《科学权威与中欧、东欧和东南欧的科学与历史政治》**

IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
Friedrich Cain, Dietlind Hüchtker, Bernhard Kleeberg, Karin Reichenbach, Jan Surman
{"title":"《科学权威与中欧、东欧和东南欧的科学与历史政治》**","authors":"Friedrich Cain,&nbsp;Dietlind Hüchtker,&nbsp;Bernhard Kleeberg,&nbsp;Karin Reichenbach,&nbsp;Jan Surman","doi":"10.1002/bewi.202100035","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>What sounds like a laborious set up for a shallow joke actually hits the core of the problem this issue covers: What do the leading archaeologist of the former German Democratic Republic in re-unifying Germany, Bulgarian scientists in the late 1960s and some recent discussions about representations of Polish ancient history have in common? They all operate along fractures in the crust of scientific authority, they mark moments in time when classical figures of knowledge reach or breach authoritative status. They serve to study how authoritative speech bridged and manifested these relations and help identify areas where scientific authority is contested. This volume transcends this topological rhetoric with a praxeological take on scientific authority. Concentrating on authority figures, it brings specific margins and contestations into sight. The papers in this volume study cases from former socialist countries of Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe, and thus examples that present us with the complexity of agonal relations within state socialism and post-socialist transformations that complicate matters of scientific authority in many ways, yet also offer illustrative examples of shifting constellations of (scientific) authority.</p><p>This issue is dedicated to historical challenges to scholarship as the paramount producer of facts and their discursive reprocessing. Focusing on historical sciences, sociology, as well as natural sciences and technology and their non-academic counterparts, it maps changes in the political configuration of knowledge production in modern societies. The historical reconstruction and analysis of scientific self-conceptions are aligned with the question of convergence or fragmentation of epistemologies, increase or decline of universalistic claims, and exploitations from particularistic groups’ perspectives. We thus approach the rationalities that divide science and the humanities and politics as well as the “boundary work”<sup>1</sup> at the intersections. When and how did the boundaries shift, were they strengthened, weakened or removed, and how did this affect the epistemic figures in different scientific disciplines? We want to know if and to which extent these dynamics, which we recently observe in the fragmentation of epistemic authority and tribalization of truth, can be regarded as an effect of political and socio-economic transformations: of processes of re-nationalization, conservative and religious turns, or the popularization of postmodernity. Where and how can we trace the consequences of the shifts in media technologies that unsettle classic information media, and what impact do social fragmentation and the subsequent emergence of specific groups have on all this?</p><p>Following these questions, this issue investigates the relations of scientific practices, reflexive scholarship and changing epistemological frames since the 1960s. Within the broader methodological framework of the history of science and knowledge, it follows the parameters of a “political epistemology” as a mode of observing the settings and developments of epistemology and rationality,<sup>2</sup> a mode informed by recent approaches to the history of cold war science,<sup>3</sup> and works on politics of knowledge.<sup>4</sup> We trace historical interrelations of changes in rhetoric and evolutions of scientific practices of truth and emphasize the local, temporal, institutional, and subjective conditions of epistemological conflicts in regard to the specific role of the scholar as a “truth figure” and her or his contested credibility.<sup>5</sup> In this respect, we can rely on studies on historical scientific personae,<sup>6</sup> on scholarly practices in natural sciences and the humanities,<sup>7</sup> and on epistemic virtues.<sup>8</sup></p><p>When discussing these phenomena, we understand “scientific authority” as a subcase of “epistemic authority”<sup>9</sup> that refers to knowledge in general, including pragmatic (and practical, tacit) and everyday (quotidian) knowledge, as knowledge related to different fields and cultures (religious knowledge, political knowledge, etc.). Scientific authority refers to trust <i>in</i> as well as the social power <i>of</i> scientific knowledge, here including the natural sciences as well as the humanities and social sciences. If, in some of the contributions, academic authority is used synonymously with scientific authority, it is not to deny the long history of the struggle between the epistemic authority of academies and universities but to highlight the aspect of the habitualization and institutionalization of epistemic authority, the apparatus or dispositif of scientific knowledge and its representative – the <i>homo academicus</i>.<sup>10</sup> Scientific or academic authority in this sense is thus based on education and sometimes current affiliation to academia, i. e., to universities or research institutions, bestowing professional authority at least in modern knowledge societies.</p><p>The 20<sup>th</sup> and 21<sup>st</sup> centuries are characterized by a large range of epistemologies, from positivist to postmodernist and more explicitly politicized nationalist, socialist, neoliberal, or evangelical epistemologies. The respective relations between knowledge and power are closely tied to the emergence or disappearance of different epistemic authorities and, amongst these, scientific authority is but one. Various other figures of epistemic authorities can be found in different cultural settings throughout history, trusted, feared, and questioned: the elders, the sage, or the oracle, the church and the priest, common sense and the eye-witness, the press and the journalist. Authority that comes with an asymmetric distribution of knowledge might be regarded as something natural by the addressee when the situation corresponds to a (habitual) cultural practice and authority is carried by an established authority figure.</p><p>Obviously, as an expression of asymmetric social relations, authority is inherently ambiguous – an ambiguity displayed in Thomas Hobbes’ notorious Leviathan, who just as much rules on the basis of the formula <i>pax et protectio</i> as he spreads fear on its behalf. Richard Sennett has pointed to the ambiguity of authority in modern societies – “the emotional expression of power,” “a bond between people who are unequal”<sup>11</sup> – as one of the basic emotional bonds. Protection being a <i>telos</i> of modern governance, this means that the state has a specific responsibility for its subjects which consists not only in protection but also in safeguarding or improving living conditions and taking the right means to achieve these goals. In the so-called “knowledge society,” it is up to scientifically educated experts to decide what these means are.</p><p>The ambiguity between trust or belief in authority, and fear of its power explains the constant shifting of authority and why some figures might lose while others gain authority. Furthermore, social figures that habitually embody epistemic authority can be – and often are – politically shaped: by granting or denying authority to individual subjects; by concretely replacing individuals and institutions (as in authoritarian states); by questioning the cultural architecture of epistemic authority or the social roles that embody it as such (the scholar, the journalist). The political shaping of figures of authority can be a deliberate act of some social groups but it may as well be the result of contingent and uncontrolled processes, structural and systemic changes, etc. Thus, it relates to what we have called “political epistemologies” elsewhere.<sup>12</sup> Since epistemic authority figures have authority regarding what has to be considered knowledge (and what does not), they resemble truth figures although their authority does not necessarily relate to truth, but to decisions.<sup>13</sup> Accordingly, scientific authority figures can appear as truth figures and as experts although in the latter case with a smaller range as, for instance, advisors or consultants.</p><p>While modern knowledge societies before the Second World War produced an academically grounded type of expertise that often came along with the exclusion of non-scientific knowledge, the division of the world into two main political camps after 1945 resulted in the emergence of experts that first and foremost were loyal to their respective blocs. These experts did not – at least not essentially – depend on their academic background, but were validated by the political systems they represented in the global struggle.<sup>14</sup> In the 1980s, the AIDS pandemic and growing environmental consciousness, Chernobyl and the collapse of scientific socialism further weakened trust in science prompting the question how unbiased and aloof from politics it really was.<sup>15</sup> This process, one could argue, supported the multiplication of authorities. Here, we can follow Naomi Oreskes, who in <i>Why Trust Science?</i> recently connected epistemic authority with trust:</p><p>The idea that science should be our dominant authority about empirical matters – about matters of fact – is one that has prevailed in Western societies since the Enlightenment, but it can no longer be sustained without an argument. <i>Should</i> we trust science?<sup>16</sup></p><p>To Oreskes, trust in science as a collective endeavor, as an institution, has replaced the “authority of the ‘man of science,’” chosen by academic societies in the 18<sup>th</sup> and 19<sup>th</sup> centuries. Alluding to a familiar problem of STS, she points out that reflection on science had shown that scientists were just people doing their work, so that trust does not come naturally, but has to be earned, which it can because of science's “sustained engagement with the world” and its social character:<sup>17</sup> “The key point is that the basis for our trust is not in scientists – as wise or upright individuals – but in science as a social process that rigorously vets claims.”<sup>18</sup> And scientists, who are trained to study the natural world and thus are the experts, have “to explain not just what they know, but how they know it” – Oreskes speaks of “informed trust.”<sup>19</sup></p><p>The changing relations between science and politics can be well shown regarding examples from Central and Eastern Europe featured in this issue. <b>Miglena Nikolchina</b> observes a differentiation between the epistemic authority of an officially acknowledged and supported science, and that of a dissident one – even if they have been intrinsically entangled and partially depended on each other. This case demonstrates that scientific authority is not only determined by structures of power and social arrangements <i>within</i> the scientific field<sup>20</sup> but also by logics of other social fields that penetrate its realm. Along the lines of Pierre Bourdieu, we could describe this as the <i>intrusion</i> of political logic into the scientific field – the <i>political</i> epistemology of scientific authority.<sup>21</sup> However, intrusion works in two directions and on several levels. Not only can we highlight general changes in the relation between science and politics but also in the individual tactics of scholars who have used (and still do) their institutional scientific capital to achieve personal goals or tried to strengthen their position by relying on social prestige. As <b>Ella Rossman</b> demonstrates in respect to Russian Gender History or <b>Michał Pawleta</b> for recent Polish archaeology, the political dimension can become more important and create conflicts between pure and institutional scientific authority.<sup>22</sup> Thus, authority is always relational and depends on social interaction: it has to be represented by someone and it has to be acknowledged by someone else.</p><p>In respect to institutional scientific authority, a modern key figure is the expert. Sociologist Felix Wassermann has pointed out that in democracies, “experts have authority when their advice cannot be easily ignored in the decision-making process,” when their advice demands consideration and actually is being heard in politics, society and the public.<sup>23</sup> Still, this definition only refers to situations where authority is displayed and can be observed but does not address the question of how it is constituted: Is it sufficient to be asked for one's knowledge in a specific field to become an expert? Is pure or institutional scientific capital needed or perhaps only social capital? As he discusses the social figure of the expert, Wassermann gives a relational explanation: “[A]n expert is someone who, compared to a <i>layperson</i>, is considered to have more or different knowledge in an area that a (political) <i>decision-maker</i> considers relevant for decision-making.”<sup>24</sup> In this issue, however, we attempt to leave aside the <i>grand figure</i> of the expert in order to identify various derivations and their situational contexts. This, of course, opens a plethora of crucially important questions. How is authority constituted in societies, in which information and the access to academia is controlled in a certain restrictive manner; which pure scientific capital might either not be acknowledged or achievable; in which the accumulation of institutional scientific capital depends on political positions; in which the institutions of the scientific field themselves are a creation of elites that try to change the political order, as <b>Andrea Pető</b> discusses for the case of Hungary? Does being part of academia suffice to build up scientific authority in systems that misuse the scientific field to generate trust and respect for their political positions? Can and do epistemic virtues like modesty, trustworthiness, or diligence play a role in these contexts at all? Are even the same areas and kinds of expertise considered relevant for decision-making and, if they are, as in the case of science studies <b>Friedrich Cain</b> examines, why does the scientific authority of the respective experts differ so considerably? How does the transition from non-democratic to democratic regimes (or the other way around) affect these issues? Which strategies do experts apply in cases of regime change in order to transfer their scientific authority from one regime to another? How do they maintain it if their scientific tools and arguments are not enough to keep up their pure scientific capital, as discussed by <b>Michał Pawleta</b>, or if they are able to keep up their scientific standing but not their institutional scientific authority, as <b>Anne Kluger</b> examines?</p><p>The wide array of examples in this issue covers a long period from the 1960s until the present; it spans across general historiographic thresholds preventing a too closed geographical denomination. One might assume that the interpenetration of science and politics – and all complications this brings with it for the question of authority of science – is a post-1945 phenomenon. Yet, scholars had already been prominently present as figures of political authority when new states were popping up after the First World War. Philosopher Tomáš Garrigue Masaryk became president of Czechoslovakia, Gabriel Narutowicz, professor for hydraulic engineering at ETH Zürich, was elected president of Poland, historian Mykhailo Hrushevsky presided over the Ukrainian parliament – not to mention the philosopher Lenin who led the Soviet Union and was succeeded by Stalin, a self-proclaimed pantomath.<sup>25</sup></p><p>In the Soviet Union, not only Sputnik but physicists as a scientific group became symbols of progress and the expected socialist victory over the bourgeois society. But this happened at the cost of “lyricists” – poets or scholars from the humanities – who in the 1960s were deemed to be slowing down the progress-oriented techno-scientists.<sup>26</sup> It is hard to estimate how important this discussion was for the diverging social attribution of authority, but while “lyricists” gained epistemic authority as dissidents contesting the regime, natural scientists gained authority as symbols of Soviet power. Yet, as criticizing Soviet Sputnik meant criticizing the Party, increase in authority for these scientists meant that there were new possibilities to claim or to maintain independence from politicians, as <b>Cain</b> reminds us in this issue. <b>Nikolchina</b> analyzes moments in the 1960s, when scientific authority of theory and history of literature emancipated itself from the intrusion of political power in Bulgaria. At the same time, especially historians were the usual go-to-scholars when it came to the big anniversaries, as it was the case for the millennial celebrations of Polish statehood in the 1960s.<sup>27</sup></p><p>Scientists in socialist states had to face special tensions. They were either acknowledged by politicians and thus able to amass resources, yet often at the cost of losing trust in the eye of the public – or they faced the invert situation as dissidents. While many politicians (not only) from socialist states regarded science as a universal problem-solving tool, it was by no means considered as an elysian hail bringer nor unconditionally accepted by its protagonists. During the 1980s and 1990s, intellectuals in many countries of Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe frequently pointed to the extension of scientific knowledge to cover more and more areas of knowing, eventually leading to the dilution of the very idea of science – an issue that was more acutely perceived during the growth of the academic landscape after 1989.<sup>28</sup> The crisis of authorities that was detected by sociologists in Poland or Russia during the 1990s then added a new dimension to the relation between science and authority.<sup>29</sup> The transformation meant the fall of what had been praised as eternal truth for decades while, at the same time, none of the authorities were able to fill the gap and find broader social acceptance (perhaps except for John Paul II in Poland, who was, until recently, acknowledged by the whole spectrum from post-socialists to new conservatives). In many cases authority was (re)arranged with the support of international foundations which helped create trusted institutions or produce authoritative book series.<sup>30</sup> However, as strongly opposing groups often gained considerable local importance, an uncritical narrative of <i>westernization</i> does not help here.<sup>31</sup> Rather, we can speak of the post-Soviet academia becoming divided into two competing groups, one following the <i>Soviet</i> paradigm and one following the Western ones.<sup>32</sup> The failure of the allegedly science-based socialist system added to a fragmentation of science's genuine epistemic authority in many ways. The question that people posed during socialist times, whether one can trust science if everything can be regarded as scientific, and the question of post-socialism, how one can trust science if a science-based ideology has failed, was joined by the phenomenon of multiplying authorities typical of the Western Bloc.</p><p>Authority can be both at once – scientific in a narrow sense and based on administrative power –, but it may also lean in one of the two directions. Hence, trust in science comes in very different shapes, and several of those will be presented in this issue. Our examples from Poland, pre- and postunification Germany, from Bulgaria, Hungary, and Russia show that trust is often linked to the specific reconfigurations of scientific authorities during and after state socialism. One should also be aware that the collapse of state socialism did damage the authority of social sciences in general. Their claim to be able to predict was shattered when the unpredicted occurred.<sup>33</sup> The equation of power and truth that has contributed to the recent rise of illiberal democracies has become normal and plausible.<sup>34</sup> Today, scientists in Hungary, Poland, or Russia – both in the natural sciences and the humanities – are again judged by state representatives according to their party affiliation and their political orientation respectively. While on a personal and institutional level this has far-reaching consequences – expulsion or internal and external emigration of non-conformist scholars, closure of disfavored institutes and creation of conformist “polypore” institutions – on a more abstract level, the scientific authority in general becomes increasingly relativized.</p><p>Interestingly, however, this return of “partiinost” (see <b>Nicholchina</b> in this issue) also changed the scope of who is considered an <i>expert</i>: if scientists are consulted by the state party they are presented not only as experts in their discipline but can be engaged in other domains as well, or they can even present themselves as general experts in societal and political issues.<sup>35</sup> This can be observed not only with regard to populist and right-wing parties that have traditionally been supported only by a limited number of scholars but increasingly also regarding other parts of the political spectrum. While in Putin's Russia the emergence of the <i>expert general</i> can be explained by a lack of alternatives, which means that the few experts present have to be able to reach beyond their discipline, this is not (yet) the case in Hungary or Poland where media logics are important. Here, the degree of trust is linked to familiarity. Who frequently appears in the media is likely to be trusted more rather than people with actual expertise but less coverage.<sup>36</sup> Thus, illiberal democracies are repeating the conflation of good vs. bad science with good vs. bad politics, but now the dividing line is not bourgeois vs. Marxist but runs between the one we can trust and the one we cannot.<sup>37</sup> But, as <b>Pető</b> argues in this issue (and elsewhere),<sup>38</sup> the academic systems in former socialist countries are far from stable, and clearly the 1989/1991 belief in a path of progress and modernization of science seems to have been (somewhat) naïve.</p><p>The following texts make up three parts that are arranged in, more or less, chronological order from State socialism through transformation/post-socialism up to the 21<sup>st</sup> century. The first part includes contributions focusing on how scientific institutions and actors (sometimes unintentionally) came into positions that allowed them to perform criticism or dissidence against the political regime. In the first paper of the issue, <b>Friedrich Cain</b> argues that socialist Science Studies in the GDR placed themselves at an external insider position to science and to industry. Based on the socialist understanding that the sciences were important and could not be left to themselves but needed directions, Science Studies were empowered to take up a speaker position which made it possible to criticize science, production, and even party and state organizations as well as their interactions. Thus, the authority of Science Studies was established in a poly-vectoral process of communication, rather than being assigned solely by the party or only based on a scientific habitus. <b>Miglena Nikolchina's</b> contribution about political control and the Humanities in 1960s Bulgaria investigates the “emancipation of scientific authority from the intrusion of communist political power” referring to the opposition between the dogmatic Stalinist theory of aesthetics and the intellectual power of non-conformist philosophers of art. Challenging the official party doctrine of art as a reflection of reality by discussing art as the production of freedom, the “true intellectuals” (re)gained scientific authority over the politically institutionalized authority of the “apparatchicks.”</p><p>The second part assembles papers which focus on the transformations and recent re-transformations of post 1989/91 science systems in reunified Germany and in Russia. Analyzing the debates about GDR archaeologist Joachim Herrmann as “‘Honecker's Vassal’ or a Prehistorian in the Service of Science?,” <b>Anne Kluger</b> shows differing and contested perspectives on academic merit and on the credibility of Herrmann's self-legitimation. Her paper suggests that especially times of transition, insecurity, and contention reveal how much “the granting or denying of academic authority and the status of the professional scholar are highly context-dependent and hence situationally determined and historically dynamic.” Another example of a struggle for recognition among peers is presented by <b>Ella Rossman</b>, who examines how women's and gender history scholars faced changing political difficulties in Russia from the 1990s until today and how they used various strategies to build up scientific and, more specifically, disciplinary authority within post-Soviet academia. The first generation of those scholars predominantly worked in the field of academia. They organized large conferences and published volumes – including very diverse contributions – and also emphasized the relevance of gender studies/gender history as well as its applicability in state policy and governmental decision-making. Yet from the 2010s onward, a new movement of feminist political activism brought a new generation of gender historians to the fore who directed their research to wider audiences and gained recognition within and outside academia. While the first generation's strategies, based on the inclusivity of contributors and topics, effectively eroded the concept and aim of gender studies and gender history, the long-term success of the new movement is not yet clearly determinable.</p><p>The two final contributions discuss contemporary challenges from (beyond) the borders of science. Focusing on reconstructions of archaeological sites in open-air reserves and theme parks in present-day Poland, <b>Michał Pawleta</b> observes a renegotiation of scientific authority within a complex clash of conflicting claims on the past made by different stakeholders. After the profound change in management and funding after 1989, former state museums and archaeological reconstruction sites now face the need to fulfill requirements of the tourism and histotainment industry and to compete with more and more new local initiatives. Pawleta describes attacks on the scientific authority of archaeologists and their attempts to maintain their epistemic authority – for example through critique of popular reconstruction sites – to illustrate conflicts that arise when the “aim of reconstructions is not congruent with scientific or conservational goals,” and when notions of authenticity differ considerably. He analyzes conflicting modes and motivations of constructing the past, and studies attitudes to scientific knowledge and legitimizing strategies, as well as the making of alternative authorities, and how these practices may destabilize scientific authority today. <b>Andrea Pető</b> discusses academic authority and Hungarian illiberal democracy. Using the idea of the illiberal “polypore state” as an explanatory framework, she shows how the science policy of the Fidesz government perverts the idea of science, turning it into a means of political control. Restructuring the institutional landscape of science, more and more “polypore” institutions are being installed that, like the polypore fungus on a tree, feed on the former academic system by transferring resources to build up their own base, produce their own elite and thus authority. Following Pető’s analysis, the illiberal state's distinctive science policy operates with classic rhetoric modes of scientific authority that are, in fact, neither scientific nor do they share in an authority relying on scientific merit or expertise.</p>","PeriodicalId":55388,"journal":{"name":"Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6000,"publicationDate":"2021-12-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/bewi.202100035","citationCount":"2","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Introduction: Scientific Authority and the Politics of Science and History in Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe**\",\"authors\":\"Friedrich Cain,&nbsp;Dietlind Hüchtker,&nbsp;Bernhard Kleeberg,&nbsp;Karin Reichenbach,&nbsp;Jan Surman\",\"doi\":\"10.1002/bewi.202100035\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>What sounds like a laborious set up for a shallow joke actually hits the core of the problem this issue covers: What do the leading archaeologist of the former German Democratic Republic in re-unifying Germany, Bulgarian scientists in the late 1960s and some recent discussions about representations of Polish ancient history have in common? They all operate along fractures in the crust of scientific authority, they mark moments in time when classical figures of knowledge reach or breach authoritative status. They serve to study how authoritative speech bridged and manifested these relations and help identify areas where scientific authority is contested. This volume transcends this topological rhetoric with a praxeological take on scientific authority. Concentrating on authority figures, it brings specific margins and contestations into sight. The papers in this volume study cases from former socialist countries of Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe, and thus examples that present us with the complexity of agonal relations within state socialism and post-socialist transformations that complicate matters of scientific authority in many ways, yet also offer illustrative examples of shifting constellations of (scientific) authority.</p><p>This issue is dedicated to historical challenges to scholarship as the paramount producer of facts and their discursive reprocessing. Focusing on historical sciences, sociology, as well as natural sciences and technology and their non-academic counterparts, it maps changes in the political configuration of knowledge production in modern societies. The historical reconstruction and analysis of scientific self-conceptions are aligned with the question of convergence or fragmentation of epistemologies, increase or decline of universalistic claims, and exploitations from particularistic groups’ perspectives. We thus approach the rationalities that divide science and the humanities and politics as well as the “boundary work”<sup>1</sup> at the intersections. When and how did the boundaries shift, were they strengthened, weakened or removed, and how did this affect the epistemic figures in different scientific disciplines? We want to know if and to which extent these dynamics, which we recently observe in the fragmentation of epistemic authority and tribalization of truth, can be regarded as an effect of political and socio-economic transformations: of processes of re-nationalization, conservative and religious turns, or the popularization of postmodernity. Where and how can we trace the consequences of the shifts in media technologies that unsettle classic information media, and what impact do social fragmentation and the subsequent emergence of specific groups have on all this?</p><p>Following these questions, this issue investigates the relations of scientific practices, reflexive scholarship and changing epistemological frames since the 1960s. Within the broader methodological framework of the history of science and knowledge, it follows the parameters of a “political epistemology” as a mode of observing the settings and developments of epistemology and rationality,<sup>2</sup> a mode informed by recent approaches to the history of cold war science,<sup>3</sup> and works on politics of knowledge.<sup>4</sup> We trace historical interrelations of changes in rhetoric and evolutions of scientific practices of truth and emphasize the local, temporal, institutional, and subjective conditions of epistemological conflicts in regard to the specific role of the scholar as a “truth figure” and her or his contested credibility.<sup>5</sup> In this respect, we can rely on studies on historical scientific personae,<sup>6</sup> on scholarly practices in natural sciences and the humanities,<sup>7</sup> and on epistemic virtues.<sup>8</sup></p><p>When discussing these phenomena, we understand “scientific authority” as a subcase of “epistemic authority”<sup>9</sup> that refers to knowledge in general, including pragmatic (and practical, tacit) and everyday (quotidian) knowledge, as knowledge related to different fields and cultures (religious knowledge, political knowledge, etc.). Scientific authority refers to trust <i>in</i> as well as the social power <i>of</i> scientific knowledge, here including the natural sciences as well as the humanities and social sciences. If, in some of the contributions, academic authority is used synonymously with scientific authority, it is not to deny the long history of the struggle between the epistemic authority of academies and universities but to highlight the aspect of the habitualization and institutionalization of epistemic authority, the apparatus or dispositif of scientific knowledge and its representative – the <i>homo academicus</i>.<sup>10</sup> Scientific or academic authority in this sense is thus based on education and sometimes current affiliation to academia, i. e., to universities or research institutions, bestowing professional authority at least in modern knowledge societies.</p><p>The 20<sup>th</sup> and 21<sup>st</sup> centuries are characterized by a large range of epistemologies, from positivist to postmodernist and more explicitly politicized nationalist, socialist, neoliberal, or evangelical epistemologies. The respective relations between knowledge and power are closely tied to the emergence or disappearance of different epistemic authorities and, amongst these, scientific authority is but one. Various other figures of epistemic authorities can be found in different cultural settings throughout history, trusted, feared, and questioned: the elders, the sage, or the oracle, the church and the priest, common sense and the eye-witness, the press and the journalist. Authority that comes with an asymmetric distribution of knowledge might be regarded as something natural by the addressee when the situation corresponds to a (habitual) cultural practice and authority is carried by an established authority figure.</p><p>Obviously, as an expression of asymmetric social relations, authority is inherently ambiguous – an ambiguity displayed in Thomas Hobbes’ notorious Leviathan, who just as much rules on the basis of the formula <i>pax et protectio</i> as he spreads fear on its behalf. Richard Sennett has pointed to the ambiguity of authority in modern societies – “the emotional expression of power,” “a bond between people who are unequal”<sup>11</sup> – as one of the basic emotional bonds. Protection being a <i>telos</i> of modern governance, this means that the state has a specific responsibility for its subjects which consists not only in protection but also in safeguarding or improving living conditions and taking the right means to achieve these goals. In the so-called “knowledge society,” it is up to scientifically educated experts to decide what these means are.</p><p>The ambiguity between trust or belief in authority, and fear of its power explains the constant shifting of authority and why some figures might lose while others gain authority. Furthermore, social figures that habitually embody epistemic authority can be – and often are – politically shaped: by granting or denying authority to individual subjects; by concretely replacing individuals and institutions (as in authoritarian states); by questioning the cultural architecture of epistemic authority or the social roles that embody it as such (the scholar, the journalist). The political shaping of figures of authority can be a deliberate act of some social groups but it may as well be the result of contingent and uncontrolled processes, structural and systemic changes, etc. Thus, it relates to what we have called “political epistemologies” elsewhere.<sup>12</sup> Since epistemic authority figures have authority regarding what has to be considered knowledge (and what does not), they resemble truth figures although their authority does not necessarily relate to truth, but to decisions.<sup>13</sup> Accordingly, scientific authority figures can appear as truth figures and as experts although in the latter case with a smaller range as, for instance, advisors or consultants.</p><p>While modern knowledge societies before the Second World War produced an academically grounded type of expertise that often came along with the exclusion of non-scientific knowledge, the division of the world into two main political camps after 1945 resulted in the emergence of experts that first and foremost were loyal to their respective blocs. These experts did not – at least not essentially – depend on their academic background, but were validated by the political systems they represented in the global struggle.<sup>14</sup> In the 1980s, the AIDS pandemic and growing environmental consciousness, Chernobyl and the collapse of scientific socialism further weakened trust in science prompting the question how unbiased and aloof from politics it really was.<sup>15</sup> This process, one could argue, supported the multiplication of authorities. Here, we can follow Naomi Oreskes, who in <i>Why Trust Science?</i> recently connected epistemic authority with trust:</p><p>The idea that science should be our dominant authority about empirical matters – about matters of fact – is one that has prevailed in Western societies since the Enlightenment, but it can no longer be sustained without an argument. <i>Should</i> we trust science?<sup>16</sup></p><p>To Oreskes, trust in science as a collective endeavor, as an institution, has replaced the “authority of the ‘man of science,’” chosen by academic societies in the 18<sup>th</sup> and 19<sup>th</sup> centuries. Alluding to a familiar problem of STS, she points out that reflection on science had shown that scientists were just people doing their work, so that trust does not come naturally, but has to be earned, which it can because of science's “sustained engagement with the world” and its social character:<sup>17</sup> “The key point is that the basis for our trust is not in scientists – as wise or upright individuals – but in science as a social process that rigorously vets claims.”<sup>18</sup> And scientists, who are trained to study the natural world and thus are the experts, have “to explain not just what they know, but how they know it” – Oreskes speaks of “informed trust.”<sup>19</sup></p><p>The changing relations between science and politics can be well shown regarding examples from Central and Eastern Europe featured in this issue. <b>Miglena Nikolchina</b> observes a differentiation between the epistemic authority of an officially acknowledged and supported science, and that of a dissident one – even if they have been intrinsically entangled and partially depended on each other. This case demonstrates that scientific authority is not only determined by structures of power and social arrangements <i>within</i> the scientific field<sup>20</sup> but also by logics of other social fields that penetrate its realm. Along the lines of Pierre Bourdieu, we could describe this as the <i>intrusion</i> of political logic into the scientific field – the <i>political</i> epistemology of scientific authority.<sup>21</sup> However, intrusion works in two directions and on several levels. Not only can we highlight general changes in the relation between science and politics but also in the individual tactics of scholars who have used (and still do) their institutional scientific capital to achieve personal goals or tried to strengthen their position by relying on social prestige. As <b>Ella Rossman</b> demonstrates in respect to Russian Gender History or <b>Michał Pawleta</b> for recent Polish archaeology, the political dimension can become more important and create conflicts between pure and institutional scientific authority.<sup>22</sup> Thus, authority is always relational and depends on social interaction: it has to be represented by someone and it has to be acknowledged by someone else.</p><p>In respect to institutional scientific authority, a modern key figure is the expert. Sociologist Felix Wassermann has pointed out that in democracies, “experts have authority when their advice cannot be easily ignored in the decision-making process,” when their advice demands consideration and actually is being heard in politics, society and the public.<sup>23</sup> Still, this definition only refers to situations where authority is displayed and can be observed but does not address the question of how it is constituted: Is it sufficient to be asked for one's knowledge in a specific field to become an expert? Is pure or institutional scientific capital needed or perhaps only social capital? As he discusses the social figure of the expert, Wassermann gives a relational explanation: “[A]n expert is someone who, compared to a <i>layperson</i>, is considered to have more or different knowledge in an area that a (political) <i>decision-maker</i> considers relevant for decision-making.”<sup>24</sup> In this issue, however, we attempt to leave aside the <i>grand figure</i> of the expert in order to identify various derivations and their situational contexts. This, of course, opens a plethora of crucially important questions. How is authority constituted in societies, in which information and the access to academia is controlled in a certain restrictive manner; which pure scientific capital might either not be acknowledged or achievable; in which the accumulation of institutional scientific capital depends on political positions; in which the institutions of the scientific field themselves are a creation of elites that try to change the political order, as <b>Andrea Pető</b> discusses for the case of Hungary? Does being part of academia suffice to build up scientific authority in systems that misuse the scientific field to generate trust and respect for their political positions? Can and do epistemic virtues like modesty, trustworthiness, or diligence play a role in these contexts at all? Are even the same areas and kinds of expertise considered relevant for decision-making and, if they are, as in the case of science studies <b>Friedrich Cain</b> examines, why does the scientific authority of the respective experts differ so considerably? How does the transition from non-democratic to democratic regimes (or the other way around) affect these issues? Which strategies do experts apply in cases of regime change in order to transfer their scientific authority from one regime to another? How do they maintain it if their scientific tools and arguments are not enough to keep up their pure scientific capital, as discussed by <b>Michał Pawleta</b>, or if they are able to keep up their scientific standing but not their institutional scientific authority, as <b>Anne Kluger</b> examines?</p><p>The wide array of examples in this issue covers a long period from the 1960s until the present; it spans across general historiographic thresholds preventing a too closed geographical denomination. One might assume that the interpenetration of science and politics – and all complications this brings with it for the question of authority of science – is a post-1945 phenomenon. Yet, scholars had already been prominently present as figures of political authority when new states were popping up after the First World War. Philosopher Tomáš Garrigue Masaryk became president of Czechoslovakia, Gabriel Narutowicz, professor for hydraulic engineering at ETH Zürich, was elected president of Poland, historian Mykhailo Hrushevsky presided over the Ukrainian parliament – not to mention the philosopher Lenin who led the Soviet Union and was succeeded by Stalin, a self-proclaimed pantomath.<sup>25</sup></p><p>In the Soviet Union, not only Sputnik but physicists as a scientific group became symbols of progress and the expected socialist victory over the bourgeois society. But this happened at the cost of “lyricists” – poets or scholars from the humanities – who in the 1960s were deemed to be slowing down the progress-oriented techno-scientists.<sup>26</sup> It is hard to estimate how important this discussion was for the diverging social attribution of authority, but while “lyricists” gained epistemic authority as dissidents contesting the regime, natural scientists gained authority as symbols of Soviet power. Yet, as criticizing Soviet Sputnik meant criticizing the Party, increase in authority for these scientists meant that there were new possibilities to claim or to maintain independence from politicians, as <b>Cain</b> reminds us in this issue. <b>Nikolchina</b> analyzes moments in the 1960s, when scientific authority of theory and history of literature emancipated itself from the intrusion of political power in Bulgaria. At the same time, especially historians were the usual go-to-scholars when it came to the big anniversaries, as it was the case for the millennial celebrations of Polish statehood in the 1960s.<sup>27</sup></p><p>Scientists in socialist states had to face special tensions. They were either acknowledged by politicians and thus able to amass resources, yet often at the cost of losing trust in the eye of the public – or they faced the invert situation as dissidents. While many politicians (not only) from socialist states regarded science as a universal problem-solving tool, it was by no means considered as an elysian hail bringer nor unconditionally accepted by its protagonists. During the 1980s and 1990s, intellectuals in many countries of Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe frequently pointed to the extension of scientific knowledge to cover more and more areas of knowing, eventually leading to the dilution of the very idea of science – an issue that was more acutely perceived during the growth of the academic landscape after 1989.<sup>28</sup> The crisis of authorities that was detected by sociologists in Poland or Russia during the 1990s then added a new dimension to the relation between science and authority.<sup>29</sup> The transformation meant the fall of what had been praised as eternal truth for decades while, at the same time, none of the authorities were able to fill the gap and find broader social acceptance (perhaps except for John Paul II in Poland, who was, until recently, acknowledged by the whole spectrum from post-socialists to new conservatives). In many cases authority was (re)arranged with the support of international foundations which helped create trusted institutions or produce authoritative book series.<sup>30</sup> However, as strongly opposing groups often gained considerable local importance, an uncritical narrative of <i>westernization</i> does not help here.<sup>31</sup> Rather, we can speak of the post-Soviet academia becoming divided into two competing groups, one following the <i>Soviet</i> paradigm and one following the Western ones.<sup>32</sup> The failure of the allegedly science-based socialist system added to a fragmentation of science's genuine epistemic authority in many ways. The question that people posed during socialist times, whether one can trust science if everything can be regarded as scientific, and the question of post-socialism, how one can trust science if a science-based ideology has failed, was joined by the phenomenon of multiplying authorities typical of the Western Bloc.</p><p>Authority can be both at once – scientific in a narrow sense and based on administrative power –, but it may also lean in one of the two directions. Hence, trust in science comes in very different shapes, and several of those will be presented in this issue. Our examples from Poland, pre- and postunification Germany, from Bulgaria, Hungary, and Russia show that trust is often linked to the specific reconfigurations of scientific authorities during and after state socialism. One should also be aware that the collapse of state socialism did damage the authority of social sciences in general. Their claim to be able to predict was shattered when the unpredicted occurred.<sup>33</sup> The equation of power and truth that has contributed to the recent rise of illiberal democracies has become normal and plausible.<sup>34</sup> Today, scientists in Hungary, Poland, or Russia – both in the natural sciences and the humanities – are again judged by state representatives according to their party affiliation and their political orientation respectively. While on a personal and institutional level this has far-reaching consequences – expulsion or internal and external emigration of non-conformist scholars, closure of disfavored institutes and creation of conformist “polypore” institutions – on a more abstract level, the scientific authority in general becomes increasingly relativized.</p><p>Interestingly, however, this return of “partiinost” (see <b>Nicholchina</b> in this issue) also changed the scope of who is considered an <i>expert</i>: if scientists are consulted by the state party they are presented not only as experts in their discipline but can be engaged in other domains as well, or they can even present themselves as general experts in societal and political issues.<sup>35</sup> This can be observed not only with regard to populist and right-wing parties that have traditionally been supported only by a limited number of scholars but increasingly also regarding other parts of the political spectrum. While in Putin's Russia the emergence of the <i>expert general</i> can be explained by a lack of alternatives, which means that the few experts present have to be able to reach beyond their discipline, this is not (yet) the case in Hungary or Poland where media logics are important. Here, the degree of trust is linked to familiarity. Who frequently appears in the media is likely to be trusted more rather than people with actual expertise but less coverage.<sup>36</sup> Thus, illiberal democracies are repeating the conflation of good vs. bad science with good vs. bad politics, but now the dividing line is not bourgeois vs. Marxist but runs between the one we can trust and the one we cannot.<sup>37</sup> But, as <b>Pető</b> argues in this issue (and elsewhere),<sup>38</sup> the academic systems in former socialist countries are far from stable, and clearly the 1989/1991 belief in a path of progress and modernization of science seems to have been (somewhat) naïve.</p><p>The following texts make up three parts that are arranged in, more or less, chronological order from State socialism through transformation/post-socialism up to the 21<sup>st</sup> century. The first part includes contributions focusing on how scientific institutions and actors (sometimes unintentionally) came into positions that allowed them to perform criticism or dissidence against the political regime. In the first paper of the issue, <b>Friedrich Cain</b> argues that socialist Science Studies in the GDR placed themselves at an external insider position to science and to industry. Based on the socialist understanding that the sciences were important and could not be left to themselves but needed directions, Science Studies were empowered to take up a speaker position which made it possible to criticize science, production, and even party and state organizations as well as their interactions. Thus, the authority of Science Studies was established in a poly-vectoral process of communication, rather than being assigned solely by the party or only based on a scientific habitus. <b>Miglena Nikolchina's</b> contribution about political control and the Humanities in 1960s Bulgaria investigates the “emancipation of scientific authority from the intrusion of communist political power” referring to the opposition between the dogmatic Stalinist theory of aesthetics and the intellectual power of non-conformist philosophers of art. Challenging the official party doctrine of art as a reflection of reality by discussing art as the production of freedom, the “true intellectuals” (re)gained scientific authority over the politically institutionalized authority of the “apparatchicks.”</p><p>The second part assembles papers which focus on the transformations and recent re-transformations of post 1989/91 science systems in reunified Germany and in Russia. Analyzing the debates about GDR archaeologist Joachim Herrmann as “‘Honecker's Vassal’ or a Prehistorian in the Service of Science?,” <b>Anne Kluger</b> shows differing and contested perspectives on academic merit and on the credibility of Herrmann's self-legitimation. Her paper suggests that especially times of transition, insecurity, and contention reveal how much “the granting or denying of academic authority and the status of the professional scholar are highly context-dependent and hence situationally determined and historically dynamic.” Another example of a struggle for recognition among peers is presented by <b>Ella Rossman</b>, who examines how women's and gender history scholars faced changing political difficulties in Russia from the 1990s until today and how they used various strategies to build up scientific and, more specifically, disciplinary authority within post-Soviet academia. The first generation of those scholars predominantly worked in the field of academia. They organized large conferences and published volumes – including very diverse contributions – and also emphasized the relevance of gender studies/gender history as well as its applicability in state policy and governmental decision-making. Yet from the 2010s onward, a new movement of feminist political activism brought a new generation of gender historians to the fore who directed their research to wider audiences and gained recognition within and outside academia. While the first generation's strategies, based on the inclusivity of contributors and topics, effectively eroded the concept and aim of gender studies and gender history, the long-term success of the new movement is not yet clearly determinable.</p><p>The two final contributions discuss contemporary challenges from (beyond) the borders of science. Focusing on reconstructions of archaeological sites in open-air reserves and theme parks in present-day Poland, <b>Michał Pawleta</b> observes a renegotiation of scientific authority within a complex clash of conflicting claims on the past made by different stakeholders. After the profound change in management and funding after 1989, former state museums and archaeological reconstruction sites now face the need to fulfill requirements of the tourism and histotainment industry and to compete with more and more new local initiatives. Pawleta describes attacks on the scientific authority of archaeologists and their attempts to maintain their epistemic authority – for example through critique of popular reconstruction sites – to illustrate conflicts that arise when the “aim of reconstructions is not congruent with scientific or conservational goals,” and when notions of authenticity differ considerably. He analyzes conflicting modes and motivations of constructing the past, and studies attitudes to scientific knowledge and legitimizing strategies, as well as the making of alternative authorities, and how these practices may destabilize scientific authority today. <b>Andrea Pető</b> discusses academic authority and Hungarian illiberal democracy. Using the idea of the illiberal “polypore state” as an explanatory framework, she shows how the science policy of the Fidesz government perverts the idea of science, turning it into a means of political control. Restructuring the institutional landscape of science, more and more “polypore” institutions are being installed that, like the polypore fungus on a tree, feed on the former academic system by transferring resources to build up their own base, produce their own elite and thus authority. Following Pető’s analysis, the illiberal state's distinctive science policy operates with classic rhetoric modes of scientific authority that are, in fact, neither scientific nor do they share in an authority relying on scientific merit or expertise.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":55388,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2021-12-07\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/bewi.202100035\",\"citationCount\":\"2\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/bewi.202100035\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/bewi.202100035","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

摘要

20世纪和21世纪的特点是广泛的认识论,从实证主义到后现代主义,以及更明确的政治化的民族主义、社会主义、新自由主义或福音派认识论。知识和权力之间的各自关系与不同的认知权威的出现或消失密切相关,其中,科学权威只是其中之一。纵观历史,在不同的文化背景下,我们可以找到各种各样的认知权威人物,他们受到信任、恐惧和质疑:长老、圣人或神谕、教堂和牧师、常识和目击者、媒体和记者。当情境与一种(习惯性的)文化实践相对应,并且权威是由一个已确立的权威人物所拥有时,与知识的不对称分布相伴而来的权威可能会被收件人视为一种自然的东西。显然,作为不对称社会关系的一种表达,权威本质上是模棱两可的——这种模棱两可在托马斯·霍布斯臭名昭著的利维坦中得到了体现,利维坦在和平与保护的公式基础上进行统治,就像他代表它传播恐惧一样。理查德·塞尼特指出,现代社会中权威的模糊性——“权力的情感表达”、“不平等人群之间的纽带”——是基本的情感纽带之一。保护是现代治理的终极目标,这意味着国家对其臣民负有特定的责任,不仅包括保护,还包括保障或改善生活条件,并采取正确的手段实现这些目标。在所谓的“知识社会”中,这些手段是由受过科学教育的专家来决定的。对权威的信任或信仰与对权力的恐惧之间的模糊解释了权威的不断变化,以及为什么有些人可能会失去权威,而另一些人可能会获得权威。此外,习惯上体现认识论权威的社会人物可以——而且经常是——在政治上塑造:通过授予或否认个体主体的权威;具体地取代个人和机构(如威权国家);通过质疑认知权威的文化架构或体现这种权威的社会角色(学者、记者)。权威人物的政治塑造可能是某些社会群体的蓄意行为,但也可能是偶然和不受控制的过程、结构和系统变化等的结果。因此,它与我们在别处所说的“政治认识论”有关由于认识论权威人物对什么应该被认为是知识(什么不应该被认为是知识)有权威,他们类似于真理人物,尽管他们的权威不一定与真理有关,而是与决策有关因此,科学权威人物可以作为真理人物和专家出现,尽管后者的范围较小,例如,作为顾问或顾问。第二次世界大战之前的现代知识社会产生了一种以学术为基础的专业知识,这种专业知识往往伴随着对非科学知识的排斥,而1945年后世界分裂为两个主要的政治阵营,导致了首先忠于各自集团的专家的出现。这些专家不依赖于他们的学术背景,至少基本上不依赖于他们的学术背景,而是得到他们在全球斗争中所代表的政治制度的认可20世纪80年代,艾滋病的流行和日益增强的环保意识、切尔诺贝利事故和科学社会主义的崩溃进一步削弱了人们对科学的信任,引发了人们对科学究竟有多公正、多超然于政治的质疑有人可能会说,这一过程支持了权力的倍增。在这里,我们可以跟随Naomi Oreskes,她在《为什么相信科学?》关于经验问题——关于事实问题——科学应该是我们的主导权威的观点,自启蒙运动以来一直盛行于西方社会,但如果没有争论,这种观点就无法持续下去。我们应该相信科学吗?对奥雷斯克斯来说,对科学作为一种集体努力、作为一种制度的信任,已经取代了18世纪和19世纪学术团体所选择的“‘科学家’的权威”。STS的暗指一个熟悉的问题,她指出,反思科学表明,科学家只是人们做他们的工作,所以信任不是与生俱来的,但必须获得,它可以因为科学的“持续参与世界”及其社会角色:17“关键的一点是,我们的信任的基础不是科学家——明智或正直的人——但是在科学作为一种社会过程,严格审查要求。 今天,匈牙利、波兰或俄罗斯的科学家——无论是在自然科学领域还是在人文科学领域——再次由国家代表根据他们的党派关系和政治倾向分别进行评判。虽然在个人和机构层面上,这产生了深远的影响——不墨守成规的学者被驱逐或内外移民,不受欢迎的研究所被关闭,墨守成规的“多孔”机构被创建——但在更抽象的层面上,科学权威总体上变得越来越相对化。然而,有趣的是,“党派主义”的回归(见本期Nicholchina)也改变了谁被认为是专家的范围:如果缔约国咨询科学家,他们不仅被视为本学科的专家,而且还可以从事其他领域的工作,或者他们甚至可以将自己视为社会和政治问题的一般专家这不仅体现在传统上只得到少数学者支持的民粹主义和右翼政党上,也越来越体现在政治光谱的其他部分上。虽然在普京治下的俄罗斯,专家将军的出现可以解释为缺乏替代方案,这意味着在场的少数专家必须能够超越他们的学科,但在媒体逻辑很重要的匈牙利或波兰,情况并非如此。在这里,信任程度与熟悉程度有关。那些经常出现在媒体上的人比那些有实际专业知识但报道较少的人更容易被信任因此,非自由民主国家正在重复将科学好坏与政治好坏混为一谈,但现在的分界线不是资产阶级与马克思主义,而是在我们可以信任的和我们不能信任的之间但是,正如佩特格在本期(以及其他地方)所指出的,38前社会主义国家的学术体系远不稳定,显然,1989/1991年对科学进步和现代化道路的信念似乎(在某种程度上)naïve。以下文本由三个部分组成,大致按照从国家社会主义到转型/后社会主义到21世纪的时间顺序排列。第一部分包括关注科学机构和行动者(有时是无意的)如何进入允许他们对政治政权进行批评或持不同政见的位置的贡献。在本期的第一篇论文中,Friedrich Cain认为,民主德国的社会主义科学研究将自己置于科学和工业的外部局内人地位。基于社会主义的理解,科学是重要的,不能留给他们自己,而是需要方向,科学研究被赋予了一个演讲者的位置,这使得批评科学,生产,甚至党和国家组织及其相互作用成为可能。因此,科学研究的权威是在一个多向量的交流过程中建立起来的,而不是由政党单独分配或仅基于科学习惯。Miglena Nikolchina在20世纪60年代对保加利亚的政治控制和人文学科的贡献调查了“从共产主义政治权力的入侵中解放科学权威”,指的是教条主义的斯大林主义美学理论与不墨墨成规的艺术哲学家的智力力量之间的对立。通过讨论艺术是自由的产物,“真正的知识分子”(重新)获得了科学权威,而不是政治上制度化的“apparatchicks”权威。第二部分汇集了集中于1989/91后统一的德国和俄罗斯科学系统的转变和最近的再转变的论文。分析关于德意志民主共和国考古学家约阿希姆·赫尔曼(Joachim Herrmann)是“昂纳克的附庸”还是为科学服务的史前学家的争论?安妮·克鲁格对赫尔曼的学术价值和自我合法化的可信度表现出不同的、有争议的观点。她的论文表明,特别是在过渡、不安全和争论的时期,“学术权威和专业学者的地位的授予或否定是高度依赖于语境的,因此是由情境决定的,是历史动态的。”埃拉·罗斯曼(Ella Rossman)提出了另一个在同行中争取认可的例子,她研究了从20世纪90年代到今天,妇女和性别历史学者如何在俄罗斯面临不断变化的政治困难,以及他们如何使用各种策略在后苏联学术界建立科学权威,更具体地说,是学科权威。第一代学者主要在学术界工作。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Introduction: Scientific Authority and the Politics of Science and History in Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe**

What sounds like a laborious set up for a shallow joke actually hits the core of the problem this issue covers: What do the leading archaeologist of the former German Democratic Republic in re-unifying Germany, Bulgarian scientists in the late 1960s and some recent discussions about representations of Polish ancient history have in common? They all operate along fractures in the crust of scientific authority, they mark moments in time when classical figures of knowledge reach or breach authoritative status. They serve to study how authoritative speech bridged and manifested these relations and help identify areas where scientific authority is contested. This volume transcends this topological rhetoric with a praxeological take on scientific authority. Concentrating on authority figures, it brings specific margins and contestations into sight. The papers in this volume study cases from former socialist countries of Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe, and thus examples that present us with the complexity of agonal relations within state socialism and post-socialist transformations that complicate matters of scientific authority in many ways, yet also offer illustrative examples of shifting constellations of (scientific) authority.

This issue is dedicated to historical challenges to scholarship as the paramount producer of facts and their discursive reprocessing. Focusing on historical sciences, sociology, as well as natural sciences and technology and their non-academic counterparts, it maps changes in the political configuration of knowledge production in modern societies. The historical reconstruction and analysis of scientific self-conceptions are aligned with the question of convergence or fragmentation of epistemologies, increase or decline of universalistic claims, and exploitations from particularistic groups’ perspectives. We thus approach the rationalities that divide science and the humanities and politics as well as the “boundary work”1 at the intersections. When and how did the boundaries shift, were they strengthened, weakened or removed, and how did this affect the epistemic figures in different scientific disciplines? We want to know if and to which extent these dynamics, which we recently observe in the fragmentation of epistemic authority and tribalization of truth, can be regarded as an effect of political and socio-economic transformations: of processes of re-nationalization, conservative and religious turns, or the popularization of postmodernity. Where and how can we trace the consequences of the shifts in media technologies that unsettle classic information media, and what impact do social fragmentation and the subsequent emergence of specific groups have on all this?

Following these questions, this issue investigates the relations of scientific practices, reflexive scholarship and changing epistemological frames since the 1960s. Within the broader methodological framework of the history of science and knowledge, it follows the parameters of a “political epistemology” as a mode of observing the settings and developments of epistemology and rationality,2 a mode informed by recent approaches to the history of cold war science,3 and works on politics of knowledge.4 We trace historical interrelations of changes in rhetoric and evolutions of scientific practices of truth and emphasize the local, temporal, institutional, and subjective conditions of epistemological conflicts in regard to the specific role of the scholar as a “truth figure” and her or his contested credibility.5 In this respect, we can rely on studies on historical scientific personae,6 on scholarly practices in natural sciences and the humanities,7 and on epistemic virtues.8

When discussing these phenomena, we understand “scientific authority” as a subcase of “epistemic authority”9 that refers to knowledge in general, including pragmatic (and practical, tacit) and everyday (quotidian) knowledge, as knowledge related to different fields and cultures (religious knowledge, political knowledge, etc.). Scientific authority refers to trust in as well as the social power of scientific knowledge, here including the natural sciences as well as the humanities and social sciences. If, in some of the contributions, academic authority is used synonymously with scientific authority, it is not to deny the long history of the struggle between the epistemic authority of academies and universities but to highlight the aspect of the habitualization and institutionalization of epistemic authority, the apparatus or dispositif of scientific knowledge and its representative – the homo academicus.10 Scientific or academic authority in this sense is thus based on education and sometimes current affiliation to academia, i. e., to universities or research institutions, bestowing professional authority at least in modern knowledge societies.

The 20th and 21st centuries are characterized by a large range of epistemologies, from positivist to postmodernist and more explicitly politicized nationalist, socialist, neoliberal, or evangelical epistemologies. The respective relations between knowledge and power are closely tied to the emergence or disappearance of different epistemic authorities and, amongst these, scientific authority is but one. Various other figures of epistemic authorities can be found in different cultural settings throughout history, trusted, feared, and questioned: the elders, the sage, or the oracle, the church and the priest, common sense and the eye-witness, the press and the journalist. Authority that comes with an asymmetric distribution of knowledge might be regarded as something natural by the addressee when the situation corresponds to a (habitual) cultural practice and authority is carried by an established authority figure.

Obviously, as an expression of asymmetric social relations, authority is inherently ambiguous – an ambiguity displayed in Thomas Hobbes’ notorious Leviathan, who just as much rules on the basis of the formula pax et protectio as he spreads fear on its behalf. Richard Sennett has pointed to the ambiguity of authority in modern societies – “the emotional expression of power,” “a bond between people who are unequal”11 – as one of the basic emotional bonds. Protection being a telos of modern governance, this means that the state has a specific responsibility for its subjects which consists not only in protection but also in safeguarding or improving living conditions and taking the right means to achieve these goals. In the so-called “knowledge society,” it is up to scientifically educated experts to decide what these means are.

The ambiguity between trust or belief in authority, and fear of its power explains the constant shifting of authority and why some figures might lose while others gain authority. Furthermore, social figures that habitually embody epistemic authority can be – and often are – politically shaped: by granting or denying authority to individual subjects; by concretely replacing individuals and institutions (as in authoritarian states); by questioning the cultural architecture of epistemic authority or the social roles that embody it as such (the scholar, the journalist). The political shaping of figures of authority can be a deliberate act of some social groups but it may as well be the result of contingent and uncontrolled processes, structural and systemic changes, etc. Thus, it relates to what we have called “political epistemologies” elsewhere.12 Since epistemic authority figures have authority regarding what has to be considered knowledge (and what does not), they resemble truth figures although their authority does not necessarily relate to truth, but to decisions.13 Accordingly, scientific authority figures can appear as truth figures and as experts although in the latter case with a smaller range as, for instance, advisors or consultants.

While modern knowledge societies before the Second World War produced an academically grounded type of expertise that often came along with the exclusion of non-scientific knowledge, the division of the world into two main political camps after 1945 resulted in the emergence of experts that first and foremost were loyal to their respective blocs. These experts did not – at least not essentially – depend on their academic background, but were validated by the political systems they represented in the global struggle.14 In the 1980s, the AIDS pandemic and growing environmental consciousness, Chernobyl and the collapse of scientific socialism further weakened trust in science prompting the question how unbiased and aloof from politics it really was.15 This process, one could argue, supported the multiplication of authorities. Here, we can follow Naomi Oreskes, who in Why Trust Science? recently connected epistemic authority with trust:

The idea that science should be our dominant authority about empirical matters – about matters of fact – is one that has prevailed in Western societies since the Enlightenment, but it can no longer be sustained without an argument. Should we trust science?16

To Oreskes, trust in science as a collective endeavor, as an institution, has replaced the “authority of the ‘man of science,’” chosen by academic societies in the 18th and 19th centuries. Alluding to a familiar problem of STS, she points out that reflection on science had shown that scientists were just people doing their work, so that trust does not come naturally, but has to be earned, which it can because of science's “sustained engagement with the world” and its social character:17 “The key point is that the basis for our trust is not in scientists – as wise or upright individuals – but in science as a social process that rigorously vets claims.”18 And scientists, who are trained to study the natural world and thus are the experts, have “to explain not just what they know, but how they know it” – Oreskes speaks of “informed trust.”19

The changing relations between science and politics can be well shown regarding examples from Central and Eastern Europe featured in this issue. Miglena Nikolchina observes a differentiation between the epistemic authority of an officially acknowledged and supported science, and that of a dissident one – even if they have been intrinsically entangled and partially depended on each other. This case demonstrates that scientific authority is not only determined by structures of power and social arrangements within the scientific field20 but also by logics of other social fields that penetrate its realm. Along the lines of Pierre Bourdieu, we could describe this as the intrusion of political logic into the scientific field – the political epistemology of scientific authority.21 However, intrusion works in two directions and on several levels. Not only can we highlight general changes in the relation between science and politics but also in the individual tactics of scholars who have used (and still do) their institutional scientific capital to achieve personal goals or tried to strengthen their position by relying on social prestige. As Ella Rossman demonstrates in respect to Russian Gender History or Michał Pawleta for recent Polish archaeology, the political dimension can become more important and create conflicts between pure and institutional scientific authority.22 Thus, authority is always relational and depends on social interaction: it has to be represented by someone and it has to be acknowledged by someone else.

In respect to institutional scientific authority, a modern key figure is the expert. Sociologist Felix Wassermann has pointed out that in democracies, “experts have authority when their advice cannot be easily ignored in the decision-making process,” when their advice demands consideration and actually is being heard in politics, society and the public.23 Still, this definition only refers to situations where authority is displayed and can be observed but does not address the question of how it is constituted: Is it sufficient to be asked for one's knowledge in a specific field to become an expert? Is pure or institutional scientific capital needed or perhaps only social capital? As he discusses the social figure of the expert, Wassermann gives a relational explanation: “[A]n expert is someone who, compared to a layperson, is considered to have more or different knowledge in an area that a (political) decision-maker considers relevant for decision-making.”24 In this issue, however, we attempt to leave aside the grand figure of the expert in order to identify various derivations and their situational contexts. This, of course, opens a plethora of crucially important questions. How is authority constituted in societies, in which information and the access to academia is controlled in a certain restrictive manner; which pure scientific capital might either not be acknowledged or achievable; in which the accumulation of institutional scientific capital depends on political positions; in which the institutions of the scientific field themselves are a creation of elites that try to change the political order, as Andrea Pető discusses for the case of Hungary? Does being part of academia suffice to build up scientific authority in systems that misuse the scientific field to generate trust and respect for their political positions? Can and do epistemic virtues like modesty, trustworthiness, or diligence play a role in these contexts at all? Are even the same areas and kinds of expertise considered relevant for decision-making and, if they are, as in the case of science studies Friedrich Cain examines, why does the scientific authority of the respective experts differ so considerably? How does the transition from non-democratic to democratic regimes (or the other way around) affect these issues? Which strategies do experts apply in cases of regime change in order to transfer their scientific authority from one regime to another? How do they maintain it if their scientific tools and arguments are not enough to keep up their pure scientific capital, as discussed by Michał Pawleta, or if they are able to keep up their scientific standing but not their institutional scientific authority, as Anne Kluger examines?

The wide array of examples in this issue covers a long period from the 1960s until the present; it spans across general historiographic thresholds preventing a too closed geographical denomination. One might assume that the interpenetration of science and politics – and all complications this brings with it for the question of authority of science – is a post-1945 phenomenon. Yet, scholars had already been prominently present as figures of political authority when new states were popping up after the First World War. Philosopher Tomáš Garrigue Masaryk became president of Czechoslovakia, Gabriel Narutowicz, professor for hydraulic engineering at ETH Zürich, was elected president of Poland, historian Mykhailo Hrushevsky presided over the Ukrainian parliament – not to mention the philosopher Lenin who led the Soviet Union and was succeeded by Stalin, a self-proclaimed pantomath.25

In the Soviet Union, not only Sputnik but physicists as a scientific group became symbols of progress and the expected socialist victory over the bourgeois society. But this happened at the cost of “lyricists” – poets or scholars from the humanities – who in the 1960s were deemed to be slowing down the progress-oriented techno-scientists.26 It is hard to estimate how important this discussion was for the diverging social attribution of authority, but while “lyricists” gained epistemic authority as dissidents contesting the regime, natural scientists gained authority as symbols of Soviet power. Yet, as criticizing Soviet Sputnik meant criticizing the Party, increase in authority for these scientists meant that there were new possibilities to claim or to maintain independence from politicians, as Cain reminds us in this issue. Nikolchina analyzes moments in the 1960s, when scientific authority of theory and history of literature emancipated itself from the intrusion of political power in Bulgaria. At the same time, especially historians were the usual go-to-scholars when it came to the big anniversaries, as it was the case for the millennial celebrations of Polish statehood in the 1960s.27

Scientists in socialist states had to face special tensions. They were either acknowledged by politicians and thus able to amass resources, yet often at the cost of losing trust in the eye of the public – or they faced the invert situation as dissidents. While many politicians (not only) from socialist states regarded science as a universal problem-solving tool, it was by no means considered as an elysian hail bringer nor unconditionally accepted by its protagonists. During the 1980s and 1990s, intellectuals in many countries of Central, Eastern, and Southeastern Europe frequently pointed to the extension of scientific knowledge to cover more and more areas of knowing, eventually leading to the dilution of the very idea of science – an issue that was more acutely perceived during the growth of the academic landscape after 1989.28 The crisis of authorities that was detected by sociologists in Poland or Russia during the 1990s then added a new dimension to the relation between science and authority.29 The transformation meant the fall of what had been praised as eternal truth for decades while, at the same time, none of the authorities were able to fill the gap and find broader social acceptance (perhaps except for John Paul II in Poland, who was, until recently, acknowledged by the whole spectrum from post-socialists to new conservatives). In many cases authority was (re)arranged with the support of international foundations which helped create trusted institutions or produce authoritative book series.30 However, as strongly opposing groups often gained considerable local importance, an uncritical narrative of westernization does not help here.31 Rather, we can speak of the post-Soviet academia becoming divided into two competing groups, one following the Soviet paradigm and one following the Western ones.32 The failure of the allegedly science-based socialist system added to a fragmentation of science's genuine epistemic authority in many ways. The question that people posed during socialist times, whether one can trust science if everything can be regarded as scientific, and the question of post-socialism, how one can trust science if a science-based ideology has failed, was joined by the phenomenon of multiplying authorities typical of the Western Bloc.

Authority can be both at once – scientific in a narrow sense and based on administrative power –, but it may also lean in one of the two directions. Hence, trust in science comes in very different shapes, and several of those will be presented in this issue. Our examples from Poland, pre- and postunification Germany, from Bulgaria, Hungary, and Russia show that trust is often linked to the specific reconfigurations of scientific authorities during and after state socialism. One should also be aware that the collapse of state socialism did damage the authority of social sciences in general. Their claim to be able to predict was shattered when the unpredicted occurred.33 The equation of power and truth that has contributed to the recent rise of illiberal democracies has become normal and plausible.34 Today, scientists in Hungary, Poland, or Russia – both in the natural sciences and the humanities – are again judged by state representatives according to their party affiliation and their political orientation respectively. While on a personal and institutional level this has far-reaching consequences – expulsion or internal and external emigration of non-conformist scholars, closure of disfavored institutes and creation of conformist “polypore” institutions – on a more abstract level, the scientific authority in general becomes increasingly relativized.

Interestingly, however, this return of “partiinost” (see Nicholchina in this issue) also changed the scope of who is considered an expert: if scientists are consulted by the state party they are presented not only as experts in their discipline but can be engaged in other domains as well, or they can even present themselves as general experts in societal and political issues.35 This can be observed not only with regard to populist and right-wing parties that have traditionally been supported only by a limited number of scholars but increasingly also regarding other parts of the political spectrum. While in Putin's Russia the emergence of the expert general can be explained by a lack of alternatives, which means that the few experts present have to be able to reach beyond their discipline, this is not (yet) the case in Hungary or Poland where media logics are important. Here, the degree of trust is linked to familiarity. Who frequently appears in the media is likely to be trusted more rather than people with actual expertise but less coverage.36 Thus, illiberal democracies are repeating the conflation of good vs. bad science with good vs. bad politics, but now the dividing line is not bourgeois vs. Marxist but runs between the one we can trust and the one we cannot.37 But, as Pető argues in this issue (and elsewhere),38 the academic systems in former socialist countries are far from stable, and clearly the 1989/1991 belief in a path of progress and modernization of science seems to have been (somewhat) naïve.

The following texts make up three parts that are arranged in, more or less, chronological order from State socialism through transformation/post-socialism up to the 21st century. The first part includes contributions focusing on how scientific institutions and actors (sometimes unintentionally) came into positions that allowed them to perform criticism or dissidence against the political regime. In the first paper of the issue, Friedrich Cain argues that socialist Science Studies in the GDR placed themselves at an external insider position to science and to industry. Based on the socialist understanding that the sciences were important and could not be left to themselves but needed directions, Science Studies were empowered to take up a speaker position which made it possible to criticize science, production, and even party and state organizations as well as their interactions. Thus, the authority of Science Studies was established in a poly-vectoral process of communication, rather than being assigned solely by the party or only based on a scientific habitus. Miglena Nikolchina's contribution about political control and the Humanities in 1960s Bulgaria investigates the “emancipation of scientific authority from the intrusion of communist political power” referring to the opposition between the dogmatic Stalinist theory of aesthetics and the intellectual power of non-conformist philosophers of art. Challenging the official party doctrine of art as a reflection of reality by discussing art as the production of freedom, the “true intellectuals” (re)gained scientific authority over the politically institutionalized authority of the “apparatchicks.”

The second part assembles papers which focus on the transformations and recent re-transformations of post 1989/91 science systems in reunified Germany and in Russia. Analyzing the debates about GDR archaeologist Joachim Herrmann as “‘Honecker's Vassal’ or a Prehistorian in the Service of Science?,” Anne Kluger shows differing and contested perspectives on academic merit and on the credibility of Herrmann's self-legitimation. Her paper suggests that especially times of transition, insecurity, and contention reveal how much “the granting or denying of academic authority and the status of the professional scholar are highly context-dependent and hence situationally determined and historically dynamic.” Another example of a struggle for recognition among peers is presented by Ella Rossman, who examines how women's and gender history scholars faced changing political difficulties in Russia from the 1990s until today and how they used various strategies to build up scientific and, more specifically, disciplinary authority within post-Soviet academia. The first generation of those scholars predominantly worked in the field of academia. They organized large conferences and published volumes – including very diverse contributions – and also emphasized the relevance of gender studies/gender history as well as its applicability in state policy and governmental decision-making. Yet from the 2010s onward, a new movement of feminist political activism brought a new generation of gender historians to the fore who directed their research to wider audiences and gained recognition within and outside academia. While the first generation's strategies, based on the inclusivity of contributors and topics, effectively eroded the concept and aim of gender studies and gender history, the long-term success of the new movement is not yet clearly determinable.

The two final contributions discuss contemporary challenges from (beyond) the borders of science. Focusing on reconstructions of archaeological sites in open-air reserves and theme parks in present-day Poland, Michał Pawleta observes a renegotiation of scientific authority within a complex clash of conflicting claims on the past made by different stakeholders. After the profound change in management and funding after 1989, former state museums and archaeological reconstruction sites now face the need to fulfill requirements of the tourism and histotainment industry and to compete with more and more new local initiatives. Pawleta describes attacks on the scientific authority of archaeologists and their attempts to maintain their epistemic authority – for example through critique of popular reconstruction sites – to illustrate conflicts that arise when the “aim of reconstructions is not congruent with scientific or conservational goals,” and when notions of authenticity differ considerably. He analyzes conflicting modes and motivations of constructing the past, and studies attitudes to scientific knowledge and legitimizing strategies, as well as the making of alternative authorities, and how these practices may destabilize scientific authority today. Andrea Pető discusses academic authority and Hungarian illiberal democracy. Using the idea of the illiberal “polypore state” as an explanatory framework, she shows how the science policy of the Fidesz government perverts the idea of science, turning it into a means of political control. Restructuring the institutional landscape of science, more and more “polypore” institutions are being installed that, like the polypore fungus on a tree, feed on the former academic system by transferring resources to build up their own base, produce their own elite and thus authority. Following Pető’s analysis, the illiberal state's distinctive science policy operates with classic rhetoric modes of scientific authority that are, in fact, neither scientific nor do they share in an authority relying on scientific merit or expertise.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte
Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 社会科学-科学史与科学哲学
CiteScore
0.80
自引率
16.70%
发文量
43
审稿时长
>12 weeks
期刊介绍: Die Geschichte der Wissenschaften ist in erster Linie eine Geschichte der Ideen und Entdeckungen, oft genug aber auch der Moden, Irrtümer und Missverständnisse. Sie hängt eng mit der Entwicklung kultureller und zivilisatorischer Leistungen zusammen und bleibt von der politischen Geschichte keineswegs unberührt.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信