实际的自我:回答

IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Anil Gomes
{"title":"实际的自我:回答","authors":"Anil Gomes","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13076","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Lichtenberg's enigmatic remarks on the <i>cogito</i> form the backbone to <i>The Practical Self</i>. Rory Madden raises a set of rich questions about their proper interpretation and the argumentative work to which they are put.</p><p>Lichtenberg writes that to say <i>cogito</i> is already too much as soon as one translates it as I am thinking. Madden contrasts two readings of this line. The traditional reading takes Lichtenberg to be raising a challenge to the claim that I am the subject of my episodes of thinking on which those episodes depend. The revisionary reading—and the one offered in <i>The Practical Self</i>—takes Lichtenberg to be raising a challenge to the claim that I am the sometime agent of my thinking. The final sentence of the passage, on this reading, responds to the challenge by suggesting that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking. To assume the I, to postulate it, is a practical requirement.</p><p>Madden worries about the translation of this final line and, with it, the claim that it offers practical grounds for assuming the I. Lichtenberg writes: <i>Das Ich anzunehmen, zu postulieren, ist praktisches Bedürfnis</i>. Günter Zöller translates the final word as ‘requirement’ (<span>1992</span>, p.418); Stephen Tester as ‘necessity’ (<span>2012</span>, p.152). Madden suggests that ‘need’ is a closer translation and that this deflates the suggestion that Lichtenberg is adverting to practical grounds. A practical need is not a necessary condition on some state of affairs but a pressing or basic impulse, like the need to stretch one's legs.</p><p>My account of the practical grounds available for our sense of ourselves as intellectual agents is modelled on Kant's account of the practical postulates. These are claims which Kant says must be assumed (<i>CPrR</i> 5:121, 126) or postulated (5:122, 125) in virtue of their connection to the demands of practical reason. In particular, they must be assumed or postulated in virtue of a connection to what Kant calls ‘a need [<i>Bedürfnis</i>] of pure practical reason’ (5:142). A need of pure practical reason—a practical need—contrasts with a need of inclination. It is a need based on duty. We might say, then, that to assume these claims about God, freedom, and immortality, to postulate them, is, for Kant, a practical need based on duty—a practical requirement. This is the context in which to understand Lichtenberg's final sentence. Madden's deflationary suggestion severs these connections.</p><p>What about the target of those sentences? Madden notes the difficulty of interpreting an aphoristic writer such as Lichtenberg. In <i>The Practical Self</i> I made the case for the revisionary reading by appeal to other passages in his writings—including, crucially, a passage in the notebooks where Lichtenberg returns to the contrast between ‘I am thinking’ or ‘it is thinking’.1 Madden is right that these are not determinative—even if the later passages show a concern with intellectual agency, it might be that Lichtenberg had not distinguished the two issues when writing the passage at K76 or that both concerns were at issue. He is right too that Lichtenberg's use of the first person in the opening sentences does not tell against the traditional reading.2 But the context of Lichtenberg's wider writings and its Kantian background should open us to the possibility that worries about subjectless episodes of thinking—important as they have been to the development of our philosophical tradition—were read into Lichtenberg given the local concerns of early analytic philosophy.3</p><p>These questions of interpretation are not Madden's main concern. On the issues of content, he argues that the problem of agency has less going for it than I suggest in <i>The Practical Self</i>—that we have perfectly good theoretical grounds for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking. And that the problem of a thinking subject has more going for it than I allow—that some answer to the traditional problem must be given if the argument to objectivity is to go through. It is in this context that he draws attention to some subtleties in Frege's discussion of self-consciousness which I missed in <i>The Practical Self</i>.</p><p>Start with the first. Madden suggests we can know that we are the agents of our thinking through the unproblematic use of causal explanatory reasoning. My knowledge that there are four people living in the house opposite may be based on the best causal explanation of the number of cars parked outside, the state of the recycling bin, and so on. Similarly, my knowledge that I am the agent of my thinking may be based on the best causal explanation of the overall pattern of my thinking. Such reasoning provides theoretical grounds of the sort which I claim are unavailable (PS, pp.88–97).</p><p>Causal explanatory reasoning involves taking up an observational stance towards the object of one's explanation. Madden notes that I am sceptical that such a stance can properly capture the relation we stand in to our prospective actions. When we reason about what we will do, we treat the constraints imposed by our decisions as revisable in a way which allows us to retract the decisions without thereby counteracting the available evidence. And that requires us to take a stance towards our decisions which contrasts fundamentally with the stance we take towards the constraints imposed by the environment (PS, pp.125–128; cf. Soteriou <span>2013</span>, p.287 f.). Madden does not here dispute these considerations. But he suggests that they do not apply to the retrospective use of causal explanatory reasoning. We can look back over episodes of thinking and reason to their best causal explanation. This gives us a growing body of evidence that we are the agents of our thinking.</p><p>This is a helpful reminder of the variety of ways in which experience can provide theoretical grounds for assent. But Madden's use of retrospective causal explanatory reasoning looks primarily geared towards establishing the habitual claim that I agentially think rather than the progressive claim at issue for Descartes. Just as I might look at the discarded books around the house and reason to the thought that I struggle with contemporary fiction, so too can I look back on some episode of thinking and reason to my status as a cognitive agent. Either Madden thinks knowledge of the progressive can be grounded in knowledge of the habitual—an approach which requires rejecting the considerations about decision-making sketched above—or he thinks that knowledge of the habitual suffices to answer Lichtenberg's challenge. Neither is straightforward.</p><p>Still, even if causal explanatory reasoning doesn't allow knowledge that we are agentially thinking in the sense at stake for Descartes, did I need to deny such knowledge in <i>The Practical Self?</i> Madden worries that my denial of knowledge—my denial of theoretical grounds for assent—sits uncomfortably with various claims I make in the positive argument for faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. These are claims about the existence and importance of deliberation, its status as a cognitive activity, and its relation to reactive attitudes and practices (see, e.g. PS, pp.120–125, pp.147–152). Do I present myself as knowing these claims in a way which contradicts the denial of knowledge presented earlier in the book?</p><p>The denial of knowledge in ch.3 of <i>The Practical Self</i> is more precisely a denial of theoretical grounds for assent, understood as grounds which bear on the truth of the claim. The distinction between theoretical and practical grounds is supposed to show that we can have reason for assenting to claims even when they cannot be established on theoretical grounds. In <i>The Practical Self</i> I claim that our status as cognitive agents is one such claim. That is to say, our recognition of ourselves as cognitive agents—as creatures who deliberate, puzzle, and decide—is available only from the practical point of view. Madden is right that I take myself to have grounds to assert that claims about deliberation which feature in the positive argument of <i>The Practical Self</i>. That is compatible with my taking them to lack theoretical grounds.</p><p>This may be a point where the term ‘knowledge’ occludes the issues. A denial of knowledge can sound like an invitation to scepticism. But would we call Kant a sceptic about morality because he denied it could be established on theoretical grounds? Kant is sometimes willing to use the terms practical cognition or knowledge for our recognition that we are subject to the moral law (see e.g. <i>CPrR</i> 5:4–5; 43). And that is compatible with his taking it to lack theoretical grounds. The kind of cognitive activity which is at stake in <i>The Practical Self</i> is accessible only from the practical point of view. The same is true of some of the arguments which establish its conclusion.</p><p>Would it be a problem to allow that we have theoretical grounds for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking? Madden points out that little, if any, of the argument for practical assent developed in chs. 4 and 5 turns on the theoretical undecidability of our status as cognitive agents. Why not allow that we have both theoretical <i>and</i> practical grounds to recognise ourselves as such? The requirement for theoretical undecidability is motivated in <i>The Practical Self</i> by appeal to Kant's account of the practical grounds available for assenting to God's existence. But all I say in support of the requirement is that it is needed to avoid a conflict within reason. For otherwise there could be practical reason to assent to a claim which was opposed by theoretical evidence (PS, p.113). And Madden could reasonably point out that the proscription of conflict excludes only cases where theoretical and practical reason point in opposite directions. There is no conflict if both concur.</p><p>This is a good and important point. In fact, it is not even clear that Kant's own discussion motivates anything beyond the avoidance of contradiction. In his discussion of conflicts within reason, he writes: “That which is required for the possibility of any use of reason as such, namely, that its principles and affirmations <i>must not contradict one another</i>, constitutes no part of its interest but is instead the condition of having reason at all’ (CPrR 5:120, my emphasis). This does not obviously rule out theoretical and practical reason supporting the same claim. Kant does characterise a postulate of pure practical reason as ‘a theoretical proposition, <i>though one not demonstrable as such</i>’ (CPrR 5:122, my emphasis). But this characterisation may apply solely to the cases of God, immortality, and freedom, rather than any claim which can be asserted on practical grounds. Madden is right that I ought to have said more to motivate a connection between practical grounds and theoretical undecidability—but it may be that moving in the direction he suggests does not involve deviation from Kant.4</p><p>Let us turn to the problem traditionally associated with Lichtenberg—the problem of introducing a subject of my episodes of thinking on which those episodes depend. Madden thinks we should take this problem seriously. On his reading of Lichtenberg's remarks, they pose a problem for those who want to explain our ability to form a generalised conception of a subject of experience on the basis of experiences which do not themselves present a subject. Filtered through Wittgenstein and early twentieth-century empiricists, this raises a conceptual problem of other minds: if we start with subjectless episodes of thinking, the result is a solipsistic refusal or inability to countenance other subjects of experience.5</p><p>The conceptual problem other minds is an important part of early analytic philosophy's engagement with Lichtenberg and through Wittgenstein's writings it influenced notable moments in twentieth-century philosophy.6 Madden thinks it matters for the project of <i>The Practical Self</i>. For if we cannot form the conception of a subject of thinking independent of its episodes of thinking, we cannot form the conception of other thinking beings. And my account of the interpersonal practices which sustain our faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking puts at its centre practices which involve thinking of other subjects <i>as</i> thinkers capable of holding and being held to account (see especially PS, pp.158–159). So if we cannot make sense of a generalisable subject of thinking, there can be no such practices, and the proffered connection to an objective world is severed.</p><p>This is the context in which Madden draws attention to an aspect of Frege's discussion in ‘The Thought’ which I passed over in <i>The Practical Self</i>. Frege's concern in that paper is to provide a counterexample to the claim that the only thing I can think about are my own ideas. The counterexample is thought about myself. For I am the bearer of my ideas and no bearer of an idea can itself be an idea. So, in thinking about myself, I am thinking about something which is not an idea. In <i>The Practical Self</i> I complained that this ignores the way in which we are presented to ourselves in episodes of thinking: it is compatible with Frege's argument that my status as the bearer of my ideas does not show up in the character of self-consciousness thought and experience.</p><p>This is what Madden denies, and he thinks that it allows Frege a response to the conceptual problem of other minds. For he thinks that Frege's discussion contains the germ of an idea later developed in more detail by both Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore: that there is a relational structure to experience which is manifest in the character of experience. That relational structure has an implied relatum which is the subject of experience. So in undergoing a sense experience, I am aware of a relational structure in which I, as subject of experience, feature as one of the essential constituents.</p><p>I think Madden is right that the conceptual problem must be taken seriously, whether or not it is ultimately to be found in Lichtenberg. And the claims about the structure of experience which he finds in Frege are a promising line of response.7 But what are the constraints on responding to the conceptual problem? In particular, which resources are we allowed to use in explaining our capacity to think about others as potential subjects of experience?</p><p>Madden offers the Fregean solution as one which meets the constraints imposed by the isolationist starting point of the Cartesian project. But he notes that we need not accept such an etiolated origin. And he quotes Bernard Williams in support of the thought that the starting point of the Cartesian project may itself preclude a solution to the conceptual problem of other minds: ‘If we have no help from anything except the pure point of view of consciousness, the only coherent way of conceiving a thought happening is to conceive of thinking it. So, sticking solely to the point of view of consciousness, we are forced back to a position in which there is, in effect, only one such point of view…’ (Williams <span>1978</span>, p.84). Madden offers his reading of Frege as assistance from within the pure view of consciousness. But he gently suggests, with Williams, that Lichtenberg may ‘share with Descartes his deepest error’ (1978, p.79).</p><p>Williams's wonderful discussion of Lichtenberg in chapter 3 of <i>Descartes: A Project of Pure Enquiry</i> needs to be situated in the context of its reprise in chapter 10. There Williams says that his argument against Descartes's isolationist starting point is ‘in effect only a development of Kant's in the <i>Paralogisms of Pure Reason</i>’ (1978, p.292). Williams takes Descartes's starting point to be episodes of conscious experience intelligible independently of their connection to the wider life of a thinking thing. And Kant's thought in the Paralogisms, at least as presented and defended by Strawson in <i>The Bounds of Sense</i>, is that such a self-contained conception of consciousness does not contain within it the material to make intelligible the idea of a persisting subject.8 If Williams is right to see his argument prefigured in Kant, my co-option of Descartes and Kant into a common project is mere whimsy.</p><p>But the isolation which begins the <i>Meditations</i> need not be understood as committing to a conception of consciousness which is intelligible independently of its connections to the wider life of a thinking being. To assume otherwise is to assume that the first-person mode of reflection at play in the <i>Meditations</i> itself already commits to the conception of consciousness which Williams, Kant, and Strawson rightly find objectionable. An alternative is to understand Descartes's entertainment of the problematic conception of consciousness as resulting from the argumentative pressure developed over the course of the First Meditation. And any seeming endorsement of that conception must be complicated by the fact that, by the Third Meditation, Descartes will insist that we cannot properly understand our form of consciousness as having its character independent of something external to us—not the wider life of a thinking being, admittedly, but an infinite substance who has left in me ‘the mark of the craftsman stamped on his work’ (<i>Med</i>. 7: 51). The first-personal character of the <i>Meditations</i> is not yet a commitment to use only the meagre resources provided by the pure view of consciousness.9</p><p>Madden contrasts the isolationist starting point with one on which our notion of a subject of experience is grounded in an objective, third-personal conception of a psychological event which is, by its nature, the undergoing of a complex unit such as a human being or other animal. And in other work, he has shown the powerful reasons for taking us to be animals of a certain sort.10 But one can accept these insights whilst insisting that this notion of a subject of experience cannot be understood independently of a first-personal conception of a psychological event which is, by its nature, the experience of a conscious subject. Kant, Strawson, and Williams are right that we cannot build up a conception of a subject of experience from a starting point of consciousness stripped of any connection to something external. But this need not be part of the Cartesian project. The dispute in <i>The Practical Self</i> is not about whether we can get to objectivity from a starting point which is intelligible independently of its connections to the external but whether those connections are established on theoretical or practical grounds.</p><p><i>The Practical Self</i> claims that we are required to have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking and that this faith is sustained by a set of practices which relate us to a world of others. Bill Brewer's comments target each of these claims. His questions can be grouped under three broad headings: the nature of cognitive agency, the argument for the claim that we must have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking, and the connection between faith and others. I'll say something about each of these in turn.</p><p>Start with cognitive agency. I claim in <i>The Practical Self</i> that there is a form of self-consciousness which involves an understanding of ourselves as the agents of our thinking. How should we understand the notion of agency involved in this characterisation? Kant contrasts the spontaneity of thinking with the passivity of sensory awareness. Brewer is sceptical that this marks a genuine contrast. We sometimes embark on perceptual projects—scanning the room to catch sight of one's child—and the end results are perceptual achievements: seeing her, half-hidden by the sofa. So too do we sometimes embark on intellectual projects—calculating the number of primes between 0 and 100, say. And the end results of these inquiries are intellectual achievements: the judgement that there are 25 primes. In both cases, the investigation is settled by how things are. To borrow a line from David Wiggins, there is nothing else to think.11</p><p>Given this structural analogy, why think that there is some distinctive kind of agency involved in thinking as opposed to perceiving? In both cases, we initiate a project. And in both cases, the end result is a state which is determined by the facts rather than our preferences about them. Indeed, Brewer thinks that we need this symmetry if we are to accept realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry. For he takes realism to be tantamount to the thought that the answers to one's questions are fixed by facts which are independent of one's knowledge of them. So if we are realists about the domains of perceptual and intellectual inquiry, not only should we treat symmetrically the achievements which settle perceptual and intellectual inquiry, we should further take those achievements to be passive responses to a world which is there anyway.</p><p>Brewer's forceful comparison between perceptual and intellectual inquiry presupposes that the achievements which end inquiry are independent of the wider activities which encompass them. This seems appropriate in the case of perceptual inquiry, since one can come to be in the perceptual states which end inquiry simply by opening one's eyes. Walking through the woods, I come across a pig—‘I can now just <i>see</i> that it is [a pig]’, says J.L. Austin, ‘the question is settled’ (1962, p.115). The passive voice is important here: perception can settle questions without one intending to settle them. And if the achievements which end intellectual inquiry are similarly independent of the wider activities which encompass them, then we seem compelled to treat judgement as equally passive to its objects. At the least, it makes it hard to see why we should treat thinking as distinctively active or spontaneous in a way that perception is not.</p><p>But this independence is not compulsory. Ryle denies it in a series of late papers on the nature of thinking. ‘It is not incidental to thoughts that they belong to trains of thought’, he writes; they are ‘constitutionally inceptive’ (Ryle <span>1958</span>, p.416, cited at PS, p.120). Ryle's claim is that the judgements which end extended episodes of cognitive activity are not separable from the trains of thought which they conclude. The judgement that there are 25 primes is individuated in part by the activity of counting the primes between 1 and 100 in which it features.</p><p>To identify this assumption is not yet to give reason to reject it. But its denial opens a way of explaining the activity of thinking which does not carry over to the case of perception. It is because the judgements which conclude intellectual inquiry depend on the extended cognitive processes which contain them that we treat these judgements as active. And it is because the perceptual states which conclude perceptual inquiry do not depend on the extended cognitive processes which contain them that we treat them as passive. The active nature of judgement is to be explained in terms of the structural features of the extended cognitive process in which it occurs.12</p><p>How does this relate to the realism which underlies Brewer's objection? Realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry can seem relevant if, given the assumption of independence, there is no difference in the relations which the end points of inquiry stand to the processes which precede them. For then it seems the only place to mark a difference between the activity of thinking and the passivity of perception is in terms of how each relates to its objects. And, as Brewer makes clear, realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry poses a constraint on making this good: the fact that we are answerable to how things are in both thought and perception enforces an understanding of both thinking and perception as passive. But once we drop the assumption of independence, we can explain the sense in which judgement is active not in terms of its relation to its objects but in terms of its relation to the processes in which it occurs.</p><p>I turn now to Brewer's comments on the argument that we must have faith in ourselves as the agent of our thinking.13 I claim that self-conscious subjects are required to settle questions about the propriety of their perspective on the world, that setting this as my end requires taking a stand on whether I will settle these questions, and that this requires assent to the claim that I am the agent of my thinking. The result is practical ground for accepting that we are the agents of our thinking, as per Lichtenberg's suggestive final line.</p><p>Brewer notes that this argument assumes that it is a condition on pursuing an end that one takes it to be attainable (see PS, pp.115–117). And he objects this is obviously too strong: crash-landing into the sea in an aeroplane, I may set out to swim to a distant island despite knowing the goal to be unattainable. If there is no connection between pursuing an end and taking it to be attainable, then the argument which purports to provide practical grounds does not go through.</p><p>What should we say about Brewer's counterexample? Well, if one's views on the attainability of an end bear no relation to whether once can decide to pursue it, why does Brewer's swimmer commit only to the project of swimming to safety? Such lack of ambition! Why not commit to the project of flying to safety or of turning into a fish and swimming the distance? The natural thought is that our knowledge that these goals are unattainable precludes us from setting them as ends. The end of swimming to a distant island, no matter how remote, is not like that.</p><p>One complicating factor here is the distinction Kant draws between ends which are willed and those which are merely wished (PS, p.116). We do not always mark this division when discussing our projects. But the claim about attainability applies only to ends that we have properly decided upon. And we must be careful to ensure that our judgements about its plausibility are not swayed by the commonplace that one can wish for ends whose attainment is outside our control. For this reason, the attainability constraint is better motivated not by appeal to cases but by reflection on structural constraints governing the setting of ends.</p><p>Consider incompatible ends. Say there are two islands in opposite directions and that I know I cannot swim to both. If it is a condition on pursuing an end that we take it to be attainable, then we have an explanation for why we cannot decide to swim to one island and, at the same time, decide to swim to the other. For that would require taking it to be attainable that I both swim to island A and swim to island B. And that is exactly what we know to be impossible. In denying the connection between setting ends and attainability, Brewer deprives himself of the resources needed to explain this incompatibility. It is these structural constraints which motivate a connection between setting an end and taking it to be attainable.14</p><p>Brewer pushes a further objection. He argues that to the extent that there are cases where setting an end involves taking that end to be attainable—his ‘brief, simple projects’—these are precisely cases in which setting an end involves no commitment to cognitive agency. Perhaps I set myself the task of finding out which animal is in front of me; I open my eyes and, as Austin puts it, the question is settled. According to Brewer, no cognitive agency is involved in this project. Thus, even if I am right that setting the end of evaluating my perspective requires taking a stand on what I will do, this need involve no commitment to the claim that I am the agent of my thinking. The argument for faith remains in trouble.</p><p>Brewer's objection here raises a set of questions about the nature of decision-making. We normally draw a distinction between two ways in which we can take a stand on what we will do in the future—one based in prediction and one based in commitment.15 Given my nervousness around condescending record-shop staff, I might predict that I will blush when browsing the new releases tomorrow. In making this prediction, I make no commitment to blushing being an instance of my agency. So the issue is not whether there are ways in which we can take a stand on what we will do without thinking of ourselves as agents—that much is without question—but whether this is possible in cases where our assent is based on our decision to pursue some end.</p><p>My reasons for thinking that there is a commitment to cognitive agency here turn on the connections between decision-making and agency more generally. When I decide to do something, I treat it as a constraint on my practical reasoning, a fixed point around which I must navigate. But it is a constraint that I can foreswear should I change my mind. In this it differs from constraints fixed by the world around me. (This is part of the reason for why we should not think of my assent to what I will do as based on evidence: see PS, pp.125–128.) We treat the constraints engendered by my decisions as different from the constraints engendered by how things are in the world—and it is in this differential treatment that we manifest an understanding of ourselves as agents. My commitment to it being true that I will do what I have <i>willed</i> is grounded in the role I play in making this the case.</p><p>Brewer thinks that this does not yet involve a commitment to my own agency because there are perceptual cases where what I will do is determined solely by how things are in the world. If I open my eyes, I will see a pig. That is not a result of any activity on my part. And, as we discussed above, Brewer thinks that perceiving and thinking are on a par in this respect. But the commitment to my own agency is not to be found in the relation between the world and my judgement. It is to be found in my recognition that the ends which I decide upon enforce constraints on practical reasoning which are under my own control. We need a connection between setting an end and taking it to be attainable if we are to explain the structural features that govern decision-making. And we need a connection between setting an end and an acceptance of our agency if we are to explain how our relation to our own decisions differs from our relation to those constraints enforced by the world.</p><p>I turn finally to Brewer's comments on the relation between faith and others. Brewer reconstructs the argument of <i>The Practical Self</i> as holding that self-consciousness requires cognitive agency, that cognitive agency is necessarily based on faith, and that faith requires engagement with others. And he objects that this argument is invalid because it is not true that faith in myself as the agent of my thinking requires engagement with others. It is compatible with all that I have said that faith in cognitive agency is sustained without any interaction with another. I agree—and indeed, emphasised in <i>The Practical Self</i> that the argument offered falls short of the kind of necessity which Descartes, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel aimed to secure (see, especially, PS, pp.159–164). For that reason, I never took myself to accept the final premise in Brewer's reconstruction of my argument. The claim was only that our faith in ourselves as intellectual agents <i>is</i> sustained by a practice which relates us to others—not that it must be.</p><p>Brewer gives some reasons to be dissatisfied with this response. He notes that I object to previous arguments which move from self-consciousness to objectivity in part by showing their failure to establish a necessary connection. But if I am allowed to avoid counterexamples by abjuring a commitment to necessary connections, why are the targets of my criticism not allowed to do likewise?</p><p>There are two possible complaints here. The first is that the arguments I criticise were not interested in establishing necessary connections and, to that extent, that the objections offered in ch.2 have no purchase. I'm not sure if Brewer intends this complaint but it would be an interesting case to make. Stuart Hampshire's <i>Thought and Action</i>—published the same year as <i>Individuals</i>—sets out in its first chapter a project which looks continuous in spirit and often in detail with what we now think of as Strawsonian metaphysics (see, e.g., Hampshire <span>1959</span>, pp.1–21). But the ‘necessary presuppositions of thought and knowledge’ (p.14) which Hampshire aims to uncover are not supposed to be the ‘only possible [principles]’: ‘this would be the error of Kant, the belief that we can anticipate and set final limits to new forms of knowledge’ (p.13, cf. p.20). If the same conception of necessary conditions is at work in the arguments under evaluation in ch.2 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, then the criticisms made there are blunted.</p><p>Let us take Strawson's argument from self-consciousness to objectivity as a test-case (discussed in PS, pp.35–48). I'm sympathetic to the thought that Strawson's understanding of his project does not fit neatly into contemporary taxonomies.16 But Strawson insists, in the introduction to <i>Individuals</i>, that his topic is that ‘massive central core of human thinking which has no history—or none recorded in histories of thought… categories and concepts which, in their most fundamental character, change not at all’ (Strawson <span>1959</span>, p.10). This looks incompatible with a conception of the necessary presuppositions of thought which allows variation across time and culture. Strawson is much more Kantian than Hampshire's relaxed historicism allows. So if the claim is that Strawson and the others considered in ch.2 were not concerned with establishing necessary connections, passages such as this need to be explained away. A case needs to be made.</p><p>The alternative complaint is that the arguments considered in ch.2 could be weakened in ways analogous to the discussion in ch.5, and that those reconstructed arguments would fare better against the objections offered in <i>The Practical Self</i> than the actual arguments considered. Here the thought would be not that differential standards are being applied in chs. 2 and 5 but that the same standards could be applied to different arguments. I agree that it would be fruitful to consider whether there are alternative arguments in the vicinity which avoid the problems raised. But it is not obvious that weakening the arguments would make them more plausible: some of the purported necessary conditions do not even look central to the lives of self-conscious beings.17 And, in any case, those are not the arguments which were given.</p><p>I suspect that part of the issue here is that Brewer wants to force the argument of <i>The Practical Self</i> into the mould of a Strawsonian transcendental argument with its emphasis on only the properly necessary. But one can admire the ambition of these arguments while sidestepping their concerns. Kant himself allowed all kinds of ways in which the historical could be put to use in properly transcendental projects—with images, symbols, practice, and ritual.18 And Hampshire is compelling on the way in which necessities may be supported by ‘the forms of our social life… the social world of conventionalised gesture, expression and habits of co-operation’ (Hampshire <span>1959</span>, p.20). The argument in <i>The Practical Self</i> is that our faith in ourselves as intellectual agents is sustained by a practice which relates us to others. That this is not necessary need not be cause for concern.</p><p>We must have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. Léa Salje gives a precise and perceptive account of the argument for this claim in <i>The Practical Self</i>. And she raises a set of concerns about whether the Kant-inspired account of practical assent outlined in <i>The Practical Self</i> can show that there is a positive epistemic basis for those claims we are required to accept on practical grounds.</p><p>When do we have practical grounds to accept some claim? In ch.4 of <i>The Practical Self</i> I argue that we have practical grounds to accept a claim when it is both theoretically undecidable and practically required. A claim is theoretically undecidable when we lack theoretical grounds to accept or deny it. And a claim is practically required when assenting to the claim is a rational requirement on the pursuit of ends that we are required to set. Since we cannot pursue ends without taking them to be attainable—contra Brewer, above—it follows that if we are required to set some end, we are rationally required to accept any claim which is a condition on taking it to be attainable.</p><p>This account of practical assent underwrites the practical grounds for accepting that we are the agents of our thinking. For I suggest that self-conscious subjects are required to set the end of settling questions about the propriety of their perspective on the world and that assent to the claim that we are the agents of our thinking is a condition on the pursuit of that end. It follows that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking.</p><p>Salje is sceptical about whether this account can explain why it is epistemically appropriate to assent to those claims which we are required to accept on practical grounds. Perhaps there are claims which we which we need to accept if we are to make sense of our status as active, inquiring creatures, living in a world of others. It is a further step, she says, to show that we are epistemically entitled to hold those claims. This is the target of her critique. She focuses on the first part of the argument for practical grounds: that we are required to settle questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. This is where she takes the positive epistemic status of practical assent to reside. And she raises two broad criticisms. First, that it does not provide practical assent with a positive epistemic status—the fact that practical assent traces back to a required end does not, in itself, show that practical assent is anything other than a form of wishful thinking. Second, that it is in any case false: we are not required to set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world. I take these in turn.</p><p>Start with practical assent and necessary ends. Salje notes that if we set ourselves some idiosyncratic end, we are not thereby entitled to assent to any claim which is a condition on our taking that end to be attainable. So why, she asks, should making the end compulsory somehow change the picture? Perhaps we must think of ourselves as kinder, smarter, more capable than others, in order to find our way around the world.19 That doesn't make it epistemically respectable to have an inflated self-conception. Indeed, Salje suggests, it may make it <i>less</i> so—for if we cannot but accept some claim, it seems, for that very reason, to lack epistemic credentials. To think otherwise is to assume that our situation cannot be tragic. Even if we cannot pursue ends without taking them to be attainable, why should the necessity of the end secure epistemic standing for assent in its attainability?</p><p>To address this charge, we need to be clear on why assent based on contingent ends lacks epistemic credentials. Salje suggests that it is because practical assent would otherwise be pervasive: we could bootstrap epistemic entitlement whenever we find it congenial. She gives the example of assenting to the claim that I am a whizz at learning language as a condition on attaining the end of learning Japanese in three months. But practical assent is constrained by theoretical grounds and, at least in my own case and as the tutors at the Oxford University Language Centre can sadly attest, there is a wealth of theoretical evidence that tells against my having any facility with learning languages. So it is not overabundance alone which tells against assent based on contingent ends.</p><p>No, the problem with assent based on contingent ends is its foundation: practical assent cannot be grounded in idiosyncratic desire. It is thus not the shift from the contingent to the necessary which insulates practical assent from the charge of wishful thinking but the shift from assent grounded in desire to assent grounded in obligation. It is because we are under a genuine <i>requirement</i> that we have grounds to accept any claim whose assent is a condition on our doing what we are required to do. Thus in order to answer Salje's charge, we need an account of why assent grounded in requirement rather than assent grounded in individual desire should endow a positive epistemic status.</p><p>The prospects of providing such an account can seem thin if one thinks of requirements as solely instrumental, fixed by an individual's desires. For then universally shared desires would serve to ground universal requirements. And there seems little reason to differentiate between desires which are idiosyncratic and those which are, of necessity, shared. Perhaps there are desires common to us all—‘the ordinary affections of human life; the anxious concern for happiness, the dread of future misery, the terror of death, the thirst of revenge, the appetite for food and other necessaries’ as Hume has it in <i>The Natural History of Religion</i> (2.5). And if these shared desires underwrite a universal requirement, then it will follow from the account of practical assent sketched in <i>The Practical Self</i> that we have practical grounds to accept any claim which is a condition on setting that end. The resulting assent—as Hume perhaps intends us to recognise—does not seem markedly different from wishful thinking.</p><p>But we need not think of necessary requirements as grounded in desire in this way. An alternative is to locate them in our nature as self-conscious beings (PS, pp.124–125). For if it is part of our nature that we are rational animals, then the requirement to evaluate our perspective will flow from our rational faculties. For someone sympathetic to Kant, this will be because it traces back to a categorical imperative given by reason itself (CPrR 5: 143, cf. PS, p.124). For someone more inclined towards Aristotelian naturalism, it will be because it is underwritten by the standards of good human life: the ‘activity of soul in accordance with reason’ (NE 1098a). In either case, its foundation is not some shared conative state but reason itself. A failure to accept those claims for which we have practical grounds thus manifests a kind of rational incoherence. It is this foundation in reason which distinguishes practical assent from wishful thinking and explains its positive epistemic status.</p><p>Salje might respond that this shows only that practical assent is a <i>rational</i> attitude not that it has a positive epistemic status. And at the end of her essay, she sketches one way in which one might decouple the two. But I worry that such decoupling has attraction only to the extent one insists on reserving epistemic status for that which is determined on evidential grounds. Kant offers us an account of assent which showcases an alternative source of good standing—when grounded in reason, when grounded in our nature, when grounded in something universal (see especially CPrR 5:143n.). The requirement to evaluate one's perspective on the world is one which flows from our status as self-conscious, rational animals. And someone who sets themselves the end of evaluating their perspective on the world but refuses to accept that they are the agent of their thinking exhibits a form of rational incoherence. The positive epistemic standing of practical assent is thus not found in its connection to evidence but in its status as reasonable, universal, natural—and secure.</p><p>Salje's second line of criticism targets the claim that we are required to set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world. She raises two questions: first, whether we do set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world, and second, whether we are required to do so. Both questions have force given the Cartesian framing of <i>The Practical Self</i>. For Descartes presents his project as an enormous undertaking, understandably postponed, and only needing to be performed once in a lifetime (<i>Med</i>. 7:17). Hence the legitimacy of Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia's complaint that ‘the life which I am constrained to lead does not leave enough time at my disposal to acquire a habit of meditation in accordance with your rules’ (<i>Corr</i>. 3:684). Why think that anyone outside of philosophical contexts actually engages in such recherché activity? Why think that anyone must do so?</p><p>Salje presses the first question through worries about over-intellectualisation. She distinguishes the beliefs and experiences which (partly) constitute our perspective on the world, the evaluative stances we take towards those beliefs and experiences, and the decision to engage in evaluative activity directed towards those beliefs and experiences. And the presentation of these phenomena as constituting three distinct levels of psychological attitude can make it seem as though there is an additional complexity at each stage: that there can be creatures who have a perspective without being able to step back and reflect on it, and that there can be creatures who can reflect on their perspective without deciding to engage in that activity.</p><p>In <i>The Practical Self</i>, I allow a gap between Salje's first and second levels: there are conscious creatures who have a perspective on the world but lack the ability to step back and evaluate that perspective. Does it follow that there can be a gap between Salje's second and third levels? As she notes, that will depend on how much is built into the setting of ends. The more that is required—expressly ridding my mind of all worries, arranging for myself a clear stretch of free time, for instance (<i>Med</i>. 7:17)—the less plausible it will be that anyone sets this end, the peculiarities of philosophical reflection excepted. And that can make it seem as if there is a gap to be bridged between Salje's second and third levels.</p><p>But there is something odd about the thought that one could reflect on one's perspective without ever deciding to do so. We do sometimes find our attention grabbed from without, as when a light flashes in the corner of our visual field. But to <i>will</i> an end as opposed to simply wishing it is to commit to taking some sort of action to bring it about. This is why the distinction has importance for both Kant and Aristotle: it captures a difference in the way desires relate to motivation which is relevant to ethical evaluation.20 We set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective whenever we purposefully engage in reflection. The commitment involved in setting it as our end thus involves no more than choosing to bring it about. So to the extent that reflection is something undertaken, it is something we have chosen to do, and thus set as our end.</p><p>This doesn't mean that human beings actually set this end, for one might think that reflection itself is more limited or circumscribed than I suggest. But drawing out the connection between willing an end and acting so as to bring it about may ease some of the concerns about over-intellectualisation. Setting oneself the end of evaluating one's perspective need not involve a moment of high drama; it does not require that the end be set under that mode of presentation; it is not something which needs to be affirmed and reaffirmed each morning. Rather, to the extent that reflection is something in which we purposefully engage—that we <i>choose</i> to stand back and reflect on whether our perspective on the world is appropriate—then the gap between Salje's second and third levels is blurred.</p><p>These considerations concern only whether people actually set themselves the end of evaluating their perspectives. Are they required to do so? Salje forcefully pushes back against this suggestion by emphasising how neurotic, self-alienating and exhausting it would be to constantly reflect on one's perspective on the world. It is often hard enough to navigate the world. Now add continual reflection on one's perspective! As Susan Wolff puts it in a related attempt to take seriously the prospects for a life lived in accordance with some purported norm: these ‘are not ideals to which it is particularly reasonable or healthy or desirable for human beings to aspire’ (Wolff 1982, p.433).</p><p>Salje's criticism is a helpful reminder of the way reflection brings with it risks of neurosis and narcissism. This is a preoccupation for Iris Murdoch whose writings are continually attentive to the way reflection gives way to self-involved concern.21 A full response to the charge should not deny these dangers. It needs rather to show the value of the reflective life, the importance of self-understanding, and the way in which reflecting on our perspective enlarges not just the domain of self-knowledge but also its structure. That will require situating reflection within the broader life of a human being.22</p><p>Absent that wider story, I'll point to two threads which connect to some of Salje's wider concerns and suggest ways in which a requirement to reflect on one's perspective is integral to a flourishing human life. First, intellectual virtue. Salje expresses sympathy at the end of her comments for a virtue epistemological framework which emphasises the epistemic benefits of well-functioning intellectual traits. But the competences involved in these virtues plausibly involve the kind of monitoring and assessment enabled by reflection on one's perspective.23 So we would expect someone who cares about the intellectual virtues to be attentive to whether her perspective is appropriate and to take deliberate steps to ensure that it remain so. When situated in a story about the value of the intellectual virtues, the requirement to evaluate one's perspective can start to seem part of a well-ordered human life.</p><p>Second, community. The mindfulness proponent who only ever lives at Salje's first level can seem like an attractive prospect given her attunement to the world around her. But part of that world will include others who disagree with her take on things. That alone will put rational pressure on her to reflect on the propriety of her perspective. And once collective projects are in the offing, policies for recognising, monitoring, and resolving disagreement will need to be in place—the participants to the common endeavour will need to reflect on their own perspectives in a deliberate and controlled manner. Salje has persuasively argued elsewhere that conversation has a cognitive value in enabling the articulation of our thoughts and ensuring they are rationally answerable.24 Maximising that value will often require sensitivity to the compatibility of one's perspective with that of one's conversational partner—a sensitivity facilitated by reflection, again in ways which can help us see the requirement to evaluate one's perspective as part of a well-ordered life.</p><p>This last connection is not intended to justify the claim that there is a requirement to evaluate the propriety of our perspective, not least since it would raise concerns about circularity given the argument in ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i>. The aim is only to make plausible that there is such a requirement by showing how a life lived in its light need not be self-alienated, neurotic, and exhausted. It might instead be an intellectually virtuous life lived in communion with others: one aspect of a life lived well.</p><p>Kant's views on self-consciousness, practical reason, and religion are a touchstone for the arguments set out in <i>The Practical Self</i>. Carla Bagnoli argues that they depart from Kant in ways which are detrimental to its project. Kant is a better guide to the connections between agential thinking and a social world of other thinkers than I allow.</p><p><i>The Practical Self</i> argues that self-conscious subjects must have faith in themselves as the agents of our thinking and that this faith is sustained by a set of practices which relate us to a world of others. Bagnoli thinks this an odd pairing. Her expansive comments centre on two main charges: that there is a much more direct connection to be found in Kant between our status as agential thinkers and a social world of other thinkers, and that, contrary to the suggestion in ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, a focus on practices and group-identities has the potential to undermine, rather than support, any connection to objectivity. The interleaving of faith and practice is both unnecessary and insufficient.</p><p>Start with the more direct connection between self-consciousness and objectivity. Bagnoli argues that there is a social dimension to practical assent which is independent of practice—or at least, independent of the practices which are the focus of ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i>. (I return to this distinction below.) This line of thought accepts that we have practical grounds to recognise ourselves as the agents of our thinking, contra Madden above. But it insists that no further step is needed to establish a connection to a world of other thinkers who are independent of me. There is a social dimension to practical assent which already connects self-conscious agents to a world of others.</p><p>How does sociality enter practical assent? Practical assent is introduced in <i>The Practical Self</i> as a mode of assent which is determined by practical grounds. And there are practical grounds to accept a claim when it is both theoretically undecidable and practically required. I use the term ‘faith’ to pick out this mode of assent—as Kant does at e.g. CPJ 5:471—but it is compatible with this that there are distinctions to be made within the class of practical assent. Bagnoli suggests one which is important for establishing a direct connection between self-consciousness and sociality: the distinction between faith and hope.</p><p>Hope has a central place in Kant's account of human reason. All interest of human reason, he tells us, is united in the questions: ‘What can I know? What should I do? What may I hope?’ (A805/B833). The last connects to faith, because it is answered by religion (JL 9:25). Some readers have accordingly treated hope and faith as equivalent.25 But Bagnoli thinks this is mistaken. She suggests that they are to be distinguished in terms of their intentional objects. Faith is directed at a world in which happiness and virtue are harmonised; hope at the realisation of an ethical community. This means that the object of hope already involves a social dimension: to hope is to recognise that the object of your practical assent is a collective project requiring the involvement of others.</p><p>Does this help with the establishment of a direct connection between self-consciousness and objectivity? If the content of hope already involves a social dimension, then it may seem as if we can sidestep the appeal to practice by establishing a link between self-consciousness and hope. For if self-conscious subjects are required to hope rather than have faith, we will already have shown that they are related, at least intentionally, to a community of others.</p><p>But this is no shortcut. Faith and hope, as attitudes, are distinguished solely in terms of their intentional objects. It is thus the content of practical assent which licences us in classifying an attitude as one of faith or hope. I do not want to insist that there are no cases in which differences in content alone are perspicuously represented by distinguishing the attitude we stand towards that content. But marking the distinction in this way means that we cannot argue directly for a connection between self-consciousness and hope and thereby take ourselves to have secured a connection to others. We must argue first for the necessity of a social content to practical assent and this will then allow us to characterise the connection as holding between self-consciousness and hope. That is to say, the issue is not whether self-consciousness requires faith or hope—it is whether the content of practical assent is necessarily social in the way required for hope.</p><p>The question of whether there is a more direct route to sociality thus turns on the content of practical assent. In ch.4 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, I argue that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking. Bagnoli's direct connection must go further: it must show that we have practical grounds to accept that we are in community with others. What is the argument for this claim?</p><p>In broad terms, the line of thought sketched by Bagnoli takes agential thinking to bring with it answerability to various norms. Some of these are epistemic and concern the truth or falsity of our assertions. Others are more broadly moral and concern the relation we stand in to others. In both cases, we can comply with the structural norms only in the context of a community of other thinkers. So to the extent that we have practical grounds available for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking, we also have practical grounds for accepting—hoping—that there is a community of other thinkers who face these challenges together.</p><p>If Bagnoli's thought can be made good, the content of practical assent is more expansive than I suggest. But there are two grounds for concern. First, there is a question about whether the content of this hope alone would suffice to establish a connection between self-consciousness and sociality. As I tell the story in ch.2 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, the twentieth century saw a retreat from the worldly ambitions of Descartes and Kant to the claim that self-conscious subjects are only intentionally directed onto an objective world (PS, pp.36–37). If hope is an attitude we can stand in to objects without being genuinely related to them, then Bagnoli's suggestion gets us no further than twentieth-century diffidence.</p><p>Second, and more importantly, the proposed extension of practical assent from cognitive agency to community turns on the claim that the structural norms of thinking can only be realised in a community of others. But even if thinking is governed by the norms which Bagnoli suggests, why think they can only be realised in communion with others? This is stronger than the claim that the norms which govern thinking <i>concern</i> others. For norms which concern others may be realisable solely through my own efforts—or, if not mine alone, at least supplemented only by divine assistance. Kant's argument to the stronger conclusion starts from an assumption about our propensity for evil (Rel. 6:97–98). Why think that anything similar holds true of the norms which govern our thinking? There is a gap between the claim that thinking is subject to norms which concern others and the claim that these norms require realisation in a community.</p><p>I turn now to Bagnoli's second charge: that, far from sustaining a commitment to objectivity, the practices appealed to in <i>The Practical Self</i> actually undermine it. How should we understand this concern? One might think that the directness of Bagnoli's route to sociality turns on its renunciation of practice and that this is the context in which to understand her concerns about the ways practices undermine objectivity. But consider the Kantian resources which she takes to underwrite practical assent. There is the practice of attributing responsibility, understood not in the Strawsonian form in which it appears in ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i> but as part of the fundamental structure of human interaction and the basis for all social agency. There is the particular way that moral agency shows up in sensibility as the feeling of respect. And there is the relation of reciprocity which places a normative constraint on deliberation.</p><p>How do these compare to the resources marshalled in <i>The Practical Self?</i> Bagnoli's Kant finds a foundation for practical assent in practices, feelings, and constraints on decision-making, all of which involve a relation to others. <i>The Practical Self</i> focussed primarily on the role of practices in scaffolding practical assent. But it also noted the way in which a commitment to the reality of others shows up in our experiences, when we disagree (PS, p.159), and in our decision-making, when we attend to diachronic considerations about the persistence of practices (PS, p.161). The difference between the direct and circumambulatory routes is not a difference in resource.</p><p>Bagnoli's objection to the argument in <i>The Practical Self</i> is thus not to its invocation of practice but to its claim that social practice is mere scaffold: something which aids practical assent but is strictly unnecessary. Her Kantian resources are instead supposed to be the very basis for intellectual agency, a social foundation for practical assent. The result is more recognisably Kantian, at least in as much as one takes Kant to care only about the properly necessary. Practical assent, by its very nature, involves others because it has its foundation in a practice of attributing responsibility, a feeling of respect, and a constraint of reciprocity. These practices, feelings, and constraints are not optional extras for those who need the additional support: they are part of the structure of human relations which underwrites the social agency involved in practical assent. Bagnoli's Kantian route is direct not because it foreswears practice but because it insists on its necessity.</p><p>This helps to spell out Bagnoli's concern about the way the two parts of the argument in <i>The Practical Self</i> fit together. The odd pairing is not faith and practice but the necessity of faith and the optionality of practice. Bagnoli worries that if practice is understood as anything less than the fundamental structure for human agency, it will mediate, weaken and distort our relation to others. Why would scaffolding have this consequence? Bagnoli's thought is that since the practices appealed to in <i>The Practical Self</i> are relative to particular forms of life (see e.g. PS, pp.138–141), the support that they provide is exclusive and independent. The result is a plethora of communities whose practices may, as it happens, sustain faith in the same content but whose structures are independently authoritative. And she takes this to be a undermine any strategy aiming at objectivity.</p><p>How seriously should we take this worry? Bagnoli is right to emphasise the dangers of group identities and the way in which distinguishing between those who are in and those who are out can inculcate hostility towards those on the outside even as it creates community among those on the inside. And she is right too that the practices involved in holding one another accountable are shaped by imbalances of power and authority in ways that I did not discuss. Social practices can constrain as much as they sustain and it is good to recognise this.</p><p>But why should this have any implication for objectivity? Bagnoli's thought seems to be that a proliferation of practice would undermine the norms involved in thinking of oneself as an autonomous thinker. For if the support provided to practical assent comes from a specific form of life, then I cannot take its support to generalise to all instances of thinking, even in the case where the distinct practices support the same norms. Convergence may allow an overlapping consensus on the model of Rawls's <i>Political Liberalism</i>. But Bagnoli insists that this falls short of universal authority. And it is this subversion of universal norms of thinking which is supposed to undermine any claim to objectivity.</p><p>But this is not the notion of objectivity at play in <i>The Practical Self</i>. I distinguish there two broad notions of objectivity—the ontological and the perspectival (PS, pp.12–16). According to the ontological notion of objectivity, something is objective when it doesn't depend for its existence on minds and subjective otherwise. According to the perspectival notion, something is objective when it is independent of a subject's point of view and subjective otherwise. The threat which Bagnoli finds in a proliferation of practices is a threat to the idea of universal norms which govern thinking—that is, to norms which apply independently of one's parochial perspective on the world. If she is right, there may be a threat to a perspectival notion of objectivity in the vicinity. But my concern in <i>The Practical Self</i> was the objectivity of things which don't depend for their existence on my awareness of them. And we don't yet have a threat to objectivity in this sense.</p><p>Consider a world of mutually independent practices, all of which centre on other thinkers, distinct from us and our mental states. It may be that we cannot take part in each practice without foreswearing the others. And it may be that Bagnoli is right to worry that the norms which issue from each practice can only ever aspire to local recognition, even when they overlap so as to allow consensus. This is no threat to the ontological notion of objectivity so long as each practice relates its participants to things which don't depend on minds. A plenitude of practices does not denigrate the objectivity of that to which they relate.</p><p>I don't see, then, that the optionality of practice threatens objectivity of the sort that was at issue in <i>The Practical Self</i>. Nor do I see that her Kantian route is more direct. Both lines of argument hold that self-consciousness requires practical assent and both think that assent is supported by practice. Bagnoli takes the content of the assent to be communal in a way that goes beyond the argument of <i>The Practical Self</i>. And she takes the connection between practical assent and practice to be necessary rather than central. I have expressed scepticism about the first claim and denied that the second is needed to secure a connection to objectivity. But even granting both, these are emendations to the approach set out in <i>The Practical Self</i> rather than its rejection.</p><p>There is still a difference of view about the scope and nature of the practice of accountability which is supposed to sustain faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. Bagnoli thinks it cannot be merely central but must be rooted in the structural and universal features of being human. But even if the practice of accountability is universal in the way that Bagnoli insists, this is not yet to show that it must relate us to other thinkers. It might be that we centre the practice on future selves, an imaginary other, or God (see PS, pp.159–161). I share with Bagnoli the thought that these practices could only ever be peripheral, a pale imitation of the joyful conversation which pervades our ordinary lives. But their possibility does not undermine the connection to others present in the ordinary case: our practice is enough.26</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"33 2","pages":"779-795"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2025-05-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13076","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Practical Self: Replies\",\"authors\":\"Anil Gomes\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/ejop.13076\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Lichtenberg's enigmatic remarks on the <i>cogito</i> form the backbone to <i>The Practical Self</i>. Rory Madden raises a set of rich questions about their proper interpretation and the argumentative work to which they are put.</p><p>Lichtenberg writes that to say <i>cogito</i> is already too much as soon as one translates it as I am thinking. Madden contrasts two readings of this line. The traditional reading takes Lichtenberg to be raising a challenge to the claim that I am the subject of my episodes of thinking on which those episodes depend. The revisionary reading—and the one offered in <i>The Practical Self</i>—takes Lichtenberg to be raising a challenge to the claim that I am the sometime agent of my thinking. The final sentence of the passage, on this reading, responds to the challenge by suggesting that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking. To assume the I, to postulate it, is a practical requirement.</p><p>Madden worries about the translation of this final line and, with it, the claim that it offers practical grounds for assuming the I. Lichtenberg writes: <i>Das Ich anzunehmen, zu postulieren, ist praktisches Bedürfnis</i>. Günter Zöller translates the final word as ‘requirement’ (<span>1992</span>, p.418); Stephen Tester as ‘necessity’ (<span>2012</span>, p.152). Madden suggests that ‘need’ is a closer translation and that this deflates the suggestion that Lichtenberg is adverting to practical grounds. A practical need is not a necessary condition on some state of affairs but a pressing or basic impulse, like the need to stretch one's legs.</p><p>My account of the practical grounds available for our sense of ourselves as intellectual agents is modelled on Kant's account of the practical postulates. These are claims which Kant says must be assumed (<i>CPrR</i> 5:121, 126) or postulated (5:122, 125) in virtue of their connection to the demands of practical reason. In particular, they must be assumed or postulated in virtue of a connection to what Kant calls ‘a need [<i>Bedürfnis</i>] of pure practical reason’ (5:142). A need of pure practical reason—a practical need—contrasts with a need of inclination. It is a need based on duty. We might say, then, that to assume these claims about God, freedom, and immortality, to postulate them, is, for Kant, a practical need based on duty—a practical requirement. This is the context in which to understand Lichtenberg's final sentence. Madden's deflationary suggestion severs these connections.</p><p>What about the target of those sentences? Madden notes the difficulty of interpreting an aphoristic writer such as Lichtenberg. In <i>The Practical Self</i> I made the case for the revisionary reading by appeal to other passages in his writings—including, crucially, a passage in the notebooks where Lichtenberg returns to the contrast between ‘I am thinking’ or ‘it is thinking’.1 Madden is right that these are not determinative—even if the later passages show a concern with intellectual agency, it might be that Lichtenberg had not distinguished the two issues when writing the passage at K76 or that both concerns were at issue. He is right too that Lichtenberg's use of the first person in the opening sentences does not tell against the traditional reading.2 But the context of Lichtenberg's wider writings and its Kantian background should open us to the possibility that worries about subjectless episodes of thinking—important as they have been to the development of our philosophical tradition—were read into Lichtenberg given the local concerns of early analytic philosophy.3</p><p>These questions of interpretation are not Madden's main concern. On the issues of content, he argues that the problem of agency has less going for it than I suggest in <i>The Practical Self</i>—that we have perfectly good theoretical grounds for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking. And that the problem of a thinking subject has more going for it than I allow—that some answer to the traditional problem must be given if the argument to objectivity is to go through. It is in this context that he draws attention to some subtleties in Frege's discussion of self-consciousness which I missed in <i>The Practical Self</i>.</p><p>Start with the first. Madden suggests we can know that we are the agents of our thinking through the unproblematic use of causal explanatory reasoning. My knowledge that there are four people living in the house opposite may be based on the best causal explanation of the number of cars parked outside, the state of the recycling bin, and so on. Similarly, my knowledge that I am the agent of my thinking may be based on the best causal explanation of the overall pattern of my thinking. Such reasoning provides theoretical grounds of the sort which I claim are unavailable (PS, pp.88–97).</p><p>Causal explanatory reasoning involves taking up an observational stance towards the object of one's explanation. Madden notes that I am sceptical that such a stance can properly capture the relation we stand in to our prospective actions. When we reason about what we will do, we treat the constraints imposed by our decisions as revisable in a way which allows us to retract the decisions without thereby counteracting the available evidence. And that requires us to take a stance towards our decisions which contrasts fundamentally with the stance we take towards the constraints imposed by the environment (PS, pp.125–128; cf. Soteriou <span>2013</span>, p.287 f.). Madden does not here dispute these considerations. But he suggests that they do not apply to the retrospective use of causal explanatory reasoning. We can look back over episodes of thinking and reason to their best causal explanation. This gives us a growing body of evidence that we are the agents of our thinking.</p><p>This is a helpful reminder of the variety of ways in which experience can provide theoretical grounds for assent. But Madden's use of retrospective causal explanatory reasoning looks primarily geared towards establishing the habitual claim that I agentially think rather than the progressive claim at issue for Descartes. Just as I might look at the discarded books around the house and reason to the thought that I struggle with contemporary fiction, so too can I look back on some episode of thinking and reason to my status as a cognitive agent. Either Madden thinks knowledge of the progressive can be grounded in knowledge of the habitual—an approach which requires rejecting the considerations about decision-making sketched above—or he thinks that knowledge of the habitual suffices to answer Lichtenberg's challenge. Neither is straightforward.</p><p>Still, even if causal explanatory reasoning doesn't allow knowledge that we are agentially thinking in the sense at stake for Descartes, did I need to deny such knowledge in <i>The Practical Self?</i> Madden worries that my denial of knowledge—my denial of theoretical grounds for assent—sits uncomfortably with various claims I make in the positive argument for faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. These are claims about the existence and importance of deliberation, its status as a cognitive activity, and its relation to reactive attitudes and practices (see, e.g. PS, pp.120–125, pp.147–152). Do I present myself as knowing these claims in a way which contradicts the denial of knowledge presented earlier in the book?</p><p>The denial of knowledge in ch.3 of <i>The Practical Self</i> is more precisely a denial of theoretical grounds for assent, understood as grounds which bear on the truth of the claim. The distinction between theoretical and practical grounds is supposed to show that we can have reason for assenting to claims even when they cannot be established on theoretical grounds. In <i>The Practical Self</i> I claim that our status as cognitive agents is one such claim. That is to say, our recognition of ourselves as cognitive agents—as creatures who deliberate, puzzle, and decide—is available only from the practical point of view. Madden is right that I take myself to have grounds to assert that claims about deliberation which feature in the positive argument of <i>The Practical Self</i>. That is compatible with my taking them to lack theoretical grounds.</p><p>This may be a point where the term ‘knowledge’ occludes the issues. A denial of knowledge can sound like an invitation to scepticism. But would we call Kant a sceptic about morality because he denied it could be established on theoretical grounds? Kant is sometimes willing to use the terms practical cognition or knowledge for our recognition that we are subject to the moral law (see e.g. <i>CPrR</i> 5:4–5; 43). And that is compatible with his taking it to lack theoretical grounds. The kind of cognitive activity which is at stake in <i>The Practical Self</i> is accessible only from the practical point of view. The same is true of some of the arguments which establish its conclusion.</p><p>Would it be a problem to allow that we have theoretical grounds for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking? Madden points out that little, if any, of the argument for practical assent developed in chs. 4 and 5 turns on the theoretical undecidability of our status as cognitive agents. Why not allow that we have both theoretical <i>and</i> practical grounds to recognise ourselves as such? The requirement for theoretical undecidability is motivated in <i>The Practical Self</i> by appeal to Kant's account of the practical grounds available for assenting to God's existence. But all I say in support of the requirement is that it is needed to avoid a conflict within reason. For otherwise there could be practical reason to assent to a claim which was opposed by theoretical evidence (PS, p.113). And Madden could reasonably point out that the proscription of conflict excludes only cases where theoretical and practical reason point in opposite directions. There is no conflict if both concur.</p><p>This is a good and important point. In fact, it is not even clear that Kant's own discussion motivates anything beyond the avoidance of contradiction. In his discussion of conflicts within reason, he writes: “That which is required for the possibility of any use of reason as such, namely, that its principles and affirmations <i>must not contradict one another</i>, constitutes no part of its interest but is instead the condition of having reason at all’ (CPrR 5:120, my emphasis). This does not obviously rule out theoretical and practical reason supporting the same claim. Kant does characterise a postulate of pure practical reason as ‘a theoretical proposition, <i>though one not demonstrable as such</i>’ (CPrR 5:122, my emphasis). But this characterisation may apply solely to the cases of God, immortality, and freedom, rather than any claim which can be asserted on practical grounds. Madden is right that I ought to have said more to motivate a connection between practical grounds and theoretical undecidability—but it may be that moving in the direction he suggests does not involve deviation from Kant.4</p><p>Let us turn to the problem traditionally associated with Lichtenberg—the problem of introducing a subject of my episodes of thinking on which those episodes depend. Madden thinks we should take this problem seriously. On his reading of Lichtenberg's remarks, they pose a problem for those who want to explain our ability to form a generalised conception of a subject of experience on the basis of experiences which do not themselves present a subject. Filtered through Wittgenstein and early twentieth-century empiricists, this raises a conceptual problem of other minds: if we start with subjectless episodes of thinking, the result is a solipsistic refusal or inability to countenance other subjects of experience.5</p><p>The conceptual problem other minds is an important part of early analytic philosophy's engagement with Lichtenberg and through Wittgenstein's writings it influenced notable moments in twentieth-century philosophy.6 Madden thinks it matters for the project of <i>The Practical Self</i>. For if we cannot form the conception of a subject of thinking independent of its episodes of thinking, we cannot form the conception of other thinking beings. And my account of the interpersonal practices which sustain our faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking puts at its centre practices which involve thinking of other subjects <i>as</i> thinkers capable of holding and being held to account (see especially PS, pp.158–159). So if we cannot make sense of a generalisable subject of thinking, there can be no such practices, and the proffered connection to an objective world is severed.</p><p>This is the context in which Madden draws attention to an aspect of Frege's discussion in ‘The Thought’ which I passed over in <i>The Practical Self</i>. Frege's concern in that paper is to provide a counterexample to the claim that the only thing I can think about are my own ideas. The counterexample is thought about myself. For I am the bearer of my ideas and no bearer of an idea can itself be an idea. So, in thinking about myself, I am thinking about something which is not an idea. In <i>The Practical Self</i> I complained that this ignores the way in which we are presented to ourselves in episodes of thinking: it is compatible with Frege's argument that my status as the bearer of my ideas does not show up in the character of self-consciousness thought and experience.</p><p>This is what Madden denies, and he thinks that it allows Frege a response to the conceptual problem of other minds. For he thinks that Frege's discussion contains the germ of an idea later developed in more detail by both Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore: that there is a relational structure to experience which is manifest in the character of experience. That relational structure has an implied relatum which is the subject of experience. So in undergoing a sense experience, I am aware of a relational structure in which I, as subject of experience, feature as one of the essential constituents.</p><p>I think Madden is right that the conceptual problem must be taken seriously, whether or not it is ultimately to be found in Lichtenberg. And the claims about the structure of experience which he finds in Frege are a promising line of response.7 But what are the constraints on responding to the conceptual problem? In particular, which resources are we allowed to use in explaining our capacity to think about others as potential subjects of experience?</p><p>Madden offers the Fregean solution as one which meets the constraints imposed by the isolationist starting point of the Cartesian project. But he notes that we need not accept such an etiolated origin. And he quotes Bernard Williams in support of the thought that the starting point of the Cartesian project may itself preclude a solution to the conceptual problem of other minds: ‘If we have no help from anything except the pure point of view of consciousness, the only coherent way of conceiving a thought happening is to conceive of thinking it. So, sticking solely to the point of view of consciousness, we are forced back to a position in which there is, in effect, only one such point of view…’ (Williams <span>1978</span>, p.84). Madden offers his reading of Frege as assistance from within the pure view of consciousness. But he gently suggests, with Williams, that Lichtenberg may ‘share with Descartes his deepest error’ (1978, p.79).</p><p>Williams's wonderful discussion of Lichtenberg in chapter 3 of <i>Descartes: A Project of Pure Enquiry</i> needs to be situated in the context of its reprise in chapter 10. There Williams says that his argument against Descartes's isolationist starting point is ‘in effect only a development of Kant's in the <i>Paralogisms of Pure Reason</i>’ (1978, p.292). Williams takes Descartes's starting point to be episodes of conscious experience intelligible independently of their connection to the wider life of a thinking thing. And Kant's thought in the Paralogisms, at least as presented and defended by Strawson in <i>The Bounds of Sense</i>, is that such a self-contained conception of consciousness does not contain within it the material to make intelligible the idea of a persisting subject.8 If Williams is right to see his argument prefigured in Kant, my co-option of Descartes and Kant into a common project is mere whimsy.</p><p>But the isolation which begins the <i>Meditations</i> need not be understood as committing to a conception of consciousness which is intelligible independently of its connections to the wider life of a thinking being. To assume otherwise is to assume that the first-person mode of reflection at play in the <i>Meditations</i> itself already commits to the conception of consciousness which Williams, Kant, and Strawson rightly find objectionable. An alternative is to understand Descartes's entertainment of the problematic conception of consciousness as resulting from the argumentative pressure developed over the course of the First Meditation. And any seeming endorsement of that conception must be complicated by the fact that, by the Third Meditation, Descartes will insist that we cannot properly understand our form of consciousness as having its character independent of something external to us—not the wider life of a thinking being, admittedly, but an infinite substance who has left in me ‘the mark of the craftsman stamped on his work’ (<i>Med</i>. 7: 51). The first-personal character of the <i>Meditations</i> is not yet a commitment to use only the meagre resources provided by the pure view of consciousness.9</p><p>Madden contrasts the isolationist starting point with one on which our notion of a subject of experience is grounded in an objective, third-personal conception of a psychological event which is, by its nature, the undergoing of a complex unit such as a human being or other animal. And in other work, he has shown the powerful reasons for taking us to be animals of a certain sort.10 But one can accept these insights whilst insisting that this notion of a subject of experience cannot be understood independently of a first-personal conception of a psychological event which is, by its nature, the experience of a conscious subject. Kant, Strawson, and Williams are right that we cannot build up a conception of a subject of experience from a starting point of consciousness stripped of any connection to something external. But this need not be part of the Cartesian project. The dispute in <i>The Practical Self</i> is not about whether we can get to objectivity from a starting point which is intelligible independently of its connections to the external but whether those connections are established on theoretical or practical grounds.</p><p><i>The Practical Self</i> claims that we are required to have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking and that this faith is sustained by a set of practices which relate us to a world of others. Bill Brewer's comments target each of these claims. His questions can be grouped under three broad headings: the nature of cognitive agency, the argument for the claim that we must have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking, and the connection between faith and others. I'll say something about each of these in turn.</p><p>Start with cognitive agency. I claim in <i>The Practical Self</i> that there is a form of self-consciousness which involves an understanding of ourselves as the agents of our thinking. How should we understand the notion of agency involved in this characterisation? Kant contrasts the spontaneity of thinking with the passivity of sensory awareness. Brewer is sceptical that this marks a genuine contrast. We sometimes embark on perceptual projects—scanning the room to catch sight of one's child—and the end results are perceptual achievements: seeing her, half-hidden by the sofa. So too do we sometimes embark on intellectual projects—calculating the number of primes between 0 and 100, say. And the end results of these inquiries are intellectual achievements: the judgement that there are 25 primes. In both cases, the investigation is settled by how things are. To borrow a line from David Wiggins, there is nothing else to think.11</p><p>Given this structural analogy, why think that there is some distinctive kind of agency involved in thinking as opposed to perceiving? In both cases, we initiate a project. And in both cases, the end result is a state which is determined by the facts rather than our preferences about them. Indeed, Brewer thinks that we need this symmetry if we are to accept realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry. For he takes realism to be tantamount to the thought that the answers to one's questions are fixed by facts which are independent of one's knowledge of them. So if we are realists about the domains of perceptual and intellectual inquiry, not only should we treat symmetrically the achievements which settle perceptual and intellectual inquiry, we should further take those achievements to be passive responses to a world which is there anyway.</p><p>Brewer's forceful comparison between perceptual and intellectual inquiry presupposes that the achievements which end inquiry are independent of the wider activities which encompass them. This seems appropriate in the case of perceptual inquiry, since one can come to be in the perceptual states which end inquiry simply by opening one's eyes. Walking through the woods, I come across a pig—‘I can now just <i>see</i> that it is [a pig]’, says J.L. Austin, ‘the question is settled’ (1962, p.115). The passive voice is important here: perception can settle questions without one intending to settle them. And if the achievements which end intellectual inquiry are similarly independent of the wider activities which encompass them, then we seem compelled to treat judgement as equally passive to its objects. At the least, it makes it hard to see why we should treat thinking as distinctively active or spontaneous in a way that perception is not.</p><p>But this independence is not compulsory. Ryle denies it in a series of late papers on the nature of thinking. ‘It is not incidental to thoughts that they belong to trains of thought’, he writes; they are ‘constitutionally inceptive’ (Ryle <span>1958</span>, p.416, cited at PS, p.120). Ryle's claim is that the judgements which end extended episodes of cognitive activity are not separable from the trains of thought which they conclude. The judgement that there are 25 primes is individuated in part by the activity of counting the primes between 1 and 100 in which it features.</p><p>To identify this assumption is not yet to give reason to reject it. But its denial opens a way of explaining the activity of thinking which does not carry over to the case of perception. It is because the judgements which conclude intellectual inquiry depend on the extended cognitive processes which contain them that we treat these judgements as active. And it is because the perceptual states which conclude perceptual inquiry do not depend on the extended cognitive processes which contain them that we treat them as passive. The active nature of judgement is to be explained in terms of the structural features of the extended cognitive process in which it occurs.12</p><p>How does this relate to the realism which underlies Brewer's objection? Realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry can seem relevant if, given the assumption of independence, there is no difference in the relations which the end points of inquiry stand to the processes which precede them. For then it seems the only place to mark a difference between the activity of thinking and the passivity of perception is in terms of how each relates to its objects. And, as Brewer makes clear, realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry poses a constraint on making this good: the fact that we are answerable to how things are in both thought and perception enforces an understanding of both thinking and perception as passive. But once we drop the assumption of independence, we can explain the sense in which judgement is active not in terms of its relation to its objects but in terms of its relation to the processes in which it occurs.</p><p>I turn now to Brewer's comments on the argument that we must have faith in ourselves as the agent of our thinking.13 I claim that self-conscious subjects are required to settle questions about the propriety of their perspective on the world, that setting this as my end requires taking a stand on whether I will settle these questions, and that this requires assent to the claim that I am the agent of my thinking. The result is practical ground for accepting that we are the agents of our thinking, as per Lichtenberg's suggestive final line.</p><p>Brewer notes that this argument assumes that it is a condition on pursuing an end that one takes it to be attainable (see PS, pp.115–117). And he objects this is obviously too strong: crash-landing into the sea in an aeroplane, I may set out to swim to a distant island despite knowing the goal to be unattainable. If there is no connection between pursuing an end and taking it to be attainable, then the argument which purports to provide practical grounds does not go through.</p><p>What should we say about Brewer's counterexample? Well, if one's views on the attainability of an end bear no relation to whether once can decide to pursue it, why does Brewer's swimmer commit only to the project of swimming to safety? Such lack of ambition! Why not commit to the project of flying to safety or of turning into a fish and swimming the distance? The natural thought is that our knowledge that these goals are unattainable precludes us from setting them as ends. The end of swimming to a distant island, no matter how remote, is not like that.</p><p>One complicating factor here is the distinction Kant draws between ends which are willed and those which are merely wished (PS, p.116). We do not always mark this division when discussing our projects. But the claim about attainability applies only to ends that we have properly decided upon. And we must be careful to ensure that our judgements about its plausibility are not swayed by the commonplace that one can wish for ends whose attainment is outside our control. For this reason, the attainability constraint is better motivated not by appeal to cases but by reflection on structural constraints governing the setting of ends.</p><p>Consider incompatible ends. Say there are two islands in opposite directions and that I know I cannot swim to both. If it is a condition on pursuing an end that we take it to be attainable, then we have an explanation for why we cannot decide to swim to one island and, at the same time, decide to swim to the other. For that would require taking it to be attainable that I both swim to island A and swim to island B. And that is exactly what we know to be impossible. In denying the connection between setting ends and attainability, Brewer deprives himself of the resources needed to explain this incompatibility. It is these structural constraints which motivate a connection between setting an end and taking it to be attainable.14</p><p>Brewer pushes a further objection. He argues that to the extent that there are cases where setting an end involves taking that end to be attainable—his ‘brief, simple projects’—these are precisely cases in which setting an end involves no commitment to cognitive agency. Perhaps I set myself the task of finding out which animal is in front of me; I open my eyes and, as Austin puts it, the question is settled. According to Brewer, no cognitive agency is involved in this project. Thus, even if I am right that setting the end of evaluating my perspective requires taking a stand on what I will do, this need involve no commitment to the claim that I am the agent of my thinking. The argument for faith remains in trouble.</p><p>Brewer's objection here raises a set of questions about the nature of decision-making. We normally draw a distinction between two ways in which we can take a stand on what we will do in the future—one based in prediction and one based in commitment.15 Given my nervousness around condescending record-shop staff, I might predict that I will blush when browsing the new releases tomorrow. In making this prediction, I make no commitment to blushing being an instance of my agency. So the issue is not whether there are ways in which we can take a stand on what we will do without thinking of ourselves as agents—that much is without question—but whether this is possible in cases where our assent is based on our decision to pursue some end.</p><p>My reasons for thinking that there is a commitment to cognitive agency here turn on the connections between decision-making and agency more generally. When I decide to do something, I treat it as a constraint on my practical reasoning, a fixed point around which I must navigate. But it is a constraint that I can foreswear should I change my mind. In this it differs from constraints fixed by the world around me. (This is part of the reason for why we should not think of my assent to what I will do as based on evidence: see PS, pp.125–128.) We treat the constraints engendered by my decisions as different from the constraints engendered by how things are in the world—and it is in this differential treatment that we manifest an understanding of ourselves as agents. My commitment to it being true that I will do what I have <i>willed</i> is grounded in the role I play in making this the case.</p><p>Brewer thinks that this does not yet involve a commitment to my own agency because there are perceptual cases where what I will do is determined solely by how things are in the world. If I open my eyes, I will see a pig. That is not a result of any activity on my part. And, as we discussed above, Brewer thinks that perceiving and thinking are on a par in this respect. But the commitment to my own agency is not to be found in the relation between the world and my judgement. It is to be found in my recognition that the ends which I decide upon enforce constraints on practical reasoning which are under my own control. We need a connection between setting an end and taking it to be attainable if we are to explain the structural features that govern decision-making. And we need a connection between setting an end and an acceptance of our agency if we are to explain how our relation to our own decisions differs from our relation to those constraints enforced by the world.</p><p>I turn finally to Brewer's comments on the relation between faith and others. Brewer reconstructs the argument of <i>The Practical Self</i> as holding that self-consciousness requires cognitive agency, that cognitive agency is necessarily based on faith, and that faith requires engagement with others. And he objects that this argument is invalid because it is not true that faith in myself as the agent of my thinking requires engagement with others. It is compatible with all that I have said that faith in cognitive agency is sustained without any interaction with another. I agree—and indeed, emphasised in <i>The Practical Self</i> that the argument offered falls short of the kind of necessity which Descartes, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel aimed to secure (see, especially, PS, pp.159–164). For that reason, I never took myself to accept the final premise in Brewer's reconstruction of my argument. The claim was only that our faith in ourselves as intellectual agents <i>is</i> sustained by a practice which relates us to others—not that it must be.</p><p>Brewer gives some reasons to be dissatisfied with this response. He notes that I object to previous arguments which move from self-consciousness to objectivity in part by showing their failure to establish a necessary connection. But if I am allowed to avoid counterexamples by abjuring a commitment to necessary connections, why are the targets of my criticism not allowed to do likewise?</p><p>There are two possible complaints here. The first is that the arguments I criticise were not interested in establishing necessary connections and, to that extent, that the objections offered in ch.2 have no purchase. I'm not sure if Brewer intends this complaint but it would be an interesting case to make. Stuart Hampshire's <i>Thought and Action</i>—published the same year as <i>Individuals</i>—sets out in its first chapter a project which looks continuous in spirit and often in detail with what we now think of as Strawsonian metaphysics (see, e.g., Hampshire <span>1959</span>, pp.1–21). But the ‘necessary presuppositions of thought and knowledge’ (p.14) which Hampshire aims to uncover are not supposed to be the ‘only possible [principles]’: ‘this would be the error of Kant, the belief that we can anticipate and set final limits to new forms of knowledge’ (p.13, cf. p.20). If the same conception of necessary conditions is at work in the arguments under evaluation in ch.2 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, then the criticisms made there are blunted.</p><p>Let us take Strawson's argument from self-consciousness to objectivity as a test-case (discussed in PS, pp.35–48). I'm sympathetic to the thought that Strawson's understanding of his project does not fit neatly into contemporary taxonomies.16 But Strawson insists, in the introduction to <i>Individuals</i>, that his topic is that ‘massive central core of human thinking which has no history—or none recorded in histories of thought… categories and concepts which, in their most fundamental character, change not at all’ (Strawson <span>1959</span>, p.10). This looks incompatible with a conception of the necessary presuppositions of thought which allows variation across time and culture. Strawson is much more Kantian than Hampshire's relaxed historicism allows. So if the claim is that Strawson and the others considered in ch.2 were not concerned with establishing necessary connections, passages such as this need to be explained away. A case needs to be made.</p><p>The alternative complaint is that the arguments considered in ch.2 could be weakened in ways analogous to the discussion in ch.5, and that those reconstructed arguments would fare better against the objections offered in <i>The Practical Self</i> than the actual arguments considered. Here the thought would be not that differential standards are being applied in chs. 2 and 5 but that the same standards could be applied to different arguments. I agree that it would be fruitful to consider whether there are alternative arguments in the vicinity which avoid the problems raised. But it is not obvious that weakening the arguments would make them more plausible: some of the purported necessary conditions do not even look central to the lives of self-conscious beings.17 And, in any case, those are not the arguments which were given.</p><p>I suspect that part of the issue here is that Brewer wants to force the argument of <i>The Practical Self</i> into the mould of a Strawsonian transcendental argument with its emphasis on only the properly necessary. But one can admire the ambition of these arguments while sidestepping their concerns. Kant himself allowed all kinds of ways in which the historical could be put to use in properly transcendental projects—with images, symbols, practice, and ritual.18 And Hampshire is compelling on the way in which necessities may be supported by ‘the forms of our social life… the social world of conventionalised gesture, expression and habits of co-operation’ (Hampshire <span>1959</span>, p.20). The argument in <i>The Practical Self</i> is that our faith in ourselves as intellectual agents is sustained by a practice which relates us to others. That this is not necessary need not be cause for concern.</p><p>We must have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. Léa Salje gives a precise and perceptive account of the argument for this claim in <i>The Practical Self</i>. And she raises a set of concerns about whether the Kant-inspired account of practical assent outlined in <i>The Practical Self</i> can show that there is a positive epistemic basis for those claims we are required to accept on practical grounds.</p><p>When do we have practical grounds to accept some claim? In ch.4 of <i>The Practical Self</i> I argue that we have practical grounds to accept a claim when it is both theoretically undecidable and practically required. A claim is theoretically undecidable when we lack theoretical grounds to accept or deny it. And a claim is practically required when assenting to the claim is a rational requirement on the pursuit of ends that we are required to set. Since we cannot pursue ends without taking them to be attainable—contra Brewer, above—it follows that if we are required to set some end, we are rationally required to accept any claim which is a condition on taking it to be attainable.</p><p>This account of practical assent underwrites the practical grounds for accepting that we are the agents of our thinking. For I suggest that self-conscious subjects are required to set the end of settling questions about the propriety of their perspective on the world and that assent to the claim that we are the agents of our thinking is a condition on the pursuit of that end. It follows that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking.</p><p>Salje is sceptical about whether this account can explain why it is epistemically appropriate to assent to those claims which we are required to accept on practical grounds. Perhaps there are claims which we which we need to accept if we are to make sense of our status as active, inquiring creatures, living in a world of others. It is a further step, she says, to show that we are epistemically entitled to hold those claims. This is the target of her critique. She focuses on the first part of the argument for practical grounds: that we are required to settle questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. This is where she takes the positive epistemic status of practical assent to reside. And she raises two broad criticisms. First, that it does not provide practical assent with a positive epistemic status—the fact that practical assent traces back to a required end does not, in itself, show that practical assent is anything other than a form of wishful thinking. Second, that it is in any case false: we are not required to set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world. I take these in turn.</p><p>Start with practical assent and necessary ends. Salje notes that if we set ourselves some idiosyncratic end, we are not thereby entitled to assent to any claim which is a condition on our taking that end to be attainable. So why, she asks, should making the end compulsory somehow change the picture? Perhaps we must think of ourselves as kinder, smarter, more capable than others, in order to find our way around the world.19 That doesn't make it epistemically respectable to have an inflated self-conception. Indeed, Salje suggests, it may make it <i>less</i> so—for if we cannot but accept some claim, it seems, for that very reason, to lack epistemic credentials. To think otherwise is to assume that our situation cannot be tragic. Even if we cannot pursue ends without taking them to be attainable, why should the necessity of the end secure epistemic standing for assent in its attainability?</p><p>To address this charge, we need to be clear on why assent based on contingent ends lacks epistemic credentials. Salje suggests that it is because practical assent would otherwise be pervasive: we could bootstrap epistemic entitlement whenever we find it congenial. She gives the example of assenting to the claim that I am a whizz at learning language as a condition on attaining the end of learning Japanese in three months. But practical assent is constrained by theoretical grounds and, at least in my own case and as the tutors at the Oxford University Language Centre can sadly attest, there is a wealth of theoretical evidence that tells against my having any facility with learning languages. So it is not overabundance alone which tells against assent based on contingent ends.</p><p>No, the problem with assent based on contingent ends is its foundation: practical assent cannot be grounded in idiosyncratic desire. It is thus not the shift from the contingent to the necessary which insulates practical assent from the charge of wishful thinking but the shift from assent grounded in desire to assent grounded in obligation. It is because we are under a genuine <i>requirement</i> that we have grounds to accept any claim whose assent is a condition on our doing what we are required to do. Thus in order to answer Salje's charge, we need an account of why assent grounded in requirement rather than assent grounded in individual desire should endow a positive epistemic status.</p><p>The prospects of providing such an account can seem thin if one thinks of requirements as solely instrumental, fixed by an individual's desires. For then universally shared desires would serve to ground universal requirements. And there seems little reason to differentiate between desires which are idiosyncratic and those which are, of necessity, shared. Perhaps there are desires common to us all—‘the ordinary affections of human life; the anxious concern for happiness, the dread of future misery, the terror of death, the thirst of revenge, the appetite for food and other necessaries’ as Hume has it in <i>The Natural History of Religion</i> (2.5). And if these shared desires underwrite a universal requirement, then it will follow from the account of practical assent sketched in <i>The Practical Self</i> that we have practical grounds to accept any claim which is a condition on setting that end. The resulting assent—as Hume perhaps intends us to recognise—does not seem markedly different from wishful thinking.</p><p>But we need not think of necessary requirements as grounded in desire in this way. An alternative is to locate them in our nature as self-conscious beings (PS, pp.124–125). For if it is part of our nature that we are rational animals, then the requirement to evaluate our perspective will flow from our rational faculties. For someone sympathetic to Kant, this will be because it traces back to a categorical imperative given by reason itself (CPrR 5: 143, cf. PS, p.124). For someone more inclined towards Aristotelian naturalism, it will be because it is underwritten by the standards of good human life: the ‘activity of soul in accordance with reason’ (NE 1098a). In either case, its foundation is not some shared conative state but reason itself. A failure to accept those claims for which we have practical grounds thus manifests a kind of rational incoherence. It is this foundation in reason which distinguishes practical assent from wishful thinking and explains its positive epistemic status.</p><p>Salje might respond that this shows only that practical assent is a <i>rational</i> attitude not that it has a positive epistemic status. And at the end of her essay, she sketches one way in which one might decouple the two. But I worry that such decoupling has attraction only to the extent one insists on reserving epistemic status for that which is determined on evidential grounds. Kant offers us an account of assent which showcases an alternative source of good standing—when grounded in reason, when grounded in our nature, when grounded in something universal (see especially CPrR 5:143n.). The requirement to evaluate one's perspective on the world is one which flows from our status as self-conscious, rational animals. And someone who sets themselves the end of evaluating their perspective on the world but refuses to accept that they are the agent of their thinking exhibits a form of rational incoherence. The positive epistemic standing of practical assent is thus not found in its connection to evidence but in its status as reasonable, universal, natural—and secure.</p><p>Salje's second line of criticism targets the claim that we are required to set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world. She raises two questions: first, whether we do set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world, and second, whether we are required to do so. Both questions have force given the Cartesian framing of <i>The Practical Self</i>. For Descartes presents his project as an enormous undertaking, understandably postponed, and only needing to be performed once in a lifetime (<i>Med</i>. 7:17). Hence the legitimacy of Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia's complaint that ‘the life which I am constrained to lead does not leave enough time at my disposal to acquire a habit of meditation in accordance with your rules’ (<i>Corr</i>. 3:684). Why think that anyone outside of philosophical contexts actually engages in such recherché activity? Why think that anyone must do so?</p><p>Salje presses the first question through worries about over-intellectualisation. She distinguishes the beliefs and experiences which (partly) constitute our perspective on the world, the evaluative stances we take towards those beliefs and experiences, and the decision to engage in evaluative activity directed towards those beliefs and experiences. And the presentation of these phenomena as constituting three distinct levels of psychological attitude can make it seem as though there is an additional complexity at each stage: that there can be creatures who have a perspective without being able to step back and reflect on it, and that there can be creatures who can reflect on their perspective without deciding to engage in that activity.</p><p>In <i>The Practical Self</i>, I allow a gap between Salje's first and second levels: there are conscious creatures who have a perspective on the world but lack the ability to step back and evaluate that perspective. Does it follow that there can be a gap between Salje's second and third levels? As she notes, that will depend on how much is built into the setting of ends. The more that is required—expressly ridding my mind of all worries, arranging for myself a clear stretch of free time, for instance (<i>Med</i>. 7:17)—the less plausible it will be that anyone sets this end, the peculiarities of philosophical reflection excepted. And that can make it seem as if there is a gap to be bridged between Salje's second and third levels.</p><p>But there is something odd about the thought that one could reflect on one's perspective without ever deciding to do so. We do sometimes find our attention grabbed from without, as when a light flashes in the corner of our visual field. But to <i>will</i> an end as opposed to simply wishing it is to commit to taking some sort of action to bring it about. This is why the distinction has importance for both Kant and Aristotle: it captures a difference in the way desires relate to motivation which is relevant to ethical evaluation.20 We set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective whenever we purposefully engage in reflection. The commitment involved in setting it as our end thus involves no more than choosing to bring it about. So to the extent that reflection is something undertaken, it is something we have chosen to do, and thus set as our end.</p><p>This doesn't mean that human beings actually set this end, for one might think that reflection itself is more limited or circumscribed than I suggest. But drawing out the connection between willing an end and acting so as to bring it about may ease some of the concerns about over-intellectualisation. Setting oneself the end of evaluating one's perspective need not involve a moment of high drama; it does not require that the end be set under that mode of presentation; it is not something which needs to be affirmed and reaffirmed each morning. Rather, to the extent that reflection is something in which we purposefully engage—that we <i>choose</i> to stand back and reflect on whether our perspective on the world is appropriate—then the gap between Salje's second and third levels is blurred.</p><p>These considerations concern only whether people actually set themselves the end of evaluating their perspectives. Are they required to do so? Salje forcefully pushes back against this suggestion by emphasising how neurotic, self-alienating and exhausting it would be to constantly reflect on one's perspective on the world. It is often hard enough to navigate the world. Now add continual reflection on one's perspective! As Susan Wolff puts it in a related attempt to take seriously the prospects for a life lived in accordance with some purported norm: these ‘are not ideals to which it is particularly reasonable or healthy or desirable for human beings to aspire’ (Wolff 1982, p.433).</p><p>Salje's criticism is a helpful reminder of the way reflection brings with it risks of neurosis and narcissism. This is a preoccupation for Iris Murdoch whose writings are continually attentive to the way reflection gives way to self-involved concern.21 A full response to the charge should not deny these dangers. It needs rather to show the value of the reflective life, the importance of self-understanding, and the way in which reflecting on our perspective enlarges not just the domain of self-knowledge but also its structure. That will require situating reflection within the broader life of a human being.22</p><p>Absent that wider story, I'll point to two threads which connect to some of Salje's wider concerns and suggest ways in which a requirement to reflect on one's perspective is integral to a flourishing human life. First, intellectual virtue. Salje expresses sympathy at the end of her comments for a virtue epistemological framework which emphasises the epistemic benefits of well-functioning intellectual traits. But the competences involved in these virtues plausibly involve the kind of monitoring and assessment enabled by reflection on one's perspective.23 So we would expect someone who cares about the intellectual virtues to be attentive to whether her perspective is appropriate and to take deliberate steps to ensure that it remain so. When situated in a story about the value of the intellectual virtues, the requirement to evaluate one's perspective can start to seem part of a well-ordered human life.</p><p>Second, community. The mindfulness proponent who only ever lives at Salje's first level can seem like an attractive prospect given her attunement to the world around her. But part of that world will include others who disagree with her take on things. That alone will put rational pressure on her to reflect on the propriety of her perspective. And once collective projects are in the offing, policies for recognising, monitoring, and resolving disagreement will need to be in place—the participants to the common endeavour will need to reflect on their own perspectives in a deliberate and controlled manner. Salje has persuasively argued elsewhere that conversation has a cognitive value in enabling the articulation of our thoughts and ensuring they are rationally answerable.24 Maximising that value will often require sensitivity to the compatibility of one's perspective with that of one's conversational partner—a sensitivity facilitated by reflection, again in ways which can help us see the requirement to evaluate one's perspective as part of a well-ordered life.</p><p>This last connection is not intended to justify the claim that there is a requirement to evaluate the propriety of our perspective, not least since it would raise concerns about circularity given the argument in ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i>. The aim is only to make plausible that there is such a requirement by showing how a life lived in its light need not be self-alienated, neurotic, and exhausted. It might instead be an intellectually virtuous life lived in communion with others: one aspect of a life lived well.</p><p>Kant's views on self-consciousness, practical reason, and religion are a touchstone for the arguments set out in <i>The Practical Self</i>. Carla Bagnoli argues that they depart from Kant in ways which are detrimental to its project. Kant is a better guide to the connections between agential thinking and a social world of other thinkers than I allow.</p><p><i>The Practical Self</i> argues that self-conscious subjects must have faith in themselves as the agents of our thinking and that this faith is sustained by a set of practices which relate us to a world of others. Bagnoli thinks this an odd pairing. Her expansive comments centre on two main charges: that there is a much more direct connection to be found in Kant between our status as agential thinkers and a social world of other thinkers, and that, contrary to the suggestion in ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, a focus on practices and group-identities has the potential to undermine, rather than support, any connection to objectivity. The interleaving of faith and practice is both unnecessary and insufficient.</p><p>Start with the more direct connection between self-consciousness and objectivity. Bagnoli argues that there is a social dimension to practical assent which is independent of practice—or at least, independent of the practices which are the focus of ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i>. (I return to this distinction below.) This line of thought accepts that we have practical grounds to recognise ourselves as the agents of our thinking, contra Madden above. But it insists that no further step is needed to establish a connection to a world of other thinkers who are independent of me. There is a social dimension to practical assent which already connects self-conscious agents to a world of others.</p><p>How does sociality enter practical assent? Practical assent is introduced in <i>The Practical Self</i> as a mode of assent which is determined by practical grounds. And there are practical grounds to accept a claim when it is both theoretically undecidable and practically required. I use the term ‘faith’ to pick out this mode of assent—as Kant does at e.g. CPJ 5:471—but it is compatible with this that there are distinctions to be made within the class of practical assent. Bagnoli suggests one which is important for establishing a direct connection between self-consciousness and sociality: the distinction between faith and hope.</p><p>Hope has a central place in Kant's account of human reason. All interest of human reason, he tells us, is united in the questions: ‘What can I know? What should I do? What may I hope?’ (A805/B833). The last connects to faith, because it is answered by religion (JL 9:25). Some readers have accordingly treated hope and faith as equivalent.25 But Bagnoli thinks this is mistaken. She suggests that they are to be distinguished in terms of their intentional objects. Faith is directed at a world in which happiness and virtue are harmonised; hope at the realisation of an ethical community. This means that the object of hope already involves a social dimension: to hope is to recognise that the object of your practical assent is a collective project requiring the involvement of others.</p><p>Does this help with the establishment of a direct connection between self-consciousness and objectivity? If the content of hope already involves a social dimension, then it may seem as if we can sidestep the appeal to practice by establishing a link between self-consciousness and hope. For if self-conscious subjects are required to hope rather than have faith, we will already have shown that they are related, at least intentionally, to a community of others.</p><p>But this is no shortcut. Faith and hope, as attitudes, are distinguished solely in terms of their intentional objects. It is thus the content of practical assent which licences us in classifying an attitude as one of faith or hope. I do not want to insist that there are no cases in which differences in content alone are perspicuously represented by distinguishing the attitude we stand towards that content. But marking the distinction in this way means that we cannot argue directly for a connection between self-consciousness and hope and thereby take ourselves to have secured a connection to others. We must argue first for the necessity of a social content to practical assent and this will then allow us to characterise the connection as holding between self-consciousness and hope. That is to say, the issue is not whether self-consciousness requires faith or hope—it is whether the content of practical assent is necessarily social in the way required for hope.</p><p>The question of whether there is a more direct route to sociality thus turns on the content of practical assent. In ch.4 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, I argue that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking. Bagnoli's direct connection must go further: it must show that we have practical grounds to accept that we are in community with others. What is the argument for this claim?</p><p>In broad terms, the line of thought sketched by Bagnoli takes agential thinking to bring with it answerability to various norms. Some of these are epistemic and concern the truth or falsity of our assertions. Others are more broadly moral and concern the relation we stand in to others. In both cases, we can comply with the structural norms only in the context of a community of other thinkers. So to the extent that we have practical grounds available for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking, we also have practical grounds for accepting—hoping—that there is a community of other thinkers who face these challenges together.</p><p>If Bagnoli's thought can be made good, the content of practical assent is more expansive than I suggest. But there are two grounds for concern. First, there is a question about whether the content of this hope alone would suffice to establish a connection between self-consciousness and sociality. As I tell the story in ch.2 of <i>The Practical Self</i>, the twentieth century saw a retreat from the worldly ambitions of Descartes and Kant to the claim that self-conscious subjects are only intentionally directed onto an objective world (PS, pp.36–37). If hope is an attitude we can stand in to objects without being genuinely related to them, then Bagnoli's suggestion gets us no further than twentieth-century diffidence.</p><p>Second, and more importantly, the proposed extension of practical assent from cognitive agency to community turns on the claim that the structural norms of thinking can only be realised in a community of others. But even if thinking is governed by the norms which Bagnoli suggests, why think they can only be realised in communion with others? This is stronger than the claim that the norms which govern thinking <i>concern</i> others. For norms which concern others may be realisable solely through my own efforts—or, if not mine alone, at least supplemented only by divine assistance. Kant's argument to the stronger conclusion starts from an assumption about our propensity for evil (Rel. 6:97–98). Why think that anything similar holds true of the norms which govern our thinking? There is a gap between the claim that thinking is subject to norms which concern others and the claim that these norms require realisation in a community.</p><p>I turn now to Bagnoli's second charge: that, far from sustaining a commitment to objectivity, the practices appealed to in <i>The Practical Self</i> actually undermine it. How should we understand this concern? One might think that the directness of Bagnoli's route to sociality turns on its renunciation of practice and that this is the context in which to understand her concerns about the ways practices undermine objectivity. But consider the Kantian resources which she takes to underwrite practical assent. There is the practice of attributing responsibility, understood not in the Strawsonian form in which it appears in ch.5 of <i>The Practical Self</i> but as part of the fundamental structure of human interaction and the basis for all social agency. There is the particular way that moral agency shows up in sensibility as the feeling of respect. And there is the relation of reciprocity which places a normative constraint on deliberation.</p><p>How do these compare to the resources marshalled in <i>The Practical Self?</i> Bagnoli's Kant finds a foundation for practical assent in practices, feelings, and constraints on decision-making, all of which involve a relation to others. <i>The Practical Self</i> focussed primarily on the role of practices in scaffolding practical assent. But it also noted the way in which a commitment to the reality of others shows up in our experiences, when we disagree (PS, p.159), and in our decision-making, when we attend to diachronic considerations about the persistence of practices (PS, p.161). The difference between the direct and circumambulatory routes is not a difference in resource.</p><p>Bagnoli's objection to the argument in <i>The Practical Self</i> is thus not to its invocation of practice but to its claim that social practice is mere scaffold: something which aids practical assent but is strictly unnecessary. Her Kantian resources are instead supposed to be the very basis for intellectual agency, a social foundation for practical assent. The result is more recognisably Kantian, at least in as much as one takes Kant to care only about the properly necessary. Practical assent, by its very nature, involves others because it has its foundation in a practice of attributing responsibility, a feeling of respect, and a constraint of reciprocity. These practices, feelings, and constraints are not optional extras for those who need the additional support: they are part of the structure of human relations which underwrites the social agency involved in practical assent. Bagnoli's Kantian route is direct not because it foreswears practice but because it insists on its necessity.</p><p>This helps to spell out Bagnoli's concern about the way the two parts of the argument in <i>The Practical Self</i> fit together. The odd pairing is not faith and practice but the necessity of faith and the optionality of practice. Bagnoli worries that if practice is understood as anything less than the fundamental structure for human agency, it will mediate, weaken and distort our relation to others. Why would scaffolding have this consequence? Bagnoli's thought is that since the practices appealed to in <i>The Practical Self</i> are relative to particular forms of life (see e.g. PS, pp.138–141), the support that they provide is exclusive and independent. The result is a plethora of communities whose practices may, as it happens, sustain faith in the same content but whose structures are independently authoritative. And she takes this to be a undermine any strategy aiming at objectivity.</p><p>How seriously should we take this worry? Bagnoli is right to emphasise the dangers of group identities and the way in which distinguishing between those who are in and those who are out can inculcate hostility towards those on the outside even as it creates community among those on the inside. And she is right too that the practices involved in holding one another accountable are shaped by imbalances of power and authority in ways that I did not discuss. Social practices can constrain as much as they sustain and it is good to recognise this.</p><p>But why should this have any implication for objectivity? Bagnoli's thought seems to be that a proliferation of practice would undermine the norms involved in thinking of oneself as an autonomous thinker. For if the support provided to practical assent comes from a specific form of life, then I cannot take its support to generalise to all instances of thinking, even in the case where the distinct practices support the same norms. Convergence may allow an overlapping consensus on the model of Rawls's <i>Political Liberalism</i>. But Bagnoli insists that this falls short of universal authority. And it is this subversion of universal norms of thinking which is supposed to undermine any claim to objectivity.</p><p>But this is not the notion of objectivity at play in <i>The Practical Self</i>. I distinguish there two broad notions of objectivity—the ontological and the perspectival (PS, pp.12–16). According to the ontological notion of objectivity, something is objective when it doesn't depend for its existence on minds and subjective otherwise. According to the perspectival notion, something is objective when it is independent of a subject's point of view and subjective otherwise. The threat which Bagnoli finds in a proliferation of practices is a threat to the idea of universal norms which govern thinking—that is, to norms which apply independently of one's parochial perspective on the world. If she is right, there may be a threat to a perspectival notion of objectivity in the vicinity. But my concern in <i>The Practical Self</i> was the objectivity of things which don't depend for their existence on my awareness of them. And we don't yet have a threat to objectivity in this sense.</p><p>Consider a world of mutually independent practices, all of which centre on other thinkers, distinct from us and our mental states. It may be that we cannot take part in each practice without foreswearing the others. And it may be that Bagnoli is right to worry that the norms which issue from each practice can only ever aspire to local recognition, even when they overlap so as to allow consensus. This is no threat to the ontological notion of objectivity so long as each practice relates its participants to things which don't depend on minds. A plenitude of practices does not denigrate the objectivity of that to which they relate.</p><p>I don't see, then, that the optionality of practice threatens objectivity of the sort that was at issue in <i>The Practical Self</i>. Nor do I see that her Kantian route is more direct. Both lines of argument hold that self-consciousness requires practical assent and both think that assent is supported by practice. Bagnoli takes the content of the assent to be communal in a way that goes beyond the argument of <i>The Practical Self</i>. And she takes the connection between practical assent and practice to be necessary rather than central. I have expressed scepticism about the first claim and denied that the second is needed to secure a connection to objectivity. But even granting both, these are emendations to the approach set out in <i>The Practical Self</i> rather than its rejection.</p><p>There is still a difference of view about the scope and nature of the practice of accountability which is supposed to sustain faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. Bagnoli thinks it cannot be merely central but must be rooted in the structural and universal features of being human. But even if the practice of accountability is universal in the way that Bagnoli insists, this is not yet to show that it must relate us to other thinkers. It might be that we centre the practice on future selves, an imaginary other, or God (see PS, pp.159–161). I share with Bagnoli the thought that these practices could only ever be peripheral, a pale imitation of the joyful conversation which pervades our ordinary lives. But their possibility does not undermine the connection to others present in the ordinary case: our practice is enough.26</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46958,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY\",\"volume\":\"33 2\",\"pages\":\"779-795\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2025-05-20\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13076\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13076\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13076","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

利希滕贝格关于我思的神秘评论构成了《实践自我》的主干。罗里·马登提出了一系列丰富的问题,关于它们的正确解释和它们所处的论证工作。利希滕贝格写道,当我在思考的时候,说“我思”已经太多了。马登对比了对这句话的两种解读。传统的解读认为利希滕伯格对我是我的思想片段的主体这一说法提出了挑战,而这些情节都依赖于我的思想片段。修订后的解读——以及《实用的自我》中提供的解读——让李希滕伯格对“我有时是自己思想的代理人”这一说法提出了挑战。在这段阅读中,文章的最后一句话回应了这一挑战,暗示我们有实践依据接受我们是自己思想的代理人这一观点。假设I,假设它,是一个实际的要求。Madden担心最后一行的翻译,以及它为假定I. Lichtenberg写道:Das Ich anzunehmen, zu postlieren, ist praktisches bed<s:1> rfnis提供了实际依据的说法。g<s:1> nter Zöller将最后一个词翻译为“要求”(1992,第418页);Stephen Tester作为“必要性”(2012,第152页)。马登认为,“需要”是一个更接近的翻译,这削弱了利希滕伯格在宣传实际理由的说法。实际需要并不是某事的必要条件,而是一种迫切的或基本的冲动,就像需要伸伸腿一样。我对我们作为智力能动者的自我意识的实践基础的描述是模仿康德对实践假设的描述的。康德认为这些主张必须被假设(CPrR, 5:121, 126)或假设(5:122,125)因为它们与实践理性的要求有关。特别地,它们必须是根据康德所说的“纯实践理性的需要”(5:142)而被假定或假定的。纯粹实际理性的需要——实际的需要——与倾向的需要形成对比。这是一种基于责任的需要。因此,我们可以说,对康德来说,假定这些关于上帝、自由和不朽的主张,并把它们作为前提,是一种基于责任的实践需要,一种实践要求。这就是理解李希滕贝格最后一句话的背景。Madden的通缩建议切断了这些联系。这些句子的目标是什么呢?马登指出,解读利希滕贝格这样的格言作家很困难。在《实践的自我》中,我通过引用他作品中的其他段落来论证修正性阅读——包括,至关重要的是,李希滕贝格在笔记本中的一段话,在那里他回到了“我在思考”和“它在思考”之间的对比马登是对的,这些都不是决定性的——即使后来的段落显示出对智力代理的关注,也可能是利希滕伯格在K76写这篇文章时没有区分这两个问题,或者这两个问题都是有争议的。他也说对了,利希滕贝格在开头几句中使用第一人称并不违背传统的阅读方式但是,李希滕贝格更广泛的著作及其康德式的背景应该让我们认识到这样一种可能性,即李希滕贝格对无主体思维的担忧——尽管它们对我们哲学传统的发展很重要——是在早期分析哲学的局部关注下被解读到李希滕贝格身上的。这些解释问题并不是《Madden》的主要关注点。在内容的问题上,他认为代理的问题并不像我在《实践的自我》中提出的那样,我们有很好的理论基础来把我们自己当作我们思想的代理。思考主体的问题比我所允许的要复杂得多——如果要通过对客观性的论证,就必须给出一些对传统问题的答案。正是在这种背景下,他让人们注意到弗雷格关于自我意识的讨论中的一些微妙之处,而我在《实践自我》中错过了这些微妙之处。从第一个开始。Madden认为,通过毫无疑问地使用因果解释推理,我们可以知道我们是自己思维的代理人。我知道对面的房子里住着四个人,这可能是基于对外面停着的汽车数量、回收箱的状态等的最佳因果解释。同样,我知道我是我思维的主体,这可能是基于对我整个思维模式的最佳因果解释。这种推理提供了我认为不可用的那种理论依据(PS,第88 - 97页)。因果解释推理包括对解释对象采取观察立场。Madden指出,我怀疑这种立场是否能够恰当地把握我们所处的与未来行动的关系。 她区分了(部分地)构成我们对世界的看法的信念和经验,我们对这些信念和经验采取的评估立场,以及针对这些信念和经验进行评估活动的决定。这些现象构成了三个不同层次的心理态度,这使得每个阶段似乎都有一个额外的复杂性:有些生物可以有一个观点,但不能退后一步反思它,有些生物可以反思他们的观点,但不决定参与那项活动。在《实际的自我》中,我允许在Salje的第一和第二层次之间有一个差距:有些有意识的生物对世界有自己的看法,但缺乏退后一步评估这种看法的能力。这是否意味着在Salje的第二级和第三级之间可能存在差距?正如她所指出的那样,这将取决于目标设定的程度。要求得越多——例如,明确地让我的头脑摆脱一切烦恼,为自己安排一段清晰的自由时间(《马太福音》7:17)——任何人设定这个目标就越不可信,哲学反思的特点除外。这让人觉得在Salje的第二和第三个层次之间似乎有一个鸿沟需要弥合。但这种想法有些奇怪,一个人可以在没有决定这样做的情况下反思自己的观点。有时候,我们确实会发现自己的注意力被外界吸引住了,就像我们视野的角落里闪过一道亮光。但是,要实现一个目标,而不是简单地希望它,就要承诺采取某种行动来实现它。这就是为什么这种区别对康德和亚里士多德都很重要:它抓住了欲望与动机之间的区别,而动机与伦理评价有关每当我们有意识地进行反思时,我们就为自己设定了评估观点的终点。因此,把它设定为我们的目标所涉及的承诺只不过是选择实现它。因此,就反思是一种主动进行的事情而言,反思是一种我们选择去做的事情,并以此作为我们的目的。这并不意味着实际上是人类设定了这个目标,因为有人可能会认为反思本身比我所说的更有局限性。但是,找出“愿意结束”和“为实现它而行动”之间的联系,可能会缓解一些对过度理智化的担忧。为评价自己的观点设定一个终点,并不需要有一个戏剧性的时刻;它并不要求将目的设定在该陈述方式下;这不是每天早上都要确认和重申的事情。相反,在某种程度上,反思是我们有目的地参与的事情——我们选择退后一步,反思我们对世界的看法是否恰当——那么Salje的第二和第三个层次之间的差距就模糊了。这些考虑只涉及人们是否真的把自己作为评估自己观点的终点。他们必须这样做吗?Salje通过强调不断反思自己对世界的看法是多么的神经质、自我疏远和疲惫,有力地反驳了这一建议。在世界上航行通常已经够难的了。现在再加上不断反思自己的观点!正如苏珊·沃尔夫(Susan Wolff)在一项相关的尝试中所说的那样,认真对待按照某种所谓的规范生活的前景:这些“不是人类特别合理、健康或渴望的理想”(Wolff 1982,第433页)。Salje的批评是一个有益的提醒,提醒我们反思会带来神经官能症和自恋的风险。这是艾里斯·默多克所关注的,她的作品一直关注反思是如何让位于自我关注的对这一指控的全面回应不应否认这些危险。相反,它需要展示反思生活的价值,自我理解的重要性,以及反思我们的视角不仅扩大了自我认识的领域,而且扩大了自我认识的结构。这需要将反思置于一个人的更广泛的生活中。如果没有更广泛的故事,我将指出两条线索,这两条线索与Salje的一些更广泛的关注有关,并指出反思一个人的观点对繁荣的人类生活是不可或缺的。第一,智力美德。Salje在评论的最后表达了对美德认识论框架的同情,该框架强调了功能良好的智力特征的认识论益处。但这些美德所包含的能力似乎包括通过反思个人观点而实现的监控和评估。 因此,我们期望那些关心智力美德的人注意自己的观点是否恰当,并采取深思熟虑的步骤来确保它保持恰当。当身处一个关于智力美德价值的故事中时,评估一个人的观点的要求似乎开始成为井然有序的人类生活的一部分。第二,社区。考虑到她对周围世界的协调,只生活在Salje的第一层次的正念支持者似乎是一个有吸引力的前景。但这个世界的一部分将包括那些不同意她观点的人。仅这一点就会给她施加合理的压力,迫使她反思自己的观点是否恰当。一旦集体项目开始,识别、监督和解决分歧的政策将需要到位——共同努力的参与者将需要以深思熟虑和可控的方式反思自己的观点。Salje在其他地方很有说服力地论证了对话在使我们的思想清晰表达和确保它们是合理的回答方面具有认知价值要使这种价值最大化,通常需要对自己的观点与对话伙伴的观点的兼容性保持敏感——这种敏感是通过反思来促进的,同样,这种敏感性可以帮助我们看到,将自己的观点作为有序生活的一部分进行评估的必要性。最后一种联系并不是为了证明有必要评估我们的观点的适当性,尤其是因为它会引起对循环性的关注,因为在《实践自我》第5章的论点中。其目的只是通过展示生活在它的光芒下的生活如何不需要自我异化、神经质和疲惫,使这样的要求变得合理。相反,它可能是一种与他人交流的智力高尚的生活:生活的一个方面。康德关于自我意识、实践理性和宗教的观点是《实践自我》中所阐述的论点的试金石。卡拉·巴格诺里认为他们偏离康德的方式不利于康德的计划。对于能动思维和其他思想家的社会世界之间的联系,康德提供了更好的指导。《实践自我》认为,自我意识主体必须相信自己是我们思维的代理人,而这种信念是通过一系列将我们与他人世界联系起来的实践来维持的。Bagnoli认为这是一个奇怪的配对。她的广泛评论集中在两个主要指控上:在康德的著作中,我们作为能动思考者的地位与由其他思考者组成的社会世界之间存在着更为直接的联系;另外,与《实践自我》第五章的建议相反,对实践和群体身份的关注有可能破坏而不是支持与客观性的任何联系。信仰和实践的交织既不必要又不充分。从自我意识和客观性之间更直接的联系开始。巴格诺里认为,实践同意有一个独立于实践的社会维度,或者至少独立于《实践自我》第5章所关注的实践。(我将在下面回到这个区别。)这条思路承认,我们有实际的理由承认自己是我们思想的代理人,与上文的Madden相反。但它坚持认为,不需要进一步的步骤来建立与其他独立于我的思想家世界的联系。实践同意有一个社会维度,它已经将自我意识的行动者与他人的世界联系起来。社会性是如何进入实践同意的?在《实践自我》中,实践同意作为一种由实践基础决定的同意模式被引入。当一项索赔在理论上是不可判定的,而在实践中又是必需的,我们就有实际的理由接受它。我用“信仰”这个词来指出这种同意的模式,就像康德在CPJ 5:471所做的那样,但与此相一致的是,在实践同意的范畴内存在着区别。巴格诺里提出了一个对于建立自我意识和社会性之间的直接联系很重要的观点:信仰和希望之间的区别。希望在康德关于人类理性的论述中占有中心地位。他告诉我们,人类理性的所有兴趣都集中在以下问题上:“我能知道什么?”我该怎么办?我能希望什么呢?”(A805 / B833)。最后一个问题与信仰有关,因为它得到了宗教的回答(约9:25)。因此,一些读者把希望和信念等同起来但是Bagnoli认为这是错误的。她认为它们是根据它们的意图对象来区分的。信仰指向一个幸福与美德和谐共存的世界;希望在实现一个道德共同体。 这意味着希望的对象已经包含了一个社会维度:希望就是认识到你实际同意的对象是一个需要他人参与的集体项目。这是否有助于建立自我意识和客观性之间的直接联系?如果希望的内容已经涉及社会层面,那么我们似乎可以通过在自我意识和希望之间建立联系来回避对实践的呼吁。因为,如果要求有自我意识的主体希望而不是信仰,我们就已经表明,他们至少是有意地与他人群体有关。但这不是捷径。信仰和希望,作为态度,仅仅根据它们的意向对象来区分。因此,正是实践同意的内容允许我们将一种态度划分为信仰态度或希望态度。我并不想坚持认为,在任何情况下,通过区分我们对内容所持的态度,就可以明显地表现出内容上的差异。但是,以这种方式标记这种区别意味着,我们不能直接论证自我意识和希望之间的联系,从而认为我们自己已经确保了与他人的联系。我们必须首先论证社会内容对于实践同意的必要性,这将使我们能够描述自我意识和希望之间的联系。也就是说,问题不在于自我意识是否需要信仰或希望,而在于实践同意的内容是否必然以希望所需的方式具有社会性。是否有一条通往社会性的更直接的途径的问题,因此转向了实践同意的内容。在《实际的自我》的第四章中,我认为我们有实际的理由接受我们是我们思想的代理人。巴格诺里的直接联系必须走得更远:它必须表明,我们有实际的理由接受我们与他人在一起。这种说法的论据是什么?从广义上讲,巴格诺里勾勒的思想路线采用了代理思维,使其能够对各种规范负责。其中一些是认识论的,关系到我们断言的真伪。另一些则更宽泛地讲道德,关注我们与他人的关系。在这两种情况下,我们只能在其他思考者组成的共同体的背景下遵守结构规范。因此,在某种程度上,我们有实际的理由把我们自己当作我们思想的代理人,我们也有实际的理由接受——希望——有一个由其他思想家组成的团体,他们共同面对这些挑战。如果巴格诺里的思想可以被证明是正确的,那么实际同意的内容比我所建议的要广泛得多。但有两点值得关注。首先,有一个问题是,这种希望的内容本身是否足以建立自我意识和社会性之间的联系。正如我在《实践的自我》第2章中讲述的那样,二十世纪见证了从笛卡尔和康德的世俗野心到声称自我意识主体只是有意地引导到客观世界的撤退(PS,第36 - 37页)。如果希望是一种态度,我们可以站在对象,而不是真正地与他们联系,那么巴格诺里的建议给我们带来的只不过是20世纪的缺乏自信。其次,更重要的是,将实践同意从认知代理扩展到社区的提议,推翻了思维的结构规范只能在他人的社区中实现的主张。但是,即使思维受到巴格诺里所提出的规范的支配,为什么认为它们只能在与他人的交流中实现呢?这比支配思维的规范与他人有关的说法更为有力。因为与他人有关的规范只能通过我自己的努力来实现——或者,如果不是我一个人的努力,至少也只能通过神的帮助来补充。康德对更强有力的结论的论证始于一个关于我们的邪恶倾向的假设(雷尔书6:97-98)。为什么认为支配我们思维的规范也适用类似的东西呢?在认为思考受制于与他人有关的规范和认为这些规范需要在一个社区中实现之间存在着差距。现在我转向Bagnoli的第二个指控:远没有维持对客观性的承诺,《实践自我》中所呼吁的实践实际上破坏了它。我们应该如何理解这种担忧?有人可能会认为,Bagnoli通往社会性的直接路线开启了对实践的放弃,这是理解她对实践破坏客观性方式的关注的背景。但是想想康德的资源,她用它来保证实际的同意。有一种归因责任的做法,不是以斯特劳森的形式来理解的它出现在。 而是作为人类互动的基本结构的一部分和所有社会代理的基础。道德能动性以一种特殊的方式在感性中表现为尊重的感觉。互惠关系对审议施加了规范性约束。这些与《实际自我》中整理的资源相比如何?巴格诺里的康德在实践、感觉和决策约束中找到了实践同意的基础,所有这些都涉及到与他人的关系。实践自我主要关注实践在构建实践同意中的作用。但它也注意到,当我们不同意时,对他人现实的承诺会出现在我们的经历中(PS,第159页),以及当我们关注实践持续性的历时性考虑时,会出现在我们的决策中(PS,第161页)。直接路线和绕行路线的区别并不是资源的不同。因此,Bagnoli对《实践自我》中的论证的反对并不在于它对实践的援引,而在于它声称社会实践仅仅是一个脚手架:一些有助于实践同意但严格来说是不必要的东西。相反,她的康德式资源被认为是智力能动性的基础,是实践同意的社会基础。结果更明显地是康德式的,至少我们认为康德只关心适当的必然性。实践同意,就其本质而言,涉及他人,因为它的基础是归因责任的实践,尊重的感觉和互惠的约束。对于那些需要额外支持的人来说,这些实践、感受和约束并不是可有可无的附加条件:它们是人类关系结构的一部分,它保证了实践同意所涉及的社会代理。巴格诺里的康德路线是直接的,不是因为它摒弃实践,而是因为它坚持实践的必要性。这有助于阐明Bagnoli对《实践自我》中论证的两部分如何结合在一起的关注。奇怪的配对不是信仰和实践,而是信仰的必要性和实践的可选择性。Bagnoli担心,如果实践被理解为人类能动性的基本结构,它将调解、削弱和扭曲我们与他人的关系。为什么脚手架会有这样的后果?Bagnoli的想法是,既然《实践自我》中所诉诸的实践是相对于特定的生活形式的(参见PS,第138 - 141页),那么它们所提供的支持是排他性的和独立的。其结果是出现了过多的社区,这些社区的实践可能碰巧维持对相同内容的信仰,但其结构具有独立的权威性。她认为这是在破坏任何旨在客观的策略。我们应该多认真地对待这种担忧?巴格诺里强调群体身份认同的危险是正确的,以及区分圈内人与圈外人的方式,可能会在圈内人之间建立社区的同时,向圈外人灌输敌意。她也说得对,相互问责的做法受到权力和权威不平衡的影响,而我没有讨论这种不平衡。社会实践既能维持,也能限制,认识到这一点是件好事。但为什么这对客观性有任何影响呢?Bagnoli的想法似乎是,实践的扩散会破坏将自己视为自主思考者的规范。因为,如果对实践同意的支持来自一种特定的生活形式,那么我就不能把它的支持推广到所有的思维实例,即使是在不同的实践支持相同规范的情况下。趋同可能允许对罗尔斯的政治自由主义模式的重叠共识。但巴格诺里坚持认为,这种说法缺乏普遍权威。正是这种对普遍思维规范的颠覆,破坏了对客观性的任何主张。但这并不是在《实践自我》中发挥作用的客观性概念。我区分了客观性的两大概念——本体论和透视(PS,第12 - 16页)。根据客观性的本体论概念,当某物的存在不依赖于心灵时,它就是客观的,否则就是主观的。根据透视概念,当某事物独立于主体的观点之外时,它就是客观的,否则就是主观的。巴格诺里在实践的扩散中发现的威胁是对支配思维的普遍规范观念的威胁,也就是说,对独立于个人狭隘世界观的规范的威胁。如果她是对的,那么附近的客观观点可能会受到威胁。 但在《实践自我》中,我关注的是事物的客观性,它们的存在并不依赖于我对它们的意识。在这个意义上,我们还没有对客观性构成威胁。考虑一个相互独立的实践世界,所有这些实践都以其他思想家为中心,与我们和我们的精神状态截然不同。也许我们不能参加每一种实践而不放弃其他实践。巴格诺里的担心也许是正确的,即从每一种做法中产生的准则永远只能得到当地的承认,即使它们重叠以便达成协商一致。这对客观性的本体论概念没有威胁,只要每个实践将参与者与不依赖于心灵的事物联系起来。丰富的实践并不会贬低与之相关的客观性。我不认为,实践的可选择性会威胁到《实践自我》中争论的客观性。我也不认为她的康德路线更直接。两种观点都认为,自我意识需要实践的同意,并且都认为同意是由实践支持的。巴格诺里以一种超越《实践自我》论证的方式,将认同的内容作为公共的。她认为实际同意和实践之间的联系是必要的,而不是核心的。我对第一种说法表示怀疑,并否认需要第二种说法来确保与客观性的联系。但即使两者都承认,这些都是对《实践自我》中提出的方法的修正,而不是对它的否定。关于问责制实践的范围和性质,人们仍有不同的看法,问责制应该维持我们作为我们思想代理人的信念。巴格诺里认为,它不能仅仅是中心,而必须植根于人类的结构和普遍特征。但是,即使问责制的实践像巴格诺里所坚持的那样是普遍的,这也并不表明它必须将我们与其他思想家联系起来。这可能是我们将实践集中在未来的自我、想象的他者或上帝上(见PS,第159 - 161页)。我和巴格诺里一样认为,这些做法只能是次要的,是对我们日常生活中普遍存在的愉快交谈的苍白模仿。但是它们的可能性并不会破坏在通常情况下与其他存在的联系:我们的实践就足够了 当我们对将要做的事情进行推理时,我们将决定所施加的约束视为可修改的,从而允许我们撤销决定,而不会因此抵消现有证据。这要求我们对我们的决定采取一种立场,这种立场与我们对环境施加的限制采取的立场形成根本对比(PS,第125 - 128页;参见Soteriou 2013, p.287 f.)。在此,Madden并没有对这些考虑提出异议。但他认为,它们并不适用于因果解释推理的回顾性使用。我们可以回顾思考和推理的片段,找到它们最好的因果解释。这为我们提供了越来越多的证据,证明我们是自己思维的代理人。这是一个有益的提醒,提醒我们经验可以通过多种方式为同意提供理论依据。但是Madden对回顾性因果解释推理的使用看起来主要是为了建立习惯性的主张,我认为这是主观的,而不是笛卡尔的渐进主张。就像我可能会看着屋子里的废弃书籍,想到我在当代小说中挣扎一样,我也可以回顾一些思考和推理的片段,想到我作为一个认知代理的地位。要么马登认为对进步的认识可以建立在对习惯的认识的基础上——这种方法要求拒绝上述关于决策的考虑——要么他认为对习惯的认识足以回答利希滕贝格的挑战。两者都不是直截了当的。尽管如此,即使因果解释推理不允许我们认识到我们是能动的,在笛卡尔看来是危险的,我有必要在《实践自我》中否认这种认识吗?马登担心,我对知识的否定——我对同意的理论依据的否定——与我在积极论证中对我们自己作为我们思考的代理人的信念所做的各种主张不一致。这些都是关于思考的存在和重要性,它作为一种认知活动的地位,以及它与反应性态度和实践的关系的主张(参见,例如PS,第120 - 125页,第147 - 152页)。我是否以一种与书中早些时候提出的否定知识相矛盾的方式来表现自己知道这些主张?《实践自我》第三章中对知识的否定,更确切地说,是对赞同的理论依据的否定,即对主张的真理性的否定。理论依据和实践依据之间的区别应该表明,我们可以有理由同意索赔,即使它们不能建立在理论依据上。在《实践自我》一书中,我认为我们作为认知能动者的地位就是这样一种主张。也就是说,我们承认自己是有认知能力的人,是会思考、迷惑和决定的生物,这只能从实践的角度来看。马登是对的,我认为自己有理由断言,在《实践自我》的肯定论证中,关于思考的主张。这与我认为他们缺乏理论依据的观点是一致的。这可能是术语“知识”掩盖问题的地方。对知识的否认听起来像是对怀疑主义的邀请。但我们会因为康德否认道德可以建立在理论基础上就称他为道德怀疑论者吗?康德有时愿意使用实践认知或知识这两个术语来表示我们承认自己受制于道德律(例如,CPrR, 5:4-5;43)。这与他认为它缺乏理论依据是一致的。《实践自我》中所涉及的那种认知活动只有从实践的角度才能理解。建立其结论的一些论据也是如此。允许我们有理论依据来把我们自己当作我们思想的代理人会是个问题吗?Madden指出,在他的著作中很少有关于实际同意的论证。第四章和第五章揭示了我们作为认知主体的地位在理论上的不确定性。为什么不允许我们在理论和实践上都承认自己是这样的人呢?在《实践的自我》中,对理论的不可判定性的要求是通过对康德关于同意上帝存在的实践依据的解释而产生的。但我支持这一要求的唯一理由是,有必要在合理范围内避免冲突。否则就会有实际的理由同意一个被理论证据所反对的主张(附注,第113页)。马登可以合理地指出,禁止冲突只排除理论和实践理由指向相反方向的情况。如果双方意见一致,就没有冲突。这一点很好,也很重要。事实上,我们甚至不清楚康德自己的讨论是否能激发出除了避免矛盾之外的任何东西。 在他对理性内部冲突的讨论中,他写道:“理性作为一种可能的使用所需要的东西,即它的原则和肯定不能相互矛盾,不构成其利益的一部分,而是拥有理性的条件”(CPrR 5:120,我强调)。这显然不能排除支持同一主张的理论和实践理由。康德确实将纯实践理性的假设描述为“一个理论命题,尽管它不能被证明”(CPrR 5:122,我的重点)。但这种定性只适用于上帝、不朽和自由的情况,而不适用于任何可以在实际理由上断言的主张。马登是对的,他认为我应该说得更多,以激发实践基础和理论的不可判定性之间的联系——但沿着他建议的方向前进,可能并不涉及偏离康德。4让我们转向传统上与利希滕伯格有关的问题——引入我的那些情节所依赖的思想情节的主题的问题。Madden认为我们应该认真对待这个问题。在他阅读Lichtenberg的评论时,他们给那些想要解释我们在经验的基础上形成经验主体的广义概念的能力的人提出了一个问题,而这些经验本身并不构成一个主体。通过维特根斯坦和二十世纪早期的经验主义者的过滤,这提出了一个关于其他心灵的概念问题:如果我们从无主体的思考开始,结果是一种唯我主义的拒绝或无法支持其他经验主体。其他思想的概念问题是早期分析哲学与利希滕贝格的接触的重要组成部分,并通过维特根斯坦的著作影响了20世纪哲学的重要时刻Madden认为这对the Practical Self项目很重要。因为如果我们不能独立于思维环节而形成思维主体的概念,我们就不能形成其他思维存在物的概念。我对人际实践的描述维持了我们对自己作为我们思维的代理人的信念,它的中心实践包括将其他主体作为能够控制和被控制的思考者进行思考(特别参见PS,第158 - 159页)。因此,如果我们不能理解一个可推广的思维主体,就不可能有这样的实践,而与客观世界的联系就被切断了。在这种背景下,Madden让人们注意到Frege在《思想》中讨论的一个方面,而我在《实践的自我》中已经忽略了这一点。弗雷格在那篇论文中所关注的是,为“我唯一能思考的就是我自己的想法”这一说法提供了一个反例。反例是关于我自己的。因为我是我的观念的承载者,而任何观念的承载者本身都不可能是观念。所以,在思考我自己的时候,我思考的不是一个观念。在《实践的自我》中,我抱怨说,这忽略了我们在思考的片段中呈现给自己的方式:这与弗雷格的论点是一致的,即我作为我的观念的承载者的地位并不表现在自我意识、思想和经验的特征中。这是Madden所否认的,他认为这允许Frege对其他思想的概念问题做出回应。因为他认为弗雷格的讨论包含了后来由伯特兰·罗素和G.E.摩尔更详细地发展起来的一种思想的萌芽:经验有一种关系结构,这种结构在经验的特征中表现出来。这种关系结构有一个隐含的关系,即经验的主体。所以在经历感官经验时,我意识到一个关系结构,在这个结构中,我作为经验的主体,作为一个基本组成部分。我认为Madden的观点是正确的,即我们必须认真对待概念问题,无论最终是否会在Lichtenberg身上找到它。他在弗雷格身上发现的关于经验结构的主张是一种很有希望的回应但是,对概念问题作出回应的约束是什么?特别是,我们可以使用哪些资源来解释我们将他人视为潜在经验主体的能力?Madden提供的Fregean解决方案满足了笛卡尔项目孤立主义起点所施加的限制。但他指出,我们不需要接受这样一种退化的起源。他还引用了伯纳德·威廉姆斯的话来支持笛卡尔理论的出发点本身就排除了解决其他心灵的概念问题的可能性"如果我们除了纯粹的意识观点之外没有任何帮助,那么唯一连贯的理解思想发生的方式就是想象自己在思考它。 因此,仅仅坚持意识的观点,我们被迫回到实际上只有一个这样的观点的位置……”(Williams 1978, p.84)。马登将他对弗雷格的解读作为纯粹意识视角的辅助。但他温和地暗示,与威廉姆斯一起,李希滕贝格可能“与笛卡尔分享他最深的错误”(1978年,第79页)。威廉姆斯在《笛卡儿:纯粹探究的计划》第三章中对利希滕贝格的精彩讨论需要放在第十章中重复的背景中。威廉姆斯在书中说,他反对笛卡尔孤立主义出发点的论点“实际上只是康德在《纯粹理性的谬误论》中的论点的发展”(1978年,第292页)。威廉姆斯认为笛卡尔的出发点是有意识经验的片段可以独立于它们与思考事物的更广泛生活的联系而被理解。在谬误推理中,康德的思想,至少是斯特劳森在《感觉的界限》中所提出和辩护的思想,是这样一种自成一体的意识概念,它并不包含使一个持续的主体的概念具有可解性的材料如果威廉姆斯正确地看到,他的论点在康德身上得到了预示,那么我将笛卡尔和康德合二为一就纯属异想天开。但是,从沉思开始的这种孤立,并不应当被理解为一种意识的概念,这种意识的概念是可以被理解的,而不去考虑它与一个有思想的存在的更广泛的生活的联系。相反的假设,就是假设在《沉思录》中,第一人称的反思模式已经致力于意识的概念,而这正是威廉姆斯、康德和斯特劳森所反对的。另一种选择是理解笛卡尔对有问题的意识概念的娱乐,这是由于第一次冥想过程中产生的争论压力。在《第三沉思》中,笛卡儿坚持认为,我们不能正确地把我们的意识形式理解为具有独立于我们之外的东西的性质,而不是一个思维存在物的更广泛的生活,而是一种无限的实体,它在我身上留下了“工匠在他的作品上的印记”(《默7:51》)。《沉思录》的第一人称特征还不是承诺只使用纯粹意识观点所提供的贫乏资源。马登将孤立主义的出发点与另一种观点进行了对比。在这种观点上,我们对经验主体的概念是以客观的、第三人称的心理事件的概念为基础的,心理事件本质上是人类或其他动物等复杂单位的经历。在其他作品中,他展示了把我们看作某种动物的有力理由但是,人们可以接受这些见解,同时坚持认为,这种经验主体的概念不能独立于对心理事件的第一人称概念来理解,心理事件本质上是一个有意识的主体的经验。康德、斯特劳森和威廉姆斯是正确的,我们不能从剥夺了与外部事物的任何联系的意识起点建立经验主体的概念。但这并不一定是笛卡尔计划的一部分。在《实践自我》中争论的不是我们能否从一个可以独立于它与外部的联系而理解的起点到达客观性而是这些联系是建立在理论还是实践的基础上的。实践自我认为,我们需要相信自己是我们思想的代理人,而这种信念是通过一系列将我们与他人世界联系起来的实践来维持的。比尔·布鲁尔的评论针对的是这些说法。他的问题可以归纳为三个大标题:认知代理的本质,我们必须相信自己是我们思考的代理的论点,以及信仰与他人之间的联系。我将依次介绍这些问题。从认知代理开始。我在《实践自我》中宣称,存在一种形式的自我意识,它包含了对我们自己作为我们思维的代理人的理解。我们应该如何理解这种特征中涉及的代理的概念?康德将思维的自发性与感官意识的被动性进行了对比。布鲁尔怀疑这是否标志着真正的对比。我们有时会进行感性的项目——扫视房间以看到自己的孩子——最终的结果是感性的成就:看到她,半藏在沙发后面。因此,我们有时也会进行智力项目——比如计算0到100之间的质数。这些调查的最终结果是智力上的成就:判断出有25个质数。 在这两种情况下,调查都是根据情况而定的。借用大卫·威金斯(David Wiggins)的一句话,没有别的事可想。考虑到这个结构类比,为什么认为思维中有某种独特的能动性,而不是感知呢?在这两种情况下,我们都启动一个项目。在这两种情况下,最终的结果是一种由事实决定的状态而不是我们对它们的偏好。事实上,布鲁尔认为,如果我们要接受关于知识探索领域的现实主义,我们就需要这种对称性。因为他认为现实主义等同于这样一种思想,即一个人的问题的答案是由事实确定的,而这些事实与他对这些事实的认识无关。因此,如果我们是感性和智力探索领域的现实主义者,我们不仅应该对称地对待解决感性和智力探索的成就,我们还应该进一步把这些成就看作是对一个无论如何都存在的世界的被动反应。布鲁尔对感性探究和理智探究的有力比较,预设了终结探究的成就独立于包含它们的更广泛的活动。在感性探究的情况下,这似乎是合适的,因为一个人可以进入感性状态,只要睁开眼睛就可以结束探究。在树林里散步时,我遇到了一头猪——J.L. Austin说,“我现在可以看到它是(一头猪)”,“问题解决了”(1962年,第115页)。被动语态在这里很重要:感知可以在没有意图的情况下解决问题。如果以智力探索为结束的成就同样独立于围绕它们的更广泛的活动,那么我们似乎不得不把判断视为同样被动地对待其对象。至少,这让我们很难理解为什么我们应该把思维看作是独特的主动或自发的,而感知却不是。但这种独立性并不是强制性的。赖尔在一系列关于思维本质的论文中否认了这一点。他写道:“思想不是偶然的,它们属于一系列的思想。”它们是“宪法上的概念”(Ryle 1958,第416页,引自PS,第120页)。赖尔的观点是,结束认知活动的长时间片断的判断与它们所总结的思路是不可分离的。有25个质数的判断,部分地是由于计算它所包含的1到100之间的质数的活动而个性化的。确认这一假设并不意味着给出拒绝它的理由。但是,否定思维活动,就开辟了一种解释思维活动的方法,而这种方法却不适用于知觉的情况。正是因为得出智力探究结论的判断依赖于包含这些判断的扩展认知过程,所以我们才把这些判断视为主动的。正是因为总结出感知探究的感知状态并不依赖于包含它们的扩展认知过程,所以我们把它们视为被动的。判断的主动性质是根据它发生的扩展认知过程的结构特征来解释的。这与布鲁尔反对的现实主义有什么关系?如果考虑到独立性的假设,研究的终点与之前的过程之间的关系没有区别,那么关于知识探索领域的现实主义似乎是相关的。因为这样看来,思维的主动性和知觉的被动性之间唯一的区别,似乎就在于二者同客体的关系。而且,正如布鲁尔明确指出的那样,关于知识探究领域的现实主义对实现这一目标构成了约束:我们要对事物在思想和感知中的表现负责,这一事实迫使我们将思想和感知都理解为被动。但是,一旦我们抛弃了独立性的假设,我们就可以解释这样一种意义,即判断的活动不是根据它同它的客体的关系,而是根据它同它所发生的过程的关系。我现在转到布鲁尔关于我们必须相信自己是我们思想的代理人这一论点的评论我认为有自我意识的主体需要解决关于他们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题,把这个作为我的目的需要我对是否解决这些问题有一个立场,这需要我同意我是我思维的主体这一说法。正如利希滕贝格的最后一句暗示的那样,这个结果为接受我们是自己思想的代理人这一观点提供了实际依据。布鲁尔指出,这一论点假设,追求一个目标是一个人认为可以达到的条件(见附言,第115 - 117页)。他反对说,这显然太强烈了:在飞机迫降到海里时,我可能会出发游到一个遥远的岛屿,尽管我知道这个目标是不可能实现的。 如果在追求一个目的和认为它是可以达到的之间没有联系,那么声称提供实际依据的论证就站不住脚。我们该如何看待布鲁尔的反例?如果一个人对终点可达性的看法与他是否能决定追求它没有关系,为什么布鲁尔的游泳者只承诺游泳到安全的地方?如此缺乏野心!为什么不致力于飞到安全的地方,或者变成一条鱼,游过这段距离呢?自然的想法是,我们知道这些目标是无法实现的,所以我们不会把它们作为目标。游到一个遥远的岛的尽头,无论多么遥远,都不是那样的。这里有一个复杂的因素,那就是康德对意志的目的和愿望的目的所作的区分(PS,第116页)。在讨论我们的项目时,我们并不总是标记这个划分。但是,关于可达性的主张只适用于我们已经正确决定的目的。我们必须小心谨慎,以确保我们对其合理性的判断不受老生常谈的影响,即人们可以希望达到我们无法控制的目标。出于这个原因,最好不是通过诉诸案例,而是通过反思控制目标设定的结构性约束来推动可达性约束。考虑不相容的目的。假设有两个方向相反的岛屿,我知道我不能同时游到它们。如果这是追求我们认为可以达到的目的的一个条件,那么我们就可以解释为什么我们不能决定游到一个岛屿,同时又决定游到另一个岛屿。因为这就要求我同时游到A岛和b岛是可能的而这正是我们所知道的不可能的。在否认设定目标和可达性之间的联系时,布鲁尔剥夺了自己解释这种不相容所需的资源。正是这些结构性约束激发了设定目标和实现目标之间的联系。布鲁尔提出了进一步的反对意见。他认为,在某些情况下,设定目标涉及到实现目标——他的“简短、简单的项目”——这些情况下,设定目标并不涉及对认知代理的承诺。也许我给自己设定的任务是找出在我面前的是哪只动物;我睁开眼睛,就像奥斯汀说的,问题解决了。根据Brewer的说法,这个项目不涉及认知代理。因此,即使我是对的,设定评估我的观点的终点需要对我将要做的事情采取立场,这也不需要承诺我是我的思想的代理人。信仰的论点仍然陷入困境。布鲁尔的反对提出了一系列关于决策本质的问题。我们通常会区分两种方式,一种是基于预测,另一种是基于承诺考虑到我对那些居高临下的唱片店工作人员感到紧张,我可以预测,明天浏览新发行的唱片时,我会脸红。在做这个预测时,我并没有承诺脸红是我的代理的一个例子。因此,问题不在于是否有办法让我们在不把自己视为行为人的情况下表明自己的立场——这点毫无疑问——而是在我们的同意是基于我们追求某种目的的决定的情况下,这是否可能。我认为这里存在认知代理的原因在于决策和代理之间更普遍的联系。当我决定做某件事时,我把它看作是对我实际推理的约束,是一个我必须围绕着它航行的固定点。但如果我改变主意,我可以放弃这种约束。在这一点上,它不同于我周围世界所固定的约束。(这就是为什么我们不应该认为我同意我将要做的事情是基于证据的部分原因:见附言,第125 - 128页。)我们把我的决定所产生的约束与世界上事物如何存在所产生的约束区别对待,正是在这种区别对待中,我们表现出对自己作为行动者的理解。我的承诺是,我将做我想做的事,这是基于我在这件事上所扮演的角色。布鲁尔认为这还不包括对我自己能动性的承诺因为在感性的情况下,我的行为完全取决于世界上事物的情况。如果我睁开眼睛,我会看到一头猪。这不是我任何行为的结果。正如我们上面所讨论的,Brewer认为感知和思考在这方面是同等重要的。但是,在世界和我的判断之间的关系中,找不到对我自己能动性的承诺。 在我的认识中可以发现,我所决定的目的对我自己控制的实践推理施加了约束。如果我们要解释支配决策的结构特征,我们就需要在设定目标和实现目标之间建立联系。我们需要在设定目标和接受我们的能动性之间建立联系如果我们要解释我们与我们自己的决定的关系与我们与世界强加的约束的关系是如何不同的。最后,我转向布鲁尔关于信仰与他人关系的评论。布鲁尔重新构建了《实践自我》的论点,认为自我意识需要认知能动性,认知能动性必须基于信仰,而信仰需要与他人交往。他反对说,这个论点是无效的,因为相信自己是我思想的代理人,并不需要与他人接触。这与我之前所说的一致,即对认知代理的信念是在没有任何相互作用的情况下维持的。我同意——事实上,我在《实践的自我》中也强调过,这种论证不符合笛卡尔、康德、费希特和黑格尔所追求的那种必然性(尤其参见《PS》,第159 - 164页)。出于这个原因,我从来没有接受布鲁尔对我的论点进行重构的最后一个前提。他的主张只是说,我们对自己作为智力主体的信念,是由一种将我们与他人联系起来的实践来维持的——并不是说必须如此。布鲁尔给出了一些对这一回应不满意的理由。他指出,我反对之前的论点,这些论点从自我意识转向客观,部分原因是它们未能建立必要的联系。但是,如果我可以通过放弃对必要联系的承诺来避免反例,为什么我批评的目标不被允许这样做呢?这里有两种可能的抱怨。首先,我所批评的论点对建立必要的联系不感兴趣,在这种程度上,第2章中提出的反对意见没有说服力。我不确定布鲁尔是否有意提出这一投诉,但这将是一个有趣的案例。斯图尔特·汉普郡的《思想与行动》与《个人》同一年出版,在第一章中提出了一个项目,这个项目看起来在精神上和细节上都与我们现在所认为的斯特劳森形而上学相一致(参见,例如,汉普郡1959年,第1 - 21页)。但是,汉普郡试图揭示的“思想和知识的必要前提”(第14页)并不被认为是“唯一可能的[原则]”:“这将是康德的错误,他相信我们可以预见并为新的知识形式设定最终的限制”(第13页,见第20页)。如果在《实践自我》第二章所评价的论证中,也存在着同样的必要条件的概念,那么,在那里所作的批判就显得迟钝了。让我们把斯特劳森从自我意识到客观性的论证作为一个测试案例(见PS,第35 - 48页)。我赞同这样一种观点,即斯特劳森对他的项目的理解并不完全符合当代的分类法但斯特劳森在《个体》的导言中坚持认为,他的主题是“人类思维的巨大核心,它没有历史——或者没有思想史上的记录……范畴和概念,就其最基本的特征而言,根本不会改变”(斯特劳森1959,第10页)。这似乎与思想的必要前提的概念不相容,因为思想的必要前提允许不同时间和文化的变化。斯特劳森比汉普郡宽松的历史决定论所允许的康德主义要多得多。因此,如果声称斯特劳森和在第2章中考虑的其他人不关心建立必要的联系,那么像这样的段落需要被解释掉。需要提出一个理由。另一种抱怨是,在第2章中考虑的论点可能会以类似于第5章讨论的方式被削弱,并且那些重构的论点会比考虑的实际论点更能反对《实践自我》中提出的反对意见。这里的想法并不是不同的标准被应用于chs。但同样的标准可以适用于不同的论证。我同意,考虑是否存在可避免所提出的问题的备选论点将是富有成效的。但是,削弱这些论点是否会使它们更有道理,这一点并不明显:一些所谓的必要条件,对有自我意识的生物的生活来说,甚至看起来并不重要在任何情况下,这些都不是给出的论点。我怀疑这里的部分问题是布鲁尔想把《实践自我》的论证,强加到斯特劳森先验论证的模式中,强调的只是适当的必要性。 但我们可以欣赏这些论点的雄心壮志,同时回避它们的担忧。18 .康德本人允许以各种方式将历史运用于适当的先验项目中——包括形象、符号、实践和仪式汉普郡在“我们社会生活的形式……社会世界中约定俗成的手势、表情和合作习惯”支持必需品的方式上引人注目(汉普郡1959,第20页)。《实践自我》的论点是,我们相信自己是智力能动者,这种信念是通过将我们与他人联系起来的实践来维持的。这是不必要的,不必担心。我们必须相信自己是我们思想的代理人。lsama Salje在《实践自我》一书中对这一观点给出了精确而敏锐的解释。她提出了一系列的担忧关于康德在《实践自我》中对实践同意的描述是否能证明我们必须在实践基础上接受的那些主张有积极的认知基础。什么时候我们有实际的理由接受索赔?在《实践的自我》第4章中,我认为,当一种主张在理论上是不可判定的,而在实践中又是必需的时,我们有实际的理由去接受它。当我们缺乏理论依据来接受或否认一项主张时,它在理论上是不可判定的。当同意一项主张是追求我们必须设定的目标的理性要求时,一项主张实际上是必要的。既然我们不能追求目标而不认为目标是可以达到的——与上文的布鲁尔相反——那么,如果我们被要求设定某个目标,我们就有理由接受任何作为实现目标的条件的要求。这种对实践同意的解释,为我们是自己思想的代理人这一观点提供了实践依据。因为我认为,有自我意识的主体必须以解决有关他们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题为目的,而同意我们是自己思维的主体这一主张是追求这一目的的一个条件。因此,我们有实际的理由接受我们是我们思想的代理人。Salje怀疑这种说法是否能解释为什么我们在实践中必须接受的那些主张在认知上是合适的。如果我们想要理解我们作为活跃的、好奇的生物,生活在他人的世界里的地位,也许我们需要接受一些主张。她说,这是进一步表明,我们在认识论上有权持有这些主张。这是她批评的对象。她从实践的角度出发,把重点放在了论证的第一部分:我们需要解决关于我们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题。在这里,她获得了实际同意的积极认知地位。她提出了两大批评。首先,它没有提供具有积极认知状态的实践同意——实践同意追溯至一个要求的目的这一事实本身并不表明实践同意不是一种一厢情愿的想法。第二,它无论如何都是错误的:我们不需要为自己设定评估我们对世界的看法的终点。我依次拿这些。从实际的同意和必要的结束开始。Salje注意到,如果我们为自己设定了一些特殊的目标,我们就没有资格同意任何要求,这是我们实现这个目标的条件。那么,她问道,为什么强制结束要以某种方式改变现状呢?也许我们必须认为自己比别人更善良、更聪明、更有能力,这样才能在世界上找到自己的路这并不意味着拥有膨胀的自我概念在认识论上是值得尊敬的。事实上,Salje认为,如果我们不得不接受某些声称,似乎正是因为这个原因,缺乏认识论的凭据,这可能会使它变得不那么如此。不这样想就是假设我们的处境不会是悲剧。即使我们不能追求目标而不认为它们是可实现的,为什么目的的必然性要保证其可实现性的认识论立场?为了解决这一指控,我们需要弄清楚为什么基于偶然目的的同意缺乏认识论的凭据。Salje认为,这是因为如果不这样做,实际的同意就会普遍存在:只要我们觉得合适,我们就可以引导认知权利。她举了一个例子,同意“我是学习语言的能手”的说法,作为在三个月内完成日语学习的条件。但实际的同意受到理论基础的限制,至少在我自己的情况下,正如牛津大学语言中心的导师可以可悲地证明的那样,有大量的理论证据表明我没有任何学习语言的能力。 因此,并不仅仅是过剩不利于基于偶然目的的同意。不,基于偶然目的的同意的问题在于它的基础:实际同意不能建立在特殊欲望的基础上。因此,将实际的同意与一厢情愿的指责隔离起来的并不是从偶然到必然的转变,而是从基于欲望的同意转变为基于义务的同意。正因为我们处于一个真正的要求之下,我们才有理由接受任何要求,只要我们的同意是我们做被要求做的事情的条件。因此,为了回答Salje的指控,我们需要解释为什么基于需求的同意而不是基于个人欲望的同意应该赋予积极的认识论地位。如果一个人认为需求仅仅是工具性的,是由个人的欲望决定的,那么提供这样一个账户的前景似乎很渺茫。因为到那时,普遍共有的愿望就会成为普遍要求的基础。似乎没有什么理由去区分那些特殊的欲望和那些必然的,共有的欲望。也许我们都有共同的欲望——人类生活的普通情感;对幸福的焦虑,对未来痛苦的恐惧,对死亡的恐惧,对复仇的渴望,对食物和其他必需品的欲望,正如休谟在《宗教自然史》(2.5)中所说的那样。如果这些共同的欲望构成了一种普遍的要求,那么根据《实践自我》中对实践同意的描述我们就有了实践的依据来接受任何作为实现这一目的的条件的要求。由此产生的同意——正如休谟可能想让我们认识到的那样——似乎与一厢情愿的想法没有明显的不同。但是我们不需要以这种方式认为必要的要求是建立在欲望基础上的。另一种选择是把它们定位在我们作为自我意识存在的本性中(PS,第124 - 125页)。因为如果我们是理性的动物是我们本性的一部分,那么评估我们的观点的要求就会从我们的理性能力中流出。对于同情康德的人来说,这将是因为它追溯到理性本身给出的绝对命令(CPrR 5: 143, cf. PS, p.124)。对于那些更倾向于亚里士多德自然主义的人来说,这将是因为它是由美好人类生活的标准所保证的:“灵魂的活动与理性相一致”(NE 1098a)。无论哪种情况,它的基础都不是某种共同的创造状态,而是理性本身。不接受那些我们有实际根据的主张,就表现出一种理性的不连贯。正是这种理性基础区分了实践同意与一厢情愿的想法,并解释了其积极的认知地位。Salje可能会回应说,这只表明实践同意是一种理性的态度,而不是它具有积极的认知地位。在文章的最后,她概述了一种将两者分离的方法。但我担心,只有在人们坚持为根据证据确定的事物保留认知地位的情况下,这种脱钩才有吸引力。康德为我们提供了一种关于同意的解释,它向我们展示了另一种良好地位的来源——当它以理性为基础时,当它以我们的本性为基础时,当它以某种普遍的东西为基础时。评估一个人对世界的看法的要求来自于我们作为自我意识的、理性的动物的地位。有些人以评估自己对世界的看法为目的,却拒绝承认自己是自己思维的主体,这表现出一种理性的不连贯。因此,实践同意的积极认识论地位并不在于它与证据的联系,而在于它是合理的、普遍的、自然的和安全的。Salje的第二条批评线针对的是这样一种说法,即我们需要把自己设定为评估我们对世界的看法的终点。她提出了两个问题:第一,我们是否为评估自己对世界的看法设定了终点;第二,我们是否被要求这样做。这两个问题在笛卡尔的《实践自我》框架下都很有说服力。因为笛卡尔把他的计划描述为一项巨大的事业,可以理解地推迟,一生中只需要执行一次(马太福音7:17)。因此,波西米亚的伊丽莎白公主抱怨“我被迫过的生活没有足够的时间让我按照你的规则养成冥想的习惯”(哥林多后书3:684)是合理的。为什么认为哲学背景之外的人会从事这样的研究活动呢?为什么认为有人必须这样做呢?Salje通过对过度理智化的担忧来强调第一个问题。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Practical Self: Replies

Lichtenberg's enigmatic remarks on the cogito form the backbone to The Practical Self. Rory Madden raises a set of rich questions about their proper interpretation and the argumentative work to which they are put.

Lichtenberg writes that to say cogito is already too much as soon as one translates it as I am thinking. Madden contrasts two readings of this line. The traditional reading takes Lichtenberg to be raising a challenge to the claim that I am the subject of my episodes of thinking on which those episodes depend. The revisionary reading—and the one offered in The Practical Self—takes Lichtenberg to be raising a challenge to the claim that I am the sometime agent of my thinking. The final sentence of the passage, on this reading, responds to the challenge by suggesting that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking. To assume the I, to postulate it, is a practical requirement.

Madden worries about the translation of this final line and, with it, the claim that it offers practical grounds for assuming the I. Lichtenberg writes: Das Ich anzunehmen, zu postulieren, ist praktisches Bedürfnis. Günter Zöller translates the final word as ‘requirement’ (1992, p.418); Stephen Tester as ‘necessity’ (2012, p.152). Madden suggests that ‘need’ is a closer translation and that this deflates the suggestion that Lichtenberg is adverting to practical grounds. A practical need is not a necessary condition on some state of affairs but a pressing or basic impulse, like the need to stretch one's legs.

My account of the practical grounds available for our sense of ourselves as intellectual agents is modelled on Kant's account of the practical postulates. These are claims which Kant says must be assumed (CPrR 5:121, 126) or postulated (5:122, 125) in virtue of their connection to the demands of practical reason. In particular, they must be assumed or postulated in virtue of a connection to what Kant calls ‘a need [Bedürfnis] of pure practical reason’ (5:142). A need of pure practical reason—a practical need—contrasts with a need of inclination. It is a need based on duty. We might say, then, that to assume these claims about God, freedom, and immortality, to postulate them, is, for Kant, a practical need based on duty—a practical requirement. This is the context in which to understand Lichtenberg's final sentence. Madden's deflationary suggestion severs these connections.

What about the target of those sentences? Madden notes the difficulty of interpreting an aphoristic writer such as Lichtenberg. In The Practical Self I made the case for the revisionary reading by appeal to other passages in his writings—including, crucially, a passage in the notebooks where Lichtenberg returns to the contrast between ‘I am thinking’ or ‘it is thinking’.1 Madden is right that these are not determinative—even if the later passages show a concern with intellectual agency, it might be that Lichtenberg had not distinguished the two issues when writing the passage at K76 or that both concerns were at issue. He is right too that Lichtenberg's use of the first person in the opening sentences does not tell against the traditional reading.2 But the context of Lichtenberg's wider writings and its Kantian background should open us to the possibility that worries about subjectless episodes of thinking—important as they have been to the development of our philosophical tradition—were read into Lichtenberg given the local concerns of early analytic philosophy.3

These questions of interpretation are not Madden's main concern. On the issues of content, he argues that the problem of agency has less going for it than I suggest in The Practical Self—that we have perfectly good theoretical grounds for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking. And that the problem of a thinking subject has more going for it than I allow—that some answer to the traditional problem must be given if the argument to objectivity is to go through. It is in this context that he draws attention to some subtleties in Frege's discussion of self-consciousness which I missed in The Practical Self.

Start with the first. Madden suggests we can know that we are the agents of our thinking through the unproblematic use of causal explanatory reasoning. My knowledge that there are four people living in the house opposite may be based on the best causal explanation of the number of cars parked outside, the state of the recycling bin, and so on. Similarly, my knowledge that I am the agent of my thinking may be based on the best causal explanation of the overall pattern of my thinking. Such reasoning provides theoretical grounds of the sort which I claim are unavailable (PS, pp.88–97).

Causal explanatory reasoning involves taking up an observational stance towards the object of one's explanation. Madden notes that I am sceptical that such a stance can properly capture the relation we stand in to our prospective actions. When we reason about what we will do, we treat the constraints imposed by our decisions as revisable in a way which allows us to retract the decisions without thereby counteracting the available evidence. And that requires us to take a stance towards our decisions which contrasts fundamentally with the stance we take towards the constraints imposed by the environment (PS, pp.125–128; cf. Soteriou 2013, p.287 f.). Madden does not here dispute these considerations. But he suggests that they do not apply to the retrospective use of causal explanatory reasoning. We can look back over episodes of thinking and reason to their best causal explanation. This gives us a growing body of evidence that we are the agents of our thinking.

This is a helpful reminder of the variety of ways in which experience can provide theoretical grounds for assent. But Madden's use of retrospective causal explanatory reasoning looks primarily geared towards establishing the habitual claim that I agentially think rather than the progressive claim at issue for Descartes. Just as I might look at the discarded books around the house and reason to the thought that I struggle with contemporary fiction, so too can I look back on some episode of thinking and reason to my status as a cognitive agent. Either Madden thinks knowledge of the progressive can be grounded in knowledge of the habitual—an approach which requires rejecting the considerations about decision-making sketched above—or he thinks that knowledge of the habitual suffices to answer Lichtenberg's challenge. Neither is straightforward.

Still, even if causal explanatory reasoning doesn't allow knowledge that we are agentially thinking in the sense at stake for Descartes, did I need to deny such knowledge in The Practical Self? Madden worries that my denial of knowledge—my denial of theoretical grounds for assent—sits uncomfortably with various claims I make in the positive argument for faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. These are claims about the existence and importance of deliberation, its status as a cognitive activity, and its relation to reactive attitudes and practices (see, e.g. PS, pp.120–125, pp.147–152). Do I present myself as knowing these claims in a way which contradicts the denial of knowledge presented earlier in the book?

The denial of knowledge in ch.3 of The Practical Self is more precisely a denial of theoretical grounds for assent, understood as grounds which bear on the truth of the claim. The distinction between theoretical and practical grounds is supposed to show that we can have reason for assenting to claims even when they cannot be established on theoretical grounds. In The Practical Self I claim that our status as cognitive agents is one such claim. That is to say, our recognition of ourselves as cognitive agents—as creatures who deliberate, puzzle, and decide—is available only from the practical point of view. Madden is right that I take myself to have grounds to assert that claims about deliberation which feature in the positive argument of The Practical Self. That is compatible with my taking them to lack theoretical grounds.

This may be a point where the term ‘knowledge’ occludes the issues. A denial of knowledge can sound like an invitation to scepticism. But would we call Kant a sceptic about morality because he denied it could be established on theoretical grounds? Kant is sometimes willing to use the terms practical cognition or knowledge for our recognition that we are subject to the moral law (see e.g. CPrR 5:4–5; 43). And that is compatible with his taking it to lack theoretical grounds. The kind of cognitive activity which is at stake in The Practical Self is accessible only from the practical point of view. The same is true of some of the arguments which establish its conclusion.

Would it be a problem to allow that we have theoretical grounds for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking? Madden points out that little, if any, of the argument for practical assent developed in chs. 4 and 5 turns on the theoretical undecidability of our status as cognitive agents. Why not allow that we have both theoretical and practical grounds to recognise ourselves as such? The requirement for theoretical undecidability is motivated in The Practical Self by appeal to Kant's account of the practical grounds available for assenting to God's existence. But all I say in support of the requirement is that it is needed to avoid a conflict within reason. For otherwise there could be practical reason to assent to a claim which was opposed by theoretical evidence (PS, p.113). And Madden could reasonably point out that the proscription of conflict excludes only cases where theoretical and practical reason point in opposite directions. There is no conflict if both concur.

This is a good and important point. In fact, it is not even clear that Kant's own discussion motivates anything beyond the avoidance of contradiction. In his discussion of conflicts within reason, he writes: “That which is required for the possibility of any use of reason as such, namely, that its principles and affirmations must not contradict one another, constitutes no part of its interest but is instead the condition of having reason at all’ (CPrR 5:120, my emphasis). This does not obviously rule out theoretical and practical reason supporting the same claim. Kant does characterise a postulate of pure practical reason as ‘a theoretical proposition, though one not demonstrable as such’ (CPrR 5:122, my emphasis). But this characterisation may apply solely to the cases of God, immortality, and freedom, rather than any claim which can be asserted on practical grounds. Madden is right that I ought to have said more to motivate a connection between practical grounds and theoretical undecidability—but it may be that moving in the direction he suggests does not involve deviation from Kant.4

Let us turn to the problem traditionally associated with Lichtenberg—the problem of introducing a subject of my episodes of thinking on which those episodes depend. Madden thinks we should take this problem seriously. On his reading of Lichtenberg's remarks, they pose a problem for those who want to explain our ability to form a generalised conception of a subject of experience on the basis of experiences which do not themselves present a subject. Filtered through Wittgenstein and early twentieth-century empiricists, this raises a conceptual problem of other minds: if we start with subjectless episodes of thinking, the result is a solipsistic refusal or inability to countenance other subjects of experience.5

The conceptual problem other minds is an important part of early analytic philosophy's engagement with Lichtenberg and through Wittgenstein's writings it influenced notable moments in twentieth-century philosophy.6 Madden thinks it matters for the project of The Practical Self. For if we cannot form the conception of a subject of thinking independent of its episodes of thinking, we cannot form the conception of other thinking beings. And my account of the interpersonal practices which sustain our faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking puts at its centre practices which involve thinking of other subjects as thinkers capable of holding and being held to account (see especially PS, pp.158–159). So if we cannot make sense of a generalisable subject of thinking, there can be no such practices, and the proffered connection to an objective world is severed.

This is the context in which Madden draws attention to an aspect of Frege's discussion in ‘The Thought’ which I passed over in The Practical Self. Frege's concern in that paper is to provide a counterexample to the claim that the only thing I can think about are my own ideas. The counterexample is thought about myself. For I am the bearer of my ideas and no bearer of an idea can itself be an idea. So, in thinking about myself, I am thinking about something which is not an idea. In The Practical Self I complained that this ignores the way in which we are presented to ourselves in episodes of thinking: it is compatible with Frege's argument that my status as the bearer of my ideas does not show up in the character of self-consciousness thought and experience.

This is what Madden denies, and he thinks that it allows Frege a response to the conceptual problem of other minds. For he thinks that Frege's discussion contains the germ of an idea later developed in more detail by both Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore: that there is a relational structure to experience which is manifest in the character of experience. That relational structure has an implied relatum which is the subject of experience. So in undergoing a sense experience, I am aware of a relational structure in which I, as subject of experience, feature as one of the essential constituents.

I think Madden is right that the conceptual problem must be taken seriously, whether or not it is ultimately to be found in Lichtenberg. And the claims about the structure of experience which he finds in Frege are a promising line of response.7 But what are the constraints on responding to the conceptual problem? In particular, which resources are we allowed to use in explaining our capacity to think about others as potential subjects of experience?

Madden offers the Fregean solution as one which meets the constraints imposed by the isolationist starting point of the Cartesian project. But he notes that we need not accept such an etiolated origin. And he quotes Bernard Williams in support of the thought that the starting point of the Cartesian project may itself preclude a solution to the conceptual problem of other minds: ‘If we have no help from anything except the pure point of view of consciousness, the only coherent way of conceiving a thought happening is to conceive of thinking it. So, sticking solely to the point of view of consciousness, we are forced back to a position in which there is, in effect, only one such point of view…’ (Williams 1978, p.84). Madden offers his reading of Frege as assistance from within the pure view of consciousness. But he gently suggests, with Williams, that Lichtenberg may ‘share with Descartes his deepest error’ (1978, p.79).

Williams's wonderful discussion of Lichtenberg in chapter 3 of Descartes: A Project of Pure Enquiry needs to be situated in the context of its reprise in chapter 10. There Williams says that his argument against Descartes's isolationist starting point is ‘in effect only a development of Kant's in the Paralogisms of Pure Reason’ (1978, p.292). Williams takes Descartes's starting point to be episodes of conscious experience intelligible independently of their connection to the wider life of a thinking thing. And Kant's thought in the Paralogisms, at least as presented and defended by Strawson in The Bounds of Sense, is that such a self-contained conception of consciousness does not contain within it the material to make intelligible the idea of a persisting subject.8 If Williams is right to see his argument prefigured in Kant, my co-option of Descartes and Kant into a common project is mere whimsy.

But the isolation which begins the Meditations need not be understood as committing to a conception of consciousness which is intelligible independently of its connections to the wider life of a thinking being. To assume otherwise is to assume that the first-person mode of reflection at play in the Meditations itself already commits to the conception of consciousness which Williams, Kant, and Strawson rightly find objectionable. An alternative is to understand Descartes's entertainment of the problematic conception of consciousness as resulting from the argumentative pressure developed over the course of the First Meditation. And any seeming endorsement of that conception must be complicated by the fact that, by the Third Meditation, Descartes will insist that we cannot properly understand our form of consciousness as having its character independent of something external to us—not the wider life of a thinking being, admittedly, but an infinite substance who has left in me ‘the mark of the craftsman stamped on his work’ (Med. 7: 51). The first-personal character of the Meditations is not yet a commitment to use only the meagre resources provided by the pure view of consciousness.9

Madden contrasts the isolationist starting point with one on which our notion of a subject of experience is grounded in an objective, third-personal conception of a psychological event which is, by its nature, the undergoing of a complex unit such as a human being or other animal. And in other work, he has shown the powerful reasons for taking us to be animals of a certain sort.10 But one can accept these insights whilst insisting that this notion of a subject of experience cannot be understood independently of a first-personal conception of a psychological event which is, by its nature, the experience of a conscious subject. Kant, Strawson, and Williams are right that we cannot build up a conception of a subject of experience from a starting point of consciousness stripped of any connection to something external. But this need not be part of the Cartesian project. The dispute in The Practical Self is not about whether we can get to objectivity from a starting point which is intelligible independently of its connections to the external but whether those connections are established on theoretical or practical grounds.

The Practical Self claims that we are required to have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking and that this faith is sustained by a set of practices which relate us to a world of others. Bill Brewer's comments target each of these claims. His questions can be grouped under three broad headings: the nature of cognitive agency, the argument for the claim that we must have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking, and the connection between faith and others. I'll say something about each of these in turn.

Start with cognitive agency. I claim in The Practical Self that there is a form of self-consciousness which involves an understanding of ourselves as the agents of our thinking. How should we understand the notion of agency involved in this characterisation? Kant contrasts the spontaneity of thinking with the passivity of sensory awareness. Brewer is sceptical that this marks a genuine contrast. We sometimes embark on perceptual projects—scanning the room to catch sight of one's child—and the end results are perceptual achievements: seeing her, half-hidden by the sofa. So too do we sometimes embark on intellectual projects—calculating the number of primes between 0 and 100, say. And the end results of these inquiries are intellectual achievements: the judgement that there are 25 primes. In both cases, the investigation is settled by how things are. To borrow a line from David Wiggins, there is nothing else to think.11

Given this structural analogy, why think that there is some distinctive kind of agency involved in thinking as opposed to perceiving? In both cases, we initiate a project. And in both cases, the end result is a state which is determined by the facts rather than our preferences about them. Indeed, Brewer thinks that we need this symmetry if we are to accept realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry. For he takes realism to be tantamount to the thought that the answers to one's questions are fixed by facts which are independent of one's knowledge of them. So if we are realists about the domains of perceptual and intellectual inquiry, not only should we treat symmetrically the achievements which settle perceptual and intellectual inquiry, we should further take those achievements to be passive responses to a world which is there anyway.

Brewer's forceful comparison between perceptual and intellectual inquiry presupposes that the achievements which end inquiry are independent of the wider activities which encompass them. This seems appropriate in the case of perceptual inquiry, since one can come to be in the perceptual states which end inquiry simply by opening one's eyes. Walking through the woods, I come across a pig—‘I can now just see that it is [a pig]’, says J.L. Austin, ‘the question is settled’ (1962, p.115). The passive voice is important here: perception can settle questions without one intending to settle them. And if the achievements which end intellectual inquiry are similarly independent of the wider activities which encompass them, then we seem compelled to treat judgement as equally passive to its objects. At the least, it makes it hard to see why we should treat thinking as distinctively active or spontaneous in a way that perception is not.

But this independence is not compulsory. Ryle denies it in a series of late papers on the nature of thinking. ‘It is not incidental to thoughts that they belong to trains of thought’, he writes; they are ‘constitutionally inceptive’ (Ryle 1958, p.416, cited at PS, p.120). Ryle's claim is that the judgements which end extended episodes of cognitive activity are not separable from the trains of thought which they conclude. The judgement that there are 25 primes is individuated in part by the activity of counting the primes between 1 and 100 in which it features.

To identify this assumption is not yet to give reason to reject it. But its denial opens a way of explaining the activity of thinking which does not carry over to the case of perception. It is because the judgements which conclude intellectual inquiry depend on the extended cognitive processes which contain them that we treat these judgements as active. And it is because the perceptual states which conclude perceptual inquiry do not depend on the extended cognitive processes which contain them that we treat them as passive. The active nature of judgement is to be explained in terms of the structural features of the extended cognitive process in which it occurs.12

How does this relate to the realism which underlies Brewer's objection? Realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry can seem relevant if, given the assumption of independence, there is no difference in the relations which the end points of inquiry stand to the processes which precede them. For then it seems the only place to mark a difference between the activity of thinking and the passivity of perception is in terms of how each relates to its objects. And, as Brewer makes clear, realism about the domain of intellectual inquiry poses a constraint on making this good: the fact that we are answerable to how things are in both thought and perception enforces an understanding of both thinking and perception as passive. But once we drop the assumption of independence, we can explain the sense in which judgement is active not in terms of its relation to its objects but in terms of its relation to the processes in which it occurs.

I turn now to Brewer's comments on the argument that we must have faith in ourselves as the agent of our thinking.13 I claim that self-conscious subjects are required to settle questions about the propriety of their perspective on the world, that setting this as my end requires taking a stand on whether I will settle these questions, and that this requires assent to the claim that I am the agent of my thinking. The result is practical ground for accepting that we are the agents of our thinking, as per Lichtenberg's suggestive final line.

Brewer notes that this argument assumes that it is a condition on pursuing an end that one takes it to be attainable (see PS, pp.115–117). And he objects this is obviously too strong: crash-landing into the sea in an aeroplane, I may set out to swim to a distant island despite knowing the goal to be unattainable. If there is no connection between pursuing an end and taking it to be attainable, then the argument which purports to provide practical grounds does not go through.

What should we say about Brewer's counterexample? Well, if one's views on the attainability of an end bear no relation to whether once can decide to pursue it, why does Brewer's swimmer commit only to the project of swimming to safety? Such lack of ambition! Why not commit to the project of flying to safety or of turning into a fish and swimming the distance? The natural thought is that our knowledge that these goals are unattainable precludes us from setting them as ends. The end of swimming to a distant island, no matter how remote, is not like that.

One complicating factor here is the distinction Kant draws between ends which are willed and those which are merely wished (PS, p.116). We do not always mark this division when discussing our projects. But the claim about attainability applies only to ends that we have properly decided upon. And we must be careful to ensure that our judgements about its plausibility are not swayed by the commonplace that one can wish for ends whose attainment is outside our control. For this reason, the attainability constraint is better motivated not by appeal to cases but by reflection on structural constraints governing the setting of ends.

Consider incompatible ends. Say there are two islands in opposite directions and that I know I cannot swim to both. If it is a condition on pursuing an end that we take it to be attainable, then we have an explanation for why we cannot decide to swim to one island and, at the same time, decide to swim to the other. For that would require taking it to be attainable that I both swim to island A and swim to island B. And that is exactly what we know to be impossible. In denying the connection between setting ends and attainability, Brewer deprives himself of the resources needed to explain this incompatibility. It is these structural constraints which motivate a connection between setting an end and taking it to be attainable.14

Brewer pushes a further objection. He argues that to the extent that there are cases where setting an end involves taking that end to be attainable—his ‘brief, simple projects’—these are precisely cases in which setting an end involves no commitment to cognitive agency. Perhaps I set myself the task of finding out which animal is in front of me; I open my eyes and, as Austin puts it, the question is settled. According to Brewer, no cognitive agency is involved in this project. Thus, even if I am right that setting the end of evaluating my perspective requires taking a stand on what I will do, this need involve no commitment to the claim that I am the agent of my thinking. The argument for faith remains in trouble.

Brewer's objection here raises a set of questions about the nature of decision-making. We normally draw a distinction between two ways in which we can take a stand on what we will do in the future—one based in prediction and one based in commitment.15 Given my nervousness around condescending record-shop staff, I might predict that I will blush when browsing the new releases tomorrow. In making this prediction, I make no commitment to blushing being an instance of my agency. So the issue is not whether there are ways in which we can take a stand on what we will do without thinking of ourselves as agents—that much is without question—but whether this is possible in cases where our assent is based on our decision to pursue some end.

My reasons for thinking that there is a commitment to cognitive agency here turn on the connections between decision-making and agency more generally. When I decide to do something, I treat it as a constraint on my practical reasoning, a fixed point around which I must navigate. But it is a constraint that I can foreswear should I change my mind. In this it differs from constraints fixed by the world around me. (This is part of the reason for why we should not think of my assent to what I will do as based on evidence: see PS, pp.125–128.) We treat the constraints engendered by my decisions as different from the constraints engendered by how things are in the world—and it is in this differential treatment that we manifest an understanding of ourselves as agents. My commitment to it being true that I will do what I have willed is grounded in the role I play in making this the case.

Brewer thinks that this does not yet involve a commitment to my own agency because there are perceptual cases where what I will do is determined solely by how things are in the world. If I open my eyes, I will see a pig. That is not a result of any activity on my part. And, as we discussed above, Brewer thinks that perceiving and thinking are on a par in this respect. But the commitment to my own agency is not to be found in the relation between the world and my judgement. It is to be found in my recognition that the ends which I decide upon enforce constraints on practical reasoning which are under my own control. We need a connection between setting an end and taking it to be attainable if we are to explain the structural features that govern decision-making. And we need a connection between setting an end and an acceptance of our agency if we are to explain how our relation to our own decisions differs from our relation to those constraints enforced by the world.

I turn finally to Brewer's comments on the relation between faith and others. Brewer reconstructs the argument of The Practical Self as holding that self-consciousness requires cognitive agency, that cognitive agency is necessarily based on faith, and that faith requires engagement with others. And he objects that this argument is invalid because it is not true that faith in myself as the agent of my thinking requires engagement with others. It is compatible with all that I have said that faith in cognitive agency is sustained without any interaction with another. I agree—and indeed, emphasised in The Practical Self that the argument offered falls short of the kind of necessity which Descartes, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel aimed to secure (see, especially, PS, pp.159–164). For that reason, I never took myself to accept the final premise in Brewer's reconstruction of my argument. The claim was only that our faith in ourselves as intellectual agents is sustained by a practice which relates us to others—not that it must be.

Brewer gives some reasons to be dissatisfied with this response. He notes that I object to previous arguments which move from self-consciousness to objectivity in part by showing their failure to establish a necessary connection. But if I am allowed to avoid counterexamples by abjuring a commitment to necessary connections, why are the targets of my criticism not allowed to do likewise?

There are two possible complaints here. The first is that the arguments I criticise were not interested in establishing necessary connections and, to that extent, that the objections offered in ch.2 have no purchase. I'm not sure if Brewer intends this complaint but it would be an interesting case to make. Stuart Hampshire's Thought and Action—published the same year as Individuals—sets out in its first chapter a project which looks continuous in spirit and often in detail with what we now think of as Strawsonian metaphysics (see, e.g., Hampshire 1959, pp.1–21). But the ‘necessary presuppositions of thought and knowledge’ (p.14) which Hampshire aims to uncover are not supposed to be the ‘only possible [principles]’: ‘this would be the error of Kant, the belief that we can anticipate and set final limits to new forms of knowledge’ (p.13, cf. p.20). If the same conception of necessary conditions is at work in the arguments under evaluation in ch.2 of The Practical Self, then the criticisms made there are blunted.

Let us take Strawson's argument from self-consciousness to objectivity as a test-case (discussed in PS, pp.35–48). I'm sympathetic to the thought that Strawson's understanding of his project does not fit neatly into contemporary taxonomies.16 But Strawson insists, in the introduction to Individuals, that his topic is that ‘massive central core of human thinking which has no history—or none recorded in histories of thought… categories and concepts which, in their most fundamental character, change not at all’ (Strawson 1959, p.10). This looks incompatible with a conception of the necessary presuppositions of thought which allows variation across time and culture. Strawson is much more Kantian than Hampshire's relaxed historicism allows. So if the claim is that Strawson and the others considered in ch.2 were not concerned with establishing necessary connections, passages such as this need to be explained away. A case needs to be made.

The alternative complaint is that the arguments considered in ch.2 could be weakened in ways analogous to the discussion in ch.5, and that those reconstructed arguments would fare better against the objections offered in The Practical Self than the actual arguments considered. Here the thought would be not that differential standards are being applied in chs. 2 and 5 but that the same standards could be applied to different arguments. I agree that it would be fruitful to consider whether there are alternative arguments in the vicinity which avoid the problems raised. But it is not obvious that weakening the arguments would make them more plausible: some of the purported necessary conditions do not even look central to the lives of self-conscious beings.17 And, in any case, those are not the arguments which were given.

I suspect that part of the issue here is that Brewer wants to force the argument of The Practical Self into the mould of a Strawsonian transcendental argument with its emphasis on only the properly necessary. But one can admire the ambition of these arguments while sidestepping their concerns. Kant himself allowed all kinds of ways in which the historical could be put to use in properly transcendental projects—with images, symbols, practice, and ritual.18 And Hampshire is compelling on the way in which necessities may be supported by ‘the forms of our social life… the social world of conventionalised gesture, expression and habits of co-operation’ (Hampshire 1959, p.20). The argument in The Practical Self is that our faith in ourselves as intellectual agents is sustained by a practice which relates us to others. That this is not necessary need not be cause for concern.

We must have faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. Léa Salje gives a precise and perceptive account of the argument for this claim in The Practical Self. And she raises a set of concerns about whether the Kant-inspired account of practical assent outlined in The Practical Self can show that there is a positive epistemic basis for those claims we are required to accept on practical grounds.

When do we have practical grounds to accept some claim? In ch.4 of The Practical Self I argue that we have practical grounds to accept a claim when it is both theoretically undecidable and practically required. A claim is theoretically undecidable when we lack theoretical grounds to accept or deny it. And a claim is practically required when assenting to the claim is a rational requirement on the pursuit of ends that we are required to set. Since we cannot pursue ends without taking them to be attainable—contra Brewer, above—it follows that if we are required to set some end, we are rationally required to accept any claim which is a condition on taking it to be attainable.

This account of practical assent underwrites the practical grounds for accepting that we are the agents of our thinking. For I suggest that self-conscious subjects are required to set the end of settling questions about the propriety of their perspective on the world and that assent to the claim that we are the agents of our thinking is a condition on the pursuit of that end. It follows that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking.

Salje is sceptical about whether this account can explain why it is epistemically appropriate to assent to those claims which we are required to accept on practical grounds. Perhaps there are claims which we which we need to accept if we are to make sense of our status as active, inquiring creatures, living in a world of others. It is a further step, she says, to show that we are epistemically entitled to hold those claims. This is the target of her critique. She focuses on the first part of the argument for practical grounds: that we are required to settle questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. This is where she takes the positive epistemic status of practical assent to reside. And she raises two broad criticisms. First, that it does not provide practical assent with a positive epistemic status—the fact that practical assent traces back to a required end does not, in itself, show that practical assent is anything other than a form of wishful thinking. Second, that it is in any case false: we are not required to set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world. I take these in turn.

Start with practical assent and necessary ends. Salje notes that if we set ourselves some idiosyncratic end, we are not thereby entitled to assent to any claim which is a condition on our taking that end to be attainable. So why, she asks, should making the end compulsory somehow change the picture? Perhaps we must think of ourselves as kinder, smarter, more capable than others, in order to find our way around the world.19 That doesn't make it epistemically respectable to have an inflated self-conception. Indeed, Salje suggests, it may make it less so—for if we cannot but accept some claim, it seems, for that very reason, to lack epistemic credentials. To think otherwise is to assume that our situation cannot be tragic. Even if we cannot pursue ends without taking them to be attainable, why should the necessity of the end secure epistemic standing for assent in its attainability?

To address this charge, we need to be clear on why assent based on contingent ends lacks epistemic credentials. Salje suggests that it is because practical assent would otherwise be pervasive: we could bootstrap epistemic entitlement whenever we find it congenial. She gives the example of assenting to the claim that I am a whizz at learning language as a condition on attaining the end of learning Japanese in three months. But practical assent is constrained by theoretical grounds and, at least in my own case and as the tutors at the Oxford University Language Centre can sadly attest, there is a wealth of theoretical evidence that tells against my having any facility with learning languages. So it is not overabundance alone which tells against assent based on contingent ends.

No, the problem with assent based on contingent ends is its foundation: practical assent cannot be grounded in idiosyncratic desire. It is thus not the shift from the contingent to the necessary which insulates practical assent from the charge of wishful thinking but the shift from assent grounded in desire to assent grounded in obligation. It is because we are under a genuine requirement that we have grounds to accept any claim whose assent is a condition on our doing what we are required to do. Thus in order to answer Salje's charge, we need an account of why assent grounded in requirement rather than assent grounded in individual desire should endow a positive epistemic status.

The prospects of providing such an account can seem thin if one thinks of requirements as solely instrumental, fixed by an individual's desires. For then universally shared desires would serve to ground universal requirements. And there seems little reason to differentiate between desires which are idiosyncratic and those which are, of necessity, shared. Perhaps there are desires common to us all—‘the ordinary affections of human life; the anxious concern for happiness, the dread of future misery, the terror of death, the thirst of revenge, the appetite for food and other necessaries’ as Hume has it in The Natural History of Religion (2.5). And if these shared desires underwrite a universal requirement, then it will follow from the account of practical assent sketched in The Practical Self that we have practical grounds to accept any claim which is a condition on setting that end. The resulting assent—as Hume perhaps intends us to recognise—does not seem markedly different from wishful thinking.

But we need not think of necessary requirements as grounded in desire in this way. An alternative is to locate them in our nature as self-conscious beings (PS, pp.124–125). For if it is part of our nature that we are rational animals, then the requirement to evaluate our perspective will flow from our rational faculties. For someone sympathetic to Kant, this will be because it traces back to a categorical imperative given by reason itself (CPrR 5: 143, cf. PS, p.124). For someone more inclined towards Aristotelian naturalism, it will be because it is underwritten by the standards of good human life: the ‘activity of soul in accordance with reason’ (NE 1098a). In either case, its foundation is not some shared conative state but reason itself. A failure to accept those claims for which we have practical grounds thus manifests a kind of rational incoherence. It is this foundation in reason which distinguishes practical assent from wishful thinking and explains its positive epistemic status.

Salje might respond that this shows only that practical assent is a rational attitude not that it has a positive epistemic status. And at the end of her essay, she sketches one way in which one might decouple the two. But I worry that such decoupling has attraction only to the extent one insists on reserving epistemic status for that which is determined on evidential grounds. Kant offers us an account of assent which showcases an alternative source of good standing—when grounded in reason, when grounded in our nature, when grounded in something universal (see especially CPrR 5:143n.). The requirement to evaluate one's perspective on the world is one which flows from our status as self-conscious, rational animals. And someone who sets themselves the end of evaluating their perspective on the world but refuses to accept that they are the agent of their thinking exhibits a form of rational incoherence. The positive epistemic standing of practical assent is thus not found in its connection to evidence but in its status as reasonable, universal, natural—and secure.

Salje's second line of criticism targets the claim that we are required to set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world. She raises two questions: first, whether we do set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective on the world, and second, whether we are required to do so. Both questions have force given the Cartesian framing of The Practical Self. For Descartes presents his project as an enormous undertaking, understandably postponed, and only needing to be performed once in a lifetime (Med. 7:17). Hence the legitimacy of Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia's complaint that ‘the life which I am constrained to lead does not leave enough time at my disposal to acquire a habit of meditation in accordance with your rules’ (Corr. 3:684). Why think that anyone outside of philosophical contexts actually engages in such recherché activity? Why think that anyone must do so?

Salje presses the first question through worries about over-intellectualisation. She distinguishes the beliefs and experiences which (partly) constitute our perspective on the world, the evaluative stances we take towards those beliefs and experiences, and the decision to engage in evaluative activity directed towards those beliefs and experiences. And the presentation of these phenomena as constituting three distinct levels of psychological attitude can make it seem as though there is an additional complexity at each stage: that there can be creatures who have a perspective without being able to step back and reflect on it, and that there can be creatures who can reflect on their perspective without deciding to engage in that activity.

In The Practical Self, I allow a gap between Salje's first and second levels: there are conscious creatures who have a perspective on the world but lack the ability to step back and evaluate that perspective. Does it follow that there can be a gap between Salje's second and third levels? As she notes, that will depend on how much is built into the setting of ends. The more that is required—expressly ridding my mind of all worries, arranging for myself a clear stretch of free time, for instance (Med. 7:17)—the less plausible it will be that anyone sets this end, the peculiarities of philosophical reflection excepted. And that can make it seem as if there is a gap to be bridged between Salje's second and third levels.

But there is something odd about the thought that one could reflect on one's perspective without ever deciding to do so. We do sometimes find our attention grabbed from without, as when a light flashes in the corner of our visual field. But to will an end as opposed to simply wishing it is to commit to taking some sort of action to bring it about. This is why the distinction has importance for both Kant and Aristotle: it captures a difference in the way desires relate to motivation which is relevant to ethical evaluation.20 We set ourselves the end of evaluating our perspective whenever we purposefully engage in reflection. The commitment involved in setting it as our end thus involves no more than choosing to bring it about. So to the extent that reflection is something undertaken, it is something we have chosen to do, and thus set as our end.

This doesn't mean that human beings actually set this end, for one might think that reflection itself is more limited or circumscribed than I suggest. But drawing out the connection between willing an end and acting so as to bring it about may ease some of the concerns about over-intellectualisation. Setting oneself the end of evaluating one's perspective need not involve a moment of high drama; it does not require that the end be set under that mode of presentation; it is not something which needs to be affirmed and reaffirmed each morning. Rather, to the extent that reflection is something in which we purposefully engage—that we choose to stand back and reflect on whether our perspective on the world is appropriate—then the gap between Salje's second and third levels is blurred.

These considerations concern only whether people actually set themselves the end of evaluating their perspectives. Are they required to do so? Salje forcefully pushes back against this suggestion by emphasising how neurotic, self-alienating and exhausting it would be to constantly reflect on one's perspective on the world. It is often hard enough to navigate the world. Now add continual reflection on one's perspective! As Susan Wolff puts it in a related attempt to take seriously the prospects for a life lived in accordance with some purported norm: these ‘are not ideals to which it is particularly reasonable or healthy or desirable for human beings to aspire’ (Wolff 1982, p.433).

Salje's criticism is a helpful reminder of the way reflection brings with it risks of neurosis and narcissism. This is a preoccupation for Iris Murdoch whose writings are continually attentive to the way reflection gives way to self-involved concern.21 A full response to the charge should not deny these dangers. It needs rather to show the value of the reflective life, the importance of self-understanding, and the way in which reflecting on our perspective enlarges not just the domain of self-knowledge but also its structure. That will require situating reflection within the broader life of a human being.22

Absent that wider story, I'll point to two threads which connect to some of Salje's wider concerns and suggest ways in which a requirement to reflect on one's perspective is integral to a flourishing human life. First, intellectual virtue. Salje expresses sympathy at the end of her comments for a virtue epistemological framework which emphasises the epistemic benefits of well-functioning intellectual traits. But the competences involved in these virtues plausibly involve the kind of monitoring and assessment enabled by reflection on one's perspective.23 So we would expect someone who cares about the intellectual virtues to be attentive to whether her perspective is appropriate and to take deliberate steps to ensure that it remain so. When situated in a story about the value of the intellectual virtues, the requirement to evaluate one's perspective can start to seem part of a well-ordered human life.

Second, community. The mindfulness proponent who only ever lives at Salje's first level can seem like an attractive prospect given her attunement to the world around her. But part of that world will include others who disagree with her take on things. That alone will put rational pressure on her to reflect on the propriety of her perspective. And once collective projects are in the offing, policies for recognising, monitoring, and resolving disagreement will need to be in place—the participants to the common endeavour will need to reflect on their own perspectives in a deliberate and controlled manner. Salje has persuasively argued elsewhere that conversation has a cognitive value in enabling the articulation of our thoughts and ensuring they are rationally answerable.24 Maximising that value will often require sensitivity to the compatibility of one's perspective with that of one's conversational partner—a sensitivity facilitated by reflection, again in ways which can help us see the requirement to evaluate one's perspective as part of a well-ordered life.

This last connection is not intended to justify the claim that there is a requirement to evaluate the propriety of our perspective, not least since it would raise concerns about circularity given the argument in ch.5 of The Practical Self. The aim is only to make plausible that there is such a requirement by showing how a life lived in its light need not be self-alienated, neurotic, and exhausted. It might instead be an intellectually virtuous life lived in communion with others: one aspect of a life lived well.

Kant's views on self-consciousness, practical reason, and religion are a touchstone for the arguments set out in The Practical Self. Carla Bagnoli argues that they depart from Kant in ways which are detrimental to its project. Kant is a better guide to the connections between agential thinking and a social world of other thinkers than I allow.

The Practical Self argues that self-conscious subjects must have faith in themselves as the agents of our thinking and that this faith is sustained by a set of practices which relate us to a world of others. Bagnoli thinks this an odd pairing. Her expansive comments centre on two main charges: that there is a much more direct connection to be found in Kant between our status as agential thinkers and a social world of other thinkers, and that, contrary to the suggestion in ch.5 of The Practical Self, a focus on practices and group-identities has the potential to undermine, rather than support, any connection to objectivity. The interleaving of faith and practice is both unnecessary and insufficient.

Start with the more direct connection between self-consciousness and objectivity. Bagnoli argues that there is a social dimension to practical assent which is independent of practice—or at least, independent of the practices which are the focus of ch.5 of The Practical Self. (I return to this distinction below.) This line of thought accepts that we have practical grounds to recognise ourselves as the agents of our thinking, contra Madden above. But it insists that no further step is needed to establish a connection to a world of other thinkers who are independent of me. There is a social dimension to practical assent which already connects self-conscious agents to a world of others.

How does sociality enter practical assent? Practical assent is introduced in The Practical Self as a mode of assent which is determined by practical grounds. And there are practical grounds to accept a claim when it is both theoretically undecidable and practically required. I use the term ‘faith’ to pick out this mode of assent—as Kant does at e.g. CPJ 5:471—but it is compatible with this that there are distinctions to be made within the class of practical assent. Bagnoli suggests one which is important for establishing a direct connection between self-consciousness and sociality: the distinction between faith and hope.

Hope has a central place in Kant's account of human reason. All interest of human reason, he tells us, is united in the questions: ‘What can I know? What should I do? What may I hope?’ (A805/B833). The last connects to faith, because it is answered by religion (JL 9:25). Some readers have accordingly treated hope and faith as equivalent.25 But Bagnoli thinks this is mistaken. She suggests that they are to be distinguished in terms of their intentional objects. Faith is directed at a world in which happiness and virtue are harmonised; hope at the realisation of an ethical community. This means that the object of hope already involves a social dimension: to hope is to recognise that the object of your practical assent is a collective project requiring the involvement of others.

Does this help with the establishment of a direct connection between self-consciousness and objectivity? If the content of hope already involves a social dimension, then it may seem as if we can sidestep the appeal to practice by establishing a link between self-consciousness and hope. For if self-conscious subjects are required to hope rather than have faith, we will already have shown that they are related, at least intentionally, to a community of others.

But this is no shortcut. Faith and hope, as attitudes, are distinguished solely in terms of their intentional objects. It is thus the content of practical assent which licences us in classifying an attitude as one of faith or hope. I do not want to insist that there are no cases in which differences in content alone are perspicuously represented by distinguishing the attitude we stand towards that content. But marking the distinction in this way means that we cannot argue directly for a connection between self-consciousness and hope and thereby take ourselves to have secured a connection to others. We must argue first for the necessity of a social content to practical assent and this will then allow us to characterise the connection as holding between self-consciousness and hope. That is to say, the issue is not whether self-consciousness requires faith or hope—it is whether the content of practical assent is necessarily social in the way required for hope.

The question of whether there is a more direct route to sociality thus turns on the content of practical assent. In ch.4 of The Practical Self, I argue that we have practical grounds to accept that we are the agents of our thinking. Bagnoli's direct connection must go further: it must show that we have practical grounds to accept that we are in community with others. What is the argument for this claim?

In broad terms, the line of thought sketched by Bagnoli takes agential thinking to bring with it answerability to various norms. Some of these are epistemic and concern the truth or falsity of our assertions. Others are more broadly moral and concern the relation we stand in to others. In both cases, we can comply with the structural norms only in the context of a community of other thinkers. So to the extent that we have practical grounds available for taking ourselves to be the agents of our thinking, we also have practical grounds for accepting—hoping—that there is a community of other thinkers who face these challenges together.

If Bagnoli's thought can be made good, the content of practical assent is more expansive than I suggest. But there are two grounds for concern. First, there is a question about whether the content of this hope alone would suffice to establish a connection between self-consciousness and sociality. As I tell the story in ch.2 of The Practical Self, the twentieth century saw a retreat from the worldly ambitions of Descartes and Kant to the claim that self-conscious subjects are only intentionally directed onto an objective world (PS, pp.36–37). If hope is an attitude we can stand in to objects without being genuinely related to them, then Bagnoli's suggestion gets us no further than twentieth-century diffidence.

Second, and more importantly, the proposed extension of practical assent from cognitive agency to community turns on the claim that the structural norms of thinking can only be realised in a community of others. But even if thinking is governed by the norms which Bagnoli suggests, why think they can only be realised in communion with others? This is stronger than the claim that the norms which govern thinking concern others. For norms which concern others may be realisable solely through my own efforts—or, if not mine alone, at least supplemented only by divine assistance. Kant's argument to the stronger conclusion starts from an assumption about our propensity for evil (Rel. 6:97–98). Why think that anything similar holds true of the norms which govern our thinking? There is a gap between the claim that thinking is subject to norms which concern others and the claim that these norms require realisation in a community.

I turn now to Bagnoli's second charge: that, far from sustaining a commitment to objectivity, the practices appealed to in The Practical Self actually undermine it. How should we understand this concern? One might think that the directness of Bagnoli's route to sociality turns on its renunciation of practice and that this is the context in which to understand her concerns about the ways practices undermine objectivity. But consider the Kantian resources which she takes to underwrite practical assent. There is the practice of attributing responsibility, understood not in the Strawsonian form in which it appears in ch.5 of The Practical Self but as part of the fundamental structure of human interaction and the basis for all social agency. There is the particular way that moral agency shows up in sensibility as the feeling of respect. And there is the relation of reciprocity which places a normative constraint on deliberation.

How do these compare to the resources marshalled in The Practical Self? Bagnoli's Kant finds a foundation for practical assent in practices, feelings, and constraints on decision-making, all of which involve a relation to others. The Practical Self focussed primarily on the role of practices in scaffolding practical assent. But it also noted the way in which a commitment to the reality of others shows up in our experiences, when we disagree (PS, p.159), and in our decision-making, when we attend to diachronic considerations about the persistence of practices (PS, p.161). The difference between the direct and circumambulatory routes is not a difference in resource.

Bagnoli's objection to the argument in The Practical Self is thus not to its invocation of practice but to its claim that social practice is mere scaffold: something which aids practical assent but is strictly unnecessary. Her Kantian resources are instead supposed to be the very basis for intellectual agency, a social foundation for practical assent. The result is more recognisably Kantian, at least in as much as one takes Kant to care only about the properly necessary. Practical assent, by its very nature, involves others because it has its foundation in a practice of attributing responsibility, a feeling of respect, and a constraint of reciprocity. These practices, feelings, and constraints are not optional extras for those who need the additional support: they are part of the structure of human relations which underwrites the social agency involved in practical assent. Bagnoli's Kantian route is direct not because it foreswears practice but because it insists on its necessity.

This helps to spell out Bagnoli's concern about the way the two parts of the argument in The Practical Self fit together. The odd pairing is not faith and practice but the necessity of faith and the optionality of practice. Bagnoli worries that if practice is understood as anything less than the fundamental structure for human agency, it will mediate, weaken and distort our relation to others. Why would scaffolding have this consequence? Bagnoli's thought is that since the practices appealed to in The Practical Self are relative to particular forms of life (see e.g. PS, pp.138–141), the support that they provide is exclusive and independent. The result is a plethora of communities whose practices may, as it happens, sustain faith in the same content but whose structures are independently authoritative. And she takes this to be a undermine any strategy aiming at objectivity.

How seriously should we take this worry? Bagnoli is right to emphasise the dangers of group identities and the way in which distinguishing between those who are in and those who are out can inculcate hostility towards those on the outside even as it creates community among those on the inside. And she is right too that the practices involved in holding one another accountable are shaped by imbalances of power and authority in ways that I did not discuss. Social practices can constrain as much as they sustain and it is good to recognise this.

But why should this have any implication for objectivity? Bagnoli's thought seems to be that a proliferation of practice would undermine the norms involved in thinking of oneself as an autonomous thinker. For if the support provided to practical assent comes from a specific form of life, then I cannot take its support to generalise to all instances of thinking, even in the case where the distinct practices support the same norms. Convergence may allow an overlapping consensus on the model of Rawls's Political Liberalism. But Bagnoli insists that this falls short of universal authority. And it is this subversion of universal norms of thinking which is supposed to undermine any claim to objectivity.

But this is not the notion of objectivity at play in The Practical Self. I distinguish there two broad notions of objectivity—the ontological and the perspectival (PS, pp.12–16). According to the ontological notion of objectivity, something is objective when it doesn't depend for its existence on minds and subjective otherwise. According to the perspectival notion, something is objective when it is independent of a subject's point of view and subjective otherwise. The threat which Bagnoli finds in a proliferation of practices is a threat to the idea of universal norms which govern thinking—that is, to norms which apply independently of one's parochial perspective on the world. If she is right, there may be a threat to a perspectival notion of objectivity in the vicinity. But my concern in The Practical Self was the objectivity of things which don't depend for their existence on my awareness of them. And we don't yet have a threat to objectivity in this sense.

Consider a world of mutually independent practices, all of which centre on other thinkers, distinct from us and our mental states. It may be that we cannot take part in each practice without foreswearing the others. And it may be that Bagnoli is right to worry that the norms which issue from each practice can only ever aspire to local recognition, even when they overlap so as to allow consensus. This is no threat to the ontological notion of objectivity so long as each practice relates its participants to things which don't depend on minds. A plenitude of practices does not denigrate the objectivity of that to which they relate.

I don't see, then, that the optionality of practice threatens objectivity of the sort that was at issue in The Practical Self. Nor do I see that her Kantian route is more direct. Both lines of argument hold that self-consciousness requires practical assent and both think that assent is supported by practice. Bagnoli takes the content of the assent to be communal in a way that goes beyond the argument of The Practical Self. And she takes the connection between practical assent and practice to be necessary rather than central. I have expressed scepticism about the first claim and denied that the second is needed to secure a connection to objectivity. But even granting both, these are emendations to the approach set out in The Practical Self rather than its rejection.

There is still a difference of view about the scope and nature of the practice of accountability which is supposed to sustain faith in ourselves as the agents of our thinking. Bagnoli thinks it cannot be merely central but must be rooted in the structural and universal features of being human. But even if the practice of accountability is universal in the way that Bagnoli insists, this is not yet to show that it must relate us to other thinkers. It might be that we centre the practice on future selves, an imaginary other, or God (see PS, pp.159–161). I share with Bagnoli the thought that these practices could only ever be peripheral, a pale imitation of the joyful conversation which pervades our ordinary lives. But their possibility does not undermine the connection to others present in the ordinary case: our practice is enough.26

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
11.10%
发文量
82
期刊介绍: ''Founded by Mark Sacks in 1993, the European Journal of Philosophy has come to occupy a distinctive and highly valued place amongst the philosophical journals. The aim of EJP has been to bring together the best work from those working within the "analytic" and "continental" traditions, and to encourage connections between them, without diluting their respective priorities and concerns. This has enabled EJP to publish a wide range of material of the highest standard from philosophers across the world, reflecting the best thinking from a variety of philosophical perspectives, in a way that is accessible to all of them.''
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信