would necessarily be more effective in the short term, as the institutional innovations we put forward might very well fail in protecting democratic institutions, as could be the case of the institutions of militant democracy. We argue, however, that by building on democratic empowerment, popular instruments might fail in a more productive way. Whether successful or not, the proposals we put forward would strengthen, rather than limit popular participation. As such, the reconstructed popular model might not be more successful at curtailing the rise of illiberal authoritarianism in countries like Hungary or Poland. A potential campaign to recall Viktor Orban or other Fides elected officials in 2010 might have worked no better at curtailing his rise than the current “European militant democracy” (Larsen, <span>2021</span>). But the process of popular mobilization needed for such a campaign would have strengthened the potential for future challenges to the Fides regime, rather than giving Orban the role as defender of the popular will against unelected, foreign technocrats and jurists.</p><p>Second, the three strategies also agree that defending individual and minority rights is crucial for upholding a democratic regime. The reason to fear an election of an autocrat is among other things that individuals, groups, and minorities are at the mercy of such unlimited, sovereign power. Again, the liberal and popular models differ at the ideal typical level in their approach to this problem. Militant democracy is as argued above an offspring of what Müller has called a “self-disciplined democracy” (Müller, <span>2011</span>, p. 125), namely, the restricted elite democracy that grew out of the experiences with fascism after WWII. Such “self-disciplined” democracies have primarily relied on antimajoritarian institutions for protecting individual and minority rights like supreme courts, constitutional courts, heightened electoral thresholds, and party bans. The popular strategies of democratic self-defense in republicanism and socialism disagree with the argument that antimajoritarian institutions are effective to protect the rights and freedoms of individuals and minorities. Because such approaches view the main threat as coming from elites, oligarchs, and the rich, they view popular institutions—that is, the institutionalization of collective power—as the most efficient way to protect rights and freedoms. By having institutions like the people's tribunes or workers’ councils individuals and minorities can be protected. These two approaches also testify to the different conception of political rights employed by the liberal and popular models of democratic self-defense in the first place. Although the liberal model understands rights as strictly individual hereby establishing a host of antimajoritarian institutions in order to curb the potential danger of mass politics, both republican and socialist models of democratic self-defense understand rights as social and as developed (and protected) through collective action. Hence, individual citizens and minorities need institutions of collective action to safeguard their rights, not only an abstract constitutional matrix as in the liberal model.</p><p>In a similar vein, the ideas of popular Tribunes or class-specific political institutions might not in themselves be ironclad guarantees for minority protection. A tribunate can, as laid out by McCormick, represent the great majority out of power, in his terms members of the bottom 90% of the income distribution that have not held elected office (McCormick, <span>2006</span>). But it could also represent specific minorities who are un- or underrepresented in existing political frameworks, such as Dalits in India, Romas in East and central Europe, or residents without citizenship. The idea behind class-specific offices is to give marginalized minorities (or marginalized majority groups) direct access to independent power resources, rather than just right enforcement by courts and state elites. A controversial, contemporary case that illustrates the two models’ different approach to minority protection could be the potential decision by the U.S. Supreme Court to over Roe v. Wade (Liptak, <span>2022</span>). While the militant model expects antimajoritarian institutions like supreme or constitutional courts to be the best guardian of individual rights, the popular model views institutions of collective power as the best safeguards of minority rights. In the case of abortion rights, the establishment of a “tribune of Women” could grant the relevant “minority” certain veto powers in order to protect their rights.</p><p>The third problem, which both liberal and popular models of democratic self-defense confront, is how to challenge the corruption of the state—that is, the turning of the state institutions toward the personal ends of elected magistrates and unelected bureaucrats. The liberal model understands such corruption through the classic prism of the tyranny of the majority. As representative government and universal suffrage has introduced the masses into politics, the chief danger is the new form of tyranny practiced not by the singular tyrant, but the electoral majority, using the institutions of the state to their own enrichment on the expense of the commonwealth. As we have seen, this fear is integral to liberalism, as in the classical liberalism of 18th and 19th centuries, the fear was that the poor would threaten the property of the rich as well as their wealth through increased taxation. As argued by Duncan Bell, this fear of the poor was transformed into a fear of the people or the electoral majority, as 20th totalitarianism was interpreted through the liberal schema. Popular models of democratic self-defense, instead, conceptualize the potential corruption of the state as stemming not from the majority, but instead from oligarchs and elites extending their personal economic power into public institutions. Such approaches provide institutional mechanisms for combating oligarchic influence by making elites accountable and removable. One contemporary example of the popular model's attempt to prevent the threat of the corruption of the state might be the spread of sortition-based climate assemblies in European countries such as Ireland, France, Scotland, England, and Denmark. If we bracketed for moment the fact that such sortition-based climate assemblies are often created by the state as a symbolic act without much legislative power (Mulvad & Popp-Madsen, <span>2021</span>), such assemblies could be interpreted as a second (legislative or consultative) chamber consisting of ordinary, nonelite citizens charged with policy making on an issue, which political elites have not been able to confront. While the population at large in many European countries are in favor of a green transition and have to a certain degree voted accordingly, political elites have not responded with the conviction. Such inability to confront substantial threats to biodiversity has been discussed as a product of an inherent flaw of liberal democratic systems (Blühdorn, <span>2013</span>). From the perspective of the popular model of democratic self-defense, the central problem is that organized interests representing carbon-based parts of the capitalist class are able to complicate democratic decision-making regarding climate change (Klein, <span>2015</span>). The popular model's response to the inability and disinterest of the political elites, inspired by popular republicanism and the plebeian assemblies imbued with veto powers, is to advocate for the institutionalization of collective power—here exemplified in sortition-based assemblies—where ordinary citizens have the chance of preventing the capture of the common good by the special interests of the elites.</p><p>Our claim is not that the popular models provide <i>guarantees</i> against the undermining of democracy by a determined executive with consistent popular support over time (just as the liberal models provide no such guarantees, as have been demonstrated by recent events in Hungary or Poland). What we argue instead is that the popular model politicizes different forms of partisan cleavages. Militant modes of self-defense posit a conflict between a popular movement against political elites such as representatives, judges, or other unelected magistrates, potentially politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive. Alternatively, the popular models’ reliance of countermeasures based on institutionalized popular contestation will move the political struggle to other terrains, less favorable for such authoritarian populist agitation. Contemporary populists operate with an anti-institutional and anti-pluralist interpretation of popular sovereignty, which essentially leads to an anti-representative understanding of democracy—the populist leader knows what the “true people” wants, even though electoral results show something different (Müller, <span>2016a</span>). In contrast, the popular model rests on a plurality of institutional, representative, and delegatory mechanisms, run by the citizenry itself, making the populist rhetorical strategy of the corrupt elite versus pure, unified people difficult to sustain.</p><p>Recent years have seen almost unparalleled electoral success of predominantly right-wing populism across both the global North and global South. Such populist parties have enjoyed electoral success, and even election into political office, due to a deep-seated dissatisfaction with the political status quo, and the perceived inability of liberal democracy to tackle the political issues of the day. One response by critics of contemporary populism has been to revitalize the discussion of Loewenstein's idea of militant democracy, in which Loewenstein proposed the creation of a “constrained democracy,” in which political extremism would have difficulties to emerge, as uncontrollable popular passions were held in check by clever, depoliticizing institutional design meant to undermine parliamentary sovereignty (Müller, <span>2011</span>, pp. 146–150). The core concern of a militant democratic model of self-defense is that undemocratic movements and parties can use the free, equal, and open electoral process to undermine the democratic regime from within. Contemporary militant democrats, though, shy away from the quasi-authoritarian commitments of Loewenstein's original proposal, and often subscribe to what Jan-Werner Müller has called a “soft” version of militant democracy that instead of outright banning extreme parties seeks to limit their room of maneuver.</p><p>While we agree with the general conviction that democracy needs defense mechanisms against antidemocratic or authoritarian forces, we argue that the proposals put forward by militant democracy should not stand along but can be productively supplemented with instruments and institutions from what we call <i>popular</i> models of democratic self-defense, resources to which can be found in republican and socialist traditions. We argue that liberal models of democratic self-defense such as militant democracy are normatively <i>elitist</i>, and <i>exclusionary</i> and empirically potentially <i>ineffective</i> approaches to democratic self-defense. Moreover, such strategies are not momentary, extraordinary deviations from the ideal of liberal democracy in which they are exercised, but instead militant democracy radicalizes already existing commitments of liberal “constrained democracy,” including the fear of popular subjects and its individualizing solutions to problems of political extremism. However, because liberal models of democratic self-defense rely on elite institutions such as constitutional courts, representative bodies, and nonelected bureaucrats, they have a tendency to demobilize the populace and restrict popular participation. As such, they potentially weaken the long-term resilience of democracy. Instead, we argue that a popular model of self-defense can offer potential solutions on several levels.</p><p><i>First</i>, on the analytical level, the popular approach to democratic self-defense offers a different lens through which to view the issues of democratic backsliding, authoritarianism, and the populist resurgence. By conceptualizing the threats of authoritarian takeover as predominantly emanating from the elite, the popular model offers a broader array of potential answers to the defense of democracy. <i>Second</i>, on a political level, the popular model offers modalities of collective practices through the popular institutions that empower ordinary people rather than elites. This has the direct effect of strengthening the long-term resilience of democracy, and the indirect effect of not provoking the sort of populist backlash—the cleavage between “the elite” and “the people” that populists successfully campaign on—that reliance on elite institutions can have. As argued by Arendt in <i>The Origins of Totalitarianism</i>, for example, one central precondition for the success of totalitarianism was its ability to spellbound already isolated and atomized individuals. The popular model of democratic self-defense works to counter such atomized individualism by relying on the institutionalization of popular power as the <i>modus operandi</i> of combating political extremism. <i>Third</i>, on a normative level, the popular approach offers a model of democratic self-defense that is based on broadening rather than limiting channels of popular participation. As such, it is a form of democratic self-defense that offers a deepening rather than a restriction of political participation.</p><p>The article does not lay out a full program or institutional blueprint for the construction of a popular model of self-defense, and much work still needs to be done in order to transform these ideas into a functioning institutional setup. Instead, the article offers a shift in <i>perspective</i>, where threats to democracy are conceptualized as stemming not only from the popular masses, but also from political elites, wealthy oligarchs, “would-be autocrats,” and aspiring tyrants. In order to offer such a perspectival shift, we draw on resources from the nonliberal parts of the democratic tradition, namely, popular republican and socialist imaginaries. These traditions, unencumbered by the fear of popular politics integral to liberal modes of democratic self-defense, allow for a more democratically robust defense against threats to democratic institutions and individual rights. In these imaginaries, we discover concrete and historically tested institutional mechanisms—such as electoral recall, imperative mandate, sortition, political trails, and class-specific offices—that have placed the citizenry as such, and not just its representatives or nonelected elites, at the center stage of democratic self-defense.</p><p>Authoritarianism is certainly on rise across the West and around the globe. The timely and paramount question is: What to do about it? The core, normative conviction of the popular model of democratic self-defense that we have developed in this article is that the citizenry ought to have ways of <i>continually</i> testing the legitimacy and support of their elected political leaders. An election every fourth, fifth, or sixth year is simply too long of an interval, as this gives “would-be autocrats” and aspiring tyrants way too much time to cripple the courts, manipulate the electoral laws, gerrymander electoral districts, restrict minority rights, and change the constitution. The popular model of democratic self-defense, instead, provides institutional mechanism through which the citizenry can confront their political leaders <i>the moment</i> they begin to undermine the freedom of the polity. This does not imply, though, that if the popular model was in place, then “would-be autocrats” would never be successful in dismantling democracy. But it at least ensures that an <i>institutionalized political conflict</i> can arise on whether this or that change to the constitutional setup of the polity is legitimate or not. A noninstitutionalized mode of confronting tyrannical rulers would be that of revolution—John Locke's famous “appeal to heaven.” The popular model of democratic self-defense thus strikes a balance between an “overpoliticizing,” noninstitutionalized revolution as a mode of overthrowing tyrannical government and the depoliticized, bureaucratized attempt to preclude tyrannical government from emerging, as implied by militant democratic approaches. By having regular and constitutionally secured institutions of popular power and control, the popular model of self-defense is able to confront attacks on the democratic constitution continually and as they happen. This conceptual shift of perspective, we argue, can prove of vital importance to democratic forces in the coming times of political uncertainty.</p>","PeriodicalId":1,"journal":{"name":"Accounts of Chemical Research","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":16.4000,"publicationDate":"2022-06-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12639","citationCount":"2","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Defending democracy: Militant and popular models of democratic self-defense\",\"authors\":\"Rune Møller Stahl, Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12639\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>With the electoral victories of authoritarian populists in a range of parliamentary democracies in recent years, there has been a growing unease with the ability of existing democratic institutions to keep such authoritarian threats under control. The election of authoritarian leaning figures in countries such as Hungary, Poland, Philippines, Brazil, Russia, and the United States has led many to doubt the capacity of the institutions of parliamentary democracy to protect themselves against democratic backsliding. This perceived inability for democratic self-defense has led to a resurgence of academic interest in the idea of <i>militant democracy</i> in recent years (Abts & Rummens, <span>2010</span>; Cappocia, <span>2013</span>; Kaltwasser, <span>2019</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Malkopoulou & Kirshner, <span>2019</span>; Müller, <span>2012</span>; Sajo, <span>2012</span>).</p><p>The concept of militant democracy was originally coined by the German-Jewish émigré and constitutional scholar Karl Loewenstein, who in two articles in <i>APSR</i> in 1937 sought to develop ways in which representative democracies could respond to the emergence of fascism. Loewenstein's argument was that free and equal political elections could open the path for a fascist dismantling of representative democracy via democratic means. Consequently, democracy had to become <i>militant</i> and safeguard itself by compromising with its foundational principles of freedom and equality by prohibiting extreme political parties and by curtailing the political rights of extremists (Loewenstein, <span>1937a, 1937b</span>). As such, it is not difficult to see why contemporary scholars want to revive Loewenstein's idea of militant democracy as a response to populism. The main threat to present-day democracies, many argue, does not stem from revolutionary movements, which seek to subvert democracy through insurrection (Runciman, <span>2018</span>, pp. 2–3; Levitsky & Ziblatt, <span>2018</span>, pp. 5–6), but rather from the gradual erosion of democratic norms and institutions by elected political leaders.</p><p>Contemporary political leaders such as Donald Trump in the United States, Victor Orban in Hungary, Silvio Berlusconi in Italy, Nicolás Maduro in Venezuela, Jaroslaw Kaczynski in Poland, Recep Erdogan in Turkey, and Vladimir Putin in Russia have all ascended to power via more or less legitimate electoral channels and have—to a varying degree—centralized power, dissolved institutional checks and balances, and rolled back political rights. Moreover, contemporary populists display an antipluralist, anti-institutional, and authoritarian interpretation of popular sovereignty, insofar as many populist leaders claim to be the true representative of the people, denying the political legitimacy of political opposition and constitutional limits to the executive (Finchelstein, <span>2017</span>; Müller, <span>2016a</span>; Rummens, 2017)<sup>1</sup>. Although militant democratic measures were developed to combat fascism in the 1930s, neo-militant models try to contain contemporary right-wing populism and prevent further democratic backsliding. Consequently, neo-militant democrats have developed institutional and juridical ways of limiting the political influence of elected populists and populist movements (Abts & Rummens, <span>2010</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Müller, <span>2012</span>; Tyulkina, <span>2015</span>). The remedy to right-wing populism from such neo-militant democrats often involves restricted access to the political sphere either in the form of party bans (Bourne, <span>2012</span>), restrictions on individual and political rights (Abts & Rummens, <span>2010</span>), increased electoral threshold, or the strengthening of independent institutions like constitutional courts (Mounk, <span>2018</span>, p. 257). In <i>How Democracies Die</i>, for example, Steven Levitsky and Daniel Ziblatt argue that the central historical and institutional precondition for the election of a populist such as Donald Trump was the demise of antimajoritarian, gatekeeping institutions and the removal of the “filtering role” of political parties in presidential nominations after the McGovern-Fraser Commission in 1971 recommended binding primary elections (Levitsky & Ziblatt, <span>2018</span>, pp. 48–52). Implied in their argument is that without the gatekeeping, antimajoritarian functions performed by the “smoke-filled room” (Levitsky & Ziblatt, <span>2018</span>, p. 41) of nonelected, unaccountable, elite officials, “the people” are free to, and will eventually, elect a demagogue like Trump. For Yascha Mounk (<span>2018</span>, pp. 257–259), the best way to contain a populist in office is to rely on constitutional courts as guardians of the constitution—a core feature of militant democracy.</p><p>In addition to his work on populism and the intellectual history of 20th century democratic ideas, Jan-Werner Müller has also been an important analyst of the nuances and problems of the militant democracy strategy in the postwar era (Müller, <span>2012, 2016b</span>). Faced with the recent rise of populism, Müller identifies a form of “soft militant democracy” as a response to the present authoritarian danger. He contrasts such “soft” version with “the ultimate ‘hard’ measure of banning a party or restricting rights to certain kinds of speech,” as the “soft” version merely “leaves a party in existence – but officially limit its possibilities for political participation, or de facto make life for the party difficult” (Müller, <span>2016b</span>, p. 259). As such, many intellectuals, who worry about the fate of liberal democracy, conceptualize one important source of liberal democracy's crisis as residing in extreme popular movements and populist parties, as an unreasoned and dissatisfied population, attracted to the dangerous political ideologies of right-wing populists, who promise the unrealistic restoration of an unbridled national sovereignty. The crisis of liberal democracy, in this line of thinking, emerges through choices and actions of an unbridled majority, and as such the remedy is to limit the popular access to the political sphere and count on antimajoritarian institutions like constitutional courts or legal obstacles like new party legislation to curb populist forces. These measures resemble the original militant democratic strategies developed by Loewenstein (<span>1937a, 1977b</span>). As such, to save liberal democracy, some critics of populism argue, the values of freedom and equality on which this regime is founded must be temporary suspended for certain political groups and demands (Abt & Rummens, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>This way of countering the potential authoritarian threats to democracy has some limitations. As such, we argue that the policy prescriptions and modes of analysis associated with both hard and soft versions of militant democracy can productively be supplemented with other, less antimajoritarian and elite-driven approaches to democratic self-defense. The problem with the modes of democratic self-defense inspired by militant democracy is twofold.</p><p>First, on a normative level, we will argue that the idea of defending democratic institutions by limiting popular participation and expression is questionable as its rests on a depoliticizing, elitist, and exclusionary understanding of politics, relying on handing power to unelected and potentially unaccountable technocrats or jurists. Second, on an empirical level, we will argue that a militant approach to democratic self-defense risks, on its own terms, being counterproductive, as the exclusion of certain popular demands by the political elites might only intensify the political narrative on which populists are already harvesting votes. Insofar as the militant model of democratic self-defense depends on creating a conflict between a popular majority and political elites such as representatives, judges, or other unelected magistrates, it risks backfiring by politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive.</p><p>To remedy these shortcomings, we propose a supplement to the militant democratic approach. Recognizing, as militant democrats point out, that existing institutions of parliamentary democracy have trouble dealing with authoritarian threats from within, we propose amending the militant model with a <i>popular</i> model of democratic self-defense. This popular understanding of democratic self-defense, drawing from both popular republican and socialist imaginaries, relies on institutional ways of <i>deepening</i>, rather than <i>restricting</i> democratic participation. Such a popular understanding of democratic self-defense involves not only an awareness of the dangers to democracy stemming from potentially authoritarian demagogues, but also to threats stemming from unaccountable economic elites, and to the inadequacy of liberal democracy to resist the translation of economic wealth into political power (McCormick, <span>2007</span>). Instead of relying predominantly on the potentially depoliticizing and exclusionary strategy of militant democracy as a remedy to the contemporary crisis of democracy, we propose an “anti-oligarchic” strategy, which reintroduces the idea of institutions of collective power in order to combat excessive elite domination. It is important to stress that actually existing political systems might utilize both militant and popular instruments in defense of their democratic constitution. Hence, a democratic polity might strengthen its constitutional court (a militant instrument) while simultaneously establishing a second chamber of “ordinary” citizens with certain veto powers (a popular instrument). In this article, though, we are mainly interested in the conceptual, normative, and political differences between militant and popular models of democratic self-defense <i>as models</i>, that is, the ways in which the different models rely on either restricting or increasing popular participation as a means to defend the democratic constitution.</p><p>In order to advance this argument, the article is structured the following way: We begin, first, by revisiting the classical and contemporary arguments for militant democracy as democratic self-defense. Second, by reconstructing the genealogy of liberal democracy, we argue that the depoliticizing strategy of militant democracy is not a last resort of a liberal democracy in crisis; instead, depoliticizing and exclusionary strategies are integral to liberal democracy, and as such, militant democracy does not represent a <i>perversion</i> of liberal democracy, but rather a <i>radicalization</i> of tendencies already rooted in the liberal tradition. Third, we outline the historical trajectories of an alternative mode of democratic self-defense through a historical engagement with institutional solutions in the republican and socialist tradition. Lastly, we argue how these insights might form the basis of a supplementary, popular model for the defense of democracy that in contrast to the militant model does not seek to restrict but rather expand popular participation in democratic processes.</p><p>Militant democracy is a broad term for different legal and political mechanisms employed to prevent political extremism to emerge in a constitutional state with a representative government. The core idea of militant democracy is that democracies, in order to protect themselves, might under certain circumstances restrict the rights and access to the political system for those who seek to undermine democracy (Müller, <span>2012, 2016b</span>). As noted above, some who deem populism an undemocratic, quasi-authoritarian political phenomena have turned to some version of militant democracy in order to contain the threat of populism (Müller, <span>2016b</span>; Abt & Rummens, 2010).</p><p>Loewenstein's classic account of militant democracy was formulated in two articles from 1937 in which he analyzes how democratic systems can counter the threat posed by fascist movements. As such, militant democracy is an attempt to counter a specific political problem that emerges in the 20th century along with the spread of representative government, mass politics, and universal suffrage: If democracy essentially consists of free elections, universal suffrage, and majoritarianism along with the freedom of speech, assembly, and press, then antidemocratic movements can use the democratic process to subdue democracy itself. As Nazi minister of propaganda Joseph Goebbels once observed, “it will always be one of the best jokes of democracy that it gives its deadly enemies the means to destroy it” (Goebbels in Fox & Nolte [<span>1995</span>, p. 1]). By upholding a naïve loyalty to the democratic principles of free and equal access to the political sphere, Loewenstein argues, “fascist exponents systematically discredit the democratic order and make it unworkable by paralyzing its functions until chaos reigns” (Loewenstein, <span>1937a</span>, p. 424). Through such “democratic fundamentalism,” democratic systems are effectively tolerating the “Trojan horse” of authoritarian movements using the democratic process of elections to subdue democracy (Loewenstein, <span>1937a</span>, p. 424). In order to fight fascism, democracy itself must instead become militant, meaning that “if democracy believes in the superiority of its absolute values over the opportunistic platitudes of fascism, it must live up to the demands of the hour, and every possible effort must be made to rescue it, even at the risk and cost of violating fundamental principles” (Loewenstein, <span>1937a</span>, p. 432). Such “every possible effort” involves a general constraining of democracy by banning subversive parties, heightening the electoral threshold, restricting freedom of the press in the form of criminalization of editorial subversive propaganda, restricting freedom of speech by prohibiting incitement to violence and hatred against particular groups of the population as well as prohibiting derogatory statements against democratic institutions, republican symbols, and high officials of the state (Loewenstein, <span>1937b</span>, pp. 651–652). As such, by applying this militant democratic legislation, democratic states have begun the “deliberate transformation of obsolete forms and rigid concepts into the instrumentalities of ‘disciplined’, or even—let us not shy away from the word—<i>‘authoritarian’ democracy</i>” (Loewenstein, <span>1937b</span>, p. 657, italics added). In short, militant democracy as a strategy of democratic self-defense involves—in classic formulation by Loewenstein—the transformation of the democratic ideal itself into a kind of political rule, which draws extensively upon the exclusionary strategies of the authoritarian ideologies, is to combat.</p><p>Contemporary neo-militant democrats have certainly moderated Loewenstein's original framework and shy away from authoritarian measures in order to make the restrictions on basic rights of political participation compatible with the fundamental principles of liberal democracy (Capoccia, <span>2013</span>, p. 219). Some neo-militant democrats distinguish between antidemocratic actions and antidemocratic ideas, and limit militant measures to the former and not latter (Bourne, <span>2012</span>, p. 209; Capoccia, <span>2005</span>, p. 57). Others argue that antidemocrats have other legitimate political interests, which make exclusion illegitimate as long as they do not violate the right to participation of other citizens (Kirshner, <span>2014</span>, pp. 40–41); yet others argue for a two-track strategy, where the threat of political exclusion increases as antidemocrats move closer to public offices and political power (Abt & Rummens, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>Militant democracy has to a large extent set the parameters of the debates around countering populism today. As such, we argue that normatively militant democracy is elitist in its conceptualization of the political <i>problem</i> it seeks to remedy—insofar as the major threat to the democratic order primarily, though not exclusively, emanates from the dissatisfaction of ordinary people—potentially exclusionary, and depoliticizing in its <i>responses</i> to this problem and potentially ineffective, if not counterproductive in its <i>results</i>. The last issue concerning the effectiveness of militant democratic instruments is indeed an empirical question, one that we cannot do full justice to in this article, although we will provide some exemplary discussion.</p><p>First, militant democracy is an elitist strategy, as the task of combating political extremism is assigned to elected politicians, bureaucrats, or unelected, antimajoritarian institutions. The problem is most often associated with mass politics, which is deemed potentially volatile and violent. As Malkopoulou and Norman (<span>2018</span>) have recently argued, militant democracy is “a fundamentally anti-participatory and elitist logic … of anti-extremist politics” (p. 444), which regards mass participation as a potential threat that political elites are to counter by restricting the public sphere, constraining the democratic system and disciplining its culture. As highlighted in an overview article by Jan-Werner Müller (<span>2016b</span>, p. 254), while some understand militant democracy as part of a “transitional constitutionalism,” where the new elites are normatively justified in using strong juridical measures to defend the new democratic constitution against its enemies, others argue for a more fundamental normative justification by which a political system, and its governing elite, can never allow antidemocratic forces to come to power. Whether one operates with context-specific or fundamental justifications of militant democracy, the heart of the matter is that democratic self-defense in the militant register is the task of political elites.</p><p>Second, militant democratic strategies of self-defense are exclusionary, and potentially depoliticizing. Instead of facing political opponents in open political struggle, hereby emphasizing the pluralistic, conflictual, and agonistic nature of democracy (Lefort, <span>1988</span>; Mouffe, <span>2013</span>), militant democracy depoliticizes conflict and transposes it from the realm of politics into the legal realm, where exclusionary means like party bans and restrictions on rights of speech and assembly are used in order to stifle political conflict. In short, although the alternative model of democratic self-defense that we develop below encourages political conflict by empowering the citizenry through different institutional means, the militant model discourages political conflict by complicating the access to the public sphere for certain groups.</p><p>Third, the strategy of militant democracy is not only elitist, and depoliticizing, but also potentially ineffective and counterproductive. Many commentators on contemporary populism argue that the primary rhetorical strategy of populists is to highlight a conflict between the “pure” and “uncorrupted” people and the “self-interested” and “deeply corrupted” elites (Finchelstein, <span>2017</span>; Mounk, <span>2018</span>, pp. 41–46; Müller, <span>2016a</span>, pp. 2–3, 103–104). By excluding certain parties from the political process as well as certain opinions from public debate, political elites might give further credibility to the “elite-versus-people”—narrative on which contemporary critics of liberal democracy are already mobilizing. It is obviously an empirical claim whether the use of militant democratic measures is responsible for creating political dissatisfaction. But, we argue, militant modes of self-defense posit a conflict between a popular majority against political elites, hereby potentially politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive.</p><p>Based on these arguments, we find there are good reasons to supplement militant democracy with different modalities of democratic self-defense, which avoids some of the pitfalls of militant democracy. Such supplements entail procedures that are citizen driven as well as open to legitimate contestation and political struggle. One might object that militant democracy is only an <i>extraordinary</i> mechanism and that the moment democracy's enemies are defeated, the <i>ordinary</i> politics of liberal democracy will continue with its non-exclusionary, open, and egalitarian political processes. This is, for example, the argument of Ruti Teitel (<span>2007</span>, p. 49), who argues that “militant constitutional democracy ought to be understood as belonging to transitional constitutionalism, associated with periods of political transformation that often demand closer judicial vigilance in the presence of fledging and often fragile democratic institutions; it may not be appropriate for mature liberal democracies.” Here, we disagree. As we shall argue below, we regard the elitist, exclusionary, and depoliticizing elements of militant democracy as a <i>radicalization</i> of already existing tenets of liberal democracy, not the temporary suspension of liberal democracy's core ideals. Hence, we agree with Jan-Werner Müller (<span>2011</span>) that democracy as it has been institutionalized in the postwar constitutional settlements is indeed a “constrained democracy,” hereby making postwar liberal democracy and militant democracy members of the same species rather than fundamentally different.</p><p>In order to demonstrate how militant democracy is not a deviation, but rather a radicalization of tendencies in the liberal tradition, we revisit below the historical origins of liberal democracy. While proponents of “liberal democracy” like to trace its roots back to John Locke and the early modern period, the concept is of a relative recent pedigree. Duncan Bell has recently shown how the term “liberal democracy” did not come into regular use until the interwar years in conjunction with an understanding of a growing threat to the liberal order and a dichotomy between liberalism and totalitarianism (Bell, <span>2014</span>). In this context, liberalism and democracy was increasingly tied together as not only connected, but mutually constitutive. This idea of liberal democracy, however, obfuscates the real political history, where liberalism and democracy, understood as broad-based popular sovereignty, have distinct histories, and have in most historical periods been in conflict.</p><p>Before the modern period, the term “democracy” was not principally used to specify a set of political institutions. Rather, democracy was defined as a type of social class rule, namely, the rule by the popular class—the poor—as opposed to the nobles or the propertied classes. In Aristotle's famous typology of state forms, “democracy” was defined by social class, rather than in institutional terms, as government in the interest of the poor (Aristotle, <span>1995</span>, III, v. 4 [1279B]). Indirectly, as the poor constituted a majority, democracy involved majority rule, but the social definition was nevertheless central. This equation of democracy as majority rule with the political power of the “Party of the Poor,” and hence with egalitarian policies, can be seen through Western history. Andreas Kalyvas describes how democracy until the 19th century was seen as the “politics of the assembled poor” (Kalyvas, <span>2019</span>, p. 539), finding the equation of democracy and the political power of the poor in figures from Xenophon to Thomas Aquinas, and Marsilius de Padua. This identification of democracy with the power of the poor reappears both with opponents of popular rule, such as the aristocratic republican Cicero (Wood, <span>2008</span>, p. 143), and with the early modern proponents of democratic constitutions, such as popular republicans in the North Italian City States (McCormick, <span>2011</span>) or the Levellers and Diggers of the English Civil War (Robertson, <span>2007</span>; Rees, <span>2016</span>).</p><p>The term “liberalism,” instead, was coined in the early 1800s, designating an ideologically centrist position on the constitutional question, in the spectrum between radical republican democrats and conservatives who defended absolutist monarchy: Liberals favored keeping monarchs, but curtailing their arbitrary power through constitutions (Fawcett, <span>2015</span>). The new ideology of liberalism is built on a century-old tradition of liberal thought, represented by thinkers such as Locke and Montesquieu who voiced a critique of monarchy without demanding a fully democratic-republican constitution (Domènech & Raventós, <span>2008</span>; Wood, <span>2008</span>). Liberal political thought of course changed in the course of the 19th and 20th century, with classical liberals being pressured into accepting universal suffrage by movements of workers, women, and other excluded groups (Therborn, <span>1977</span>). This gradual democratization of liberalism ended in the situation, where in the first decades of the 20th century it was possible to construct the idea of the eternal connection between liberalism and democracy that emerged in the interwar years. Despite this, however, some of liberalism's skepticism toward popular power remains. Paradoxically this can be seen in the liberal response to threats against liberal democracy itself. Here, defenders of liberal democracy, both in its militant and nonmilitant forms, have inherited a skepticism toward the popular masses that have survived the “democratization” of the liberal tradition.</p><p>The main problem of liberal theory, from this perspective, is that it has traditionally primarily been able to imagine threats against democracy as coming from either the state or the mob. David Held, for example, describes classical liberal democracy as essentially a form of “protective democracy” (Held, <span>2006</span>, p. 99). This protection means on the one hand using the state to protect life and property against the mob, and on the other hand using the division of power, rule of law, and (limited) representation to protect the individual against the state. Of special concern was what Alexis de Tocqueville called the “tyranny of the majority” (De Tocqueville, <span>2003</span>, p. 286), which followed from the introduction of representative government in the 18th and 19th century. This fear of the “tyranny of the majority” as a result of representative government is, as we have argued in the above, similar to the problem Loewenstein's militant democracy set out to solve a century later. With elected governments, the two dangers of the state and the mob could be combined by a poor majority using the power granted by general suffrage to confiscate property or tax away the wealth of the rich minority. When early advocates of what would become the liberal tradition like Madison or Montesquieu advocated for a mixed constitution, and opposed the notion of democracy, it was precisely in order to make sure that popular power was balanced with elements of elite rule. As Madison famously argued in federalist paper no. 10, “democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and contention; have ever been incompatible with personal security or the rights of property; and have in general been as short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths” (Madison et al., <span>1961</span>, p. 76). In short, Madison forcefully condenses the liberal fear of the people, insofar as he regards popular rule as volatile, unruly, and insecure as well as threatening to private property. For that reason, Madison argued in paper no. 63 that the defining characteristic of the American Constitution “lies <i>in the total exclusion of the people in their collective capacity</i>” (Madon et al., <span>1961</span>, p. 385). Instead, liberals like Madison proposed representative government and division of power as <i>explicitly</i> nondemocratic means of governing the polity and preventing “the tyranny of the majority.” John Stuart Mill, arguably one of the greatest proponents of inclusive government within 19th century liberalism, also used the term widely and advocated for limiting the democratic elements of the constitution and create institutions that should be “protecting minorities by admitting them to a substantial participation in political power” (Mill, <span>2008</span>, p. 302). In this way, proponents of liberalism envisioned protective institutions as necessary in order to protect individuals against the state, and protect executive state power against democracy, that is, the political power of the poor. This resulted in a set of antimajoritarian institutions, such as powerful political courts with appointed (elite) officers and constitutional limits to democracy.</p><p>One way to further demonstrate the relation between the elitist and depoliticizing strategy of militant democracy specifically and liberal democracy more generally is to note how liberal democrats interpreted the rise of the fascism in the first half of the 20th century. This gives us a good indicator of how liberal and militant democrats understand political problems and potential remedies alike. Interestingly, when liberal democracy was reinvented in the wake of the Second World War and the experiences of fascism, it was comparable forms of antimajoritarian institutions that were set up, as when liberals in the 18th and 19th centuries were trying to diminish the direct popular influence on their newly established constitutional states. The experiences of fascism were largely interpreted as a case of the excess of popular majority power, and the need was therefore to rein in democracy, creating a “disciplined democracy” (Müller, <span>2011</span>, p. 39). This development was especially prominent in the European context. Michael Wilkinson describes how in the postwar era “European elites attributed the collapse of interwar liberal democracy to over-politicization” and that the relationship between state and mass democracy therefore had to be “reconstituted through a process of internal depoliticization” (Wilkinson, <span>2021</span>, p. 74). What was different in the postwar period was that instead of conceptualizing these antimajoritarian institutions as limits to a popular majority appropriating private property, they were now construed as necessary safeguards for protecting democratic majorities against their own antidemocratic proclivities. Parallelly, even though the issue of minority protection was now cast in terms of protections for ethnic and minority rights, the type of institutional setup proposed to remedy these threats was to large extent similar to the antimajoritarian institutions that 19th-century liberals had envisioned for protection of the wealthy minorities (Moyn, <span>2018</span>).</p><p>This is interesting, because the interpretation that interwar fascism sprang from an excess of popular power hardly seems the only explanation—or even, as shall argue below, an especially convincing explanation. Similarly, although some commentators link the electoral success of contemporary populism to various pathologies within the citizenry (i.e., the emotional, short-sighted, and irrational nature of the “the people”), other researchers show how populism is essentially an elite phenomenon (Herman & Muldoon, <span>2018</span>; Mondon & Winter, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>If we trace Mussolini's rise as a political figure, we see a situation where elite actors play a far more central role than electoral victories. The emergence of the fascists as a political force merged out of the political and economic turbulence after WWI. Here, economic elites, especially landowners in the Po Valley, turned toward protofascists organizations for protection against a wave of labor organizing and unrest (Paxton, <span>2007</span>, pp. 73–86). When Mussolini was eventually appointed to prime minister, it was not as a product of a sweeping electoral victory, or the forceful seizure of power through the “march on Rome” as implied by fascist mythology, but rather through a series of deals with central actors in the economic and political establishment (Lyttelton, <span>2004</span>, p. 94). Figures such as Franco in Spain or Horthy in Hungary likewise emerged against, or in spite of, electoral majorities and popular power. The best case for the rise of a fascist leader through the ballot box is of course Hitler. But here as well, his actual ascension to state power was not a product of an outright electoral victory, but rather by backroom dealings with representatives of factions of the traditional elite, notably the military, landowners, and sections of industry (Kershaw, <span>2014</span>; Paxton, <span>2007</span>). As Levitsky and Ziblatt (<span>2018</span>, p. 15) argue, historically, political elites have often helped fascists and semi-authoritarians into power by striking a “devil's bargain,” thinking they could control such political actors while simultaneously achieving short-term electoral gains. Given these examples, one could as reasonably have drawn very different lessons from the rise of fascism than the ones prevalent among constitutional architects of the postwar era. Instead of “disciplining” the popular masses, and creating a set of expert-run, antimajoritarian institutions, one could as reasonably have argued for expanding democracy and creating a set of institutions to “discipline” economic and political elites. When this did not happen, we argue that it is because in the liberal imaginary, threats to constitutional governments primarily stem from an excess of popular power.</p><p>What happens if we assume that the liberal approach to protecting democracy is really elitist and potentially antidemocratic? Does it necessarily follow that these protections are dangerous and unwanted? Might it not be the case that in order for democracy to function, it needs non- or even antidemocratic protections? Must democracies turn militant or die?</p><p>We will argue that this is not the case. Rather there are alternative, prodemocratic, or popular ways of conceptualizing the defense against authoritarian threats that potentially avoid some of the shortcomings associated with militant democracy. Hence we want to offer a perspective that can supplement to the militant model. But this requires a change of perspective. The liberal perspective, as we have argued above, primarily sees threats as stemming from either the state or the mob, leading to solutions involving divisions of power and antimajoritarian (often elite-led) institutions. But historically, other political traditions have conceptualized the problem differently. We argue that we can find the intellectual resources for a democratic notion of political self-defense in the popular republican and the socialist tradition.<sup>3</sup> These traditions share the liberal skepticism toward state power and traditional hierarchies. But in contrast to liberalism, they identify the main threats to democracy as stemming from societal elites, rather than the masses. These perspectives on democratic self-defense can properly be understood as “anti-oligarchic” in nature, meaning that their main concern is defending democracy from being taken over by elites from within or outside of the state. This anti-oligarchic perspective aims to defend democracy in both direct and indirect ways. Directly, a popular, anti-oligarchic perspective aims to avoid unaccountable elites making devil's bargain with undemocratic forces in order to overturn democracy (as seen in Italy and Germany). Indirectly, a popular, anti-oligarchic perspective aims to drain away popular support for antidemocratic movements by keeping democracy more responsive to popular demands, less prone to elite takeover, and thus avoiding the sort of discontent that leads large numbers of people to turn toward antidemocratic movements. As Hannah Arendt argued already in <i>The Origins of Totalitarianism</i> (1951), a central precondition for tyrannical and totalitarian government is isolation and loneliness of individuals, as—in her vocabulary—these sentiments destroy the public realm of appearances and the distinctly political opportunity of acting in concert (Arendt, <span>1968</span>, pp. 474–475). For our purposes, Arendt's argument points to the dangers of the depoliticizing effects of militant democratic and antimajoritarian models of democratic self-defense. By restricting the political realm and excluding groups or questions from the political process, these attempts risk further strengthening the sort of political isolation and alienation that draw people to authoritarian movements. Instead, the popular model of democratic self-defense developed below relies on the institutionalization of collective power as the principal mechanism of self-defense—that is, to counter individual isolation by creating public spaces, where acting in concert becomes politically possible. In short, if contemporary antidemocratic sentiments gain support from a critique of liberal democracy as elitist and exclusionary, it might be counterproductive to confront such antidemocratic sentiments with further depoliticization, as entailed in the militant model. What we lay out below are not institutional blueprints for a popular model self-defense but attempts at drawing alternative theoretical groundings for democratic self-defense from two political traditions, which allow for a shift in perspective from the liberal understandings of democratic self-defense.</p><p>It is one thing to argue that different traditions of democratic self-defense exist, it is another, more demanding task to argue that republican and socialist models of self-defense—what we group together as <i>popular</i> models of self-defense—can offer a viable supplement to militant democratic instruments given the contemporary crisis of democracy and rising right-wing authoritarianism.</p><p>Table 1 summarizes the analysis by distinguishing between two ideal typical models of democratic self-defense—the liberal and popular model. We are well-aware that real-world polities might productively combine instruments from the two models, and that upholding a democratic constitution might require attention to antidemocratic movements <i>as well as</i> to oligarchic elites. What we are interested in here is the difference between the models <i>as models</i>, that is, at the general and abstract level. Other interventions in this debate could productively explore specific, combined approaches to context-specific situations. While the main ambitions and primary instruments of each of the three strategies of democratic self-defense are explained in our analysis above, we want to highlight in Table 2 how each strategy of self-defense confronts three major problems intimately related to the defense of democracy, namely: (1) the election of a dictator, (2) the defense of minority rights, and (3) corruption of the state by elected politicians and bureaucrats.</p><p>In order to exemplify the popular defenses against the different threats outlined here, we have in addition to the theoretical discussion below also added some reflections on the contrasting practical implementation of the models.</p><p>First, the three strategies differ in their approach to the potential threat of an election of a dictator. All three approaches agree on the possibility of such an election, as the free, equal, and open nature of the democratic system makes possible the election of a dictator or a “would-be autocrat” as Levitsky and Ziblatt coin the term. The liberal approach of militant democracy is predominantly <i>preemptive</i> in its approach, insofar as militant democrats seek to counter “would-be autocrats” by restricting political rights and liberties in order to repress potentially subversive movements <i>before</i> they gain widespread popular support. Contemporary critics of populism often combine this approach with a call for stronger courts and softer instruments such as increased civic education in order to curb the extremist inclinations of ordinary voters. As such, such strategies somewhat shy away from political conflict by employing preemptive instruments of restriction and education. In contrast, the popular models are more <i>reactive</i> in their responses to the potential election of a dictator. Popular republicanism has employed political trails and ostracism and the socialist tradition has developed electoral recall as mechanisms of superseding dictators, hence relying on institutions of collective power in which a political conflict can take place rather than suppressing conflict and transposing it into the realm of law like militant democrats propose.</p><p>Our claim when it comes to preventing the election of a dictator is not that popular instruments of democratic self-defense would necessarily be more effective in the short term, as the institutional innovations we put forward might very well fail in protecting democratic institutions, as could be the case of the institutions of militant democracy. We argue, however, that by building on democratic empowerment, popular instruments might fail in a more productive way. Whether successful or not, the proposals we put forward would strengthen, rather than limit popular participation. As such, the reconstructed popular model might not be more successful at curtailing the rise of illiberal authoritarianism in countries like Hungary or Poland. A potential campaign to recall Viktor Orban or other Fides elected officials in 2010 might have worked no better at curtailing his rise than the current “European militant democracy” (Larsen, <span>2021</span>). But the process of popular mobilization needed for such a campaign would have strengthened the potential for future challenges to the Fides regime, rather than giving Orban the role as defender of the popular will against unelected, foreign technocrats and jurists.</p><p>Second, the three strategies also agree that defending individual and minority rights is crucial for upholding a democratic regime. The reason to fear an election of an autocrat is among other things that individuals, groups, and minorities are at the mercy of such unlimited, sovereign power. Again, the liberal and popular models differ at the ideal typical level in their approach to this problem. Militant democracy is as argued above an offspring of what Müller has called a “self-disciplined democracy” (Müller, <span>2011</span>, p. 125), namely, the restricted elite democracy that grew out of the experiences with fascism after WWII. Such “self-disciplined” democracies have primarily relied on antimajoritarian institutions for protecting individual and minority rights like supreme courts, constitutional courts, heightened electoral thresholds, and party bans. The popular strategies of democratic self-defense in republicanism and socialism disagree with the argument that antimajoritarian institutions are effective to protect the rights and freedoms of individuals and minorities. Because such approaches view the main threat as coming from elites, oligarchs, and the rich, they view popular institutions—that is, the institutionalization of collective power—as the most efficient way to protect rights and freedoms. By having institutions like the people's tribunes or workers’ councils individuals and minorities can be protected. These two approaches also testify to the different conception of political rights employed by the liberal and popular models of democratic self-defense in the first place. Although the liberal model understands rights as strictly individual hereby establishing a host of antimajoritarian institutions in order to curb the potential danger of mass politics, both republican and socialist models of democratic self-defense understand rights as social and as developed (and protected) through collective action. Hence, individual citizens and minorities need institutions of collective action to safeguard their rights, not only an abstract constitutional matrix as in the liberal model.</p><p>In a similar vein, the ideas of popular Tribunes or class-specific political institutions might not in themselves be ironclad guarantees for minority protection. A tribunate can, as laid out by McCormick, represent the great majority out of power, in his terms members of the bottom 90% of the income distribution that have not held elected office (McCormick, <span>2006</span>). But it could also represent specific minorities who are un- or underrepresented in existing political frameworks, such as Dalits in India, Romas in East and central Europe, or residents without citizenship. The idea behind class-specific offices is to give marginalized minorities (or marginalized majority groups) direct access to independent power resources, rather than just right enforcement by courts and state elites. A controversial, contemporary case that illustrates the two models’ different approach to minority protection could be the potential decision by the U.S. Supreme Court to over Roe v. Wade (Liptak, <span>2022</span>). While the militant model expects antimajoritarian institutions like supreme or constitutional courts to be the best guardian of individual rights, the popular model views institutions of collective power as the best safeguards of minority rights. In the case of abortion rights, the establishment of a “tribune of Women” could grant the relevant “minority” certain veto powers in order to protect their rights.</p><p>The third problem, which both liberal and popular models of democratic self-defense confront, is how to challenge the corruption of the state—that is, the turning of the state institutions toward the personal ends of elected magistrates and unelected bureaucrats. The liberal model understands such corruption through the classic prism of the tyranny of the majority. As representative government and universal suffrage has introduced the masses into politics, the chief danger is the new form of tyranny practiced not by the singular tyrant, but the electoral majority, using the institutions of the state to their own enrichment on the expense of the commonwealth. As we have seen, this fear is integral to liberalism, as in the classical liberalism of 18th and 19th centuries, the fear was that the poor would threaten the property of the rich as well as their wealth through increased taxation. As argued by Duncan Bell, this fear of the poor was transformed into a fear of the people or the electoral majority, as 20th totalitarianism was interpreted through the liberal schema. Popular models of democratic self-defense, instead, conceptualize the potential corruption of the state as stemming not from the majority, but instead from oligarchs and elites extending their personal economic power into public institutions. Such approaches provide institutional mechanisms for combating oligarchic influence by making elites accountable and removable. One contemporary example of the popular model's attempt to prevent the threat of the corruption of the state might be the spread of sortition-based climate assemblies in European countries such as Ireland, France, Scotland, England, and Denmark. If we bracketed for moment the fact that such sortition-based climate assemblies are often created by the state as a symbolic act without much legislative power (Mulvad & Popp-Madsen, <span>2021</span>), such assemblies could be interpreted as a second (legislative or consultative) chamber consisting of ordinary, nonelite citizens charged with policy making on an issue, which political elites have not been able to confront. While the population at large in many European countries are in favor of a green transition and have to a certain degree voted accordingly, political elites have not responded with the conviction. Such inability to confront substantial threats to biodiversity has been discussed as a product of an inherent flaw of liberal democratic systems (Blühdorn, <span>2013</span>). From the perspective of the popular model of democratic self-defense, the central problem is that organized interests representing carbon-based parts of the capitalist class are able to complicate democratic decision-making regarding climate change (Klein, <span>2015</span>). The popular model's response to the inability and disinterest of the political elites, inspired by popular republicanism and the plebeian assemblies imbued with veto powers, is to advocate for the institutionalization of collective power—here exemplified in sortition-based assemblies—where ordinary citizens have the chance of preventing the capture of the common good by the special interests of the elites.</p><p>Our claim is not that the popular models provide <i>guarantees</i> against the undermining of democracy by a determined executive with consistent popular support over time (just as the liberal models provide no such guarantees, as have been demonstrated by recent events in Hungary or Poland). What we argue instead is that the popular model politicizes different forms of partisan cleavages. Militant modes of self-defense posit a conflict between a popular movement against political elites such as representatives, judges, or other unelected magistrates, potentially politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive. Alternatively, the popular models’ reliance of countermeasures based on institutionalized popular contestation will move the political struggle to other terrains, less favorable for such authoritarian populist agitation. Contemporary populists operate with an anti-institutional and anti-pluralist interpretation of popular sovereignty, which essentially leads to an anti-representative understanding of democracy—the populist leader knows what the “true people” wants, even though electoral results show something different (Müller, <span>2016a</span>). In contrast, the popular model rests on a plurality of institutional, representative, and delegatory mechanisms, run by the citizenry itself, making the populist rhetorical strategy of the corrupt elite versus pure, unified people difficult to sustain.</p><p>Recent years have seen almost unparalleled electoral success of predominantly right-wing populism across both the global North and global South. Such populist parties have enjoyed electoral success, and even election into political office, due to a deep-seated dissatisfaction with the political status quo, and the perceived inability of liberal democracy to tackle the political issues of the day. One response by critics of contemporary populism has been to revitalize the discussion of Loewenstein's idea of militant democracy, in which Loewenstein proposed the creation of a “constrained democracy,” in which political extremism would have difficulties to emerge, as uncontrollable popular passions were held in check by clever, depoliticizing institutional design meant to undermine parliamentary sovereignty (Müller, <span>2011</span>, pp. 146–150). The core concern of a militant democratic model of self-defense is that undemocratic movements and parties can use the free, equal, and open electoral process to undermine the democratic regime from within. Contemporary militant democrats, though, shy away from the quasi-authoritarian commitments of Loewenstein's original proposal, and often subscribe to what Jan-Werner Müller has called a “soft” version of militant democracy that instead of outright banning extreme parties seeks to limit their room of maneuver.</p><p>While we agree with the general conviction that democracy needs defense mechanisms against antidemocratic or authoritarian forces, we argue that the proposals put forward by militant democracy should not stand along but can be productively supplemented with instruments and institutions from what we call <i>popular</i> models of democratic self-defense, resources to which can be found in republican and socialist traditions. We argue that liberal models of democratic self-defense such as militant democracy are normatively <i>elitist</i>, and <i>exclusionary</i> and empirically potentially <i>ineffective</i> approaches to democratic self-defense. Moreover, such strategies are not momentary, extraordinary deviations from the ideal of liberal democracy in which they are exercised, but instead militant democracy radicalizes already existing commitments of liberal “constrained democracy,” including the fear of popular subjects and its individualizing solutions to problems of political extremism. However, because liberal models of democratic self-defense rely on elite institutions such as constitutional courts, representative bodies, and nonelected bureaucrats, they have a tendency to demobilize the populace and restrict popular participation. As such, they potentially weaken the long-term resilience of democracy. Instead, we argue that a popular model of self-defense can offer potential solutions on several levels.</p><p><i>First</i>, on the analytical level, the popular approach to democratic self-defense offers a different lens through which to view the issues of democratic backsliding, authoritarianism, and the populist resurgence. By conceptualizing the threats of authoritarian takeover as predominantly emanating from the elite, the popular model offers a broader array of potential answers to the defense of democracy. <i>Second</i>, on a political level, the popular model offers modalities of collective practices through the popular institutions that empower ordinary people rather than elites. This has the direct effect of strengthening the long-term resilience of democracy, and the indirect effect of not provoking the sort of populist backlash—the cleavage between “the elite” and “the people” that populists successfully campaign on—that reliance on elite institutions can have. As argued by Arendt in <i>The Origins of Totalitarianism</i>, for example, one central precondition for the success of totalitarianism was its ability to spellbound already isolated and atomized individuals. The popular model of democratic self-defense works to counter such atomized individualism by relying on the institutionalization of popular power as the <i>modus operandi</i> of combating political extremism. <i>Third</i>, on a normative level, the popular approach offers a model of democratic self-defense that is based on broadening rather than limiting channels of popular participation. As such, it is a form of democratic self-defense that offers a deepening rather than a restriction of political participation.</p><p>The article does not lay out a full program or institutional blueprint for the construction of a popular model of self-defense, and much work still needs to be done in order to transform these ideas into a functioning institutional setup. Instead, the article offers a shift in <i>perspective</i>, where threats to democracy are conceptualized as stemming not only from the popular masses, but also from political elites, wealthy oligarchs, “would-be autocrats,” and aspiring tyrants. In order to offer such a perspectival shift, we draw on resources from the nonliberal parts of the democratic tradition, namely, popular republican and socialist imaginaries. These traditions, unencumbered by the fear of popular politics integral to liberal modes of democratic self-defense, allow for a more democratically robust defense against threats to democratic institutions and individual rights. In these imaginaries, we discover concrete and historically tested institutional mechanisms—such as electoral recall, imperative mandate, sortition, political trails, and class-specific offices—that have placed the citizenry as such, and not just its representatives or nonelected elites, at the center stage of democratic self-defense.</p><p>Authoritarianism is certainly on rise across the West and around the globe. The timely and paramount question is: What to do about it? The core, normative conviction of the popular model of democratic self-defense that we have developed in this article is that the citizenry ought to have ways of <i>continually</i> testing the legitimacy and support of their elected political leaders. An election every fourth, fifth, or sixth year is simply too long of an interval, as this gives “would-be autocrats” and aspiring tyrants way too much time to cripple the courts, manipulate the electoral laws, gerrymander electoral districts, restrict minority rights, and change the constitution. The popular model of democratic self-defense, instead, provides institutional mechanism through which the citizenry can confront their political leaders <i>the moment</i> they begin to undermine the freedom of the polity. This does not imply, though, that if the popular model was in place, then “would-be autocrats” would never be successful in dismantling democracy. But it at least ensures that an <i>institutionalized political conflict</i> can arise on whether this or that change to the constitutional setup of the polity is legitimate or not. A noninstitutionalized mode of confronting tyrannical rulers would be that of revolution—John Locke's famous “appeal to heaven.” The popular model of democratic self-defense thus strikes a balance between an “overpoliticizing,” noninstitutionalized revolution as a mode of overthrowing tyrannical government and the depoliticized, bureaucratized attempt to preclude tyrannical government from emerging, as implied by militant democratic approaches. By having regular and constitutionally secured institutions of popular power and control, the popular model of self-defense is able to confront attacks on the democratic constitution continually and as they happen. This conceptual shift of perspective, we argue, can prove of vital importance to democratic forces in the coming times of political uncertainty.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":1,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Accounts of Chemical Research\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":16.4000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-06-10\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12639\",\"citationCount\":\"2\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Accounts of Chemical Research\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12639\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"化学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"CHEMISTRY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Accounts of Chemical Research","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12639","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"化学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"CHEMISTRY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
摘要
近年来,随着专制民粹主义者在一系列议会民主国家的选举中获胜,人们越来越担心现有民主制度是否有能力控制这种专制威胁。在匈牙利、波兰、菲律宾、巴西、俄罗斯和美国等国家,有独裁倾向的人物当选,导致许多人怀疑议会民主制度保护自己免受民主倒退的能力。这种民主自卫的无能导致了近年来学术界对军事民主概念的兴趣的复苏。Rummens, 2010;Cappocia, 2013;Kaltwasser, 2019;科什纳,2014;Malkopoulou,科什纳,2019;穆勒,2012;Sajo, 2012)。激进民主的概念最初是由德裔犹太公民、宪法学者卡尔·洛温斯坦(Karl Loewenstein)提出的,他于1937年在APSR上发表了两篇文章,试图发展代议制民主应对法西斯主义出现的方式。Loewenstein的论点是,自由和平等的政治选举可能为法西斯主义者通过民主手段瓦解代议制民主开辟道路。因此,民主必须变得激进起来,并通过禁止极端政党和限制极端分子的政治权利,对其自由和平等的基本原则作出妥协来保护自己(Loewenstein, 1937年a, 1937年b)。因此,不难理解为什么当代学者想要复兴Loewenstein的激进民主思想,作为对民粹主义的回应。许多人认为,当今民主国家面临的主要威胁并非来自革命运动,后者试图通过起义颠覆民主(Runciman, 2018,第2-3页;Levitsky,Ziblatt, 2018,第5-6页),而是来自民选政治领导人对民主规范和制度的逐渐侵蚀。当代政治领导人,如美国的唐纳德·特朗普、匈牙利的维克托·欧尔班、意大利的西尔维奥·贝卢斯科尼、委内瑞拉的Nicolás马杜罗、波兰的雅罗斯瓦夫·卡钦斯基、土耳其的雷杰普·埃尔多安和俄罗斯的弗拉基米尔·普京,都或多或少通过合法的选举渠道上台,并在不同程度上集中了权力,解散了机构制衡,削弱了政治权利。此外,当代民粹主义者对人民主权表现出一种反多元主义、反体制和威权主义的解释,因为许多民粹主义领导人声称自己是人民的真正代表,否认政治反对派的政治合法性和宪法对行政机构的限制(Finchelstein, 2017;穆勒,2016;Rummens, 2017) 1。尽管激进的民主措施是在20世纪30年代为对抗法西斯主义而发展起来的,但新激进模式试图遏制当代右翼民粹主义,防止民主进一步倒退。因此,新激进的民主主义者已经发展出制度和法律上的方法来限制民选的民粹主义者和民粹主义运动的政治影响。Rummens, 2010;科什纳,2014;穆勒,2012;Tyulkina, 2015)。这种新激进民主派对右翼民粹主义的补救措施往往涉及以政党禁令的形式限制进入政治领域(Bourne, 2012),限制个人和政治权利(Abts &Rummens, 2010),提高选举门槛,或加强宪法法院等独立机构(Mounk, 2018,第257页)。例如,在《民主如何消亡》一书中,史蒂文·列维茨基和丹尼尔·齐布拉特认为,唐纳德·特朗普这样的民粹主义者当选的核心历史和制度前提是,在1971年麦戈文-弗雷泽委员会(McGovern-Fraser Commission)建议进行有约束力的初选后,反主流主义、守门机构的消亡,以及政党在总统提名中的“过滤作用”的消除。Ziblatt, 2018,第48-52页)。他们的论点暗示,如果没有守门人,“烟雾弥漫的房间”就会发挥反多数主义的作用(列维茨基&Ziblatt, 2018,第41页)的非选举,不负责任的精英官员,“人民”可以自由地,并最终将选出像特朗普这样的煽动家。对于Yascha Mounk(2018,第257-259页)来说,遏制民粹主义者执政的最佳方式是依靠宪法法院作为宪法的守护者——这是激进民主的核心特征。除了对民粹主义和20世纪民主思想思想史的研究之外,Jan-Werner m<e:1>勒还是战后时期激进民主战略的细微差别和问题的重要分析师(m<e:1>勒,2012,2016b)。面对最近兴起的民粹主义,米勒将一种“软的激进民主”作为对当前威权主义危险的回应。 就堕胎权利而言,设立“妇女论坛”可以给予有关的“少数”某些否决权,以保护她们的权利。自由主义和流行的民主自卫模式都面临的第三个问题是,如何挑战国家的腐败——也就是说,国家机构向选举产生的地方官员和非选举产生的官僚的个人目标转变。自由主义模式通过多数人暴政的经典棱镜来理解这种腐败。随着代议制政府和普选权将大众引入政治,主要的危险是新形式的暴政,这种暴政不是由单个暴君实施的,而是由选举中的多数人实施的,他们以牺牲联邦为代价,利用国家机构为自己谋利。正如我们所看到的,这种恐惧是自由主义不可或缺的一部分,就像18世纪和19世纪的古典自由主义一样,人们担心穷人会通过增加税收来威胁富人的财产以及他们的财富。正如邓肯·贝尔(Duncan Bell)所说,这种对穷人的恐惧转变为对人民或选举多数派的恐惧,因为20世纪的极权主义是通过自由主义模式来解释的。相反,流行的民主自卫模式将国家的潜在腐败概念化,认为它不是源于多数人,而是源于寡头和精英将其个人经济权力扩展到公共机构。这些方法提供了对抗寡头影响的制度性机制,使精英们负起责任并可被清除。当代流行模式试图防止国家腐败威胁的一个例子,可能是在爱尔兰、法国、苏格兰、英格兰和丹麦等欧洲国家以分选为基础的气候大会的传播。如果我们暂时考虑这样一个事实,即这种基于分类的气候大会通常是由国家创建的,作为一种象征性的行为,没有太多的立法权(Mulvad &Popp-Madsen, 2021),这样的议会可以被解释为由普通的非精英公民组成的第二议院(立法或咨询),他们负责就政治精英无法面对的问题制定政策。虽然许多欧洲国家的民众普遍支持绿色转型,并在一定程度上进行了相应的投票,但政治精英们并没有对此做出坚定的回应。这种无法面对对生物多样性的实质性威胁的能力被认为是自由民主制度固有缺陷的产物(bl<s:1> hdorn, 2013)。从流行的民主自卫模式的角度来看,核心问题是代表资产阶级中以碳为基础的部分的有组织利益能够使有关气候变化的民主决策复杂化(Klein, 2015)。受大众共和主义和拥有否决权的平民议会的启发,大众模式对政治精英的无能和冷漠的回应是提倡集体权力的制度化——以投票为基础的议会为例——普通公民有机会阻止精英的特殊利益夺取公共利益。我们的主张并不是说,流行模式提供了保证,可以防止一位意志坚定、长期得到一致民众支持的行政官员破坏民主(正如自由模式没有提供这样的保证,匈牙利或波兰最近发生的事件就证明了这一点)。相反,我们认为流行的模型将不同形式的党派分裂政治化了。激进的自卫模式在反对政治精英(如代表、法官或其他未经选举的地方官员)的大众运动之间形成了冲突,潜在地将真正的人民和技术官僚精英之间的分裂政治化,通过这种分裂,威权主义的民粹主义项目往往会蓬勃发展。另一方面,流行模式对基于制度化的民众辩论的对策的依赖,将把政治斗争转移到其他领域,从而不利于这种威权主义的民粹主义煽动。当代民粹主义者以反制度和反多元主义的人民主权解释运作,这本质上导致了对民主的反代议制理解——民粹主义领导人知道“真正的人民”想要什么,即使选举结果显示出一些不同的东西(m<e:1>勒,2016a)。相比之下,流行的模式依赖于由公民自己运行的多种制度、代表和授权机制,这使得腐败精英对抗纯粹、团结的人民的民粹主义修辞策略难以维持。近年来,右翼民粹主义在全球北方和南方都取得了几乎无与伦比的选举成功。 这些民粹主义政党在选举中取得了成功,甚至当选了政治职位,这是由于对政治现状的根深蒂固的不满,以及自由民主在解决当今政治问题方面的无能。当代民粹主义批评者的一个回应是重新讨论Loewenstein的激进民主思想,其中Loewenstein提出了一种“受约束的民主”,在这种民主中,政治极端主义将很难出现,因为无法控制的民众激情被旨在破坏议会主权的聪明的、非政治化的制度设计所控制(m<e:1>勒,2011,第146-150页)。军事民主自卫模式的核心担忧是,非民主运动和政党可以利用自由、平等和公开的选举程序从内部破坏民主政权。然而,当代的激进民主主义者回避了Loewenstein最初提议的准专制承诺,而经常赞同Jan-Werner m<e:1>勒所称的激进民主的“软”版本,而不是彻底禁止极端政党,寻求限制他们的回旋余地。虽然我们同意民主需要防御机制来对抗反民主或专制力量的普遍信念,但我们认为,激进民主提出的建议不应该孤立无援,而可以有效地补充我们所说的民主自卫的流行模式中的工具和制度,这些资源可以在共和和社会主义传统中找到。我们认为,民主自卫的自由主义模式,如军事民主,在规范上是精英主义的,是排他性的,在经验上可能是无效的民主自卫方法。此外,这样的策略并不是暂时的,对自由民主理想的非凡偏离,相反,激进的民主使已经存在的自由主义“约束民主”的承诺变得激进,包括对大众主体的恐惧,以及对政治极端主义问题的个性化解决方案。然而,由于民主自卫的自由主义模式依赖于精英机构,如宪法法院、代议制机构和非选举产生的官僚,它们有使民众复员和限制民众参与的倾向。因此,它们有可能削弱民主的长期韧性。相反,我们认为,一种流行的自卫模式可以在几个层面上提供潜在的解决方案。首先,在分析层面上,流行的民主自卫方法提供了一个不同的视角来看待民主倒退、威权主义和民粹主义复苏等问题。通过将威权接管的威胁概念化为主要来自精英阶层,流行的模式为捍卫民主提供了更广泛的潜在答案。其次,在政治层面上,大众模式通过大众机构提供了集体实践的模式,赋予普通人而不是精英权力。这样做的直接效果是加强民主的长期韧性,间接效果是避免引发民粹主义的反弹——民粹主义者在竞选中成功地利用了“精英”和“人民”之间的分裂——这是依赖精英机构可能产生的结果。例如,正如阿伦特在《极权主义的起源》中所论述的那样,极权主义成功的一个核心先决条件是它能够迷惑已经孤立和原子化的个人。民主自卫的流行模式通过依靠民众权力的制度化作为对抗政治极端主义的运作方式,来对抗这种原子化的个人主义。第三,在规范层面上,大众方法提供了一种民主自卫的模式,其基础是拓宽而不是限制大众参与的渠道。因此,这是一种民主自卫的形式,它提供了一种深化而不是限制政治参与的方式。本文并没有为构建一种流行的自卫模式提出一个完整的方案或制度蓝图,为了将这些想法转化为一种有效的制度设置,还有很多工作要做。相反,这篇文章提供了一种视角的转变,对民主的威胁不仅来自大众,还来自政治精英、富有的寡头、“潜在的独裁者”和有抱负的暴君。为了提供这样一种视角转变,我们从民主传统的非自由部分,即大众的共和主义和社会主义想象中汲取资源。 这些传统不受对大众政治的恐惧的阻碍,这是民主自卫的自由模式的组成部分,允许对民主制度和个人权利的威胁进行更民主的有力防御。在这些想象中,我们发现了具体的、经过历史检验的制度机制——比如选举召回、强制授权、分类、政治路径和特定阶级的办公室——这些机制将公民置于民主自卫的中心舞台,而不仅仅是其代表或非选举产生的精英。在西方乃至全球,威权主义无疑正在崛起。当务之急是:该怎么办?我们在这篇文章中发展的民主自卫的流行模式的核心,规范性信念是公民应该有办法不断地测试他们选出的政治领导人的合法性和支持。每隔四年、五年或六年举行一次选举实在是间隔太长了,因为这给了“准独裁者”和有抱负的暴君太多的时间来削弱法院、操纵选举法、不公正地划分选区、限制少数民族的权利和修改宪法。相反,流行的民主自卫模式提供了一种制度机制,公民可以通过这种机制在他们的政治领导人开始破坏政体的自由时与他们对抗。然而,这并不意味着,如果流行的模式到位,那么“潜在的独裁者”永远不会成功地瓦解民主。但它至少确保了一场制度化的政治冲突可能会出现在政体的宪法设置的这种或那种改变是否合法的问题上。对抗暴虐统治者的一种非制度化模式将是革命——约翰·洛克著名的“上苍”。因此,流行的民主自卫模式在一种“过度政治化”、非制度化的革命(作为推翻专制政府的模式)和一种非政治化、官僚化的尝试(如激进民主方法所暗示的那样)之间取得了平衡。通过拥有常规的和宪法保障的民众权力和控制机构,民众的自卫模式能够不断地面对对民主宪法的攻击,当它们发生时。我们认为,在即将到来的政治不确定时期,这种观念上的转变对民主力量至关重要。 一些新激进民主派区分了反民主行动和反民主思想,并将激进措施限制在前者而不是后者(Bourne, 2012, p. 209;Capoccia, 2005,第57页)。另一些人则认为,反民主主义者还有其他合法的政治利益,只要他们不侵犯其他公民的参与权,这就使得排斥是非法的(Kirshner, 2014, pp. 40-41);另一些人则主张采取双轨战略,即随着反民主人士越来越接近公职和政治权力,政治排斥的威胁会增加。Rummens, 2010)。好战的民主在很大程度上为今天围绕反民粹主义的辩论设定了参数。因此,我们认为,规范的激进民主在其试图解决的政治问题的概念化方面是精英主义的,因为对民主秩序的主要威胁主要(尽管不是唯一)来自普通人的不满——在其对这一问题的反应中,潜在地排他性和非政治化,并且在其结果中可能无效,如果不是适得其反的话。最后一个关于激进民主手段有效性的问题确实是一个经验性问题,我们无法在本文中充分公正地对待这个问题,尽管我们将提供一些示范性的讨论。首先,激进民主是一种精英主义策略,因为打击政治极端主义的任务被分配给民选的政治家、官僚或非民选的反多数主义机构。这个问题通常与大众政治有关,大众政治被认为是潜在的不稳定和暴力。正如Malkopoulou和Norman(2018)最近所指出的那样,激进民主是“反极端主义政治的一种根本上的反参与和精英主义逻辑”(第444页),它将大众参与视为一种潜在的威胁,政治精英需要通过限制公共领域、约束民主制度和约束其文化来应对。正如Jan-Werner m<s:1> ller (2016b, p. 254)在一篇概述文章中所强调的那样,虽然有些人将激进民主理解为“过渡宪政”的一部分,其中新精英在规范上有理由使用强有力的司法措施来捍卫新民主宪法反对其敌人,但其他人则认为政治制度及其统治精英永远不能允许反民主力量上台的更基本的规范性理由。无论一个人是根据特定的背景还是激进民主的基本理由来运作,问题的核心是,在激进登记册中进行民主自卫是政治精英的任务。其次,激进的民主自卫策略是排他性的,可能会去政治化。而不是在公开的政治斗争中面对政治对手,从而强调民主的多元化、冲突性和对抗性(Lefort, 1988;Mouffe, 2013),激进民主将冲突去政治化,并将其从政治领域转移到法律领域,在法律领域,使用政党禁令和限制言论和集会权利等排他性手段来扼杀政治冲突。简而言之,尽管我们下面发展的民主自卫的替代模式通过通过不同的制度手段赋予公民权力来鼓励政治冲突,但战斗模式通过使某些群体进入公共领域的途径复杂化来阻止政治冲突。第三,激进民主的策略不仅是精英主义和非政治化的,而且可能是无效和适得其反的。许多当代民粹主义评论家认为,民粹主义者的主要修辞策略是强调“纯粹”和“廉洁”的人民与“自私自利”和“严重腐败”的精英之间的冲突(Finchelstein, 2017;蒙克,2018,第41-46页;《科学》,2016年第1期,第2-3页,第103-104页。通过将某些政党排除在政治进程之外,以及将某些观点排除在公共辩论之外,政治精英可能会进一步赋予“精英对抗人民”的可信度——当代自由民主的批评者已经在动员这种叙事。使用激进的民主措施是否要为产生政治不满负责,这显然是一个经验性的主张。但是,我们认为,激进的自卫模式假定了多数民众与政治精英之间的冲突,从而潜在地将真正的人民与技术官僚精英之间的分裂政治化,通过这种分裂,威权民粹主义项目往往会蓬勃发展。基于这些论点,我们发现有充分的理由用不同形式的民主自卫来补充激进民主,这避免了激进民主的一些陷阱。这种补充需要由公民推动的程序,并对合法的争论和政治斗争开放。 有人可能会反对说,激进的民主只是一种特殊的机制,一旦民主的敌人被击败,自由民主的普通政治将继续其非排他性、开放和平等的政治进程。例如,Ruti Teitel(2007,第49页)的观点是,“激进的宪政民主应该被理解为属于过渡性宪政主义,与政治转型时期有关,这一时期往往要求在羽翼未丰且往往脆弱的民主机构面前加强司法警惕;这可能不适合成熟的自由民主国家。”在这一点上,我们不同意。正如我们将在下面讨论的那样,我们认为激进民主的精英主义、排斥性和非政治化因素是对现有自由民主原则的激进化,而不是对自由民主核心理想的暂时中止。因此,我们同意Jan-Werner m<e:1> ller(2011)的观点,即在战后宪法解决方案中制度化的民主确实是一种“受约束的民主”,从而使战后自由民主与激进民主成为同一物种的成员,而不是根本不同。为了证明好战的民主不是一种偏离,而是自由主义传统倾向的激进化,我们重新审视自由民主的历史起源。虽然“自由民主”的支持者喜欢将其根源追溯到约翰·洛克(John Locke)和近代早期,但这一概念的起源相对较近。邓肯·贝尔(Duncan Bell)最近展示了“自由民主”一词是如何在两次世界大战之间的几年里,随着对自由秩序日益增长的威胁的理解以及自由主义与极权主义之间的二分法的理解,才开始被经常使用的(贝尔,2014)。在这种背景下,自由主义和民主越来越紧密地联系在一起,不仅是相互联系,而且是相互构成的。然而,这种自由民主的观念混淆了真实的政治历史,自由主义和民主被理解为基础广泛的人民主权,它们有着不同的历史,并且在大多数历史时期都是相互冲突的。在现代之前,“民主”一词主要不是用来指定一套政治制度。相反,民主被定义为一种社会阶级统治,即由大众阶级——穷人——统治,而不是贵族或有产阶级。在亚里士多德著名的国家形式类型学中,“民主”是由社会阶级定义的,而不是从制度角度来定义的,即政府是为了穷人的利益(亚里士多德,1995,III, v. 4 [1279B])。间接地,由于穷人构成多数,民主涉及多数统治,但社会定义仍然是中心。在西方历史中,我们可以看到多数人统治的民主与“穷人党”的政治权力,从而与平等主义政策相一致。Andreas Kalyvas描述了19世纪之前的民主是如何被视为“穷人的政治”(Kalyvas, 2019,第539页),他从色诺冯、托马斯·阿奎那和马西利乌斯·德·帕多瓦等人物身上找到了民主和穷人政治权力的等式。这种将民主与穷人的权力等同起来的观点,既出现在反对民众统治的人身上,如贵族共和派的西塞罗(Wood, 2008,第143页),也出现在民主宪法的早期现代支持者身上,如意大利北部城市各州的受欢迎的共和党人(McCormick, 2011)或英国内战中的平等主义者和挖掘者(Robertson, 2007;里斯,2016)。相反,“自由主义”一词是在19世纪初创造的,指的是在宪法问题上的意识形态中间派立场,介于激进的共和民主派和捍卫君主专制主义的保守派之间:自由派赞成保留君主,但通过宪法限制君主的专断权力(Fawcett, 2015)。自由主义的新意识形态建立在一个世纪的自由主义思想传统之上,以洛克和孟德斯鸠等思想家为代表,他们对君主制提出了批评,但没有要求建立一个完全民主共和的宪法(dom<e:1> nech &Raventos, 2008;木,2008)。自由主义政治思想在19世纪和20世纪发生了变化,古典自由主义者在工人、妇女和其他被排斥群体的运动的压力下接受了普选权(Therborn, 1977)。这种自由主义的逐渐民主化在这样的情况下结束了,在20世纪的头几十年里,有可能构建在两次世界大战之间出现的自由主义与民主之间永恒联系的想法。然而,尽管如此,自由主义对民众权力的一些怀疑仍然存在。矛盾的是,这可以从自由主义者对自由民主本身受到威胁的反应中看到。 在这里,自由民主的捍卫者,无论是激进形式还是非激进形式,都继承了对在自由传统的“民主化”中幸存下来的大众的怀疑态度。从这个角度来看,自由主义理论的主要问题是,它传统上主要能够想象对民主的威胁来自国家或暴民。例如,David Held将古典自由民主描述为本质上的一种“保护性民主”(Held, 2006, p. 99)。这种保护一方面意味着利用国家来保护生命和财产不受暴民的侵害,另一方面又意味着利用分权、法治和(有限的)代表权来保护个人不受国家的侵害。特别值得关注的是亚历克西斯·德·托克维尔所称的“多数人的暴政”(德·托克维尔,2003,第286页),它紧随18世纪和19世纪代议制政府的引入。如上所述,这种对代议制政府导致的“多数人暴政”的恐惧,类似于一个世纪后Loewenstein的激进民主所要解决的问题。有了民选政府,国家和暴民这两种危险可能会被贫穷的多数人利用普选权没收财产或对富裕少数人的财富征税而结合在一起。早期自由主义传统的倡导者,如麦迪逊或孟德斯鸠,提倡混合宪法,反对民主的概念,正是为了确保大众权力与精英统治的要素保持平衡。正如麦迪逊在《联邦党人文集》中所说的那样。10、“民主国家一直是动荡和争论的舞台;有与人身安全或者财产权利相抵触的;一般来说,他们的生命和他们的死亡一样短暂”(麦迪逊等人,1961年,第76页)。简而言之,麦迪逊有力地浓缩了自由主义者对人民的恐惧,因为他认为人民统治是不稳定的、不守规矩的、不安全的,而且对私有财产构成威胁。因此,麦迪逊在第1号论文中提出。63 .美国宪法的决定性特征“在于完全排除人民的集体能力”(Madon et al., 1961, p. 385)。相反,像麦迪逊这样的自由主义者提出,代议制政府和权力划分显然是治理政体和防止“多数人的暴政”的非民主手段。约翰·斯图亚特·密尔(John Stuart Mill)可以说是19世纪自由主义中包容性政府最伟大的支持者之一,他也广泛使用了这个词,并主张限制宪法中的民主元素,并创建应该“通过允许少数民族实质性参与政治权力来保护他们”的机构(Mill, 2008, p. 302)。通过这种方式,自由主义的支持者设想保护性制度是必要的,以保护个人免受国家的侵害,并保护国家行政权力免受民主的侵害,即穷人的政治权力。这导致了一系列反多数主义的机构,比如由任命的(精英)官员组成的强大的政治法庭,以及宪法对民主的限制。一种进一步证明激进民主的精英主义和非政治化策略与自由民主之间关系的方法是注意自由民主主义者如何解释20世纪上半叶法西斯主义的兴起。这为我们提供了一个很好的指标,表明自由主义者和激进的民主主义者是如何理解政治问题和潜在的补救措施的。有趣的是,当自由民主在第二次世界大战和法西斯主义的经历之后被重新发明时,建立了类似形式的反多数主义机构,就像18世纪和19世纪的自由主义者试图减少民众对他们新建立的宪政国家的直接影响一样。法西斯主义的经历在很大程度上被解释为大众多数权力过剩的情况,因此需要控制民主,创造“有纪律的民主”(m<e:1>勒,2011年,第39页)。这一发展在欧洲尤为突出。迈克尔·威尔金森(Michael Wilkinson)描述了战后时期“欧洲精英如何将两次世界大战之间自由民主的崩溃归咎于过度政治化”,因此,国家与大众民主之间的关系必须“通过内部去政治化的过程来重建”(Wilkinson, 2021,第74页)。战后时期的不同之处在于,这些反多数主义的制度不再被视为限制多数人占有私有财产的概念,而是被视为保护民主多数人不受其自身反民主倾向影响的必要保障。 与此同时,尽管少数群体保护问题现在被视为对种族和少数群体权利的保护,但为补救这些威胁而提出的制度设置类型在很大程度上类似于19世纪自由主义者为保护富有的少数群体而设想的反多数主义制度(Moyn, 2018)。这很有趣,因为认为两次世界大战之间的法西斯主义源于民众权力过剩的解释似乎不是唯一的解释——甚至,正如下面将要论证的那样,也不是一个特别令人信服的解释。同样,尽管一些评论家将当代民粹主义的选举成功与公民内部的各种病态(即“人民”的情绪化、短视和非理性本质)联系起来,但其他研究人员表明,民粹主义本质上是一种精英现象(Herman &马尔登,2018;Mondon,冬天,2019)。如果我们追溯墨索里尼作为一个政治人物的崛起历程,我们会看到一种情况,即精英演员发挥的作用远比选举胜利重要。法西斯主义作为一种政治力量的出现是在第一次世界大战后的政治和经济动荡中形成的。在这里,经济精英,特别是波河流域的土地所有者,转向原始法西斯组织,以保护自己免受劳工组织和动荡浪潮的影响(帕克斯顿,2007,第73-86页)。当墨索里尼最终被任命为总理时,这并不是一次大获全胜的选举胜利,也不是法西斯神话所暗示的通过“向罗马进军”强行夺取权力的结果,而是通过与经济和政治机构中的核心人物达成的一系列协议(Lyttelton, 2004, p. 94)。西班牙的佛朗哥(Franco)和匈牙利的霍尔蒂(Horthy)等人物也同样反对或无视选举中的多数和民众权力。通过选举产生法西斯主义领导人的最佳例子当然是希特勒。但在这里,他实际升格为国家权力并不是直接选举胜利的产物,而是通过与传统精英派系代表的幕后交易,特别是军队、土地所有者和工业部门(Kershaw, 2014;帕克斯顿,2007)。正如Levitsky和Ziblatt(2018,第15页)所指出的,从历史上看,政治精英经常通过达成“魔鬼交易”来帮助法西斯主义者和半威权主义者掌权,他们认为自己可以控制这些政治行为者,同时获得短期选举收益。考虑到这些例子,人们可以合理地从法西斯主义的崛起中吸取与战后宪法缔造者们普遍吸取的教训截然不同的教训。与其“约束”大众,创建一套由专家管理的反主流机构,不如合理地主张扩大民主,创建一套“约束”经济和政治精英的机构。当这种情况没有发生时,我们认为,这是因为在自由主义者的想象中,对宪政政府的威胁主要源于民众权力的过剩。如果我们假设保护民主的自由主义方法真的是精英主义的,而且可能是反民主的,会发生什么?这就必然意味着这些保护措施是危险和不必要的吗?为了让民主发挥作用,它是否需要非民主甚至反民主的保护?民主政体必须变得好战还是灭亡?我们会说事实并非如此。相反,有一些替代的、亲民主的或流行的方式来概念化对专制威胁的防御,这些方式可能避免与激进民主相关的一些缺点。因此,我们想提供一种可以补充战斗模式的视角。但这需要改变视角。正如我们上面所说的,自由主义的观点主要认为威胁要么来自国家,要么来自暴民,从而导致涉及权力划分和反多数主义(通常是精英领导的)机构的解决方案。但从历史上看,其他政治传统对这个问题的概念不同。我们认为,我们可以在大众的共和主义和社会主义传统中找到政治自卫的民主概念的思想资源这些传统都对国家权力和传统等级制度持自由主义的怀疑态度。但与自由主义不同的是,他们认为民主的主要威胁来自社会精英,而不是大众。这些关于民主自卫的观点在本质上可以被恰当地理解为“反寡头”,这意味着他们主要关注的是保护民主不被国家内外的精英所接管。这种反寡头的观点旨在以直接和间接的方式捍卫民主。 直接地说,一种流行的反寡头观点旨在避免不负责任的精英与不民主的力量进行魔鬼交易,以推翻民主(就像在意大利和德国看到的那样)。间接地,一个流行的、反寡头的观点旨在通过保持民主更能响应大众的要求,更不容易被精英接管,从而避免导致大量人转向反民主运动的那种不满情绪,从而减少公众对反民主运动的支持。正如汉娜·阿伦特(Hannah Arendt)在《极权主义的起源》(1951)中所指出的那样,专制和极权政府的核心先决条件是个人的孤立和孤独,用她的话说,这些情绪破坏了表象的公共领域和协同行动的明显政治机会(阿伦特,1968,第474-475页)。出于我们的目的,阿伦特的论点指出了民主自卫的激进民主和反多数主义模式的非政治化效果的危险。通过限制政治领域和将群体或问题排除在政治进程之外,这些尝试有可能进一步加强政治孤立和异化,而这种孤立和异化正是将人们吸引到专制运动中去的。相反,下面发展起来的民主自卫的流行模式依赖于集体权力的制度化,作为自卫的主要机制——也就是说,通过创造公共空间来对抗个人孤立,在公共空间中,一致行动在政治上是可能的。简而言之,如果当代的反民主情绪从对精英主义和排他性的自由民主的批评中获得支持,那么以进一步的去政治化来对抗这种反民主情绪可能会适得其反,就像激进模式所包含的那样。我们在下面列出的不是一种流行的自卫模式的制度蓝图,而是试图从两种政治传统中为民主自卫绘制替代的理论基础,这允许从自由主义对民主自卫的理解的角度转变。认为存在不同的民主自卫传统是一回事,而认为共和主义和社会主义的自卫模式——我们称之为流行的自卫模式——可以在当代民主危机和右翼威权主义抬头的情况下,为激进的民主手段提供可行的补充,则是另一件更艰巨的任务。表1通过区分民主自卫的两种理想典型模式——自由主义模式和大众模式,总结了分析结果。我们很清楚,现实世界的政治可能会有效地结合这两种模式的工具,维护民主宪法可能需要关注反民主运动和寡头精英。我们在这里感兴趣的是作为模型的模型之间的区别,也就是说,在一般和抽象的层面上。辩论中的其他干预措施可以富有成效地探讨针对具体情况的具体综合办法。虽然我们在上面的分析中解释了三种民主自卫策略的主要目标和主要工具,但我们想在表2中强调每种自卫策略如何面对与捍卫民主密切相关的三个主要问题,即:(1)选举独裁者,(2)捍卫少数民族的权利,以及(3)民选政治家和官僚对国家的腐败。为了举例说明针对这里概述的不同威胁的流行防御,除了下面的理论讨论之外,我们还对模型的对比实际实现进行了一些反思。首先,这三种战略在应对独裁者当选的潜在威胁方面有所不同。所有这三种方法都同意这种选举的可能性,因为民主制度的自由、平等和开放的性质使得选举独裁者或列维茨基和齐布拉特创造的术语“准独裁者”成为可能。好战民主的自由主义方法主要是先发制人的方法,因为好战的民主主义者试图通过限制政治权利和自由来对抗“潜在的独裁者”,以便在潜在的颠覆运动获得广泛的民众支持之前压制它们。当代民粹主义的批评者经常将这种方法与呼吁更强大的法院和更温和的手段(如增加公民教育)结合起来,以遏制普通选民的极端主义倾向。因此,这种策略通过采用先发制人的限制和教育手段,在某种程度上避免了政治冲突。相比之下,流行的模型对潜在的独裁者选举的反应更为积极。 大众共和主义采用了政治追踪和排斥,社会主义传统发展了选举召回作为取代独裁者的机制,因此依赖于集体权力的机构,在这种机构中可能发生政治冲突,而不是像激进的民主主义者所建议的那样压制冲突并将其转移到法律领域。当谈到防止独裁者的选举时,我们的主张并不是说民主自卫的流行工具在短期内一定会更有效,因为我们提出的制度创新很可能在保护民主制度方面失败,就像激进民主制度的情况一样。然而,我们认为,通过建立在民主授权的基础上,流行的工具可能会以更有效的方式失败。无论成功与否,我们提出的建议都将加强而不是限制民众的参与。因此,重建的流行模式可能不会更成功地遏制匈牙利或波兰等国非自由威权主义的崛起。2010年罢免维克托·欧尔班或其他信仰党当选官员的潜在运动可能不会比当前的“欧洲激进民主”更好地遏制他的崛起(Larsen, 2021)。但是,这样一场运动所需要的民众动员过程将加强未来挑战信仰党的潜力,而不是让欧尔班成为反对未经选举的外国技术官僚和法学家的民众意志的捍卫者。其次,这三种战略还一致认为,捍卫个人和少数群体的权利对于维护民主政权至关重要。担心独裁者当选的原因之一是,个人、群体和少数群体都受这种无限的主权权力的支配。再一次,自由主义和流行模式在解决这个问题的理想典型水平上有所不同。如上所述,战斗性民主是m<e:1>勒所称的“自律民主”的后代(m<e:1>勒,2011,第125页),即二战后法西斯主义经验中产生的受限制的精英民主。这些“自律”的民主国家主要依靠反多数主义的机构来保护个人和少数人的权利,如最高法院、宪法法院、提高选举门槛和政党禁令。共和主义和社会主义中流行的民主自卫策略不同意反多数主义机构有效保护个人和少数群体的权利和自由的观点。因为这些方法认为主要威胁来自精英、寡头和富人,他们认为大众制度——也就是集体权力的制度化——是保护权利和自由的最有效方式。通过设立人民保民委员会或工人代表会等机构,个人和少数群体可以得到保护。这两种方法也首先证明了自由主义和流行的民主自卫模式所采用的不同的政治权利概念。尽管自由主义模式将权利理解为严格的个人权利,因此建立了一系列反主流主义的机构,以遏制大众政治的潜在危险,但共和主义和社会主义的民主自卫模式都将权利理解为社会权利,并通过集体行动发展(和保护)。因此,公民个人和少数群体需要集体行动的机构来维护他们的权利,而不仅仅是自由主义模式中抽象的宪法矩阵。同样,流行的论坛或特定阶级的政治机构的想法本身可能不是保护少数群体的牢不可破的保证。正如麦考密克所提出的那样,保民官可以代表绝大多数失去权力的人,用他的话说,收入分配中底部90%的人没有担任民选公职(麦考密克,2006)。但它也可以代表在现有政治框架中没有或代表性不足的特定少数群体,例如印度的达利特人,东欧和中欧的罗姆人,或没有公民身份的居民。特定阶层办公室背后的理念是,让边缘化的少数群体(或边缘化的多数群体)直接获得独立的权力资源,而不仅仅是由法院和国家精英强制执行。一个有争议的当代案例可以说明这两种模式对少数群体保护的不同方法,这可能是美国最高法院对Roe v. Wade的潜在裁决(Liptak, 2022)。激进主义模式认为,像最高法院或宪法法院这样的反多数主义机构是个人权利的最佳守护者,而流行主义模式则认为,集体权力机构是少数人权利的最佳保障。
Defending democracy: Militant and popular models of democratic self-defense
With the electoral victories of authoritarian populists in a range of parliamentary democracies in recent years, there has been a growing unease with the ability of existing democratic institutions to keep such authoritarian threats under control. The election of authoritarian leaning figures in countries such as Hungary, Poland, Philippines, Brazil, Russia, and the United States has led many to doubt the capacity of the institutions of parliamentary democracy to protect themselves against democratic backsliding. This perceived inability for democratic self-defense has led to a resurgence of academic interest in the idea of militant democracy in recent years (Abts & Rummens, 2010; Cappocia, 2013; Kaltwasser, 2019; Kirshner, 2014; Malkopoulou & Kirshner, 2019; Müller, 2012; Sajo, 2012).
The concept of militant democracy was originally coined by the German-Jewish émigré and constitutional scholar Karl Loewenstein, who in two articles in APSR in 1937 sought to develop ways in which representative democracies could respond to the emergence of fascism. Loewenstein's argument was that free and equal political elections could open the path for a fascist dismantling of representative democracy via democratic means. Consequently, democracy had to become militant and safeguard itself by compromising with its foundational principles of freedom and equality by prohibiting extreme political parties and by curtailing the political rights of extremists (Loewenstein, 1937a, 1937b). As such, it is not difficult to see why contemporary scholars want to revive Loewenstein's idea of militant democracy as a response to populism. The main threat to present-day democracies, many argue, does not stem from revolutionary movements, which seek to subvert democracy through insurrection (Runciman, 2018, pp. 2–3; Levitsky & Ziblatt, 2018, pp. 5–6), but rather from the gradual erosion of democratic norms and institutions by elected political leaders.
Contemporary political leaders such as Donald Trump in the United States, Victor Orban in Hungary, Silvio Berlusconi in Italy, Nicolás Maduro in Venezuela, Jaroslaw Kaczynski in Poland, Recep Erdogan in Turkey, and Vladimir Putin in Russia have all ascended to power via more or less legitimate electoral channels and have—to a varying degree—centralized power, dissolved institutional checks and balances, and rolled back political rights. Moreover, contemporary populists display an antipluralist, anti-institutional, and authoritarian interpretation of popular sovereignty, insofar as many populist leaders claim to be the true representative of the people, denying the political legitimacy of political opposition and constitutional limits to the executive (Finchelstein, 2017; Müller, 2016a; Rummens, 2017)1. Although militant democratic measures were developed to combat fascism in the 1930s, neo-militant models try to contain contemporary right-wing populism and prevent further democratic backsliding. Consequently, neo-militant democrats have developed institutional and juridical ways of limiting the political influence of elected populists and populist movements (Abts & Rummens, 2010; Kirshner, 2014; Müller, 2012; Tyulkina, 2015). The remedy to right-wing populism from such neo-militant democrats often involves restricted access to the political sphere either in the form of party bans (Bourne, 2012), restrictions on individual and political rights (Abts & Rummens, 2010), increased electoral threshold, or the strengthening of independent institutions like constitutional courts (Mounk, 2018, p. 257). In How Democracies Die, for example, Steven Levitsky and Daniel Ziblatt argue that the central historical and institutional precondition for the election of a populist such as Donald Trump was the demise of antimajoritarian, gatekeeping institutions and the removal of the “filtering role” of political parties in presidential nominations after the McGovern-Fraser Commission in 1971 recommended binding primary elections (Levitsky & Ziblatt, 2018, pp. 48–52). Implied in their argument is that without the gatekeeping, antimajoritarian functions performed by the “smoke-filled room” (Levitsky & Ziblatt, 2018, p. 41) of nonelected, unaccountable, elite officials, “the people” are free to, and will eventually, elect a demagogue like Trump. For Yascha Mounk (2018, pp. 257–259), the best way to contain a populist in office is to rely on constitutional courts as guardians of the constitution—a core feature of militant democracy.
In addition to his work on populism and the intellectual history of 20th century democratic ideas, Jan-Werner Müller has also been an important analyst of the nuances and problems of the militant democracy strategy in the postwar era (Müller, 2012, 2016b). Faced with the recent rise of populism, Müller identifies a form of “soft militant democracy” as a response to the present authoritarian danger. He contrasts such “soft” version with “the ultimate ‘hard’ measure of banning a party or restricting rights to certain kinds of speech,” as the “soft” version merely “leaves a party in existence – but officially limit its possibilities for political participation, or de facto make life for the party difficult” (Müller, 2016b, p. 259). As such, many intellectuals, who worry about the fate of liberal democracy, conceptualize one important source of liberal democracy's crisis as residing in extreme popular movements and populist parties, as an unreasoned and dissatisfied population, attracted to the dangerous political ideologies of right-wing populists, who promise the unrealistic restoration of an unbridled national sovereignty. The crisis of liberal democracy, in this line of thinking, emerges through choices and actions of an unbridled majority, and as such the remedy is to limit the popular access to the political sphere and count on antimajoritarian institutions like constitutional courts or legal obstacles like new party legislation to curb populist forces. These measures resemble the original militant democratic strategies developed by Loewenstein (1937a, 1977b). As such, to save liberal democracy, some critics of populism argue, the values of freedom and equality on which this regime is founded must be temporary suspended for certain political groups and demands (Abt & Rummens, 2010).
This way of countering the potential authoritarian threats to democracy has some limitations. As such, we argue that the policy prescriptions and modes of analysis associated with both hard and soft versions of militant democracy can productively be supplemented with other, less antimajoritarian and elite-driven approaches to democratic self-defense. The problem with the modes of democratic self-defense inspired by militant democracy is twofold.
First, on a normative level, we will argue that the idea of defending democratic institutions by limiting popular participation and expression is questionable as its rests on a depoliticizing, elitist, and exclusionary understanding of politics, relying on handing power to unelected and potentially unaccountable technocrats or jurists. Second, on an empirical level, we will argue that a militant approach to democratic self-defense risks, on its own terms, being counterproductive, as the exclusion of certain popular demands by the political elites might only intensify the political narrative on which populists are already harvesting votes. Insofar as the militant model of democratic self-defense depends on creating a conflict between a popular majority and political elites such as representatives, judges, or other unelected magistrates, it risks backfiring by politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive.
To remedy these shortcomings, we propose a supplement to the militant democratic approach. Recognizing, as militant democrats point out, that existing institutions of parliamentary democracy have trouble dealing with authoritarian threats from within, we propose amending the militant model with a popular model of democratic self-defense. This popular understanding of democratic self-defense, drawing from both popular republican and socialist imaginaries, relies on institutional ways of deepening, rather than restricting democratic participation. Such a popular understanding of democratic self-defense involves not only an awareness of the dangers to democracy stemming from potentially authoritarian demagogues, but also to threats stemming from unaccountable economic elites, and to the inadequacy of liberal democracy to resist the translation of economic wealth into political power (McCormick, 2007). Instead of relying predominantly on the potentially depoliticizing and exclusionary strategy of militant democracy as a remedy to the contemporary crisis of democracy, we propose an “anti-oligarchic” strategy, which reintroduces the idea of institutions of collective power in order to combat excessive elite domination. It is important to stress that actually existing political systems might utilize both militant and popular instruments in defense of their democratic constitution. Hence, a democratic polity might strengthen its constitutional court (a militant instrument) while simultaneously establishing a second chamber of “ordinary” citizens with certain veto powers (a popular instrument). In this article, though, we are mainly interested in the conceptual, normative, and political differences between militant and popular models of democratic self-defense as models, that is, the ways in which the different models rely on either restricting or increasing popular participation as a means to defend the democratic constitution.
In order to advance this argument, the article is structured the following way: We begin, first, by revisiting the classical and contemporary arguments for militant democracy as democratic self-defense. Second, by reconstructing the genealogy of liberal democracy, we argue that the depoliticizing strategy of militant democracy is not a last resort of a liberal democracy in crisis; instead, depoliticizing and exclusionary strategies are integral to liberal democracy, and as such, militant democracy does not represent a perversion of liberal democracy, but rather a radicalization of tendencies already rooted in the liberal tradition. Third, we outline the historical trajectories of an alternative mode of democratic self-defense through a historical engagement with institutional solutions in the republican and socialist tradition. Lastly, we argue how these insights might form the basis of a supplementary, popular model for the defense of democracy that in contrast to the militant model does not seek to restrict but rather expand popular participation in democratic processes.
Militant democracy is a broad term for different legal and political mechanisms employed to prevent political extremism to emerge in a constitutional state with a representative government. The core idea of militant democracy is that democracies, in order to protect themselves, might under certain circumstances restrict the rights and access to the political system for those who seek to undermine democracy (Müller, 2012, 2016b). As noted above, some who deem populism an undemocratic, quasi-authoritarian political phenomena have turned to some version of militant democracy in order to contain the threat of populism (Müller, 2016b; Abt & Rummens, 2010).
Loewenstein's classic account of militant democracy was formulated in two articles from 1937 in which he analyzes how democratic systems can counter the threat posed by fascist movements. As such, militant democracy is an attempt to counter a specific political problem that emerges in the 20th century along with the spread of representative government, mass politics, and universal suffrage: If democracy essentially consists of free elections, universal suffrage, and majoritarianism along with the freedom of speech, assembly, and press, then antidemocratic movements can use the democratic process to subdue democracy itself. As Nazi minister of propaganda Joseph Goebbels once observed, “it will always be one of the best jokes of democracy that it gives its deadly enemies the means to destroy it” (Goebbels in Fox & Nolte [1995, p. 1]). By upholding a naïve loyalty to the democratic principles of free and equal access to the political sphere, Loewenstein argues, “fascist exponents systematically discredit the democratic order and make it unworkable by paralyzing its functions until chaos reigns” (Loewenstein, 1937a, p. 424). Through such “democratic fundamentalism,” democratic systems are effectively tolerating the “Trojan horse” of authoritarian movements using the democratic process of elections to subdue democracy (Loewenstein, 1937a, p. 424). In order to fight fascism, democracy itself must instead become militant, meaning that “if democracy believes in the superiority of its absolute values over the opportunistic platitudes of fascism, it must live up to the demands of the hour, and every possible effort must be made to rescue it, even at the risk and cost of violating fundamental principles” (Loewenstein, 1937a, p. 432). Such “every possible effort” involves a general constraining of democracy by banning subversive parties, heightening the electoral threshold, restricting freedom of the press in the form of criminalization of editorial subversive propaganda, restricting freedom of speech by prohibiting incitement to violence and hatred against particular groups of the population as well as prohibiting derogatory statements against democratic institutions, republican symbols, and high officials of the state (Loewenstein, 1937b, pp. 651–652). As such, by applying this militant democratic legislation, democratic states have begun the “deliberate transformation of obsolete forms and rigid concepts into the instrumentalities of ‘disciplined’, or even—let us not shy away from the word—‘authoritarian’ democracy” (Loewenstein, 1937b, p. 657, italics added). In short, militant democracy as a strategy of democratic self-defense involves—in classic formulation by Loewenstein—the transformation of the democratic ideal itself into a kind of political rule, which draws extensively upon the exclusionary strategies of the authoritarian ideologies, is to combat.
Contemporary neo-militant democrats have certainly moderated Loewenstein's original framework and shy away from authoritarian measures in order to make the restrictions on basic rights of political participation compatible with the fundamental principles of liberal democracy (Capoccia, 2013, p. 219). Some neo-militant democrats distinguish between antidemocratic actions and antidemocratic ideas, and limit militant measures to the former and not latter (Bourne, 2012, p. 209; Capoccia, 2005, p. 57). Others argue that antidemocrats have other legitimate political interests, which make exclusion illegitimate as long as they do not violate the right to participation of other citizens (Kirshner, 2014, pp. 40–41); yet others argue for a two-track strategy, where the threat of political exclusion increases as antidemocrats move closer to public offices and political power (Abt & Rummens, 2010).
Militant democracy has to a large extent set the parameters of the debates around countering populism today. As such, we argue that normatively militant democracy is elitist in its conceptualization of the political problem it seeks to remedy—insofar as the major threat to the democratic order primarily, though not exclusively, emanates from the dissatisfaction of ordinary people—potentially exclusionary, and depoliticizing in its responses to this problem and potentially ineffective, if not counterproductive in its results. The last issue concerning the effectiveness of militant democratic instruments is indeed an empirical question, one that we cannot do full justice to in this article, although we will provide some exemplary discussion.
First, militant democracy is an elitist strategy, as the task of combating political extremism is assigned to elected politicians, bureaucrats, or unelected, antimajoritarian institutions. The problem is most often associated with mass politics, which is deemed potentially volatile and violent. As Malkopoulou and Norman (2018) have recently argued, militant democracy is “a fundamentally anti-participatory and elitist logic … of anti-extremist politics” (p. 444), which regards mass participation as a potential threat that political elites are to counter by restricting the public sphere, constraining the democratic system and disciplining its culture. As highlighted in an overview article by Jan-Werner Müller (2016b, p. 254), while some understand militant democracy as part of a “transitional constitutionalism,” where the new elites are normatively justified in using strong juridical measures to defend the new democratic constitution against its enemies, others argue for a more fundamental normative justification by which a political system, and its governing elite, can never allow antidemocratic forces to come to power. Whether one operates with context-specific or fundamental justifications of militant democracy, the heart of the matter is that democratic self-defense in the militant register is the task of political elites.
Second, militant democratic strategies of self-defense are exclusionary, and potentially depoliticizing. Instead of facing political opponents in open political struggle, hereby emphasizing the pluralistic, conflictual, and agonistic nature of democracy (Lefort, 1988; Mouffe, 2013), militant democracy depoliticizes conflict and transposes it from the realm of politics into the legal realm, where exclusionary means like party bans and restrictions on rights of speech and assembly are used in order to stifle political conflict. In short, although the alternative model of democratic self-defense that we develop below encourages political conflict by empowering the citizenry through different institutional means, the militant model discourages political conflict by complicating the access to the public sphere for certain groups.
Third, the strategy of militant democracy is not only elitist, and depoliticizing, but also potentially ineffective and counterproductive. Many commentators on contemporary populism argue that the primary rhetorical strategy of populists is to highlight a conflict between the “pure” and “uncorrupted” people and the “self-interested” and “deeply corrupted” elites (Finchelstein, 2017; Mounk, 2018, pp. 41–46; Müller, 2016a, pp. 2–3, 103–104). By excluding certain parties from the political process as well as certain opinions from public debate, political elites might give further credibility to the “elite-versus-people”—narrative on which contemporary critics of liberal democracy are already mobilizing. It is obviously an empirical claim whether the use of militant democratic measures is responsible for creating political dissatisfaction. But, we argue, militant modes of self-defense posit a conflict between a popular majority against political elites, hereby potentially politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive.
Based on these arguments, we find there are good reasons to supplement militant democracy with different modalities of democratic self-defense, which avoids some of the pitfalls of militant democracy. Such supplements entail procedures that are citizen driven as well as open to legitimate contestation and political struggle. One might object that militant democracy is only an extraordinary mechanism and that the moment democracy's enemies are defeated, the ordinary politics of liberal democracy will continue with its non-exclusionary, open, and egalitarian political processes. This is, for example, the argument of Ruti Teitel (2007, p. 49), who argues that “militant constitutional democracy ought to be understood as belonging to transitional constitutionalism, associated with periods of political transformation that often demand closer judicial vigilance in the presence of fledging and often fragile democratic institutions; it may not be appropriate for mature liberal democracies.” Here, we disagree. As we shall argue below, we regard the elitist, exclusionary, and depoliticizing elements of militant democracy as a radicalization of already existing tenets of liberal democracy, not the temporary suspension of liberal democracy's core ideals. Hence, we agree with Jan-Werner Müller (2011) that democracy as it has been institutionalized in the postwar constitutional settlements is indeed a “constrained democracy,” hereby making postwar liberal democracy and militant democracy members of the same species rather than fundamentally different.
In order to demonstrate how militant democracy is not a deviation, but rather a radicalization of tendencies in the liberal tradition, we revisit below the historical origins of liberal democracy. While proponents of “liberal democracy” like to trace its roots back to John Locke and the early modern period, the concept is of a relative recent pedigree. Duncan Bell has recently shown how the term “liberal democracy” did not come into regular use until the interwar years in conjunction with an understanding of a growing threat to the liberal order and a dichotomy between liberalism and totalitarianism (Bell, 2014). In this context, liberalism and democracy was increasingly tied together as not only connected, but mutually constitutive. This idea of liberal democracy, however, obfuscates the real political history, where liberalism and democracy, understood as broad-based popular sovereignty, have distinct histories, and have in most historical periods been in conflict.
Before the modern period, the term “democracy” was not principally used to specify a set of political institutions. Rather, democracy was defined as a type of social class rule, namely, the rule by the popular class—the poor—as opposed to the nobles or the propertied classes. In Aristotle's famous typology of state forms, “democracy” was defined by social class, rather than in institutional terms, as government in the interest of the poor (Aristotle, 1995, III, v. 4 [1279B]). Indirectly, as the poor constituted a majority, democracy involved majority rule, but the social definition was nevertheless central. This equation of democracy as majority rule with the political power of the “Party of the Poor,” and hence with egalitarian policies, can be seen through Western history. Andreas Kalyvas describes how democracy until the 19th century was seen as the “politics of the assembled poor” (Kalyvas, 2019, p. 539), finding the equation of democracy and the political power of the poor in figures from Xenophon to Thomas Aquinas, and Marsilius de Padua. This identification of democracy with the power of the poor reappears both with opponents of popular rule, such as the aristocratic republican Cicero (Wood, 2008, p. 143), and with the early modern proponents of democratic constitutions, such as popular republicans in the North Italian City States (McCormick, 2011) or the Levellers and Diggers of the English Civil War (Robertson, 2007; Rees, 2016).
The term “liberalism,” instead, was coined in the early 1800s, designating an ideologically centrist position on the constitutional question, in the spectrum between radical republican democrats and conservatives who defended absolutist monarchy: Liberals favored keeping monarchs, but curtailing their arbitrary power through constitutions (Fawcett, 2015). The new ideology of liberalism is built on a century-old tradition of liberal thought, represented by thinkers such as Locke and Montesquieu who voiced a critique of monarchy without demanding a fully democratic-republican constitution (Domènech & Raventós, 2008; Wood, 2008). Liberal political thought of course changed in the course of the 19th and 20th century, with classical liberals being pressured into accepting universal suffrage by movements of workers, women, and other excluded groups (Therborn, 1977). This gradual democratization of liberalism ended in the situation, where in the first decades of the 20th century it was possible to construct the idea of the eternal connection between liberalism and democracy that emerged in the interwar years. Despite this, however, some of liberalism's skepticism toward popular power remains. Paradoxically this can be seen in the liberal response to threats against liberal democracy itself. Here, defenders of liberal democracy, both in its militant and nonmilitant forms, have inherited a skepticism toward the popular masses that have survived the “democratization” of the liberal tradition.
The main problem of liberal theory, from this perspective, is that it has traditionally primarily been able to imagine threats against democracy as coming from either the state or the mob. David Held, for example, describes classical liberal democracy as essentially a form of “protective democracy” (Held, 2006, p. 99). This protection means on the one hand using the state to protect life and property against the mob, and on the other hand using the division of power, rule of law, and (limited) representation to protect the individual against the state. Of special concern was what Alexis de Tocqueville called the “tyranny of the majority” (De Tocqueville, 2003, p. 286), which followed from the introduction of representative government in the 18th and 19th century. This fear of the “tyranny of the majority” as a result of representative government is, as we have argued in the above, similar to the problem Loewenstein's militant democracy set out to solve a century later. With elected governments, the two dangers of the state and the mob could be combined by a poor majority using the power granted by general suffrage to confiscate property or tax away the wealth of the rich minority. When early advocates of what would become the liberal tradition like Madison or Montesquieu advocated for a mixed constitution, and opposed the notion of democracy, it was precisely in order to make sure that popular power was balanced with elements of elite rule. As Madison famously argued in federalist paper no. 10, “democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and contention; have ever been incompatible with personal security or the rights of property; and have in general been as short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths” (Madison et al., 1961, p. 76). In short, Madison forcefully condenses the liberal fear of the people, insofar as he regards popular rule as volatile, unruly, and insecure as well as threatening to private property. For that reason, Madison argued in paper no. 63 that the defining characteristic of the American Constitution “lies in the total exclusion of the people in their collective capacity” (Madon et al., 1961, p. 385). Instead, liberals like Madison proposed representative government and division of power as explicitly nondemocratic means of governing the polity and preventing “the tyranny of the majority.” John Stuart Mill, arguably one of the greatest proponents of inclusive government within 19th century liberalism, also used the term widely and advocated for limiting the democratic elements of the constitution and create institutions that should be “protecting minorities by admitting them to a substantial participation in political power” (Mill, 2008, p. 302). In this way, proponents of liberalism envisioned protective institutions as necessary in order to protect individuals against the state, and protect executive state power against democracy, that is, the political power of the poor. This resulted in a set of antimajoritarian institutions, such as powerful political courts with appointed (elite) officers and constitutional limits to democracy.
One way to further demonstrate the relation between the elitist and depoliticizing strategy of militant democracy specifically and liberal democracy more generally is to note how liberal democrats interpreted the rise of the fascism in the first half of the 20th century. This gives us a good indicator of how liberal and militant democrats understand political problems and potential remedies alike. Interestingly, when liberal democracy was reinvented in the wake of the Second World War and the experiences of fascism, it was comparable forms of antimajoritarian institutions that were set up, as when liberals in the 18th and 19th centuries were trying to diminish the direct popular influence on their newly established constitutional states. The experiences of fascism were largely interpreted as a case of the excess of popular majority power, and the need was therefore to rein in democracy, creating a “disciplined democracy” (Müller, 2011, p. 39). This development was especially prominent in the European context. Michael Wilkinson describes how in the postwar era “European elites attributed the collapse of interwar liberal democracy to over-politicization” and that the relationship between state and mass democracy therefore had to be “reconstituted through a process of internal depoliticization” (Wilkinson, 2021, p. 74). What was different in the postwar period was that instead of conceptualizing these antimajoritarian institutions as limits to a popular majority appropriating private property, they were now construed as necessary safeguards for protecting democratic majorities against their own antidemocratic proclivities. Parallelly, even though the issue of minority protection was now cast in terms of protections for ethnic and minority rights, the type of institutional setup proposed to remedy these threats was to large extent similar to the antimajoritarian institutions that 19th-century liberals had envisioned for protection of the wealthy minorities (Moyn, 2018).
This is interesting, because the interpretation that interwar fascism sprang from an excess of popular power hardly seems the only explanation—or even, as shall argue below, an especially convincing explanation. Similarly, although some commentators link the electoral success of contemporary populism to various pathologies within the citizenry (i.e., the emotional, short-sighted, and irrational nature of the “the people”), other researchers show how populism is essentially an elite phenomenon (Herman & Muldoon, 2018; Mondon & Winter, 2019).
If we trace Mussolini's rise as a political figure, we see a situation where elite actors play a far more central role than electoral victories. The emergence of the fascists as a political force merged out of the political and economic turbulence after WWI. Here, economic elites, especially landowners in the Po Valley, turned toward protofascists organizations for protection against a wave of labor organizing and unrest (Paxton, 2007, pp. 73–86). When Mussolini was eventually appointed to prime minister, it was not as a product of a sweeping electoral victory, or the forceful seizure of power through the “march on Rome” as implied by fascist mythology, but rather through a series of deals with central actors in the economic and political establishment (Lyttelton, 2004, p. 94). Figures such as Franco in Spain or Horthy in Hungary likewise emerged against, or in spite of, electoral majorities and popular power. The best case for the rise of a fascist leader through the ballot box is of course Hitler. But here as well, his actual ascension to state power was not a product of an outright electoral victory, but rather by backroom dealings with representatives of factions of the traditional elite, notably the military, landowners, and sections of industry (Kershaw, 2014; Paxton, 2007). As Levitsky and Ziblatt (2018, p. 15) argue, historically, political elites have often helped fascists and semi-authoritarians into power by striking a “devil's bargain,” thinking they could control such political actors while simultaneously achieving short-term electoral gains. Given these examples, one could as reasonably have drawn very different lessons from the rise of fascism than the ones prevalent among constitutional architects of the postwar era. Instead of “disciplining” the popular masses, and creating a set of expert-run, antimajoritarian institutions, one could as reasonably have argued for expanding democracy and creating a set of institutions to “discipline” economic and political elites. When this did not happen, we argue that it is because in the liberal imaginary, threats to constitutional governments primarily stem from an excess of popular power.
What happens if we assume that the liberal approach to protecting democracy is really elitist and potentially antidemocratic? Does it necessarily follow that these protections are dangerous and unwanted? Might it not be the case that in order for democracy to function, it needs non- or even antidemocratic protections? Must democracies turn militant or die?
We will argue that this is not the case. Rather there are alternative, prodemocratic, or popular ways of conceptualizing the defense against authoritarian threats that potentially avoid some of the shortcomings associated with militant democracy. Hence we want to offer a perspective that can supplement to the militant model. But this requires a change of perspective. The liberal perspective, as we have argued above, primarily sees threats as stemming from either the state or the mob, leading to solutions involving divisions of power and antimajoritarian (often elite-led) institutions. But historically, other political traditions have conceptualized the problem differently. We argue that we can find the intellectual resources for a democratic notion of political self-defense in the popular republican and the socialist tradition.3 These traditions share the liberal skepticism toward state power and traditional hierarchies. But in contrast to liberalism, they identify the main threats to democracy as stemming from societal elites, rather than the masses. These perspectives on democratic self-defense can properly be understood as “anti-oligarchic” in nature, meaning that their main concern is defending democracy from being taken over by elites from within or outside of the state. This anti-oligarchic perspective aims to defend democracy in both direct and indirect ways. Directly, a popular, anti-oligarchic perspective aims to avoid unaccountable elites making devil's bargain with undemocratic forces in order to overturn democracy (as seen in Italy and Germany). Indirectly, a popular, anti-oligarchic perspective aims to drain away popular support for antidemocratic movements by keeping democracy more responsive to popular demands, less prone to elite takeover, and thus avoiding the sort of discontent that leads large numbers of people to turn toward antidemocratic movements. As Hannah Arendt argued already in The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951), a central precondition for tyrannical and totalitarian government is isolation and loneliness of individuals, as—in her vocabulary—these sentiments destroy the public realm of appearances and the distinctly political opportunity of acting in concert (Arendt, 1968, pp. 474–475). For our purposes, Arendt's argument points to the dangers of the depoliticizing effects of militant democratic and antimajoritarian models of democratic self-defense. By restricting the political realm and excluding groups or questions from the political process, these attempts risk further strengthening the sort of political isolation and alienation that draw people to authoritarian movements. Instead, the popular model of democratic self-defense developed below relies on the institutionalization of collective power as the principal mechanism of self-defense—that is, to counter individual isolation by creating public spaces, where acting in concert becomes politically possible. In short, if contemporary antidemocratic sentiments gain support from a critique of liberal democracy as elitist and exclusionary, it might be counterproductive to confront such antidemocratic sentiments with further depoliticization, as entailed in the militant model. What we lay out below are not institutional blueprints for a popular model self-defense but attempts at drawing alternative theoretical groundings for democratic self-defense from two political traditions, which allow for a shift in perspective from the liberal understandings of democratic self-defense.
It is one thing to argue that different traditions of democratic self-defense exist, it is another, more demanding task to argue that republican and socialist models of self-defense—what we group together as popular models of self-defense—can offer a viable supplement to militant democratic instruments given the contemporary crisis of democracy and rising right-wing authoritarianism.
Table 1 summarizes the analysis by distinguishing between two ideal typical models of democratic self-defense—the liberal and popular model. We are well-aware that real-world polities might productively combine instruments from the two models, and that upholding a democratic constitution might require attention to antidemocratic movements as well as to oligarchic elites. What we are interested in here is the difference between the models as models, that is, at the general and abstract level. Other interventions in this debate could productively explore specific, combined approaches to context-specific situations. While the main ambitions and primary instruments of each of the three strategies of democratic self-defense are explained in our analysis above, we want to highlight in Table 2 how each strategy of self-defense confronts three major problems intimately related to the defense of democracy, namely: (1) the election of a dictator, (2) the defense of minority rights, and (3) corruption of the state by elected politicians and bureaucrats.
In order to exemplify the popular defenses against the different threats outlined here, we have in addition to the theoretical discussion below also added some reflections on the contrasting practical implementation of the models.
First, the three strategies differ in their approach to the potential threat of an election of a dictator. All three approaches agree on the possibility of such an election, as the free, equal, and open nature of the democratic system makes possible the election of a dictator or a “would-be autocrat” as Levitsky and Ziblatt coin the term. The liberal approach of militant democracy is predominantly preemptive in its approach, insofar as militant democrats seek to counter “would-be autocrats” by restricting political rights and liberties in order to repress potentially subversive movements before they gain widespread popular support. Contemporary critics of populism often combine this approach with a call for stronger courts and softer instruments such as increased civic education in order to curb the extremist inclinations of ordinary voters. As such, such strategies somewhat shy away from political conflict by employing preemptive instruments of restriction and education. In contrast, the popular models are more reactive in their responses to the potential election of a dictator. Popular republicanism has employed political trails and ostracism and the socialist tradition has developed electoral recall as mechanisms of superseding dictators, hence relying on institutions of collective power in which a political conflict can take place rather than suppressing conflict and transposing it into the realm of law like militant democrats propose.
Our claim when it comes to preventing the election of a dictator is not that popular instruments of democratic self-defense would necessarily be more effective in the short term, as the institutional innovations we put forward might very well fail in protecting democratic institutions, as could be the case of the institutions of militant democracy. We argue, however, that by building on democratic empowerment, popular instruments might fail in a more productive way. Whether successful or not, the proposals we put forward would strengthen, rather than limit popular participation. As such, the reconstructed popular model might not be more successful at curtailing the rise of illiberal authoritarianism in countries like Hungary or Poland. A potential campaign to recall Viktor Orban or other Fides elected officials in 2010 might have worked no better at curtailing his rise than the current “European militant democracy” (Larsen, 2021). But the process of popular mobilization needed for such a campaign would have strengthened the potential for future challenges to the Fides regime, rather than giving Orban the role as defender of the popular will against unelected, foreign technocrats and jurists.
Second, the three strategies also agree that defending individual and minority rights is crucial for upholding a democratic regime. The reason to fear an election of an autocrat is among other things that individuals, groups, and minorities are at the mercy of such unlimited, sovereign power. Again, the liberal and popular models differ at the ideal typical level in their approach to this problem. Militant democracy is as argued above an offspring of what Müller has called a “self-disciplined democracy” (Müller, 2011, p. 125), namely, the restricted elite democracy that grew out of the experiences with fascism after WWII. Such “self-disciplined” democracies have primarily relied on antimajoritarian institutions for protecting individual and minority rights like supreme courts, constitutional courts, heightened electoral thresholds, and party bans. The popular strategies of democratic self-defense in republicanism and socialism disagree with the argument that antimajoritarian institutions are effective to protect the rights and freedoms of individuals and minorities. Because such approaches view the main threat as coming from elites, oligarchs, and the rich, they view popular institutions—that is, the institutionalization of collective power—as the most efficient way to protect rights and freedoms. By having institutions like the people's tribunes or workers’ councils individuals and minorities can be protected. These two approaches also testify to the different conception of political rights employed by the liberal and popular models of democratic self-defense in the first place. Although the liberal model understands rights as strictly individual hereby establishing a host of antimajoritarian institutions in order to curb the potential danger of mass politics, both republican and socialist models of democratic self-defense understand rights as social and as developed (and protected) through collective action. Hence, individual citizens and minorities need institutions of collective action to safeguard their rights, not only an abstract constitutional matrix as in the liberal model.
In a similar vein, the ideas of popular Tribunes or class-specific political institutions might not in themselves be ironclad guarantees for minority protection. A tribunate can, as laid out by McCormick, represent the great majority out of power, in his terms members of the bottom 90% of the income distribution that have not held elected office (McCormick, 2006). But it could also represent specific minorities who are un- or underrepresented in existing political frameworks, such as Dalits in India, Romas in East and central Europe, or residents without citizenship. The idea behind class-specific offices is to give marginalized minorities (or marginalized majority groups) direct access to independent power resources, rather than just right enforcement by courts and state elites. A controversial, contemporary case that illustrates the two models’ different approach to minority protection could be the potential decision by the U.S. Supreme Court to over Roe v. Wade (Liptak, 2022). While the militant model expects antimajoritarian institutions like supreme or constitutional courts to be the best guardian of individual rights, the popular model views institutions of collective power as the best safeguards of minority rights. In the case of abortion rights, the establishment of a “tribune of Women” could grant the relevant “minority” certain veto powers in order to protect their rights.
The third problem, which both liberal and popular models of democratic self-defense confront, is how to challenge the corruption of the state—that is, the turning of the state institutions toward the personal ends of elected magistrates and unelected bureaucrats. The liberal model understands such corruption through the classic prism of the tyranny of the majority. As representative government and universal suffrage has introduced the masses into politics, the chief danger is the new form of tyranny practiced not by the singular tyrant, but the electoral majority, using the institutions of the state to their own enrichment on the expense of the commonwealth. As we have seen, this fear is integral to liberalism, as in the classical liberalism of 18th and 19th centuries, the fear was that the poor would threaten the property of the rich as well as their wealth through increased taxation. As argued by Duncan Bell, this fear of the poor was transformed into a fear of the people or the electoral majority, as 20th totalitarianism was interpreted through the liberal schema. Popular models of democratic self-defense, instead, conceptualize the potential corruption of the state as stemming not from the majority, but instead from oligarchs and elites extending their personal economic power into public institutions. Such approaches provide institutional mechanisms for combating oligarchic influence by making elites accountable and removable. One contemporary example of the popular model's attempt to prevent the threat of the corruption of the state might be the spread of sortition-based climate assemblies in European countries such as Ireland, France, Scotland, England, and Denmark. If we bracketed for moment the fact that such sortition-based climate assemblies are often created by the state as a symbolic act without much legislative power (Mulvad & Popp-Madsen, 2021), such assemblies could be interpreted as a second (legislative or consultative) chamber consisting of ordinary, nonelite citizens charged with policy making on an issue, which political elites have not been able to confront. While the population at large in many European countries are in favor of a green transition and have to a certain degree voted accordingly, political elites have not responded with the conviction. Such inability to confront substantial threats to biodiversity has been discussed as a product of an inherent flaw of liberal democratic systems (Blühdorn, 2013). From the perspective of the popular model of democratic self-defense, the central problem is that organized interests representing carbon-based parts of the capitalist class are able to complicate democratic decision-making regarding climate change (Klein, 2015). The popular model's response to the inability and disinterest of the political elites, inspired by popular republicanism and the plebeian assemblies imbued with veto powers, is to advocate for the institutionalization of collective power—here exemplified in sortition-based assemblies—where ordinary citizens have the chance of preventing the capture of the common good by the special interests of the elites.
Our claim is not that the popular models provide guarantees against the undermining of democracy by a determined executive with consistent popular support over time (just as the liberal models provide no such guarantees, as have been demonstrated by recent events in Hungary or Poland). What we argue instead is that the popular model politicizes different forms of partisan cleavages. Militant modes of self-defense posit a conflict between a popular movement against political elites such as representatives, judges, or other unelected magistrates, potentially politicizing the cleavage between an authentic people and technocratic elites, through which authoritarian populist projects tend to thrive. Alternatively, the popular models’ reliance of countermeasures based on institutionalized popular contestation will move the political struggle to other terrains, less favorable for such authoritarian populist agitation. Contemporary populists operate with an anti-institutional and anti-pluralist interpretation of popular sovereignty, which essentially leads to an anti-representative understanding of democracy—the populist leader knows what the “true people” wants, even though electoral results show something different (Müller, 2016a). In contrast, the popular model rests on a plurality of institutional, representative, and delegatory mechanisms, run by the citizenry itself, making the populist rhetorical strategy of the corrupt elite versus pure, unified people difficult to sustain.
Recent years have seen almost unparalleled electoral success of predominantly right-wing populism across both the global North and global South. Such populist parties have enjoyed electoral success, and even election into political office, due to a deep-seated dissatisfaction with the political status quo, and the perceived inability of liberal democracy to tackle the political issues of the day. One response by critics of contemporary populism has been to revitalize the discussion of Loewenstein's idea of militant democracy, in which Loewenstein proposed the creation of a “constrained democracy,” in which political extremism would have difficulties to emerge, as uncontrollable popular passions were held in check by clever, depoliticizing institutional design meant to undermine parliamentary sovereignty (Müller, 2011, pp. 146–150). The core concern of a militant democratic model of self-defense is that undemocratic movements and parties can use the free, equal, and open electoral process to undermine the democratic regime from within. Contemporary militant democrats, though, shy away from the quasi-authoritarian commitments of Loewenstein's original proposal, and often subscribe to what Jan-Werner Müller has called a “soft” version of militant democracy that instead of outright banning extreme parties seeks to limit their room of maneuver.
While we agree with the general conviction that democracy needs defense mechanisms against antidemocratic or authoritarian forces, we argue that the proposals put forward by militant democracy should not stand along but can be productively supplemented with instruments and institutions from what we call popular models of democratic self-defense, resources to which can be found in republican and socialist traditions. We argue that liberal models of democratic self-defense such as militant democracy are normatively elitist, and exclusionary and empirically potentially ineffective approaches to democratic self-defense. Moreover, such strategies are not momentary, extraordinary deviations from the ideal of liberal democracy in which they are exercised, but instead militant democracy radicalizes already existing commitments of liberal “constrained democracy,” including the fear of popular subjects and its individualizing solutions to problems of political extremism. However, because liberal models of democratic self-defense rely on elite institutions such as constitutional courts, representative bodies, and nonelected bureaucrats, they have a tendency to demobilize the populace and restrict popular participation. As such, they potentially weaken the long-term resilience of democracy. Instead, we argue that a popular model of self-defense can offer potential solutions on several levels.
First, on the analytical level, the popular approach to democratic self-defense offers a different lens through which to view the issues of democratic backsliding, authoritarianism, and the populist resurgence. By conceptualizing the threats of authoritarian takeover as predominantly emanating from the elite, the popular model offers a broader array of potential answers to the defense of democracy. Second, on a political level, the popular model offers modalities of collective practices through the popular institutions that empower ordinary people rather than elites. This has the direct effect of strengthening the long-term resilience of democracy, and the indirect effect of not provoking the sort of populist backlash—the cleavage between “the elite” and “the people” that populists successfully campaign on—that reliance on elite institutions can have. As argued by Arendt in The Origins of Totalitarianism, for example, one central precondition for the success of totalitarianism was its ability to spellbound already isolated and atomized individuals. The popular model of democratic self-defense works to counter such atomized individualism by relying on the institutionalization of popular power as the modus operandi of combating political extremism. Third, on a normative level, the popular approach offers a model of democratic self-defense that is based on broadening rather than limiting channels of popular participation. As such, it is a form of democratic self-defense that offers a deepening rather than a restriction of political participation.
The article does not lay out a full program or institutional blueprint for the construction of a popular model of self-defense, and much work still needs to be done in order to transform these ideas into a functioning institutional setup. Instead, the article offers a shift in perspective, where threats to democracy are conceptualized as stemming not only from the popular masses, but also from political elites, wealthy oligarchs, “would-be autocrats,” and aspiring tyrants. In order to offer such a perspectival shift, we draw on resources from the nonliberal parts of the democratic tradition, namely, popular republican and socialist imaginaries. These traditions, unencumbered by the fear of popular politics integral to liberal modes of democratic self-defense, allow for a more democratically robust defense against threats to democratic institutions and individual rights. In these imaginaries, we discover concrete and historically tested institutional mechanisms—such as electoral recall, imperative mandate, sortition, political trails, and class-specific offices—that have placed the citizenry as such, and not just its representatives or nonelected elites, at the center stage of democratic self-defense.
Authoritarianism is certainly on rise across the West and around the globe. The timely and paramount question is: What to do about it? The core, normative conviction of the popular model of democratic self-defense that we have developed in this article is that the citizenry ought to have ways of continually testing the legitimacy and support of their elected political leaders. An election every fourth, fifth, or sixth year is simply too long of an interval, as this gives “would-be autocrats” and aspiring tyrants way too much time to cripple the courts, manipulate the electoral laws, gerrymander electoral districts, restrict minority rights, and change the constitution. The popular model of democratic self-defense, instead, provides institutional mechanism through which the citizenry can confront their political leaders the moment they begin to undermine the freedom of the polity. This does not imply, though, that if the popular model was in place, then “would-be autocrats” would never be successful in dismantling democracy. But it at least ensures that an institutionalized political conflict can arise on whether this or that change to the constitutional setup of the polity is legitimate or not. A noninstitutionalized mode of confronting tyrannical rulers would be that of revolution—John Locke's famous “appeal to heaven.” The popular model of democratic self-defense thus strikes a balance between an “overpoliticizing,” noninstitutionalized revolution as a mode of overthrowing tyrannical government and the depoliticized, bureaucratized attempt to preclude tyrannical government from emerging, as implied by militant democratic approaches. By having regular and constitutionally secured institutions of popular power and control, the popular model of self-defense is able to confront attacks on the democratic constitution continually and as they happen. This conceptual shift of perspective, we argue, can prove of vital importance to democratic forces in the coming times of political uncertainty.
期刊介绍:
Accounts of Chemical Research presents short, concise and critical articles offering easy-to-read overviews of basic research and applications in all areas of chemistry and biochemistry. These short reviews focus on research from the author’s own laboratory and are designed to teach the reader about a research project. In addition, Accounts of Chemical Research publishes commentaries that give an informed opinion on a current research problem. Special Issues online are devoted to a single topic of unusual activity and significance.
Accounts of Chemical Research replaces the traditional article abstract with an article "Conspectus." These entries synopsize the research affording the reader a closer look at the content and significance of an article. Through this provision of a more detailed description of the article contents, the Conspectus enhances the article's discoverability by search engines and the exposure for the research.