走向神话批判理论:意识形态、习得的无知和想象成功的条件

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Carmen Lea Dege, Tae-Yeoun Keum
{"title":"走向神话批判理论:意识形态、习得的无知和想象成功的条件","authors":"Carmen Lea Dege,&nbsp;Tae-Yeoun Keum","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12813","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Sweeping accounts of the history of the human species—from Rousseau (<span>1997</span> [1755]) to Toynbee (<span>1934–1961</span>) to Diamond (<span>1997</span>) to Harari (<span>2014</span>)—are no novelty in popular culture, just as they are no strangers to controversy. But the debate that ensued around David Graeber and David Wengrow's <i>The Dawn of Everything: A New History of Humanity</i> (<span>2021</span>), perhaps the most significant recent addition to this genre, was different. One especially striking instance of its peculiar reception unfolded in the pages of the <i>New York Review of Books</i> letters section between Wengrow and the philosopher Kwame Anthony Appiah, who had written a lengthy review.</p><p>Appiah was clearly taken with Graeber and Wengrow's project. Expressing admiration for its vision of freedom and political possibility, he rounded off his review with the verdict that, “whatever its empirical shortcomings, the book must be counted an imaginative success” (Appiah <span>2021</span>). But this conclusion also came, almost like an afterthought, at the heels of a detailed report on those very empirical shortcomings, which took up the greater part of his review. In their book, Graeber and Wengrow had positioned themselves as debunkers of a pervasive “myth” about human history: a Rousseauian narrative about the birth of political society from out of an original, prepolitical state, whereby the privatization of property and domination by centralized governments were the necessary price humans had to pay for the complexity of civilization. But among the preponderance of archaeological counterexamples the authors marshaled as a corrective to this myth, not a single one, Appiah judged, held up to strict scrutiny. “Two half-truths, alas, do not make a truth,” he concluded, “and neither do a thousand” (Appiah <span>2021</span>).</p><p>If Appiah had meant to praise the book as an imaginative success, this certainly got lost in the ensuing conversation, which quickly hardened into a debate over facts. In a fiery response, Wengrow defended their empirical foundations, accusing Appiah of being too beholden to the old myth to face the archaeological evidence challenging it. Appiah responded, for his part, by once again highlighting the ambiguities surrounding the evidence, and reaffirming his regard for the authors’ imaginative vision (Wengrow and Appiah <span>2022</span>).</p><p>In this paper, we suggest something crucial is at stake in the crossfire of this conversation. All the parties to the debate agree that disrupting our sense of what is possible in politics is valuable, and that social criticism to this end is ultimately aimed at bringing about conceptual shifts in its audience that are, in essence, imaginative. Such shifts require their subjects to rework their attachments to tacit, subconscious values in the background of their worldviews. As such, successful social critique involves engaging the affective, aesthetic, and indeed mythic dimensions of our thinking that go beyond the realm of empirical facts. Appiah, who has elsewhere defended the value of philosophical fictions that are not factually true (Appiah <span>2017</span>), would be the first to endorse this view. But despite this common ground, both Graeber and Wengrow's book and the ensuing discussion have clearly failed to escape appeals to and squabbles about facts—controversy over which could not help but drown out the imaginative ambition of the broader project. We believe that the tension between the book's aim to produce such an imaginative shift, on the one hand, and the difficulty it has encountered casting this endeavor in terms that are not strictly empirical, on the other, is indicative of a wider problem. Namely, the lack of a more robust theoretical framework for understanding the conditions under which the critique of myths—of the kind that Graeber and Wengrow claim to take up in the <i>Dawn of Everything</i>—can be counted as an imaginative success. What does it mean to critique the deep-seated stories in our inheritance that frame our ideas about who we are, where we come from, and where we are headed? Can we only criticize such stories from the perspective of facts—as factually correct or false—or from the perspective of values, as morally acceptable or problematic?</p><p>In what follows, we attempt to outline a different approach to critiquing myths, one that offers an alternative to both factual debunking and more traditional forms of ideology critique. The idea that the larger-scale stories we tell about our world and its possibilities have a complicated relationship to objective facts is well documented by scholars. Indeed, the crisis of representation was a cornerstone of the so-called “narrative” and “aesthetic turns” that spanned philosophy (e.g., Cavell <span>1976</span>; Latour <span>1993</span>; Rancière <span>1999</span>; Taylor <span>1989</span>), sociology (Berger and Luckmann <span>1966</span>; Goffman <span>1981</span>), psychology (Gergen <span>1999</span>), literary studies (Scarry <span>1994</span>), and history (White <span>2014</span> [1973]). The central concern at the heart of both these turns—a deep skepticism about whether knowledge can be based on secure and certain foundations<i>—</i>has become fraught in recent years, amidst growing anxieties over the political effectiveness of facts, and their uncertain relationship to cultural and social values now often designated as forms of ideology or “pseudo-science” (McIntyre <span>2019</span>). These developments have also accompanied a renewed interest in the role of myths in politics, usually in a negative capacity, as practices of manipulation, gaslighting, or willful distortion and misrepresentation (Brennan <span>2016</span>; Butter and Knight <span>2019</span>; Cassam <span>2019</span>).</p><p>At the same time, there has been a growing acknowledgment within a separate tradition for the need for social critics to return to certain varieties of ideology critique (Cooke <span>n.d</span>.; Hall <span>1986</span>, Haslanger <span>2017</span>; Lafont <span>2023</span>). The push for a more properly “immanent” ideology critique, however, has simultaneously shined a light on the constraints posed by its commitment to the assumption that the self-reflexivity of social criticism demands a rational core (Winter, <span>2025</span>). As such, ideology critique that fails to offer clear rational criteria for drawing distinctions between good and bad myths can risk devolving into an irrational relativism, ultimately fueling the pathologies of authoritarian and populist politics.</p><p>The crossroads at which the tradition of ideology critique stands today highlights the need for further critical reflection on the undertheorized cost it bears for its enduring commitment—however necessary—to the primacy of rationality in social criticism. For one, there is the question of whether such a commitment can be maintained without simultaneously conjuring a prejudice for certain forms of knowledge or privileging <i>knowingness</i> as an epistemic standpoint. These tendencies cannot help but reinforce the proverbial dichotomy between facts and values, encouraging us to idealize objectivity while relativizing subjectivity. To accept these ramifications, in turn, is also to compel us to reconsider the value and efficacy of social critique in polarized political landscapes, where too many individuals, unlikely to be swayed by the authority of facts, will experience such critique as overbearing, moralistic, or elitist.</p><p>Conversely, it remains unclear what kind of social criticism is made possible by the experiential and contextualist—and some might argue relativist—understandings of knowledge to come out of both the aesthetic and narrative turns. Scholars of myth, who have long defined myth precisely in terms of its resistance to fact and argument (Cassirer <span>1965</span>, 29–31; Habermas <span>1987 [1981]</span>, 52–53; Sorel <span>1999</span>, 29), have perennially acknowledged the need to rework the dominant narratives of our political imaginaries, pointing out, in turn, that such projects raise the additional difficulty of determining the criteria by which we might evaluate and critique myths (e.g., Bottici <span>2007</span>, 16). If social critique is ultimately aimed at initiating the kinds of imaginative breakthroughs that free us from our accustomed stories about the world, neither correct facts nor the right ideology might be sufficient to the task.</p><p>Our own effort to think through this challenge is focused on developing an account of one kind of social critique aimed specifically at myths. For our purposes, we define myths as inherited and tacit narratives entrenched in our social world that address, without necessarily giving explanatory answers for, large-scale questions of existential significance for individuals and communities. <i>Myth critique</i>, in our view, requires the critic to creatively rework such myths while preserving a distinctly reflexive admission of ignorance on the questions they address.</p><p>We begin by returning to Graeber and Wengrow's conceptualization of Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth.” Pointing to the ways they deploy both archaeological facts and normative value statements to challenge it, we suggest that Graeber and Wengrow undertake a form of ideology critique that is ultimately inappropriate to myth: a medium that has the distinct attitudinal function of structuring our relationship with opacity and that requires a corresponding form of critique that preserves this function. In the second part of our argument, we build on this insight to outline a framework for conceptualizing myth and what the critique of myths—of the kind that succeeds in a more imaginative overhaul of our deeply held concepts—looks like. Drawing from Karl Jaspers, Hans Blumenberg, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, we argue that <i>myth critique</i> must (1) begin from a position of acknowledging the opacity of its subjects and, as a consequence, (2) is likely to take an aesthetic form. But to mitigate the special pitfalls that aesthetic modes of critique can exacerbate, it must, in addition, (3) cultivate an ethic of what we call <i>learned ignorance</i>. Finally, we develop our own account of this ethic by turning to the work of another anthropologist, Nastassja Martin, who shares Graeber and Wengrow's imaginative ambition, but who, unlike them, chooses to refrain from ideology critique. Martin's own unconventional approach to the critique of myths, we argue, can be productively brought in comparison with more rationalist proposals.</p><p>The word “myth” comes up often in David Graeber's larger oeuvre. In Debt, the “Myth of Barter” and “myth of primordial debt” appear as a pair of “origin stories” and “founding myth[s]” underpinning the history of modern economic thought (Graeber <span>2011</span>, 75, 28), alongside the specter of “mythic communism” that has haunted understandings of the nature and feasibility of communistic forms of social organization (95). In <i>Direct Action</i>, Graeber borrows Michael Taussig's terminology of “mythological warfare” to make sense of both the imagery and narrative frames associated with the police in contemporary America and the media strategies of anarchist protesters, including the myth-making of radical puppeteers (Graeber <span>2009</span>, 487).1 Likewise in <i>The Dawn of Everything</i>, Graeber and Wengrow resort to the language of myth to refer to the stories we have inherited and come to take for granted about humanity's distant past, which also circumscribe our understanding of its future possibilities. Such narratives, for the authors, are myths in the sense that they are origin stories which reflect “our collective fantasies” and structure our current experience (Graeber and Wengrow <span>2021</span>, 78, 525). But they are also myths because the particular stories that happen to frame how we currently tend to imagine human prehistory have “almost nothing to do with the facts” made available by recent empirical scholarship (4–5). One myth in particular was the target of the book, and, to great controversy, the authors attributed its source to Rousseau's <i>Second Discourse</i>.</p><p>For Graeber and Wengrow, we still live in the shadow of a distinct origin myth: a linear narrative about the birth of civilization out of the State of Nature through a succession of discrete stages. In Rousseau's consequential rendering of this account, the final civilizing step that seals humanity's unfreedom is set in motion by the discovery of agriculture and metallurgy—a pair of events that lead to the institutionalization of private property and a centralized government dedicated to protecting it. Thus, for Rousseau (<span>1997</span>, 161), the “true founder of civil society” was “the first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, to whom it occurred to say <i>this is mine</i>, and found people sufficiently simple to believe him.” The problem with this narrative, for Graeber and Wengrow, is not that Rousseau tied his account of humanity's moral decline to the advent of property—an insight they argue Rousseau owed to an indigenous critique of private property articulated by the Huron-Wendat chief Kandiaronk (Graeber and Wengrow <span>2021</span>, 48-59). Rather, Graeber and Wengrow fault Rousseau and the European reception of his conjectural history for failing to grasp Kandiaronk's point that society might be “based on anything else” other than property (66). By perpetuating the assumption that hierarchical domination organized around the privatization of property is hardwired in our nature, Rousseau's narrative helped trap the modern imagination in “such tight conceptual shackles that we can no longer even imagine the possibility of reinventing ourselves” (9). It is not so much our original harmony with nature that has been lost, but our sense of possibility.</p><p>Accordingly, the primary motivation behind Graeber and Wengrow's move to present Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth” is to begin undoing the long-term damage they claim it has done to our political imagination. At stake in such myths was the very “imaginative” project that Appiah had lauded them for taking on: a conceptual shift that might restore “that freedom to imagine and enact other forms of social existence” (Graeber and Wengrow <span>2021</span>, 502).</p><p>Graeber and Wengrow's approach to confronting the myth they identify, however, was a striking blend of empirical debunking and what essentially amounted to ideology critique. One prominent line of their attack was to expose the Rousseauian narrative as false, presenting an exhaustive catalog of archaeological evidence across their 450-page tome—from Göbekli Tepe, Stonehenge, Minoa, and Teotihuacan—suggesting the existence of large, complex early societies that were not dependent on domination by a centralized source of authority. But if Graeber and Wengrow attempted to counter a myth with a deluge of facts, their facts were also hardly ideologically neutral. Another strand of their effort to respond to their Rousseauian myth consistently emphasized that progress in the social sciences depends on practices of rupture and provocation that destabilize their own hegemonic assumptions. “Real change,” they argued, was the result of transformative moments of social breakthrough in which “the lines between myth and history, science and magic become blurred” (524). Social theory, on this view, was ultimately a “game of make-believe” for critics to actively intervene in (21), and Graeber and Wengrow accordingly saw their own task as the telling of a better story that can provide at once “a more accurate, and hopeful, picture of world history” (8). The authority wielded by the sheer volume of their empirical evidence operated within the performative framework of such a game, presenting a curious combination of rationalism and voluntarism that blurred the line between facts and values. The result was a form of critique predicated on a perspective external to the myth they set out to overturn—a privileged standpoint of knowingness from which they could judge the Rousseauvian account as “not only wrong, but quite needlessly dull” (21, see also 3).</p><p>In many ways, this quasi-rational ideology critique reflects a more general uncertainty in the political and theoretic discourse on the appropriate way to respond to myths. Theorists of myth have repeatedly emphasized that myths cannot be reduced to factual falsehoods (Bottici <span>2007</span>; De Vriese <span>2017</span>), just as a rich tradition of scholarship reminds us that the cultural authority of the modern fact is the product of a contingent history (Poovey <span>1998</span>; see White <span>2014</span>), and that this authority is often instrumentalized to serve distorted narratives about reality. All the same, political discourse and theory have yet to shake off the reigning intuition that myths are best countered by exposing them as factually or epistemologically deficient.</p><p>More significantly, Graeber and Wengrow's project obscures a theoretical tension that has of late been gaining traction within the long tradition of ideology critique. Once defined by a distinctly German idealist focus on critique and an emphasis on the Marxist concept of false consciousness (Ng <span>2015</span>), this tradition conventionally positioned the social critic as an external adjudicator, evaluating society from an Archimedean vantage point. Ideology critique has since converged on a more immanent approach (Stahl <span>2021</span>). In the wake of models offered by philosophical genealogy and the psychoanalytic method (Koopman <span>2013</span>; Saar <span>2007</span>; Žižek <span>1994</span>), as well as from radical democratic theory (Celikates <span>2018</span>; Rancière <span>1999</span>; Laclau and Mouffe <span>2001</span>), contemporary understandings of ideology critique have increasingly shifted toward seeing the objects of their criticism, not as logical ideational structures, but as tacit, often preconscious, systems of social meaning that implicate the critic in the very contradictions they seek to shed light on. How exactly the social critic can grasp the logical structure of such ideas <i>immanently</i> has long been a topic of heated debate (Cooke <span>n.d</span>.; Habermas <span>1987 [1981]</span>; Horkheimer <span>1972</span>; Jaeggi <span>2014</span>). Against the backdrop of an increasingly multipolar, crisis-ridden world, the question turns on whether ideology critics, deprived of their privileged vantage point, can still insist on a rationalist framework of critique that claims to distinguish between the authentic and the alienated, the progressive and the regressive. Pointing to this tension, Yves Winter (<span>2025</span>, 6) rightly observes that ideology critique, thus understood, “must be able to draw from a ‘rational element’ within ideology, in other words, something that is true and that is objective.” While the move toward immanent critique, then, helps ideology critics adopt a more nuanced view both of society's value commitments and of their internal contradictions—as practical systems of belief that are dynamic rather than static, and open to reworking from within—the presumption of such a rational kernel still leaves them in a position of epistemic and moral authority over others. As long as it remains committed to this assumption, immanent ideology critique understands the critic to operate at a special remove from those whose practices they seek to examine: more able to discern what is false, distorted, or morally inconsistent in society, and better positioned to envision paths for overcoming conditions of unfreedom. Emancipation, thus understood, remains at its core a rational endeavor.</p><p>Graeber and Wengrow's <i>The Dawn of Everything</i> encapsulates these more recent developments in ideology critique, along with the double bind that critics in this tradition face as they simultaneously refuse and reproduce the practices they criticize. It is clear that Graeber and Wengrow do not view their subject in terms of the traditional concept of false consciousness, and their genealogical reinterpretation of Rousseau's <i>Second Discourse</i> intimates that Gramsci's antihegemonic practices are close to their heart. It is equally clear that their critique is launched from a standpoint rooted in the idea of a rational truth outside the myth in question, where the rigor of scientific falsification ultimately meets the disruptive tactics of the activist seeking to denaturalize the status quo. From this perspective, our entrenched narratives about property and hierarchical domination reveal their ideological nature—a distorted aspiration to the rational idea of freedom.</p><p>But if Graeber and Wengrow's approach reflects where ideology critique currently stands, it also brings its constraints into starker relief. At one level, the fixation in the book's public reception on the accuracy of its empirical claims—rather than on the imaginative shift they aimed to inspire—highlights how narrowly their discourse was confined to an ideological base already committed to the value of envisioning alternatives to the established order. At another level, Graeber and Wengrow's unwitting adoption of the tools and epistemological assumptions of ideology critique also constricts their ability to address the imaginaries in question on their own terms. Too quick to present their critique as emancipatory without acknowledging those who, lacking their plethora of facts and clarity of moral insight, would not experience it as such, the authors miss an opportunity to engage the deeper cognitive attachments people may have to the narratives they set out to unmask. This can paint a rather limited picture of what social criticism can mean.</p><p>But if we take seriously Graeber and Wengrow's characterization of Rousseau's conjectural history as a myth, there is reason to question whether this kind of ideology critique is ultimately appropriate to the medium. For all the eccentricity of their take, Graeber and Wengrow are by no means the only ones to read Rousseau's conjectural history in mythic terms. Throughout the reception of the <i>Second Discourse</i>, debates over its truth-status have tended to converge on two traditional camps: those who believe Rousseau's conjectural history was constructed purely as a thought experiment, never intended to be taken literally, and those who believe he did in fact aim to give “a factually accurate description of the original human situation” (Brennan <span>2020</span>, 586; see Neuhouser <span>2014</span>; Rousseau <span>1997</span> [1755], 132; Scott <span>1992</span>). As Christopher Kelly (<span>2006</span>, 78) suggested in a landmark survey, a third position that resisted both these answers was to understand Rousseau's prehistory as a “myth.” For Kelly, who rejected this reading himself, the mythic interpretation of Rousseau's prehistory meant ruling out the idea that it was meant to have “any genuine explanatory use.” Instead, its function would be “solely rhetorical, having the goal of stimulating nostalgia for a non-existent past in which the problems of modern life did not exist” (78). In a different vein, another familiar way the concept of myth has been applied to the <i>Second Discourse</i> stems from Carole Pateman's (<span>1988</span>) iconic critique of the social contract tradition as having an obscuring or veiling function. This is something that several readers of Pateman's <i>The Sexual Contract</i> have often drawn out more explicitly, by referring several times to her reading of Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth” that, deceptively, naturalizes conjugal relations in the state of nature (Anderson <span>2002</span>, 108; Hirschmann <span>1990</span>).2</p><p>Both these senses in which Rousseau's conjectural history can be considered “mythic” are helpful, in that they emphasize the narrative and figurative features of how the conjectural history helps penetrate into the imaginative framework in which Rousseau expects his readers to operate, as well as the distinctive opaqueness that this introduces to its effect. But the rhetorical and ideological accounts are also partial in that they play down the capacity of these features to be more constructive and, indeed, to advance human freedom. This is an important point of emphasis in the interpretation offered by Emma Planinc (<span>2023</span>) of Rousseau as a “political mythologist” invested in the possibility of an original natural language that could “persuade without convincing” (6, 21). This mythic language, for Planinc, is a form of “storytelling over fact founding” that directs Rousseau's audience away from the realities of the societal status quo he is seeking to denaturalize (2). The image of the natural man is persuasive precisely because it is not meant “to convince us of its truth,” but to provide a vivid contrast between this condition and our distorted nature in civilized society: “Man must be persuaded that he is born free,” she tells us, “if he is to see that everywhere he is in chains” (23–24). So transforming and directing hearts toward freedom crucially rest not on ideological certainty but on creating an awareness that “we do not know ourselves as well as we think we do” (22). While Rousseau's prehistory may lack an explanatory function, it serves an attitudinal one: of organizing and structuring our relationship with that which we do not know.</p><p>A definitive verdict on what Rousseau truly intended is outside the scope of this article. But we need not take sides on the question here to see how “mythic” readings of Rousseau's conjectural history offer insight into the possibilities of myth that Graeber and Wengrow's critique overlook. First, as Planinc's mythic reading of Rousseau suggests, myths are not necessarily incompatible with an emancipatory political vision. Second, myths can create awareness of what we do not know. Such an awareness, in turn, is essential for social criticism, a source of epistemic humility, and a recognition of the importance of nonrational commitments for communal welfare and solidarity. Myths about prehistory can help us distance ourselves from the images that hold us captive. When we view the large-scale narratives we tell about our origins through this more expansive mythic lens, we can see that it requires a form of critique that preserves these possibilities. Where more established models of criticizing factual untruths or ideology are predicated on a sense of scientific and ideological knowingness that judges from a perspective external to myths, reversing this mode of criticism might help us embrace the ways myth structures our relationship with opacity without overcoming it. In so doing, we can take more seriously the constructive role that ignorance can play as the negation, rejection, or undoing of knowingness.</p><p>We have seen that there is a case for conceiving of prehistories like Rousseau's in mythic terms and that there is a problem of critique specific to myth. Myths, as we elaborate below, can be conceptualized as a specific response to the contingencies that surround us and, in contrast to knowledge and power, and despite their projection of authoritativeness, myths do not aim at recuperating certainty. Rather, they sustain and embed forms of opacity as they persuade <i>nonrationally</i> by reworking and organizing the individual, sociocultural and political responses to what we do not know. In what follows, we outline a framework for a form of critique that foregrounds the significance of these qualities.</p><p>If Graeber and Wengrow had missed an important opportunity in conceiving of Rousseau's prehistory as a myth but ultimately subjecting it to a form of ideology critique, what would constitute an approach that's more appropriate to their critical target—and to the imaginative shift they sought to spark? In the remainder of this article, we present a counterpoint to Graeber and Wengrow's critical endeavor, offering a different vision of what the critique of myth can look like. We turn, in particular, to Nastassja Martin's <i>In the Eye of the Wild</i> (<span>2021</span>) as an illustrative example of social critique that takes unknowing as a precondition for engaging mythic narratives that are foundational to our worldviews. Like Graeber and Wengrow, Martin seeks to disarm an especially pervasive set of imaginative frameworks structuring Western culture. But in contrast to Graeber and Wengrow, who engage with indigenous perspectives only insofar as they provide, for the purposes of ideology critique, a critical mirror that reflects back at Europeans their own historicity, Martin discovers in them the ground for an original language that “persuades without convincing.” In turn, she tackles the dangers of denialism regarding the epistemic limits of such a project, by offering instead an aesthetic form of critique bounded by an ethic of learned ignorance. Opacity, on this approach, becomes a central component of philosophical reflection itself. This is an insight that Martin develops through a critical engagement with the trope of “the wild” and, with it, our customary ways of relating to nature.</p><p>Both <i>The Dawn of Everything</i> and <i>In the Eye of the Wild</i> are visionary works by anthropologists that tackle longstanding myths ingrained in Western social imaginaries and aspire to loosen the hold they have on our capacity to imagine alternative ways of living. While the former engages in a form of ideology critique aimed at exposing an entrenched narrative about the progress of human civilization as both untrue and morally wrong, the latter reworks our go-to templates for envisioning our relationship to nature, connecting them to dreams and bodily experiences that invite a non-dominating mode of attunement with it. We have sought in this article to present a framework for an approach to critiquing myths that takes seriously the qualities that render them opaque to reason, suggesting that these very qualities can serve an important attitudinal function that the critique of myths should accordingly preserve and strengthen. To assume a position of learned ignorance toward what we take for granted, as we read Martin as demonstrating, is to clear a path for introducing imaginative shifts in historically entrenched, naturalized stories that invite retelling rather than abandonment.</p><p>Doing anthropology in a mode sensitive to this rhythm involves for Martin a process of translation that resonates with Merleau-Ponty's, Blumenberg's and Jaspers's central insight that it is yet possible to address the dominant narratives in society, not as ideologies that are illusory and wrong, but as mythologies that have forgotten their indebtedness to what remains ambiguous and opaque. This reframing helps us recognize the continuity linking such narratives to larger traditions of storytelling and interpretive practice, foregrounding their imaginative character as well as their multiplicity. In this sense, the creative process of translating from one iteration of a myth to another does not yield a discourse aimed at establishing a rational truth based on principled agreement. We could, rather, following a thought of Walter Benjamin, argue that such translation “touches” truth (<span>2007</span> [1955], 80), as the original features of the myth change aesthetic forms and bring the existential needs driving it within the reach of what we can actively relate to. To use a different analogy, we could say with Wittgenstein, “Don't think, but look!” (<span>1986</span>, 66). Just as his famous rabbit–duck illusion reminds us how shifting perspectives can expand what we see, the critical reworking and retelling of our myths can help us cultivate a different political optics—one that sharpens our ability to notice those aspects of those narratives that broaden its range of possibilities. Before all other normative considerations, the standpoint of myth critique first of all demands an ethic of learned ignorance that suspends the contours of a particular shape in order to see and inhabit another.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"32 2","pages":"286-297"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2025-05-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12813","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Toward a Theory of Myth Critique: Ideology, Learned Ignorance, and the Conditions of Imaginative Success\",\"authors\":\"Carmen Lea Dege,&nbsp;Tae-Yeoun Keum\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12813\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Sweeping accounts of the history of the human species—from Rousseau (<span>1997</span> [1755]) to Toynbee (<span>1934–1961</span>) to Diamond (<span>1997</span>) to Harari (<span>2014</span>)—are no novelty in popular culture, just as they are no strangers to controversy. But the debate that ensued around David Graeber and David Wengrow's <i>The Dawn of Everything: A New History of Humanity</i> (<span>2021</span>), perhaps the most significant recent addition to this genre, was different. One especially striking instance of its peculiar reception unfolded in the pages of the <i>New York Review of Books</i> letters section between Wengrow and the philosopher Kwame Anthony Appiah, who had written a lengthy review.</p><p>Appiah was clearly taken with Graeber and Wengrow's project. Expressing admiration for its vision of freedom and political possibility, he rounded off his review with the verdict that, “whatever its empirical shortcomings, the book must be counted an imaginative success” (Appiah <span>2021</span>). But this conclusion also came, almost like an afterthought, at the heels of a detailed report on those very empirical shortcomings, which took up the greater part of his review. In their book, Graeber and Wengrow had positioned themselves as debunkers of a pervasive “myth” about human history: a Rousseauian narrative about the birth of political society from out of an original, prepolitical state, whereby the privatization of property and domination by centralized governments were the necessary price humans had to pay for the complexity of civilization. But among the preponderance of archaeological counterexamples the authors marshaled as a corrective to this myth, not a single one, Appiah judged, held up to strict scrutiny. “Two half-truths, alas, do not make a truth,” he concluded, “and neither do a thousand” (Appiah <span>2021</span>).</p><p>If Appiah had meant to praise the book as an imaginative success, this certainly got lost in the ensuing conversation, which quickly hardened into a debate over facts. In a fiery response, Wengrow defended their empirical foundations, accusing Appiah of being too beholden to the old myth to face the archaeological evidence challenging it. Appiah responded, for his part, by once again highlighting the ambiguities surrounding the evidence, and reaffirming his regard for the authors’ imaginative vision (Wengrow and Appiah <span>2022</span>).</p><p>In this paper, we suggest something crucial is at stake in the crossfire of this conversation. All the parties to the debate agree that disrupting our sense of what is possible in politics is valuable, and that social criticism to this end is ultimately aimed at bringing about conceptual shifts in its audience that are, in essence, imaginative. Such shifts require their subjects to rework their attachments to tacit, subconscious values in the background of their worldviews. As such, successful social critique involves engaging the affective, aesthetic, and indeed mythic dimensions of our thinking that go beyond the realm of empirical facts. Appiah, who has elsewhere defended the value of philosophical fictions that are not factually true (Appiah <span>2017</span>), would be the first to endorse this view. But despite this common ground, both Graeber and Wengrow's book and the ensuing discussion have clearly failed to escape appeals to and squabbles about facts—controversy over which could not help but drown out the imaginative ambition of the broader project. We believe that the tension between the book's aim to produce such an imaginative shift, on the one hand, and the difficulty it has encountered casting this endeavor in terms that are not strictly empirical, on the other, is indicative of a wider problem. Namely, the lack of a more robust theoretical framework for understanding the conditions under which the critique of myths—of the kind that Graeber and Wengrow claim to take up in the <i>Dawn of Everything</i>—can be counted as an imaginative success. What does it mean to critique the deep-seated stories in our inheritance that frame our ideas about who we are, where we come from, and where we are headed? Can we only criticize such stories from the perspective of facts—as factually correct or false—or from the perspective of values, as morally acceptable or problematic?</p><p>In what follows, we attempt to outline a different approach to critiquing myths, one that offers an alternative to both factual debunking and more traditional forms of ideology critique. The idea that the larger-scale stories we tell about our world and its possibilities have a complicated relationship to objective facts is well documented by scholars. Indeed, the crisis of representation was a cornerstone of the so-called “narrative” and “aesthetic turns” that spanned philosophy (e.g., Cavell <span>1976</span>; Latour <span>1993</span>; Rancière <span>1999</span>; Taylor <span>1989</span>), sociology (Berger and Luckmann <span>1966</span>; Goffman <span>1981</span>), psychology (Gergen <span>1999</span>), literary studies (Scarry <span>1994</span>), and history (White <span>2014</span> [1973]). The central concern at the heart of both these turns—a deep skepticism about whether knowledge can be based on secure and certain foundations<i>—</i>has become fraught in recent years, amidst growing anxieties over the political effectiveness of facts, and their uncertain relationship to cultural and social values now often designated as forms of ideology or “pseudo-science” (McIntyre <span>2019</span>). These developments have also accompanied a renewed interest in the role of myths in politics, usually in a negative capacity, as practices of manipulation, gaslighting, or willful distortion and misrepresentation (Brennan <span>2016</span>; Butter and Knight <span>2019</span>; Cassam <span>2019</span>).</p><p>At the same time, there has been a growing acknowledgment within a separate tradition for the need for social critics to return to certain varieties of ideology critique (Cooke <span>n.d</span>.; Hall <span>1986</span>, Haslanger <span>2017</span>; Lafont <span>2023</span>). The push for a more properly “immanent” ideology critique, however, has simultaneously shined a light on the constraints posed by its commitment to the assumption that the self-reflexivity of social criticism demands a rational core (Winter, <span>2025</span>). As such, ideology critique that fails to offer clear rational criteria for drawing distinctions between good and bad myths can risk devolving into an irrational relativism, ultimately fueling the pathologies of authoritarian and populist politics.</p><p>The crossroads at which the tradition of ideology critique stands today highlights the need for further critical reflection on the undertheorized cost it bears for its enduring commitment—however necessary—to the primacy of rationality in social criticism. For one, there is the question of whether such a commitment can be maintained without simultaneously conjuring a prejudice for certain forms of knowledge or privileging <i>knowingness</i> as an epistemic standpoint. These tendencies cannot help but reinforce the proverbial dichotomy between facts and values, encouraging us to idealize objectivity while relativizing subjectivity. To accept these ramifications, in turn, is also to compel us to reconsider the value and efficacy of social critique in polarized political landscapes, where too many individuals, unlikely to be swayed by the authority of facts, will experience such critique as overbearing, moralistic, or elitist.</p><p>Conversely, it remains unclear what kind of social criticism is made possible by the experiential and contextualist—and some might argue relativist—understandings of knowledge to come out of both the aesthetic and narrative turns. Scholars of myth, who have long defined myth precisely in terms of its resistance to fact and argument (Cassirer <span>1965</span>, 29–31; Habermas <span>1987 [1981]</span>, 52–53; Sorel <span>1999</span>, 29), have perennially acknowledged the need to rework the dominant narratives of our political imaginaries, pointing out, in turn, that such projects raise the additional difficulty of determining the criteria by which we might evaluate and critique myths (e.g., Bottici <span>2007</span>, 16). If social critique is ultimately aimed at initiating the kinds of imaginative breakthroughs that free us from our accustomed stories about the world, neither correct facts nor the right ideology might be sufficient to the task.</p><p>Our own effort to think through this challenge is focused on developing an account of one kind of social critique aimed specifically at myths. For our purposes, we define myths as inherited and tacit narratives entrenched in our social world that address, without necessarily giving explanatory answers for, large-scale questions of existential significance for individuals and communities. <i>Myth critique</i>, in our view, requires the critic to creatively rework such myths while preserving a distinctly reflexive admission of ignorance on the questions they address.</p><p>We begin by returning to Graeber and Wengrow's conceptualization of Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth.” Pointing to the ways they deploy both archaeological facts and normative value statements to challenge it, we suggest that Graeber and Wengrow undertake a form of ideology critique that is ultimately inappropriate to myth: a medium that has the distinct attitudinal function of structuring our relationship with opacity and that requires a corresponding form of critique that preserves this function. In the second part of our argument, we build on this insight to outline a framework for conceptualizing myth and what the critique of myths—of the kind that succeeds in a more imaginative overhaul of our deeply held concepts—looks like. Drawing from Karl Jaspers, Hans Blumenberg, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, we argue that <i>myth critique</i> must (1) begin from a position of acknowledging the opacity of its subjects and, as a consequence, (2) is likely to take an aesthetic form. But to mitigate the special pitfalls that aesthetic modes of critique can exacerbate, it must, in addition, (3) cultivate an ethic of what we call <i>learned ignorance</i>. Finally, we develop our own account of this ethic by turning to the work of another anthropologist, Nastassja Martin, who shares Graeber and Wengrow's imaginative ambition, but who, unlike them, chooses to refrain from ideology critique. Martin's own unconventional approach to the critique of myths, we argue, can be productively brought in comparison with more rationalist proposals.</p><p>The word “myth” comes up often in David Graeber's larger oeuvre. In Debt, the “Myth of Barter” and “myth of primordial debt” appear as a pair of “origin stories” and “founding myth[s]” underpinning the history of modern economic thought (Graeber <span>2011</span>, 75, 28), alongside the specter of “mythic communism” that has haunted understandings of the nature and feasibility of communistic forms of social organization (95). In <i>Direct Action</i>, Graeber borrows Michael Taussig's terminology of “mythological warfare” to make sense of both the imagery and narrative frames associated with the police in contemporary America and the media strategies of anarchist protesters, including the myth-making of radical puppeteers (Graeber <span>2009</span>, 487).1 Likewise in <i>The Dawn of Everything</i>, Graeber and Wengrow resort to the language of myth to refer to the stories we have inherited and come to take for granted about humanity's distant past, which also circumscribe our understanding of its future possibilities. Such narratives, for the authors, are myths in the sense that they are origin stories which reflect “our collective fantasies” and structure our current experience (Graeber and Wengrow <span>2021</span>, 78, 525). But they are also myths because the particular stories that happen to frame how we currently tend to imagine human prehistory have “almost nothing to do with the facts” made available by recent empirical scholarship (4–5). One myth in particular was the target of the book, and, to great controversy, the authors attributed its source to Rousseau's <i>Second Discourse</i>.</p><p>For Graeber and Wengrow, we still live in the shadow of a distinct origin myth: a linear narrative about the birth of civilization out of the State of Nature through a succession of discrete stages. In Rousseau's consequential rendering of this account, the final civilizing step that seals humanity's unfreedom is set in motion by the discovery of agriculture and metallurgy—a pair of events that lead to the institutionalization of private property and a centralized government dedicated to protecting it. Thus, for Rousseau (<span>1997</span>, 161), the “true founder of civil society” was “the first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, to whom it occurred to say <i>this is mine</i>, and found people sufficiently simple to believe him.” The problem with this narrative, for Graeber and Wengrow, is not that Rousseau tied his account of humanity's moral decline to the advent of property—an insight they argue Rousseau owed to an indigenous critique of private property articulated by the Huron-Wendat chief Kandiaronk (Graeber and Wengrow <span>2021</span>, 48-59). Rather, Graeber and Wengrow fault Rousseau and the European reception of his conjectural history for failing to grasp Kandiaronk's point that society might be “based on anything else” other than property (66). By perpetuating the assumption that hierarchical domination organized around the privatization of property is hardwired in our nature, Rousseau's narrative helped trap the modern imagination in “such tight conceptual shackles that we can no longer even imagine the possibility of reinventing ourselves” (9). It is not so much our original harmony with nature that has been lost, but our sense of possibility.</p><p>Accordingly, the primary motivation behind Graeber and Wengrow's move to present Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth” is to begin undoing the long-term damage they claim it has done to our political imagination. At stake in such myths was the very “imaginative” project that Appiah had lauded them for taking on: a conceptual shift that might restore “that freedom to imagine and enact other forms of social existence” (Graeber and Wengrow <span>2021</span>, 502).</p><p>Graeber and Wengrow's approach to confronting the myth they identify, however, was a striking blend of empirical debunking and what essentially amounted to ideology critique. One prominent line of their attack was to expose the Rousseauian narrative as false, presenting an exhaustive catalog of archaeological evidence across their 450-page tome—from Göbekli Tepe, Stonehenge, Minoa, and Teotihuacan—suggesting the existence of large, complex early societies that were not dependent on domination by a centralized source of authority. But if Graeber and Wengrow attempted to counter a myth with a deluge of facts, their facts were also hardly ideologically neutral. Another strand of their effort to respond to their Rousseauian myth consistently emphasized that progress in the social sciences depends on practices of rupture and provocation that destabilize their own hegemonic assumptions. “Real change,” they argued, was the result of transformative moments of social breakthrough in which “the lines between myth and history, science and magic become blurred” (524). Social theory, on this view, was ultimately a “game of make-believe” for critics to actively intervene in (21), and Graeber and Wengrow accordingly saw their own task as the telling of a better story that can provide at once “a more accurate, and hopeful, picture of world history” (8). The authority wielded by the sheer volume of their empirical evidence operated within the performative framework of such a game, presenting a curious combination of rationalism and voluntarism that blurred the line between facts and values. The result was a form of critique predicated on a perspective external to the myth they set out to overturn—a privileged standpoint of knowingness from which they could judge the Rousseauvian account as “not only wrong, but quite needlessly dull” (21, see also 3).</p><p>In many ways, this quasi-rational ideology critique reflects a more general uncertainty in the political and theoretic discourse on the appropriate way to respond to myths. Theorists of myth have repeatedly emphasized that myths cannot be reduced to factual falsehoods (Bottici <span>2007</span>; De Vriese <span>2017</span>), just as a rich tradition of scholarship reminds us that the cultural authority of the modern fact is the product of a contingent history (Poovey <span>1998</span>; see White <span>2014</span>), and that this authority is often instrumentalized to serve distorted narratives about reality. All the same, political discourse and theory have yet to shake off the reigning intuition that myths are best countered by exposing them as factually or epistemologically deficient.</p><p>More significantly, Graeber and Wengrow's project obscures a theoretical tension that has of late been gaining traction within the long tradition of ideology critique. Once defined by a distinctly German idealist focus on critique and an emphasis on the Marxist concept of false consciousness (Ng <span>2015</span>), this tradition conventionally positioned the social critic as an external adjudicator, evaluating society from an Archimedean vantage point. Ideology critique has since converged on a more immanent approach (Stahl <span>2021</span>). In the wake of models offered by philosophical genealogy and the psychoanalytic method (Koopman <span>2013</span>; Saar <span>2007</span>; Žižek <span>1994</span>), as well as from radical democratic theory (Celikates <span>2018</span>; Rancière <span>1999</span>; Laclau and Mouffe <span>2001</span>), contemporary understandings of ideology critique have increasingly shifted toward seeing the objects of their criticism, not as logical ideational structures, but as tacit, often preconscious, systems of social meaning that implicate the critic in the very contradictions they seek to shed light on. How exactly the social critic can grasp the logical structure of such ideas <i>immanently</i> has long been a topic of heated debate (Cooke <span>n.d</span>.; Habermas <span>1987 [1981]</span>; Horkheimer <span>1972</span>; Jaeggi <span>2014</span>). Against the backdrop of an increasingly multipolar, crisis-ridden world, the question turns on whether ideology critics, deprived of their privileged vantage point, can still insist on a rationalist framework of critique that claims to distinguish between the authentic and the alienated, the progressive and the regressive. Pointing to this tension, Yves Winter (<span>2025</span>, 6) rightly observes that ideology critique, thus understood, “must be able to draw from a ‘rational element’ within ideology, in other words, something that is true and that is objective.” While the move toward immanent critique, then, helps ideology critics adopt a more nuanced view both of society's value commitments and of their internal contradictions—as practical systems of belief that are dynamic rather than static, and open to reworking from within—the presumption of such a rational kernel still leaves them in a position of epistemic and moral authority over others. As long as it remains committed to this assumption, immanent ideology critique understands the critic to operate at a special remove from those whose practices they seek to examine: more able to discern what is false, distorted, or morally inconsistent in society, and better positioned to envision paths for overcoming conditions of unfreedom. Emancipation, thus understood, remains at its core a rational endeavor.</p><p>Graeber and Wengrow's <i>The Dawn of Everything</i> encapsulates these more recent developments in ideology critique, along with the double bind that critics in this tradition face as they simultaneously refuse and reproduce the practices they criticize. It is clear that Graeber and Wengrow do not view their subject in terms of the traditional concept of false consciousness, and their genealogical reinterpretation of Rousseau's <i>Second Discourse</i> intimates that Gramsci's antihegemonic practices are close to their heart. It is equally clear that their critique is launched from a standpoint rooted in the idea of a rational truth outside the myth in question, where the rigor of scientific falsification ultimately meets the disruptive tactics of the activist seeking to denaturalize the status quo. From this perspective, our entrenched narratives about property and hierarchical domination reveal their ideological nature—a distorted aspiration to the rational idea of freedom.</p><p>But if Graeber and Wengrow's approach reflects where ideology critique currently stands, it also brings its constraints into starker relief. At one level, the fixation in the book's public reception on the accuracy of its empirical claims—rather than on the imaginative shift they aimed to inspire—highlights how narrowly their discourse was confined to an ideological base already committed to the value of envisioning alternatives to the established order. At another level, Graeber and Wengrow's unwitting adoption of the tools and epistemological assumptions of ideology critique also constricts their ability to address the imaginaries in question on their own terms. Too quick to present their critique as emancipatory without acknowledging those who, lacking their plethora of facts and clarity of moral insight, would not experience it as such, the authors miss an opportunity to engage the deeper cognitive attachments people may have to the narratives they set out to unmask. This can paint a rather limited picture of what social criticism can mean.</p><p>But if we take seriously Graeber and Wengrow's characterization of Rousseau's conjectural history as a myth, there is reason to question whether this kind of ideology critique is ultimately appropriate to the medium. For all the eccentricity of their take, Graeber and Wengrow are by no means the only ones to read Rousseau's conjectural history in mythic terms. Throughout the reception of the <i>Second Discourse</i>, debates over its truth-status have tended to converge on two traditional camps: those who believe Rousseau's conjectural history was constructed purely as a thought experiment, never intended to be taken literally, and those who believe he did in fact aim to give “a factually accurate description of the original human situation” (Brennan <span>2020</span>, 586; see Neuhouser <span>2014</span>; Rousseau <span>1997</span> [1755], 132; Scott <span>1992</span>). As Christopher Kelly (<span>2006</span>, 78) suggested in a landmark survey, a third position that resisted both these answers was to understand Rousseau's prehistory as a “myth.” For Kelly, who rejected this reading himself, the mythic interpretation of Rousseau's prehistory meant ruling out the idea that it was meant to have “any genuine explanatory use.” Instead, its function would be “solely rhetorical, having the goal of stimulating nostalgia for a non-existent past in which the problems of modern life did not exist” (78). In a different vein, another familiar way the concept of myth has been applied to the <i>Second Discourse</i> stems from Carole Pateman's (<span>1988</span>) iconic critique of the social contract tradition as having an obscuring or veiling function. This is something that several readers of Pateman's <i>The Sexual Contract</i> have often drawn out more explicitly, by referring several times to her reading of Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth” that, deceptively, naturalizes conjugal relations in the state of nature (Anderson <span>2002</span>, 108; Hirschmann <span>1990</span>).2</p><p>Both these senses in which Rousseau's conjectural history can be considered “mythic” are helpful, in that they emphasize the narrative and figurative features of how the conjectural history helps penetrate into the imaginative framework in which Rousseau expects his readers to operate, as well as the distinctive opaqueness that this introduces to its effect. But the rhetorical and ideological accounts are also partial in that they play down the capacity of these features to be more constructive and, indeed, to advance human freedom. This is an important point of emphasis in the interpretation offered by Emma Planinc (<span>2023</span>) of Rousseau as a “political mythologist” invested in the possibility of an original natural language that could “persuade without convincing” (6, 21). This mythic language, for Planinc, is a form of “storytelling over fact founding” that directs Rousseau's audience away from the realities of the societal status quo he is seeking to denaturalize (2). The image of the natural man is persuasive precisely because it is not meant “to convince us of its truth,” but to provide a vivid contrast between this condition and our distorted nature in civilized society: “Man must be persuaded that he is born free,” she tells us, “if he is to see that everywhere he is in chains” (23–24). So transforming and directing hearts toward freedom crucially rest not on ideological certainty but on creating an awareness that “we do not know ourselves as well as we think we do” (22). While Rousseau's prehistory may lack an explanatory function, it serves an attitudinal one: of organizing and structuring our relationship with that which we do not know.</p><p>A definitive verdict on what Rousseau truly intended is outside the scope of this article. But we need not take sides on the question here to see how “mythic” readings of Rousseau's conjectural history offer insight into the possibilities of myth that Graeber and Wengrow's critique overlook. First, as Planinc's mythic reading of Rousseau suggests, myths are not necessarily incompatible with an emancipatory political vision. Second, myths can create awareness of what we do not know. Such an awareness, in turn, is essential for social criticism, a source of epistemic humility, and a recognition of the importance of nonrational commitments for communal welfare and solidarity. Myths about prehistory can help us distance ourselves from the images that hold us captive. When we view the large-scale narratives we tell about our origins through this more expansive mythic lens, we can see that it requires a form of critique that preserves these possibilities. Where more established models of criticizing factual untruths or ideology are predicated on a sense of scientific and ideological knowingness that judges from a perspective external to myths, reversing this mode of criticism might help us embrace the ways myth structures our relationship with opacity without overcoming it. In so doing, we can take more seriously the constructive role that ignorance can play as the negation, rejection, or undoing of knowingness.</p><p>We have seen that there is a case for conceiving of prehistories like Rousseau's in mythic terms and that there is a problem of critique specific to myth. Myths, as we elaborate below, can be conceptualized as a specific response to the contingencies that surround us and, in contrast to knowledge and power, and despite their projection of authoritativeness, myths do not aim at recuperating certainty. Rather, they sustain and embed forms of opacity as they persuade <i>nonrationally</i> by reworking and organizing the individual, sociocultural and political responses to what we do not know. In what follows, we outline a framework for a form of critique that foregrounds the significance of these qualities.</p><p>If Graeber and Wengrow had missed an important opportunity in conceiving of Rousseau's prehistory as a myth but ultimately subjecting it to a form of ideology critique, what would constitute an approach that's more appropriate to their critical target—and to the imaginative shift they sought to spark? In the remainder of this article, we present a counterpoint to Graeber and Wengrow's critical endeavor, offering a different vision of what the critique of myth can look like. We turn, in particular, to Nastassja Martin's <i>In the Eye of the Wild</i> (<span>2021</span>) as an illustrative example of social critique that takes unknowing as a precondition for engaging mythic narratives that are foundational to our worldviews. Like Graeber and Wengrow, Martin seeks to disarm an especially pervasive set of imaginative frameworks structuring Western culture. But in contrast to Graeber and Wengrow, who engage with indigenous perspectives only insofar as they provide, for the purposes of ideology critique, a critical mirror that reflects back at Europeans their own historicity, Martin discovers in them the ground for an original language that “persuades without convincing.” In turn, she tackles the dangers of denialism regarding the epistemic limits of such a project, by offering instead an aesthetic form of critique bounded by an ethic of learned ignorance. Opacity, on this approach, becomes a central component of philosophical reflection itself. This is an insight that Martin develops through a critical engagement with the trope of “the wild” and, with it, our customary ways of relating to nature.</p><p>Both <i>The Dawn of Everything</i> and <i>In the Eye of the Wild</i> are visionary works by anthropologists that tackle longstanding myths ingrained in Western social imaginaries and aspire to loosen the hold they have on our capacity to imagine alternative ways of living. While the former engages in a form of ideology critique aimed at exposing an entrenched narrative about the progress of human civilization as both untrue and morally wrong, the latter reworks our go-to templates for envisioning our relationship to nature, connecting them to dreams and bodily experiences that invite a non-dominating mode of attunement with it. We have sought in this article to present a framework for an approach to critiquing myths that takes seriously the qualities that render them opaque to reason, suggesting that these very qualities can serve an important attitudinal function that the critique of myths should accordingly preserve and strengthen. To assume a position of learned ignorance toward what we take for granted, as we read Martin as demonstrating, is to clear a path for introducing imaginative shifts in historically entrenched, naturalized stories that invite retelling rather than abandonment.</p><p>Doing anthropology in a mode sensitive to this rhythm involves for Martin a process of translation that resonates with Merleau-Ponty's, Blumenberg's and Jaspers's central insight that it is yet possible to address the dominant narratives in society, not as ideologies that are illusory and wrong, but as mythologies that have forgotten their indebtedness to what remains ambiguous and opaque. This reframing helps us recognize the continuity linking such narratives to larger traditions of storytelling and interpretive practice, foregrounding their imaginative character as well as their multiplicity. In this sense, the creative process of translating from one iteration of a myth to another does not yield a discourse aimed at establishing a rational truth based on principled agreement. We could, rather, following a thought of Walter Benjamin, argue that such translation “touches” truth (<span>2007</span> [1955], 80), as the original features of the myth change aesthetic forms and bring the existential needs driving it within the reach of what we can actively relate to. To use a different analogy, we could say with Wittgenstein, “Don't think, but look!” (<span>1986</span>, 66). Just as his famous rabbit–duck illusion reminds us how shifting perspectives can expand what we see, the critical reworking and retelling of our myths can help us cultivate a different political optics—one that sharpens our ability to notice those aspects of those narratives that broaden its range of possibilities. Before all other normative considerations, the standpoint of myth critique first of all demands an ethic of learned ignorance that suspends the contours of a particular shape in order to see and inhabit another.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"32 2\",\"pages\":\"286-297\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2025-05-12\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12813\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12813\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12813","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

从卢梭(1997[1755])到汤因比(1934-1961),从戴蒙德(1997)到赫拉利(2014),对人类历史的全面描述在流行文化中并不新鲜,就像他们对争议并不陌生一样。但围绕大卫·格雷伯和大卫·温格罗的《万物的黎明:人类的新历史》(2021年出版)展开的争论却有所不同,这本书可能是这一流派最近最重要的新作。在《纽约书评》(New York Review of Books)上,温格罗与哲学家夸梅·安东尼·阿皮亚(Kwame Anthony Appiah)之间的书信部分,出现了一个特别引人注目的例子,后者写了一篇长篇评论。阿皮亚显然被格雷伯和温格罗的项目所吸引。他对其对自由和政治可能性的愿景表示钦佩,并在评论中总结道:“无论它在经验上有什么缺点,这本书必须被视为想象力上的成功”(Appiah 2021)。但是,这个结论几乎是在一份详细的报告之后才得出的,这份报告占据了他的评论的大部分篇幅。在他们的书中,格雷伯和温格罗将自己定位为一个关于人类历史的普遍“神话”的拆解者:一个卢梭式的关于政治社会诞生于原始的、前政治国家的叙述,在这个国家中,财产私有化和中央政府的统治是人类必须为文明的复杂性付出的必要代价。但阿皮亚认为,在作者列举的众多考古学反例中,没有一个能经得起严格审查。“唉,两个半真半假的事实不能构成一个事实,”他总结道,“一千个也不能”(Appiah 2021)。如果阿皮亚是想称赞这本书是一个富有想象力的成功,那么在随后的谈话中,这一点肯定被忽略了,谈话很快就变成了对事实的争论。在激烈的回应中,温格罗为他们的经验基础辩护,指责阿皮亚过于依赖古老的神话,而不去面对挑战它的考古证据。Appiah对此的回应是,他再次强调了证据的模糊性,并重申了他对作者想象力的尊重(Wengrow and Appiah 2022)。在本文中,我们认为在这场对话的交火中,一些至关重要的东西处于危险之中。辩论的各方都同意,破坏我们对政治可能性的认识是有价值的,为此目的的社会批评的最终目的是在其受众中带来概念上的转变,这种转变本质上是富有想象力的。这种转变要求他们的主体在他们的世界观背景下重新处理他们对隐性的、潜意识的价值观的依恋。因此,成功的社会批判涉及到超越经验事实领域的情感、美学,甚至是我们思维的神话维度。阿皮亚(Appiah, 2017)在其他地方为并非事实的哲学虚构的价值辩护,他将是第一个支持这一观点的人。但是,尽管有这些共同点,格雷伯和温格罗的书以及随后的讨论显然都未能避免对事实的呼吁和争论——这些争论无法帮助淹没了更广泛项目的想象力雄心。我们认为,一方面,这本书的目的是产生这样一种富有想象力的转变,另一方面,它遇到的困难是在不严格的经验主义的条件下进行这种努力,这表明了一个更广泛的问题。也就是说,缺乏一个更强大的理论框架来理解对神话的批判的条件——格雷伯和温格罗在《万物的黎明》中所宣称的那种——可以算作是想象上的成功。批评我们继承的根深蒂固的故事意味着什么?这些故事构成了我们对自己是谁、我们来自哪里、我们将走向何方的看法。我们是否只能从事实的角度来批评这些故事——事实是正确的还是错误的?或者从价值观的角度来批评这些故事,道德上是可以接受的还是有问题的?在接下来的内容中,我们试图概述一种不同的批评神话的方法,这种方法为事实揭穿和更传统的意识形态批评形式提供了另一种选择。学者们有充分的证据表明,我们讲述的关于我们的世界及其可能性的更大范围的故事与客观事实有着复杂的关系。事实上,再现危机是跨越哲学的所谓“叙事”和“美学转向”的基石(例如,Cavell 1976;拉图1993;Ranciere 1999;Taylor 1989),社会学(Berger and Luckmann 1966;戈夫曼(Goffman, 1981)、心理学(Gergen, 1999)、文学研究(Scarry, 1994)和历史(White, 2014[1973])。 近年来,随着人们对事实的政治有效性以及它们与文化和社会价值之间的不确定关系日益感到焦虑,这两种转变的核心关注点——对知识是否可以建立在安全和确定的基础上的深刻怀疑——变得令人担忧,而事实与文化和社会价值之间的不确定关系现在通常被称为意识形态形式或“伪科学”(McIntyre 2019)。这些发展还伴随着对神话在政治中的作用的重新关注,通常以消极的方式,作为操纵、煤气灯或故意扭曲和歪曲的做法(Brennan 2016;黄油和骑士2019;Cassam 2019)。与此同时,在一个独立的传统中,越来越多的人认识到社会批评家需要回归到某些意识形态批评的种类(Cooke等人;Hall 1986, Haslanger 2017;拉丰2023)。然而,对更恰当的“内在”意识形态批判的推动,同时也揭示了其对社会批评的自我反思要求理性核心这一假设的承诺所构成的约束(Winter, 2025)。因此,意识形态批判如果不能为区分好神话和坏神话提供明确的理性标准,就有可能沦为非理性的相对主义,最终助长威权主义和民粹主义政治的病态。意识形态批判传统今天所处的十字路口,突出了对其持久承诺——无论多么必要——在社会批判中理性至上——所承担的未理论化成本的进一步批判反思的必要性。首先,存在这样一个问题,即这种承诺是否能够在不同时产生对某些形式的知识的偏见或将知识作为认识论立场的特权的情况下得以维持。这些倾向只能强化众所周知的事实与价值的二分法,鼓励我们将客观性理想化,同时将主观性相对化。接受这些后果,反过来,也迫使我们重新考虑社会批评在两极分化的政治景观中的价值和效力,在那里,太多的个人,不太可能被事实的权威所左右,将经历这样的批评,专横的,道德主义的,或精英主义的。相反,尚不清楚的是,经验主义和语境主义——有些人可能认为是相对主义——对知识的理解从美学和叙事的转折中产生,从而使什么样的社会批评成为可能。研究神话的学者们,他们长期以来精确地根据神话对事实和论证的抵抗来定义神话(Cassirer 1965, 29-31;Habermas 1987 [1981], 52-53;Sorel 1999,29)一直承认有必要重新设计我们政治想象的主导叙事,并指出,反过来,这些项目增加了确定我们可能评估和批评神话的标准的额外困难(例如,Bottici 2007,16)。如果社会批判的最终目的是发起各种富有想象力的突破,将我们从我们对世界的习惯故事中解放出来,那么无论是正确的事实还是正确的意识形态都不足以完成这项任务。我们自己思考这个挑战的努力,集中在发展一种专门针对神话的社会批判。为了达到我们的目的,我们将神话定义为在我们的社会世界中根深蒂固的继承和隐性叙事,它解决了对个人和社区存在意义的大规模问题,而不一定给出解释性的答案。在我们看来,神话批判要求批评家创造性地重新创作这些神话,同时对它们所涉及的问题保持一种明显的反身性承认。我们首先回到格雷伯和温格罗将卢梭的推测史概念化为“神话”。指出他们利用考古事实和规范价值陈述来挑战它的方式,我们认为格雷伯和温格罗采取了一种最终不适合神话的意识形态批判形式:一种具有独特态度功能的媒介,它构建了我们与不透明的关系,并且需要一种相应的批评形式来保持这种功能。在我们论证的第二部分,我们将以此为基础,勾勒出一个将神话概念化的框架,以及对神话的批评——这种批评成功地对我们根深蒂固的概念进行了更具想象力的彻底检查——是什么样子的。借鉴卡尔·雅斯贝尔斯、汉斯·布鲁门伯格和莫里斯·梅洛-庞蒂的观点,我们认为神话批判必须(1)从承认其主体的不透明性的立场开始,因此,(2)很可能采取一种美学形式。但是,为了减轻审美批判模式可能加剧的特殊陷阱,它还必须(3)培养一种我们称之为习得的无知的伦理。 最后,我们通过另一位人类学家纳斯塔西娅·马丁(Nastassja Martin)的作品来发展我们自己对这种伦理的解释。马丁与格雷伯和温格罗有着同样富有想象力的抱负,但与他们不同的是,他选择避免对意识形态进行批判。我们认为,马丁自己对神话批判的非常规方法,可以与更理性主义的建议进行富有成效的比较。“神话”这个词在大卫·格雷伯的大型作品中经常出现。​在《直接行动》一书中,格雷伯借用了迈克尔·陶西格(Michael Taussig)的术语“神话战争”来理解与当代美国警察和无政府主义抗议者的媒体策略相关的意象和叙事框架,包括激进木偶操纵者的神话制造(格雷伯2009,487)同样,在《万物的黎明》中,格雷伯和温格罗用神话的语言来描述我们继承下来的故事,这些故事讲述了人类遥远的过去,我们认为这是理所当然的,这也限制了我们对未来可能性的理解。对于作者来说,这样的叙述是神话,因为它们是反映“我们的集体幻想”并构建我们当前经验的起源故事(Graeber和Wengrow 2021, 78,525)。但它们也是神话,因为恰好构成我们目前对人类史前历史的想象的特定故事,“几乎与最近的实证研究所提供的事实无关”(4-5)。其中一个神话是这本书的主要目标,尽管引起了巨大的争议,但作者们将其来源归因于卢梭的《第二论述》。对于格雷伯和温格罗来说,我们仍然生活在一个独特的起源神话的阴影下:一个关于文明诞生的线性叙事,通过一系列离散的阶段从自然状态中诞生。在卢梭对这一描述的相应描述中,农业和冶金的发现开启了人类不自由的最后一个文明步骤——这两件事导致了私有财产的制度化和一个致力于保护私有财产的中央政府。因此,对于卢梭(1997,161)来说,“公民社会的真正缔造者”是“第一个圈定了一块土地,对他说这是我的,并发现人们足够简单而相信他的人”。对格雷伯和温格罗来说,这一叙述的问题并不在于卢梭将他对人类道德衰落的描述与财产的出现联系在一起——他们认为卢梭的洞察力应归功于休伦-温达特酋长坎迪亚翁克对私有财产的本土批判(格雷伯和温格罗2021年,48-59)。相反,格雷伯和温格罗指责卢梭和欧洲人对他的推测历史的接受,因为他们没有领会坎迪亚翁克的观点,即社会可能“基于任何其他东西”,而不是财产(66)。通过延续围绕财产私有化组织起来的等级统治的假设,卢梭的叙述有助于将现代想象力困在“如此紧密的概念枷锁中,以至于我们甚至无法想象重塑自我的可能性”(9)。与其说我们失去了与自然的和谐,不如说我们失去了对可能性的感觉。因此,格雷伯和温格罗将卢梭的臆测历史描述为“神话”背后的主要动机是开始消除他们声称卢梭的臆测历史对我们的政治想象力造成的长期损害。这些神话的关键是阿皮亚称赞他们所承担的非常“富有想象力”的项目:一种概念上的转变,可能会恢复“想象和制定其他形式的社会存在的自由”(格雷伯和温格罗2021年,502)。然而,格雷伯和温格罗面对他们所认定的神话的方法,是实证揭穿和本质上相当于意识形态批判的惊人结合。他们攻击的一个突出路线是揭露卢梭的叙述是错误的,在他们450页的大部头中展示了详尽的考古证据目录——从Göbekli特佩、巨石阵、米诺阿和特奥蒂瓦坎——表明存在着大型、复杂的早期社会,这些社会不依赖于中央集权的统治。但是,如果格雷伯和温格罗试图用大量的事实来反驳一个神话,他们的事实也很难在意识形态上保持中立。他们回应卢梭神话的另一种努力始终强调,社会科学的进步依赖于破坏和挑衅的实践,这些实践破坏了他们自己的霸权假设。 他们认为,“真正的变化”是社会突破的变革时刻的结果,在这些时刻,“神话与历史、科学与魔法之间的界限变得模糊”(524)。在这种观点下,社会理论最终是一场“假装的游戏”,让评论家积极介入(21),因此格雷伯和温格罗认为他们自己的任务是讲述一个更好的故事,能够立即提供“一幅更准确、更有希望的世界历史图景”(8)。在这种游戏的表演框架内,大量的经验证据所掌握的权威,呈现出一种理性主义和唯意志主义的奇怪结合,模糊了事实与价值之间的界限。其结果是一种基于他们着手推翻的神话之外的观点的批判形式——一种特权的认识立场,他们可以从中判断卢梭的叙述“不仅是错误的,而且是相当不必要的沉闷”(21,也见3)。在许多方面,这种准理性的意识形态批判反映了政治和理论话语中对回应神话的适当方式的更普遍的不确定性。神话理论家一再强调,神话不能被简化为事实谬误(波提奇2007;De Vriese 2017),正如丰富的学术传统提醒我们,现代事实的文化权威是偶然历史的产物(Poovey 1998;(见White 2014),而且这种权威经常被用来服务于对现实的扭曲叙述。尽管如此,政治话语和理论尚未摆脱主流的直觉,即神话的最佳反击方式是将其暴露为事实或认识论上的缺陷。更重要的是,格雷伯和温格罗的项目掩盖了一种理论张力,这种张力最近在意识形态批判的悠久传统中获得了牵引力。一旦被一个明显的德国唯心主义者定义为批判和强调马克思主义的错误意识概念(Ng 2015),这一传统通常将社会批评家定位为外部审查员,从阿基米德的优势角度评估社会。从那以后,意识形态批判转向了一种更内在的方法(Stahl 2021)。在哲学谱系学和精神分析方法提供的模型之后(Koopman 2013;萨尔州2007;Žižek 1994),以及激进民主理论(Celikates 2018;Ranciere 1999;Laclau and Mouffe 2001),当代对意识形态批判的理解已经越来越多地转向将他们的批评对象视为不符合逻辑的观念结构,而是作为默示的,通常是前意识的社会意义系统,这些系统将评论家隐含在他们试图揭示的矛盾中。长期以来,社会批评家究竟如何内在地把握这些思想的逻辑结构一直是一个激烈争论的话题(Cooke等人;Habermas 1987 [1981];霍克1972;杰西2014)。在一个日益多极化、危机四伏的世界背景下,问题转向了意识形态批评家,他们被剥夺了特权优势,是否还能坚持一种理性主义的批评框架,声称能够区分真实与异化,进步与倒退。伊夫·温特(Yves Winter, 2025, 6)指出了这种紧张关系,他正确地指出,意识形态批判,由此理解,“必须能够从意识形态中的‘理性元素’中汲取,换句话说,就是真实和客观的东西。”因此,虽然走向内在批判有助于意识形态批评家对社会的价值承诺及其内部矛盾采取更细致入微的观点——作为动态而非静态的实用信仰体系,并且可以从内部进行改造——但这种理性内核的假设仍然使他们处于认知和道德权威的地位。只要内在意识形态批判坚持这一假设,它就能理解批评家与那些他们试图审视的人的实践有一个特殊的距离:更能辨别出社会中什么是虚假的、扭曲的或道德上不一致的,并能更好地设想克服不自由条件的途径。这样理解的解放,其核心仍然是一种理性的努力。格雷伯和温格罗的《万物的黎明》概括了意识形态批判的这些最新发展,以及这一传统的批评者在拒绝和复制他们所批评的实践时所面临的双重困境。很明显,格雷伯和温格罗并没有按照传统的错误意识概念来看待他们的主题,他们对卢梭《第二话语》的宗谱重新解释表明葛兰西的反霸权实践接近他们的内心。 虽然卢梭的史前史可能缺乏解释功能,但它提供了一种态度:组织和构建我们与未知事物的关系。关于卢梭真正意图的明确判断超出了本文的范围。但是,我们不需要在这个问题上偏袒任何一方,就可以看到卢梭的“神话”解读是如何为神话的可能性提供洞见的,而这正是格雷伯和温格罗的批判所忽视的。首先,正如普兰宁对卢梭的神话解读所表明的那样,神话不一定与解放的政治愿景不相容。其次,神话可以让我们意识到我们所不知道的事情。反过来,这种意识对于社会批评是必不可少的,它是认知谦卑的来源,也是对非理性承诺对社区福利和团结的重要性的认识。关于史前的神话可以帮助我们远离束缚我们的形象。当我们通过更广阔的神话镜头来看待我们讲述的关于我们起源的大规模叙事时,我们可以看到,它需要一种保留这些可能性的批判形式。更成熟的批评事实谎言或意识形态的模式是基于科学和意识形态的认知,从神话之外的角度进行判断,扭转这种批评模式可能有助于我们接受神话构建我们与不透明关系的方式,而不是克服它。这样,我们就可以更认真地看待无知所扮演的否定、拒绝或破坏知识的建设性角色。我们已经看到,有一种情况,可以用神话的术语来理解像卢梭这样的史前史,也有一个神话特有的批判问题。神话,正如我们在下面详细阐述的,可以被概念化为对我们周围的偶然事件的具体反应,与知识和权力相反,尽管它们的权威投射,神话的目的不是恢复确定性。相反,他们通过重新设计和组织个人、社会文化和政治对我们所不知道的事情的反应,非理性地说服人们,从而维持和嵌入不透明的形式。在接下来的内容中,我们概述了一种批判形式的框架,它突出了这些品质的重要性。如果格雷伯和温格罗错过了一个重要的机会,将卢梭的史前史视为一个神话,但最终将其置于一种意识形态批判的形式之下,那么,什么样的方法更适合他们的批判目标——以及他们试图引发的想象转变?在本文的剩余部分,我们将提出与格雷伯和温格罗的批判努力相对应的观点,为神话批判提供一种不同的视角。我们特别把纳斯塔西娅·马丁的《荒野之眼》(in the Eye of the Wild, 2021)作为社会批判的一个说明性例子,它把不知道作为参与神话叙事的先决条件,而神话叙事是我们世界观的基础。像格雷伯和温格罗一样,马丁试图解除构建西方文化的一套特别普遍的想象框架。但与格雷伯和温格罗相反,马丁在他们身上发现了一种“说服而不令人信服”的原创语言的基础,而格雷伯和温格罗只是在意识形态批判的目的下,就本土视角而言,他们提供了一面反映欧洲人自身历史的批判性镜子。反过来,她通过提供一种美学形式的批判,以博学无知的伦理为界限,解决了关于这种项目的认知限制的否认主义的危险。在这种方法中,不透明成为哲学反思本身的核心组成部分。这是马丁通过对“荒野”这一比喻的批判性接触,以及与之相关的我们与自然的习惯方式而发展起来的一种洞察力。《万物的黎明》和《荒野之眼》都是人类学家富有远见的作品,它们解决了西方社会想象中根深蒂固的长期神话,并渴望放松它们对我们想象另一种生活方式的能力的束缚。前者是一种意识形态批判,旨在揭露一种关于人类文明进步的根深蒂固的叙述,这种叙述既不真实,又在道德上是错误的,而后者则重新设计了我们设想我们与自然关系的模板,将它们与梦想和身体体验联系起来,邀请一种非主导模式的协调。在这篇文章中,我们试图提出一个框架,为一种批评神话的方法,这种方法认真对待使神话不透明的品质,表明这些品质可以发挥重要的态度功能,因此,神话的批评应该保留和加强。 就像我们读到马丁所展示的那样,对我们认为理所当然的东西采取一种习得性无知的立场,是为在历史上根深蒂固的、自然化的故事中引入富有想象力的转变扫清了道路,这些故事会引起重述,而不是被抛弃。对马丁来说,在一种对这种节奏敏感的模式下做人类学涉及到一个翻译过程,这个过程与梅洛-庞蒂、布鲁门伯格和雅斯贝尔斯的核心见解产生共鸣,即仍然有可能解决社会中的主导叙事,而不是将其视为虚幻和错误的意识形态,而是将其视为忘记了对仍然模棱两可和不透明的东西的债务的神话。这种重构有助于我们认识到这种叙事与更大的讲故事和解释实践传统之间的连续性,突出了它们的想象力特征和多样性。从这个意义上说,从神话的一个迭代到另一个迭代的创作过程并没有产生一个旨在建立基于原则一致的理性真理的话语。相反,我们可以遵循沃尔特·本雅明(Walter Benjamin)的思想,认为这种翻译“触及”了真理(2007[1955],80),因为神话的原始特征改变了审美形式,并将推动它的存在主义需求置于我们能够积极联系的范围内。用一个不同的类比,我们可以用维特根斯坦的话来说,“不要思考,要看!”(1986, 66)。正如他著名的“兔鸭错觉”提醒我们,不断变化的视角可以扩展我们所看到的东西,对神话进行批判性的改造和复述可以帮助我们培养一种不同的政治光学——这种光学可以提高我们注意到叙事中那些方面的能力,从而扩大叙事的可能性范围。在所有其他规范性考虑之前,神话批判的立场首先要求一种博学无知的伦理,这种伦理悬置了特定形状的轮廓,以便看到并居住在另一个形状中。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Toward a Theory of Myth Critique: Ideology, Learned Ignorance, and the Conditions of Imaginative Success

Sweeping accounts of the history of the human species—from Rousseau (1997 [1755]) to Toynbee (1934–1961) to Diamond (1997) to Harari (2014)—are no novelty in popular culture, just as they are no strangers to controversy. But the debate that ensued around David Graeber and David Wengrow's The Dawn of Everything: A New History of Humanity (2021), perhaps the most significant recent addition to this genre, was different. One especially striking instance of its peculiar reception unfolded in the pages of the New York Review of Books letters section between Wengrow and the philosopher Kwame Anthony Appiah, who had written a lengthy review.

Appiah was clearly taken with Graeber and Wengrow's project. Expressing admiration for its vision of freedom and political possibility, he rounded off his review with the verdict that, “whatever its empirical shortcomings, the book must be counted an imaginative success” (Appiah 2021). But this conclusion also came, almost like an afterthought, at the heels of a detailed report on those very empirical shortcomings, which took up the greater part of his review. In their book, Graeber and Wengrow had positioned themselves as debunkers of a pervasive “myth” about human history: a Rousseauian narrative about the birth of political society from out of an original, prepolitical state, whereby the privatization of property and domination by centralized governments were the necessary price humans had to pay for the complexity of civilization. But among the preponderance of archaeological counterexamples the authors marshaled as a corrective to this myth, not a single one, Appiah judged, held up to strict scrutiny. “Two half-truths, alas, do not make a truth,” he concluded, “and neither do a thousand” (Appiah 2021).

If Appiah had meant to praise the book as an imaginative success, this certainly got lost in the ensuing conversation, which quickly hardened into a debate over facts. In a fiery response, Wengrow defended their empirical foundations, accusing Appiah of being too beholden to the old myth to face the archaeological evidence challenging it. Appiah responded, for his part, by once again highlighting the ambiguities surrounding the evidence, and reaffirming his regard for the authors’ imaginative vision (Wengrow and Appiah 2022).

In this paper, we suggest something crucial is at stake in the crossfire of this conversation. All the parties to the debate agree that disrupting our sense of what is possible in politics is valuable, and that social criticism to this end is ultimately aimed at bringing about conceptual shifts in its audience that are, in essence, imaginative. Such shifts require their subjects to rework their attachments to tacit, subconscious values in the background of their worldviews. As such, successful social critique involves engaging the affective, aesthetic, and indeed mythic dimensions of our thinking that go beyond the realm of empirical facts. Appiah, who has elsewhere defended the value of philosophical fictions that are not factually true (Appiah 2017), would be the first to endorse this view. But despite this common ground, both Graeber and Wengrow's book and the ensuing discussion have clearly failed to escape appeals to and squabbles about facts—controversy over which could not help but drown out the imaginative ambition of the broader project. We believe that the tension between the book's aim to produce such an imaginative shift, on the one hand, and the difficulty it has encountered casting this endeavor in terms that are not strictly empirical, on the other, is indicative of a wider problem. Namely, the lack of a more robust theoretical framework for understanding the conditions under which the critique of myths—of the kind that Graeber and Wengrow claim to take up in the Dawn of Everything—can be counted as an imaginative success. What does it mean to critique the deep-seated stories in our inheritance that frame our ideas about who we are, where we come from, and where we are headed? Can we only criticize such stories from the perspective of facts—as factually correct or false—or from the perspective of values, as morally acceptable or problematic?

In what follows, we attempt to outline a different approach to critiquing myths, one that offers an alternative to both factual debunking and more traditional forms of ideology critique. The idea that the larger-scale stories we tell about our world and its possibilities have a complicated relationship to objective facts is well documented by scholars. Indeed, the crisis of representation was a cornerstone of the so-called “narrative” and “aesthetic turns” that spanned philosophy (e.g., Cavell 1976; Latour 1993; Rancière 1999; Taylor 1989), sociology (Berger and Luckmann 1966; Goffman 1981), psychology (Gergen 1999), literary studies (Scarry 1994), and history (White 2014 [1973]). The central concern at the heart of both these turns—a deep skepticism about whether knowledge can be based on secure and certain foundationshas become fraught in recent years, amidst growing anxieties over the political effectiveness of facts, and their uncertain relationship to cultural and social values now often designated as forms of ideology or “pseudo-science” (McIntyre 2019). These developments have also accompanied a renewed interest in the role of myths in politics, usually in a negative capacity, as practices of manipulation, gaslighting, or willful distortion and misrepresentation (Brennan 2016; Butter and Knight 2019; Cassam 2019).

At the same time, there has been a growing acknowledgment within a separate tradition for the need for social critics to return to certain varieties of ideology critique (Cooke n.d.; Hall 1986, Haslanger 2017; Lafont 2023). The push for a more properly “immanent” ideology critique, however, has simultaneously shined a light on the constraints posed by its commitment to the assumption that the self-reflexivity of social criticism demands a rational core (Winter, 2025). As such, ideology critique that fails to offer clear rational criteria for drawing distinctions between good and bad myths can risk devolving into an irrational relativism, ultimately fueling the pathologies of authoritarian and populist politics.

The crossroads at which the tradition of ideology critique stands today highlights the need for further critical reflection on the undertheorized cost it bears for its enduring commitment—however necessary—to the primacy of rationality in social criticism. For one, there is the question of whether such a commitment can be maintained without simultaneously conjuring a prejudice for certain forms of knowledge or privileging knowingness as an epistemic standpoint. These tendencies cannot help but reinforce the proverbial dichotomy between facts and values, encouraging us to idealize objectivity while relativizing subjectivity. To accept these ramifications, in turn, is also to compel us to reconsider the value and efficacy of social critique in polarized political landscapes, where too many individuals, unlikely to be swayed by the authority of facts, will experience such critique as overbearing, moralistic, or elitist.

Conversely, it remains unclear what kind of social criticism is made possible by the experiential and contextualist—and some might argue relativist—understandings of knowledge to come out of both the aesthetic and narrative turns. Scholars of myth, who have long defined myth precisely in terms of its resistance to fact and argument (Cassirer 1965, 29–31; Habermas 1987 [1981], 52–53; Sorel 1999, 29), have perennially acknowledged the need to rework the dominant narratives of our political imaginaries, pointing out, in turn, that such projects raise the additional difficulty of determining the criteria by which we might evaluate and critique myths (e.g., Bottici 2007, 16). If social critique is ultimately aimed at initiating the kinds of imaginative breakthroughs that free us from our accustomed stories about the world, neither correct facts nor the right ideology might be sufficient to the task.

Our own effort to think through this challenge is focused on developing an account of one kind of social critique aimed specifically at myths. For our purposes, we define myths as inherited and tacit narratives entrenched in our social world that address, without necessarily giving explanatory answers for, large-scale questions of existential significance for individuals and communities. Myth critique, in our view, requires the critic to creatively rework such myths while preserving a distinctly reflexive admission of ignorance on the questions they address.

We begin by returning to Graeber and Wengrow's conceptualization of Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth.” Pointing to the ways they deploy both archaeological facts and normative value statements to challenge it, we suggest that Graeber and Wengrow undertake a form of ideology critique that is ultimately inappropriate to myth: a medium that has the distinct attitudinal function of structuring our relationship with opacity and that requires a corresponding form of critique that preserves this function. In the second part of our argument, we build on this insight to outline a framework for conceptualizing myth and what the critique of myths—of the kind that succeeds in a more imaginative overhaul of our deeply held concepts—looks like. Drawing from Karl Jaspers, Hans Blumenberg, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, we argue that myth critique must (1) begin from a position of acknowledging the opacity of its subjects and, as a consequence, (2) is likely to take an aesthetic form. But to mitigate the special pitfalls that aesthetic modes of critique can exacerbate, it must, in addition, (3) cultivate an ethic of what we call learned ignorance. Finally, we develop our own account of this ethic by turning to the work of another anthropologist, Nastassja Martin, who shares Graeber and Wengrow's imaginative ambition, but who, unlike them, chooses to refrain from ideology critique. Martin's own unconventional approach to the critique of myths, we argue, can be productively brought in comparison with more rationalist proposals.

The word “myth” comes up often in David Graeber's larger oeuvre. In Debt, the “Myth of Barter” and “myth of primordial debt” appear as a pair of “origin stories” and “founding myth[s]” underpinning the history of modern economic thought (Graeber 2011, 75, 28), alongside the specter of “mythic communism” that has haunted understandings of the nature and feasibility of communistic forms of social organization (95). In Direct Action, Graeber borrows Michael Taussig's terminology of “mythological warfare” to make sense of both the imagery and narrative frames associated with the police in contemporary America and the media strategies of anarchist protesters, including the myth-making of radical puppeteers (Graeber 2009, 487).1 Likewise in The Dawn of Everything, Graeber and Wengrow resort to the language of myth to refer to the stories we have inherited and come to take for granted about humanity's distant past, which also circumscribe our understanding of its future possibilities. Such narratives, for the authors, are myths in the sense that they are origin stories which reflect “our collective fantasies” and structure our current experience (Graeber and Wengrow 2021, 78, 525). But they are also myths because the particular stories that happen to frame how we currently tend to imagine human prehistory have “almost nothing to do with the facts” made available by recent empirical scholarship (4–5). One myth in particular was the target of the book, and, to great controversy, the authors attributed its source to Rousseau's Second Discourse.

For Graeber and Wengrow, we still live in the shadow of a distinct origin myth: a linear narrative about the birth of civilization out of the State of Nature through a succession of discrete stages. In Rousseau's consequential rendering of this account, the final civilizing step that seals humanity's unfreedom is set in motion by the discovery of agriculture and metallurgy—a pair of events that lead to the institutionalization of private property and a centralized government dedicated to protecting it. Thus, for Rousseau (1997, 161), the “true founder of civil society” was “the first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, to whom it occurred to say this is mine, and found people sufficiently simple to believe him.” The problem with this narrative, for Graeber and Wengrow, is not that Rousseau tied his account of humanity's moral decline to the advent of property—an insight they argue Rousseau owed to an indigenous critique of private property articulated by the Huron-Wendat chief Kandiaronk (Graeber and Wengrow 2021, 48-59). Rather, Graeber and Wengrow fault Rousseau and the European reception of his conjectural history for failing to grasp Kandiaronk's point that society might be “based on anything else” other than property (66). By perpetuating the assumption that hierarchical domination organized around the privatization of property is hardwired in our nature, Rousseau's narrative helped trap the modern imagination in “such tight conceptual shackles that we can no longer even imagine the possibility of reinventing ourselves” (9). It is not so much our original harmony with nature that has been lost, but our sense of possibility.

Accordingly, the primary motivation behind Graeber and Wengrow's move to present Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth” is to begin undoing the long-term damage they claim it has done to our political imagination. At stake in such myths was the very “imaginative” project that Appiah had lauded them for taking on: a conceptual shift that might restore “that freedom to imagine and enact other forms of social existence” (Graeber and Wengrow 2021, 502).

Graeber and Wengrow's approach to confronting the myth they identify, however, was a striking blend of empirical debunking and what essentially amounted to ideology critique. One prominent line of their attack was to expose the Rousseauian narrative as false, presenting an exhaustive catalog of archaeological evidence across their 450-page tome—from Göbekli Tepe, Stonehenge, Minoa, and Teotihuacan—suggesting the existence of large, complex early societies that were not dependent on domination by a centralized source of authority. But if Graeber and Wengrow attempted to counter a myth with a deluge of facts, their facts were also hardly ideologically neutral. Another strand of their effort to respond to their Rousseauian myth consistently emphasized that progress in the social sciences depends on practices of rupture and provocation that destabilize their own hegemonic assumptions. “Real change,” they argued, was the result of transformative moments of social breakthrough in which “the lines between myth and history, science and magic become blurred” (524). Social theory, on this view, was ultimately a “game of make-believe” for critics to actively intervene in (21), and Graeber and Wengrow accordingly saw their own task as the telling of a better story that can provide at once “a more accurate, and hopeful, picture of world history” (8). The authority wielded by the sheer volume of their empirical evidence operated within the performative framework of such a game, presenting a curious combination of rationalism and voluntarism that blurred the line between facts and values. The result was a form of critique predicated on a perspective external to the myth they set out to overturn—a privileged standpoint of knowingness from which they could judge the Rousseauvian account as “not only wrong, but quite needlessly dull” (21, see also 3).

In many ways, this quasi-rational ideology critique reflects a more general uncertainty in the political and theoretic discourse on the appropriate way to respond to myths. Theorists of myth have repeatedly emphasized that myths cannot be reduced to factual falsehoods (Bottici 2007; De Vriese 2017), just as a rich tradition of scholarship reminds us that the cultural authority of the modern fact is the product of a contingent history (Poovey 1998; see White 2014), and that this authority is often instrumentalized to serve distorted narratives about reality. All the same, political discourse and theory have yet to shake off the reigning intuition that myths are best countered by exposing them as factually or epistemologically deficient.

More significantly, Graeber and Wengrow's project obscures a theoretical tension that has of late been gaining traction within the long tradition of ideology critique. Once defined by a distinctly German idealist focus on critique and an emphasis on the Marxist concept of false consciousness (Ng 2015), this tradition conventionally positioned the social critic as an external adjudicator, evaluating society from an Archimedean vantage point. Ideology critique has since converged on a more immanent approach (Stahl 2021). In the wake of models offered by philosophical genealogy and the psychoanalytic method (Koopman 2013; Saar 2007; Žižek 1994), as well as from radical democratic theory (Celikates 2018; Rancière 1999; Laclau and Mouffe 2001), contemporary understandings of ideology critique have increasingly shifted toward seeing the objects of their criticism, not as logical ideational structures, but as tacit, often preconscious, systems of social meaning that implicate the critic in the very contradictions they seek to shed light on. How exactly the social critic can grasp the logical structure of such ideas immanently has long been a topic of heated debate (Cooke n.d.; Habermas 1987 [1981]; Horkheimer 1972; Jaeggi 2014). Against the backdrop of an increasingly multipolar, crisis-ridden world, the question turns on whether ideology critics, deprived of their privileged vantage point, can still insist on a rationalist framework of critique that claims to distinguish between the authentic and the alienated, the progressive and the regressive. Pointing to this tension, Yves Winter (2025, 6) rightly observes that ideology critique, thus understood, “must be able to draw from a ‘rational element’ within ideology, in other words, something that is true and that is objective.” While the move toward immanent critique, then, helps ideology critics adopt a more nuanced view both of society's value commitments and of their internal contradictions—as practical systems of belief that are dynamic rather than static, and open to reworking from within—the presumption of such a rational kernel still leaves them in a position of epistemic and moral authority over others. As long as it remains committed to this assumption, immanent ideology critique understands the critic to operate at a special remove from those whose practices they seek to examine: more able to discern what is false, distorted, or morally inconsistent in society, and better positioned to envision paths for overcoming conditions of unfreedom. Emancipation, thus understood, remains at its core a rational endeavor.

Graeber and Wengrow's The Dawn of Everything encapsulates these more recent developments in ideology critique, along with the double bind that critics in this tradition face as they simultaneously refuse and reproduce the practices they criticize. It is clear that Graeber and Wengrow do not view their subject in terms of the traditional concept of false consciousness, and their genealogical reinterpretation of Rousseau's Second Discourse intimates that Gramsci's antihegemonic practices are close to their heart. It is equally clear that their critique is launched from a standpoint rooted in the idea of a rational truth outside the myth in question, where the rigor of scientific falsification ultimately meets the disruptive tactics of the activist seeking to denaturalize the status quo. From this perspective, our entrenched narratives about property and hierarchical domination reveal their ideological nature—a distorted aspiration to the rational idea of freedom.

But if Graeber and Wengrow's approach reflects where ideology critique currently stands, it also brings its constraints into starker relief. At one level, the fixation in the book's public reception on the accuracy of its empirical claims—rather than on the imaginative shift they aimed to inspire—highlights how narrowly their discourse was confined to an ideological base already committed to the value of envisioning alternatives to the established order. At another level, Graeber and Wengrow's unwitting adoption of the tools and epistemological assumptions of ideology critique also constricts their ability to address the imaginaries in question on their own terms. Too quick to present their critique as emancipatory without acknowledging those who, lacking their plethora of facts and clarity of moral insight, would not experience it as such, the authors miss an opportunity to engage the deeper cognitive attachments people may have to the narratives they set out to unmask. This can paint a rather limited picture of what social criticism can mean.

But if we take seriously Graeber and Wengrow's characterization of Rousseau's conjectural history as a myth, there is reason to question whether this kind of ideology critique is ultimately appropriate to the medium. For all the eccentricity of their take, Graeber and Wengrow are by no means the only ones to read Rousseau's conjectural history in mythic terms. Throughout the reception of the Second Discourse, debates over its truth-status have tended to converge on two traditional camps: those who believe Rousseau's conjectural history was constructed purely as a thought experiment, never intended to be taken literally, and those who believe he did in fact aim to give “a factually accurate description of the original human situation” (Brennan 2020, 586; see Neuhouser 2014; Rousseau 1997 [1755], 132; Scott 1992). As Christopher Kelly (2006, 78) suggested in a landmark survey, a third position that resisted both these answers was to understand Rousseau's prehistory as a “myth.” For Kelly, who rejected this reading himself, the mythic interpretation of Rousseau's prehistory meant ruling out the idea that it was meant to have “any genuine explanatory use.” Instead, its function would be “solely rhetorical, having the goal of stimulating nostalgia for a non-existent past in which the problems of modern life did not exist” (78). In a different vein, another familiar way the concept of myth has been applied to the Second Discourse stems from Carole Pateman's (1988) iconic critique of the social contract tradition as having an obscuring or veiling function. This is something that several readers of Pateman's The Sexual Contract have often drawn out more explicitly, by referring several times to her reading of Rousseau's conjectural history as a “myth” that, deceptively, naturalizes conjugal relations in the state of nature (Anderson 2002, 108; Hirschmann 1990).2

Both these senses in which Rousseau's conjectural history can be considered “mythic” are helpful, in that they emphasize the narrative and figurative features of how the conjectural history helps penetrate into the imaginative framework in which Rousseau expects his readers to operate, as well as the distinctive opaqueness that this introduces to its effect. But the rhetorical and ideological accounts are also partial in that they play down the capacity of these features to be more constructive and, indeed, to advance human freedom. This is an important point of emphasis in the interpretation offered by Emma Planinc (2023) of Rousseau as a “political mythologist” invested in the possibility of an original natural language that could “persuade without convincing” (6, 21). This mythic language, for Planinc, is a form of “storytelling over fact founding” that directs Rousseau's audience away from the realities of the societal status quo he is seeking to denaturalize (2). The image of the natural man is persuasive precisely because it is not meant “to convince us of its truth,” but to provide a vivid contrast between this condition and our distorted nature in civilized society: “Man must be persuaded that he is born free,” she tells us, “if he is to see that everywhere he is in chains” (23–24). So transforming and directing hearts toward freedom crucially rest not on ideological certainty but on creating an awareness that “we do not know ourselves as well as we think we do” (22). While Rousseau's prehistory may lack an explanatory function, it serves an attitudinal one: of organizing and structuring our relationship with that which we do not know.

A definitive verdict on what Rousseau truly intended is outside the scope of this article. But we need not take sides on the question here to see how “mythic” readings of Rousseau's conjectural history offer insight into the possibilities of myth that Graeber and Wengrow's critique overlook. First, as Planinc's mythic reading of Rousseau suggests, myths are not necessarily incompatible with an emancipatory political vision. Second, myths can create awareness of what we do not know. Such an awareness, in turn, is essential for social criticism, a source of epistemic humility, and a recognition of the importance of nonrational commitments for communal welfare and solidarity. Myths about prehistory can help us distance ourselves from the images that hold us captive. When we view the large-scale narratives we tell about our origins through this more expansive mythic lens, we can see that it requires a form of critique that preserves these possibilities. Where more established models of criticizing factual untruths or ideology are predicated on a sense of scientific and ideological knowingness that judges from a perspective external to myths, reversing this mode of criticism might help us embrace the ways myth structures our relationship with opacity without overcoming it. In so doing, we can take more seriously the constructive role that ignorance can play as the negation, rejection, or undoing of knowingness.

We have seen that there is a case for conceiving of prehistories like Rousseau's in mythic terms and that there is a problem of critique specific to myth. Myths, as we elaborate below, can be conceptualized as a specific response to the contingencies that surround us and, in contrast to knowledge and power, and despite their projection of authoritativeness, myths do not aim at recuperating certainty. Rather, they sustain and embed forms of opacity as they persuade nonrationally by reworking and organizing the individual, sociocultural and political responses to what we do not know. In what follows, we outline a framework for a form of critique that foregrounds the significance of these qualities.

If Graeber and Wengrow had missed an important opportunity in conceiving of Rousseau's prehistory as a myth but ultimately subjecting it to a form of ideology critique, what would constitute an approach that's more appropriate to their critical target—and to the imaginative shift they sought to spark? In the remainder of this article, we present a counterpoint to Graeber and Wengrow's critical endeavor, offering a different vision of what the critique of myth can look like. We turn, in particular, to Nastassja Martin's In the Eye of the Wild (2021) as an illustrative example of social critique that takes unknowing as a precondition for engaging mythic narratives that are foundational to our worldviews. Like Graeber and Wengrow, Martin seeks to disarm an especially pervasive set of imaginative frameworks structuring Western culture. But in contrast to Graeber and Wengrow, who engage with indigenous perspectives only insofar as they provide, for the purposes of ideology critique, a critical mirror that reflects back at Europeans their own historicity, Martin discovers in them the ground for an original language that “persuades without convincing.” In turn, she tackles the dangers of denialism regarding the epistemic limits of such a project, by offering instead an aesthetic form of critique bounded by an ethic of learned ignorance. Opacity, on this approach, becomes a central component of philosophical reflection itself. This is an insight that Martin develops through a critical engagement with the trope of “the wild” and, with it, our customary ways of relating to nature.

Both The Dawn of Everything and In the Eye of the Wild are visionary works by anthropologists that tackle longstanding myths ingrained in Western social imaginaries and aspire to loosen the hold they have on our capacity to imagine alternative ways of living. While the former engages in a form of ideology critique aimed at exposing an entrenched narrative about the progress of human civilization as both untrue and morally wrong, the latter reworks our go-to templates for envisioning our relationship to nature, connecting them to dreams and bodily experiences that invite a non-dominating mode of attunement with it. We have sought in this article to present a framework for an approach to critiquing myths that takes seriously the qualities that render them opaque to reason, suggesting that these very qualities can serve an important attitudinal function that the critique of myths should accordingly preserve and strengthen. To assume a position of learned ignorance toward what we take for granted, as we read Martin as demonstrating, is to clear a path for introducing imaginative shifts in historically entrenched, naturalized stories that invite retelling rather than abandonment.

Doing anthropology in a mode sensitive to this rhythm involves for Martin a process of translation that resonates with Merleau-Ponty's, Blumenberg's and Jaspers's central insight that it is yet possible to address the dominant narratives in society, not as ideologies that are illusory and wrong, but as mythologies that have forgotten their indebtedness to what remains ambiguous and opaque. This reframing helps us recognize the continuity linking such narratives to larger traditions of storytelling and interpretive practice, foregrounding their imaginative character as well as their multiplicity. In this sense, the creative process of translating from one iteration of a myth to another does not yield a discourse aimed at establishing a rational truth based on principled agreement. We could, rather, following a thought of Walter Benjamin, argue that such translation “touches” truth (2007 [1955], 80), as the original features of the myth change aesthetic forms and bring the existential needs driving it within the reach of what we can actively relate to. To use a different analogy, we could say with Wittgenstein, “Don't think, but look!” (1986, 66). Just as his famous rabbit–duck illusion reminds us how shifting perspectives can expand what we see, the critical reworking and retelling of our myths can help us cultivate a different political optics—one that sharpens our ability to notice those aspects of those narratives that broaden its range of possibilities. Before all other normative considerations, the standpoint of myth critique first of all demands an ethic of learned ignorance that suspends the contours of a particular shape in order to see and inhabit another.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信