巴门尼德和奇爱博士,或者我是如何学会停止对一元论的担忧并接受关系世界的,至少是为了善

IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Michael A. Rosenthal
{"title":"巴门尼德和奇爱博士,或者我是如何学会停止对一元论的担忧并接受关系世界的,至少是为了善","authors":"Michael A. Rosenthal","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13057","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>I want to start with a movie: <i>Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb</i>.<sup>1</sup></p><p>This 1964 film, directed by Stanley Kubrick, and starring Peter Sellers in multiple roles, satirizes the Cold War defense establishment. It tells the story of a renegade base commander, General Jack D. Ripper, played by Sterling Hayden, who takes advantage of a malfunction in the communications system to send his wing of B-52 bombers to attack the Soviet Union. When the President of the United States is alerted to this dire state of affairs by the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, General Buck Turgidson, played by George C. Scott, he tries to make a deal with his Soviet counterpart, Premier Kissov, for a limited proportional response, but is startled to discover, as his advisor, the former Nazi scientist, Dr. Strangelove, informs him, that the Soviets have recently activated a “Doomsday” device, whose purpose is to deter a single attack by immediately triggering a conflagration that would destroy the entire world. After failed attempts to thwart the attack, whether by the visiting British officer, Group Captain Lionel Mandrake, at Burpelson Airbase, or by the Soviet Air Defense system, the defense officials gathered in the War Room are left to contemplate their only option, which is to gather top government officials in a deep underground shelter, where they will work to repopulate the world. At the end, one bomber, piloted by Major T. J. “King” Kong, manages to get through to deliver the payload and trigger Armageddon. The final scene is of Dr. Strangelove getting out of his wheelchair, exclaiming ecstatically, “<i>Mein Führer</i>, I can walk!,” which then cuts to scenes of giant nuclear mushroom clouds exploding in the air accompanied by the melancholy song, “We'll meet again.”</p><p>This is a great movie, undoubtedly a classic, and you should see it, if you haven't already. But why am I bringing it up here? The answer is that, in my view, it perfectly illustrates the nature of acosmism. As I was reading Michael Della Rocca's recent book, <i>The Parmenidean Ascent</i>, this was the story that almost immediately came to mind. At first, I tried to ignore it, thinking that it was just a glib association, but when it came back again, I realized that my philosophical unconscious was speaking to me and that perhaps I should pay attention to it. Here are some of the points of comparison.</p><p>The main point is the doomsday principle of deterrence. Half measures don't add up to much. If you want to preserve the world, then you must threaten to destroy it completely.</p><p>There is the mad scientist, Dr. Strangelove, whose very name embodies the paradox. He is one of the designers of the system itself, the Parmenides figure. One thing to note is that in the movie, this character has a dubious past, as a servant to a totalizing Reich, and also a weak character. In contrast to Major Kong, who has the simple-minded audacity to carry out his world-destroying duty, we learn in the end, when it becomes apparent that no-one can stop the renegade bomber, that Dr. Strangelove is not committed fully to the principle that he has articulated. He is secretly a “tamer” who, even as the rest of the world has been destroyed, embraces the idea that a small group of elites will survive in a deep mine, stocked for the duration of a radioactive future, whose only purpose will be to breed a new race of people to repopulate the world.</p><p>There is the instigator, General Jack D. Ripper: who unleashes the whole thing via a pathological concern for purity focused on his fear of fluoride being added to the water. Despite his paranoia, he can be quite reasonable. He asks the right questions. If we have devoted so much time and energy to developing this project, and we have a functioning system in place, then why not use it? The modern rationalist.</p><p>Ripper's counterpoint is the Group Captain Lionel Mandrake, who tries to reason with Gen. Ripper through appeals to common sense. The “tamer” par excellence, the British philosopher of common sense. He is doomed to be ineffectual.</p><p>Then there is the loyal soldier: Major T. J. “King” Kong, who commands the B-52 that eludes the Soviet air defense system. Played by the well-known former rodeo performer and star of Westerns, “Slim” Pickens, Kong is single-mindedly driven by his duty. When the bomb doors of the plane he is piloting become stuck, he descends into the belly of the beast to fix the problem. He literally rides the bomb to its target, whooping with joy, as he initiates the doomsday scenario and the end of the world. This image is the epitome of the “happy suicide of thought,” as the philosopher F.H. Bradley labeled the ideal.</p><p>The most important character of the film, of course, is the Bomb, a.k.a., the PSR (Principle of Sufficient Reason). It is the technology that not only gets the job done but determines the values of the system of which it is the heart.</p><p>What is the purpose of the satire? Let us remember that, although the movie gleefully recounts how the world is destroyed, that the purpose of the system was deterrence, that is, to preserve the world. At its margins, then, the film considers some obvious and important questions: What would a world without any living beings within it look like? What would the value of such a world be? Some would argue that these questions are not really the point of the film, though. The real issue is to highlight the inefficacy of the instrument chosen to protect the world. Both critics and proponents of deterrence share the same concerns. While a critic would point out the folies of deterrence, as it raises the chances that the very world we want to protect might be destroyed, a proponent would just say, on the very same grounds, that we simply need to correct and improve the systems that we have in place. It is a debate about the means and not the ends.</p><p>Of course, along these lines, Kubrick also wants to point out the hypocrisy, which is revealed among those that benefit from the system. The secret taming strategy of the inventors of the system reveals that they do care about finite existence. What is problematic about it is that it shows that they only value their own lives and not those of everyone else who will be destroyed.</p><p>But the subversive purpose of the satire might be something more sinister than either questioning the instrumental value of a system of deterrence or pointing out the hypocrisy of its advocates. Rather, the point of the film is something else entirely, namely, that the technology of the system is no longer an instrument to preserve some other set of values—say the glories of mid-century American capitalism or the Soviet version of communism—but itself the true meaning of the system. We need an elaborate system to maintain the bomb, but the ostensible purpose of the weapon—to prevent war—is belied by the fact that the key to the whole principle of deterrence is destruction itself. That, Kubrick suggests, is the ultimate value of the system, as the true heroes of the film demonstrate in their actions, when they embrace it.</p><p>Hegel's critique of Spinoza is not comedic in form but straightforwardly philosophical. He aims to show that Spinoza's pantheism—the view that nature and God are one—leads to a perverse effect—the denial that all things in the world except for God are real—in other words, acosmism. Nonetheless, the comparison to Kubrick's film is useful in two ways. For one thing, the film, as I hope to show, reveals something about the structure of Hegel's argument. For another, Hegel's argument shares some elements of literary satire in its reliance upon ironic effects and an implicit moral and social critique. In contrast to Kubrick's <i>Dr. Strangelove</i>, however, Hegel's version of satire is far less bleak. You might see what I mean if I distinguish between two traditional kinds of satire: one that assumes a moral vision and of which it is in service; and another one that is darker and calls into question the possibility of moral value itself. Hegel offers the first version. As Yitzhak Melamed reminds us, Hegel's reading of Spinoza depends on, but also starkly differs from that of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (79).<sup>2</sup> Like Hegel, Jacobi wants to use Spinoza's views as a kind of warning, though his fear is more extreme. Jacobi thought that Spinoza had obliterated not only the finite (“Individual things, therefore, so far as they only exist in a certain determinate mode, are <i>non-entia</i>” [220]) but the infinite as well,<sup>3</sup> at least in the sense that the infinite, which Jacobi thinks can have neither intellect nor will (222), has any resemblance to a traditional idea of God, which leads to the conclusion that Spinoza is not only an atheist (“Spinozism is atheism” 233) but also a nihilist.<sup>4</sup> Hegel, in contrast, accepts Spinoza as a kind of religious thinker, albeit one who has gone horribly wrong. As he writes, “The charge of <i>Atheism</i>, which used often to be brought against philosophy (that it has <i>too little</i> of God), has grown rare: the more widespread grows the charge of Pantheism, that it has <i>too much</i> of him.”<sup>5</sup> For Hegel, it is pantheism that leads to acosmism.</p><p>The problems with pantheism have been discussed in detail by many scholars. In a nutshell, Hegel thinks that for Spinoza the only thing that actually exists is a single substance.<sup>6</sup> It is simple yet contains both thought and extension. There are, what he calls, two determinations of substance within itself, one that is universal and has being for itself, the other that is the particular and has being only in a dependent way. Hegel thinks that many of Spinoza's distinctions—among attributes and between attributes and modes—are not justified but only presupposed. He seems to endorse as a fundamental principle the notion that “all determination is negation,” even though it is unclear in the way and the extent of its application in Spinoza's system. Crucially, Hegel thinks that Spinoza fails to explain how the finite can be derived from the infinite. Not only are the consequences of Spinoza's view problematic, but so it its justification. Of course, there is a great deal of debate over these claims. Some scholars would disagree with them as a caricature of Spinoza's system, others would suggest that they have some merit. The one charge that I want to focus on, though, relates to the metaphysics of his morals.</p><p>What stands behind and motivates Hegel's critique of pantheism is his own substantive view of the metaphysical basis of morality. When he makes his critique of pantheism through showing how acosmism (the denial of finite subjects) results from it, he already has an alternative conception of morality, based primarily on his notion of subjectivity for God and for us, as finite beings, that is informing his arguments. For Hegel, the problem with Spinoza in this regard is that the fundamental ontological principle, substance, does not exhibit the principle of subjectivity. His idea of substance is abstract, not vital and alive (154). To be clear, I am not saying that Hegel simply has some arbitrary moral standpoint that he contrasts with that of Spinoza. He thinks that he has a rational justification for his view of divine and finite subjectivity and the moral and political system that follows from it. The point is that if we accept Spinoza's view, that reason leads us to an undifferentiated God, which undermines the possibility of meaningful moral life, then we must have an inadequate view either of reason itself or the fundamental concepts that reason has discovered. For Hegel, the project of explanation is never distinct from its moral content.</p><p>In this, he explicitly compares Spinoza's view to and categorizes it as an example of “Oriental” thought and religion.<sup>7</sup> As Paul Franks remarks, Bayle had already made the association of Spinoza with the Orient, and it subsequently became a commonplace among other thinkers (154). In the <i>Encyclopedia Logic</i>, Hegel is reported to have said, “Spinoza was a Jew by descent, and what found expression in the form of thought in his philosophy is in general on the oriental intuition according to which everything finite appears merely as something transient, as something vanishing” (cited by Franks, 531). The static and undifferentiated substance is not a God to be venerated. Rather, he is an abstract version of a despot who treats his subjects either as tools or as non-existing. The subjects, in turn, with this strange conception of themselves act as if they don't exist, that is, as slaves.</p><p>Thus, for Hegel, acosmism is the parody of a proper order. It is the parody of a religious system, in which God directs the world providentially; the parody of a philosophical system in which actions are determined through the activity of subject; and the parody of a moral and political system, in which freedom is the reigning value. It is true that Spinoza claims that he defends a robust concept of freedom at the core of his system, but he has a hard time defending himself due to his attack on free-will and divine providence.</p><p>This is a good point to transition back to a discussion of Michael Della Rocca's book, <i>The Parmenidean Ascent</i>.<sup>8</sup> Della Rocca and Hegel share some important features. Both Della Rocca and Hegel share an interest in Spinoza and Acosmism. But they also differ in several respects. For one thing, while Della Rocca is an engaging writer, Hegel produces a lot of turgid prose. More significantly, Della Rocca exhibits little or no satirical intent. Although he has a good sense of humor, which he frequently exhibits, he is deadly earnest in his embrace of Acosmism. (Interestingly, though Spinoza is clearly in the background, as he mentions in a couple of places, there is little or no systematic discussion of Spinoza. That is perhaps because, on his reading at least, Spinoza is not one of the tamers so common among interpreters. Spinoza is the only rationalist who could be read as living up to his own principles and doesn't belong among the list of failures that he gives us).</p><p>Della Rocca specifies that the “crux” of this failure, as F. H. Bradley understood, is the “rationalist argument against the reality of the relevant kind of relation, and hence against the reality of differentiated substance, action, knowledge, or meaning” (xvi). The idea, then, is that if we follow the demands of reason, we can explain the world without relying on any primitives, falling into an infinite regress, or getting trapped in a vicious circle, by doing away with all relations and the differentiated experience of the world that follows from them.</p><p>The fact that he has reserved it for another occasion is a sign that he is also aware of the importance of the topic. I would argue that the domain of the moral is not just one of many philosophical issues to which we can apply the PSR but connected in a special way to the employment of the PSR itself.</p><p>Whether this answer is sufficient—and I suspect that Della Rocca does not think that it is—is something that I return to at the end. But the point of bringing it up now is that I think that it is a problem that Spinoza does consider to be at the heart of his project. In Della Rocca's essay on Bradley's <i>Appearance and Reality</i>, he does link Bradley and Spinoza, but besides pointing out that Spinoza also seems to approve the idea of the overcoming of relations through knowledge of the One, he does not consider Bradley's own moral philosophy or suggest what the implications of Bradley's view might be for his own.<sup>9</sup> I want to suggest that until we provide an account of the moral motivation of the project itself, that is, of the moral content of the PSR, then we cannot be satisfied with this gesture of throwing away the ladder.</p><p>Let us turn now to Spinoza. There has been a resurgence of interest in the acosmic reading of Spinoza and debates over the degree of its application within Spinoza's system. Some have argued for the reality, albeit qualified, of the finite individual in the system<sup>10</sup>; others for its ultimate unreality.<sup>11</sup> Here I want to focus on the moral question of the acosmic reading. First, I want to say something about the development of Spinoza's system and how that sheds some light on how he conceives of the nature of the highest good. Then I will turn to his analysis of the meaning of the good and how that bears on the nature of the highest good.</p><p>Just a bit later, he announces that he has an idea of the true good (§12), and then in the following section he tells us in three steps in what this highest good consists. First, we have to realize that “good and bad are said of things only in a certain respect” and that from the point of view of the eternal nothing is in itself good or bad.<sup>14</sup> Second, we must recognize that, due to our weakness, we do not grasp the point of view of the eternal, and hence “man conceives a human nature much stronger and more enduring than his own” (TdIE, §13). (An important corollary to this point is that we come to realize that we could acquire this nature and that we seek the means to do so.) Third, we realize that this ideal human nature “is the knowledge of the union that the mind has with the whole of Nature” (TdIE, §13).</p><p>We find an apparently similar tri-partite structure in the last two parts of the <i>Ethics</i>. First, in the preface of Part IV, Spinoza notes that, “As far as good and evil are concerned, they also indicate nothing positive in things, considered in themselves, nor are they anything other than modes of thinking, or notions we form because we compare things to one another” (E4pref). Second, despite these limitations, we desire to form a model of human nature, whose very purpose is to provide a common standard of good.<sup>15</sup> An adequate idea of this model, some have argued, can be found in the discussion of the “free man” at the end of Part IV.<sup>16</sup> And then this model, in turn, is a stepping stone to the knowledge of God that serves as the basis of what Spinoza in Part V of the <i>Ethics</i> calls our “blessedness” [<i>beatitude</i>]: “From this we clearly understand wherein our salvation, or blessedness, or Freedom, consists, viz. in a constant and eternal Love of God, or in God's Love for men” (E5p36c).</p><p>But there are also some important differences between the early and later works, both in fine details and in the larger conceptual scheme. The language that Spinoza uses differs. In the TdIE, it is “true good,” which doesn't appear in the <i>Ethics</i>, but rather “certain good.” And, although we do see the “highest good” (E5p19dem) mentioned in both places, we now see descriptions of it that seem to emphasize the individual state of mind, such as the “highest satisfaction” [<i>summa acquiescentia</i>] (E5p38s) or blessedness, as we just saw (E5p36c). Spinoza only uses the word “union” [<i>unionis</i>] with God in the TdIE. In the <i>Ethics</i>, there is no such explicit conjunction between the individual and nature. We do find phrases like “God's love of men and the mind's intellectual love of God are one and the same” (E5p36c), which some might argue is more or less equivalent with the idea of a union. As we have seen, scholars disagree over whether the object of the third kind of knowledge is a finite essence or an infinite essence. Yet the fact that we need to argue for an interpretation of the highest good at this point indicates that there is at least a prima facie problem with any simple conception based on the dissolution of the individual.</p><p>The persistence of a gap between the finite individual and the infinite is suggested not only in the slightly different conceptual vocabulary utilized, but also in the amount and kind of work that is required to close the gap. In the early texts, Spinoza takes what might be considered as a neo-Stoic approach to ethical life, in which we arrive at the highest good primarily through the correction of our false judgments. There is room for the cognitive therapy of the passions, which he treats rather stoically as mistaken ideas, but there is little or no discussion of social and political life.<sup>17</sup> When we do come across political language, it is as a metaphor for our abject lack of autonomy, as is clearly seen in the <i>Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being (Korte Verhandeling</i>, or KV) where he writes, “it follows from this [the fact that we are part of nature and are determined by its laws] that we are truly God's servants—indeed, his slaves—and that our greatest perfection is to be such necessarily” (KV, Part 2, ch. 18.1; C127).</p><p>However, as I and others have argued, Spinoza's engagement with politics, expressed in the composition and publication of the TTP, changed his conception of the ethical project.<sup>18</sup> Spinoza does not merely require the philosopher to correct his ideas and conduct a cognitive therapy of the passions, he also enjoins him [and I am using the gendered term to remind us that Spinoza due to his prejudice excluded women as rational political agents] to participate in political life as a condition of the ethical life. We see this concretely in the adoption of Hobbesian concepts of the <i>conatus</i> (the desire to preserve oneself, E3p6), the claim that the foundation of virtue is self-preservation (E4p18s), the requirement of the freeman to engage with the state (E4p70s and especially E4p73), and the striking claim in the penultimate proposition that, “Even if we did not know that our Mind is eternal, we would still regard as of the first importance Morality, Religion, and absolutely all the things we have shown (in Part IV) to be related to Tenacity and Nobility” (E5p41).</p><p>These observations are interesting, but they are only suggestive, open to interpretative differences, and hardly decisive. Here I want to propose a sketch of a philosophical reading of Spinoza's conception of the good that places it more squarely in the acosmic tradition, but, as we shall see, with a twist. The basic idea is that the idea of the good that Spinoza proposes is fundamentally relational, but that it is only possible to understand this fact with certainty once we understand the point of view of the infinite, which itself is amoral. There are three points that support this claim:</p><p>The good does not exist independently of us, whether in God, in nature, or in some third realm; rather, it is a projection of our desire onto the world.<sup>19</sup> On this level, our understanding of the good will prove to be unendingly relational, due to our shifting relations with the external world and even our shifting relation to our self, which proves to be far less stable or given than we had imagined it.<sup>20</sup></p><p>2) The attempts to ground these individual, relational conceptions of the good in a model of human nature, which can be either inadequately or adequately conceived, do add a layer of certainty, especially when they are adequate. When Spinoza defines the good at the beginning of Part IV, he writes, “By good I shall understand what we certainly know to be useful to us” (E4d1). Likewise, “By evil, however, I shall understand what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good” (E4d2). The useful could be just what we desire, hence the definition is consistent with the ontology of desire and value in Part III. Spinoza knows that this is a radically unstable definition, lacking any certainty, even from the point of view of the individual. Hence, when he provides an additional explanation, and writes, “On these definitions, see the preceding preface [208/18-22],” he refers us back precisely to the discussion of models of human nature, which are supposed to provide a stable, because intersubjective, basis for our value judgments.</p><p>However, even these models are always relational in some sense. In the case of an inadequate model of human nature, then we are faced with the problem that we are just conflating a set of particular experiences and the ideas of those experiences into a single idea that we falsely label as a “universal” (see E2p40s1).<sup>21</sup> In the case of an adequate model, the idea is more certain because it is based on properties that reason discerns are in the part and whole, i.e., common notions. Nonetheless, the idea is still relative to the set of properties in nature that we construct as “human,” which in turn are relative to other classifications of properties in the natural world. In other words, a meaningful, true idea of human nature, depends on the existence of particular properties and the differences with other patterns of properties in the world, all of which leads us to consider the order and system of nature itself that produces this infinite differentiation.</p><p>3) We can come to the realization through reason that Nature (or God) does not contain any intrinsic value. There is both a negative and positive aspect of this realization. The negative view is expressed clearly in the appendix to Part 1 of the <i>Ethics</i>. There, Spinoza argues that our traditional conceptions of God, his attributes, and His relation to nature are mostly due to an anthropomorphic projection of our mostly mistaken self-conceptions onto the order of nature itself. If we can argue for a positive conception of God that does not include these anthropomorphic properties, then we can not only understand that God does not have these properties but that he cannot have them. Two adjacent passages in the <i>Ethics</i> provide the best evidence that Spinoza thought something like this. First, Spinoza writes that “from this [i.e., that knowledge of evil is inadequate knowledge], it follows that if the human mind had only adequate ideas, it would form no notion of evil” (E4p64c). But this is inadequate because it is consistent with the long theological and philosophical tradition of seeing evil as a lack or something that has no reality at all. Thus, Spinoza makes a second, more comprehensive point: “If men were born free, they would form no concept of good and evil so long as they remained free” (E4p68). Those who reason call into question the human projections of value onto nature and know that, since the definition of good is relational, a being that did not have relations would not have any conception of the good, and yet we also know, from the starting point of our own experience, that we inevitably form conceptions of good and evil, and we can see on the basis of reason that it is our nature to do so. When we glimpse the perspective of God, then we see the infinitely perspectival and, insofar as we use models of various kinds, the recursive nature of the good.</p><p>The conclusion is that when we understand that our own sense of value is relational and that God does not have any fundamental values that might ground them in any deeper sense than the complex patterns we experience in nature, then we can embrace the idea of an infinitely qualified sense of value, in which we sometimes manage to agree with one another but more often than not disagree. In other words, we have an explanation of our moral world.</p><p>The reason appears to be that the very nature of an explanation requires an ultimate <i>how</i>, which an endless regress can in principle simply never satisfy.</p><p>However, hopefully, now we can see that a commitment to this explanatory condition leads to an unpalatable dilemma when it comes to the nature of the Good, at least in Spinoza, namely, that it couldn't be conceived except as infinitely relational.</p><p>The nature of the good in Spinoza's system is obviously a very complex topic, and my purpose here is hardly to give even a basic let alone an exhaustive account of it. Nonetheless, the scant few texts I have cited should allow me to make a couple of observations that are germane to the problem of the moral aspect of acosmism.</p><p>Spinoza can't be committed to the independence of some conception of the good that precedes, logically speaking, the system itself. Nor can he be committed to the entire dissolution of the idea of the good in either the unification of the individual with God (as in the early writings) or the intellectual love of God (in the later writings, which, as I have argued, are more ambiguous about the status of the subject). Somehow, we must avoid this Scylla and Charybdis and search for an alternative, one that allows us to maintain the paradox that we have discerned at the heart of the system. That is, we achieve the highest good when we realize that there is no ultimate good, that is, a good that is unqualified.</p><p>I said at the beginning that I thought we could use the logic of deterrence in <i>Dr. Strangelove</i> to help us understand some of the problems of acosmism. Let me now suggest in conclusion that we can use it as the blueprint for a solution to the moral problem. Let's call it the reverse Strangelove paradox: instead of saying that we need to threaten to destroy the world to save it, let us say that we need to embrace the world in order to destroy it. Or call it, if you'd like, the Parmenidean descent, which, as Della Rocca notes, is a possible translation of the Greek <i>katabasis</i>, though one he rejects for both rhetorical and philosophical reasons.<sup>22</sup> What we discover when we follow the PSR and ascend to the level of substance is that the world of finite beings is essential to the possibility of making sense of the highest good. And so we must, following the discovery of the logic of the Good, or what the PSR reveals about what the nature of the good is, namely, the endless recursive definition of it in terms of finite relations, descend back into the midst of endless relations precisely to find a reason to accept the One. Thus, contrary to Della Rocca's Wittgensteinian point, we cannot do away with the ladder. Rather, we must embrace it.</p><p>The good for any finite thing is always defined in relation to itself and to other finite things (even if we conflate them into an imaginative universal or discover some true property that they share in common). However, what we discover as we know the nature of God is that what is One, the infinite substance or nature or God, does not have any relations in its essence. For that reason, Spinoza thinks that substance is, as Nietzsche would later put it, “beyond good and evil.” But if we are to be motivated to pursue the demands of reason, we must seek the good for us, that is, as finite beings. So, instead of throwing away the ladder, and doing away with morality altogether, which Spinoza recognizes would be the case (and I don't know if Della Rocca thinks this or not), the paradoxical result is that we must cycle back from the One to the Many, which is the very source of the motivation to achieve this state of knowledge. If this is true of morality, then perhaps this dynamic might be true of every other domain as well. Instead of doing away with the many, the search for the One motivates us to return to our finite natures.<sup>23</sup> Whether we take this seriously or as yet another fictional satire, will be the subject of the sequel.<sup>24</sup></p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"33 1","pages":"354-364"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2025-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13057","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Parmenides and Dr. Strangelove, Or How I Learned to Stop Worrying about Monism and Accept the World of Relations, at least for the sake of the Good\",\"authors\":\"Michael A. Rosenthal\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/ejop.13057\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>I want to start with a movie: <i>Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb</i>.<sup>1</sup></p><p>This 1964 film, directed by Stanley Kubrick, and starring Peter Sellers in multiple roles, satirizes the Cold War defense establishment. It tells the story of a renegade base commander, General Jack D. Ripper, played by Sterling Hayden, who takes advantage of a malfunction in the communications system to send his wing of B-52 bombers to attack the Soviet Union. When the President of the United States is alerted to this dire state of affairs by the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, General Buck Turgidson, played by George C. Scott, he tries to make a deal with his Soviet counterpart, Premier Kissov, for a limited proportional response, but is startled to discover, as his advisor, the former Nazi scientist, Dr. Strangelove, informs him, that the Soviets have recently activated a “Doomsday” device, whose purpose is to deter a single attack by immediately triggering a conflagration that would destroy the entire world. After failed attempts to thwart the attack, whether by the visiting British officer, Group Captain Lionel Mandrake, at Burpelson Airbase, or by the Soviet Air Defense system, the defense officials gathered in the War Room are left to contemplate their only option, which is to gather top government officials in a deep underground shelter, where they will work to repopulate the world. At the end, one bomber, piloted by Major T. J. “King” Kong, manages to get through to deliver the payload and trigger Armageddon. The final scene is of Dr. Strangelove getting out of his wheelchair, exclaiming ecstatically, “<i>Mein Führer</i>, I can walk!,” which then cuts to scenes of giant nuclear mushroom clouds exploding in the air accompanied by the melancholy song, “We'll meet again.”</p><p>This is a great movie, undoubtedly a classic, and you should see it, if you haven't already. But why am I bringing it up here? The answer is that, in my view, it perfectly illustrates the nature of acosmism. As I was reading Michael Della Rocca's recent book, <i>The Parmenidean Ascent</i>, this was the story that almost immediately came to mind. At first, I tried to ignore it, thinking that it was just a glib association, but when it came back again, I realized that my philosophical unconscious was speaking to me and that perhaps I should pay attention to it. Here are some of the points of comparison.</p><p>The main point is the doomsday principle of deterrence. Half measures don't add up to much. If you want to preserve the world, then you must threaten to destroy it completely.</p><p>There is the mad scientist, Dr. Strangelove, whose very name embodies the paradox. He is one of the designers of the system itself, the Parmenides figure. One thing to note is that in the movie, this character has a dubious past, as a servant to a totalizing Reich, and also a weak character. In contrast to Major Kong, who has the simple-minded audacity to carry out his world-destroying duty, we learn in the end, when it becomes apparent that no-one can stop the renegade bomber, that Dr. Strangelove is not committed fully to the principle that he has articulated. He is secretly a “tamer” who, even as the rest of the world has been destroyed, embraces the idea that a small group of elites will survive in a deep mine, stocked for the duration of a radioactive future, whose only purpose will be to breed a new race of people to repopulate the world.</p><p>There is the instigator, General Jack D. Ripper: who unleashes the whole thing via a pathological concern for purity focused on his fear of fluoride being added to the water. Despite his paranoia, he can be quite reasonable. He asks the right questions. If we have devoted so much time and energy to developing this project, and we have a functioning system in place, then why not use it? The modern rationalist.</p><p>Ripper's counterpoint is the Group Captain Lionel Mandrake, who tries to reason with Gen. Ripper through appeals to common sense. The “tamer” par excellence, the British philosopher of common sense. He is doomed to be ineffectual.</p><p>Then there is the loyal soldier: Major T. J. “King” Kong, who commands the B-52 that eludes the Soviet air defense system. Played by the well-known former rodeo performer and star of Westerns, “Slim” Pickens, Kong is single-mindedly driven by his duty. When the bomb doors of the plane he is piloting become stuck, he descends into the belly of the beast to fix the problem. He literally rides the bomb to its target, whooping with joy, as he initiates the doomsday scenario and the end of the world. This image is the epitome of the “happy suicide of thought,” as the philosopher F.H. Bradley labeled the ideal.</p><p>The most important character of the film, of course, is the Bomb, a.k.a., the PSR (Principle of Sufficient Reason). It is the technology that not only gets the job done but determines the values of the system of which it is the heart.</p><p>What is the purpose of the satire? Let us remember that, although the movie gleefully recounts how the world is destroyed, that the purpose of the system was deterrence, that is, to preserve the world. At its margins, then, the film considers some obvious and important questions: What would a world without any living beings within it look like? What would the value of such a world be? Some would argue that these questions are not really the point of the film, though. The real issue is to highlight the inefficacy of the instrument chosen to protect the world. Both critics and proponents of deterrence share the same concerns. While a critic would point out the folies of deterrence, as it raises the chances that the very world we want to protect might be destroyed, a proponent would just say, on the very same grounds, that we simply need to correct and improve the systems that we have in place. It is a debate about the means and not the ends.</p><p>Of course, along these lines, Kubrick also wants to point out the hypocrisy, which is revealed among those that benefit from the system. The secret taming strategy of the inventors of the system reveals that they do care about finite existence. What is problematic about it is that it shows that they only value their own lives and not those of everyone else who will be destroyed.</p><p>But the subversive purpose of the satire might be something more sinister than either questioning the instrumental value of a system of deterrence or pointing out the hypocrisy of its advocates. Rather, the point of the film is something else entirely, namely, that the technology of the system is no longer an instrument to preserve some other set of values—say the glories of mid-century American capitalism or the Soviet version of communism—but itself the true meaning of the system. We need an elaborate system to maintain the bomb, but the ostensible purpose of the weapon—to prevent war—is belied by the fact that the key to the whole principle of deterrence is destruction itself. That, Kubrick suggests, is the ultimate value of the system, as the true heroes of the film demonstrate in their actions, when they embrace it.</p><p>Hegel's critique of Spinoza is not comedic in form but straightforwardly philosophical. He aims to show that Spinoza's pantheism—the view that nature and God are one—leads to a perverse effect—the denial that all things in the world except for God are real—in other words, acosmism. Nonetheless, the comparison to Kubrick's film is useful in two ways. For one thing, the film, as I hope to show, reveals something about the structure of Hegel's argument. For another, Hegel's argument shares some elements of literary satire in its reliance upon ironic effects and an implicit moral and social critique. In contrast to Kubrick's <i>Dr. Strangelove</i>, however, Hegel's version of satire is far less bleak. You might see what I mean if I distinguish between two traditional kinds of satire: one that assumes a moral vision and of which it is in service; and another one that is darker and calls into question the possibility of moral value itself. Hegel offers the first version. As Yitzhak Melamed reminds us, Hegel's reading of Spinoza depends on, but also starkly differs from that of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (79).<sup>2</sup> Like Hegel, Jacobi wants to use Spinoza's views as a kind of warning, though his fear is more extreme. Jacobi thought that Spinoza had obliterated not only the finite (“Individual things, therefore, so far as they only exist in a certain determinate mode, are <i>non-entia</i>” [220]) but the infinite as well,<sup>3</sup> at least in the sense that the infinite, which Jacobi thinks can have neither intellect nor will (222), has any resemblance to a traditional idea of God, which leads to the conclusion that Spinoza is not only an atheist (“Spinozism is atheism” 233) but also a nihilist.<sup>4</sup> Hegel, in contrast, accepts Spinoza as a kind of religious thinker, albeit one who has gone horribly wrong. As he writes, “The charge of <i>Atheism</i>, which used often to be brought against philosophy (that it has <i>too little</i> of God), has grown rare: the more widespread grows the charge of Pantheism, that it has <i>too much</i> of him.”<sup>5</sup> For Hegel, it is pantheism that leads to acosmism.</p><p>The problems with pantheism have been discussed in detail by many scholars. In a nutshell, Hegel thinks that for Spinoza the only thing that actually exists is a single substance.<sup>6</sup> It is simple yet contains both thought and extension. There are, what he calls, two determinations of substance within itself, one that is universal and has being for itself, the other that is the particular and has being only in a dependent way. Hegel thinks that many of Spinoza's distinctions—among attributes and between attributes and modes—are not justified but only presupposed. He seems to endorse as a fundamental principle the notion that “all determination is negation,” even though it is unclear in the way and the extent of its application in Spinoza's system. Crucially, Hegel thinks that Spinoza fails to explain how the finite can be derived from the infinite. Not only are the consequences of Spinoza's view problematic, but so it its justification. Of course, there is a great deal of debate over these claims. Some scholars would disagree with them as a caricature of Spinoza's system, others would suggest that they have some merit. The one charge that I want to focus on, though, relates to the metaphysics of his morals.</p><p>What stands behind and motivates Hegel's critique of pantheism is his own substantive view of the metaphysical basis of morality. When he makes his critique of pantheism through showing how acosmism (the denial of finite subjects) results from it, he already has an alternative conception of morality, based primarily on his notion of subjectivity for God and for us, as finite beings, that is informing his arguments. For Hegel, the problem with Spinoza in this regard is that the fundamental ontological principle, substance, does not exhibit the principle of subjectivity. His idea of substance is abstract, not vital and alive (154). To be clear, I am not saying that Hegel simply has some arbitrary moral standpoint that he contrasts with that of Spinoza. He thinks that he has a rational justification for his view of divine and finite subjectivity and the moral and political system that follows from it. The point is that if we accept Spinoza's view, that reason leads us to an undifferentiated God, which undermines the possibility of meaningful moral life, then we must have an inadequate view either of reason itself or the fundamental concepts that reason has discovered. For Hegel, the project of explanation is never distinct from its moral content.</p><p>In this, he explicitly compares Spinoza's view to and categorizes it as an example of “Oriental” thought and religion.<sup>7</sup> As Paul Franks remarks, Bayle had already made the association of Spinoza with the Orient, and it subsequently became a commonplace among other thinkers (154). In the <i>Encyclopedia Logic</i>, Hegel is reported to have said, “Spinoza was a Jew by descent, and what found expression in the form of thought in his philosophy is in general on the oriental intuition according to which everything finite appears merely as something transient, as something vanishing” (cited by Franks, 531). The static and undifferentiated substance is not a God to be venerated. Rather, he is an abstract version of a despot who treats his subjects either as tools or as non-existing. The subjects, in turn, with this strange conception of themselves act as if they don't exist, that is, as slaves.</p><p>Thus, for Hegel, acosmism is the parody of a proper order. It is the parody of a religious system, in which God directs the world providentially; the parody of a philosophical system in which actions are determined through the activity of subject; and the parody of a moral and political system, in which freedom is the reigning value. It is true that Spinoza claims that he defends a robust concept of freedom at the core of his system, but he has a hard time defending himself due to his attack on free-will and divine providence.</p><p>This is a good point to transition back to a discussion of Michael Della Rocca's book, <i>The Parmenidean Ascent</i>.<sup>8</sup> Della Rocca and Hegel share some important features. Both Della Rocca and Hegel share an interest in Spinoza and Acosmism. But they also differ in several respects. For one thing, while Della Rocca is an engaging writer, Hegel produces a lot of turgid prose. More significantly, Della Rocca exhibits little or no satirical intent. Although he has a good sense of humor, which he frequently exhibits, he is deadly earnest in his embrace of Acosmism. (Interestingly, though Spinoza is clearly in the background, as he mentions in a couple of places, there is little or no systematic discussion of Spinoza. That is perhaps because, on his reading at least, Spinoza is not one of the tamers so common among interpreters. Spinoza is the only rationalist who could be read as living up to his own principles and doesn't belong among the list of failures that he gives us).</p><p>Della Rocca specifies that the “crux” of this failure, as F. H. Bradley understood, is the “rationalist argument against the reality of the relevant kind of relation, and hence against the reality of differentiated substance, action, knowledge, or meaning” (xvi). The idea, then, is that if we follow the demands of reason, we can explain the world without relying on any primitives, falling into an infinite regress, or getting trapped in a vicious circle, by doing away with all relations and the differentiated experience of the world that follows from them.</p><p>The fact that he has reserved it for another occasion is a sign that he is also aware of the importance of the topic. I would argue that the domain of the moral is not just one of many philosophical issues to which we can apply the PSR but connected in a special way to the employment of the PSR itself.</p><p>Whether this answer is sufficient—and I suspect that Della Rocca does not think that it is—is something that I return to at the end. But the point of bringing it up now is that I think that it is a problem that Spinoza does consider to be at the heart of his project. In Della Rocca's essay on Bradley's <i>Appearance and Reality</i>, he does link Bradley and Spinoza, but besides pointing out that Spinoza also seems to approve the idea of the overcoming of relations through knowledge of the One, he does not consider Bradley's own moral philosophy or suggest what the implications of Bradley's view might be for his own.<sup>9</sup> I want to suggest that until we provide an account of the moral motivation of the project itself, that is, of the moral content of the PSR, then we cannot be satisfied with this gesture of throwing away the ladder.</p><p>Let us turn now to Spinoza. There has been a resurgence of interest in the acosmic reading of Spinoza and debates over the degree of its application within Spinoza's system. Some have argued for the reality, albeit qualified, of the finite individual in the system<sup>10</sup>; others for its ultimate unreality.<sup>11</sup> Here I want to focus on the moral question of the acosmic reading. First, I want to say something about the development of Spinoza's system and how that sheds some light on how he conceives of the nature of the highest good. Then I will turn to his analysis of the meaning of the good and how that bears on the nature of the highest good.</p><p>Just a bit later, he announces that he has an idea of the true good (§12), and then in the following section he tells us in three steps in what this highest good consists. First, we have to realize that “good and bad are said of things only in a certain respect” and that from the point of view of the eternal nothing is in itself good or bad.<sup>14</sup> Second, we must recognize that, due to our weakness, we do not grasp the point of view of the eternal, and hence “man conceives a human nature much stronger and more enduring than his own” (TdIE, §13). (An important corollary to this point is that we come to realize that we could acquire this nature and that we seek the means to do so.) Third, we realize that this ideal human nature “is the knowledge of the union that the mind has with the whole of Nature” (TdIE, §13).</p><p>We find an apparently similar tri-partite structure in the last two parts of the <i>Ethics</i>. First, in the preface of Part IV, Spinoza notes that, “As far as good and evil are concerned, they also indicate nothing positive in things, considered in themselves, nor are they anything other than modes of thinking, or notions we form because we compare things to one another” (E4pref). Second, despite these limitations, we desire to form a model of human nature, whose very purpose is to provide a common standard of good.<sup>15</sup> An adequate idea of this model, some have argued, can be found in the discussion of the “free man” at the end of Part IV.<sup>16</sup> And then this model, in turn, is a stepping stone to the knowledge of God that serves as the basis of what Spinoza in Part V of the <i>Ethics</i> calls our “blessedness” [<i>beatitude</i>]: “From this we clearly understand wherein our salvation, or blessedness, or Freedom, consists, viz. in a constant and eternal Love of God, or in God's Love for men” (E5p36c).</p><p>But there are also some important differences between the early and later works, both in fine details and in the larger conceptual scheme. The language that Spinoza uses differs. In the TdIE, it is “true good,” which doesn't appear in the <i>Ethics</i>, but rather “certain good.” And, although we do see the “highest good” (E5p19dem) mentioned in both places, we now see descriptions of it that seem to emphasize the individual state of mind, such as the “highest satisfaction” [<i>summa acquiescentia</i>] (E5p38s) or blessedness, as we just saw (E5p36c). Spinoza only uses the word “union” [<i>unionis</i>] with God in the TdIE. In the <i>Ethics</i>, there is no such explicit conjunction between the individual and nature. We do find phrases like “God's love of men and the mind's intellectual love of God are one and the same” (E5p36c), which some might argue is more or less equivalent with the idea of a union. As we have seen, scholars disagree over whether the object of the third kind of knowledge is a finite essence or an infinite essence. Yet the fact that we need to argue for an interpretation of the highest good at this point indicates that there is at least a prima facie problem with any simple conception based on the dissolution of the individual.</p><p>The persistence of a gap between the finite individual and the infinite is suggested not only in the slightly different conceptual vocabulary utilized, but also in the amount and kind of work that is required to close the gap. In the early texts, Spinoza takes what might be considered as a neo-Stoic approach to ethical life, in which we arrive at the highest good primarily through the correction of our false judgments. There is room for the cognitive therapy of the passions, which he treats rather stoically as mistaken ideas, but there is little or no discussion of social and political life.<sup>17</sup> When we do come across political language, it is as a metaphor for our abject lack of autonomy, as is clearly seen in the <i>Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being (Korte Verhandeling</i>, or KV) where he writes, “it follows from this [the fact that we are part of nature and are determined by its laws] that we are truly God's servants—indeed, his slaves—and that our greatest perfection is to be such necessarily” (KV, Part 2, ch. 18.1; C127).</p><p>However, as I and others have argued, Spinoza's engagement with politics, expressed in the composition and publication of the TTP, changed his conception of the ethical project.<sup>18</sup> Spinoza does not merely require the philosopher to correct his ideas and conduct a cognitive therapy of the passions, he also enjoins him [and I am using the gendered term to remind us that Spinoza due to his prejudice excluded women as rational political agents] to participate in political life as a condition of the ethical life. We see this concretely in the adoption of Hobbesian concepts of the <i>conatus</i> (the desire to preserve oneself, E3p6), the claim that the foundation of virtue is self-preservation (E4p18s), the requirement of the freeman to engage with the state (E4p70s and especially E4p73), and the striking claim in the penultimate proposition that, “Even if we did not know that our Mind is eternal, we would still regard as of the first importance Morality, Religion, and absolutely all the things we have shown (in Part IV) to be related to Tenacity and Nobility” (E5p41).</p><p>These observations are interesting, but they are only suggestive, open to interpretative differences, and hardly decisive. Here I want to propose a sketch of a philosophical reading of Spinoza's conception of the good that places it more squarely in the acosmic tradition, but, as we shall see, with a twist. The basic idea is that the idea of the good that Spinoza proposes is fundamentally relational, but that it is only possible to understand this fact with certainty once we understand the point of view of the infinite, which itself is amoral. There are three points that support this claim:</p><p>The good does not exist independently of us, whether in God, in nature, or in some third realm; rather, it is a projection of our desire onto the world.<sup>19</sup> On this level, our understanding of the good will prove to be unendingly relational, due to our shifting relations with the external world and even our shifting relation to our self, which proves to be far less stable or given than we had imagined it.<sup>20</sup></p><p>2) The attempts to ground these individual, relational conceptions of the good in a model of human nature, which can be either inadequately or adequately conceived, do add a layer of certainty, especially when they are adequate. When Spinoza defines the good at the beginning of Part IV, he writes, “By good I shall understand what we certainly know to be useful to us” (E4d1). Likewise, “By evil, however, I shall understand what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good” (E4d2). The useful could be just what we desire, hence the definition is consistent with the ontology of desire and value in Part III. Spinoza knows that this is a radically unstable definition, lacking any certainty, even from the point of view of the individual. Hence, when he provides an additional explanation, and writes, “On these definitions, see the preceding preface [208/18-22],” he refers us back precisely to the discussion of models of human nature, which are supposed to provide a stable, because intersubjective, basis for our value judgments.</p><p>However, even these models are always relational in some sense. In the case of an inadequate model of human nature, then we are faced with the problem that we are just conflating a set of particular experiences and the ideas of those experiences into a single idea that we falsely label as a “universal” (see E2p40s1).<sup>21</sup> In the case of an adequate model, the idea is more certain because it is based on properties that reason discerns are in the part and whole, i.e., common notions. Nonetheless, the idea is still relative to the set of properties in nature that we construct as “human,” which in turn are relative to other classifications of properties in the natural world. In other words, a meaningful, true idea of human nature, depends on the existence of particular properties and the differences with other patterns of properties in the world, all of which leads us to consider the order and system of nature itself that produces this infinite differentiation.</p><p>3) We can come to the realization through reason that Nature (or God) does not contain any intrinsic value. There is both a negative and positive aspect of this realization. The negative view is expressed clearly in the appendix to Part 1 of the <i>Ethics</i>. There, Spinoza argues that our traditional conceptions of God, his attributes, and His relation to nature are mostly due to an anthropomorphic projection of our mostly mistaken self-conceptions onto the order of nature itself. If we can argue for a positive conception of God that does not include these anthropomorphic properties, then we can not only understand that God does not have these properties but that he cannot have them. Two adjacent passages in the <i>Ethics</i> provide the best evidence that Spinoza thought something like this. First, Spinoza writes that “from this [i.e., that knowledge of evil is inadequate knowledge], it follows that if the human mind had only adequate ideas, it would form no notion of evil” (E4p64c). But this is inadequate because it is consistent with the long theological and philosophical tradition of seeing evil as a lack or something that has no reality at all. Thus, Spinoza makes a second, more comprehensive point: “If men were born free, they would form no concept of good and evil so long as they remained free” (E4p68). Those who reason call into question the human projections of value onto nature and know that, since the definition of good is relational, a being that did not have relations would not have any conception of the good, and yet we also know, from the starting point of our own experience, that we inevitably form conceptions of good and evil, and we can see on the basis of reason that it is our nature to do so. When we glimpse the perspective of God, then we see the infinitely perspectival and, insofar as we use models of various kinds, the recursive nature of the good.</p><p>The conclusion is that when we understand that our own sense of value is relational and that God does not have any fundamental values that might ground them in any deeper sense than the complex patterns we experience in nature, then we can embrace the idea of an infinitely qualified sense of value, in which we sometimes manage to agree with one another but more often than not disagree. In other words, we have an explanation of our moral world.</p><p>The reason appears to be that the very nature of an explanation requires an ultimate <i>how</i>, which an endless regress can in principle simply never satisfy.</p><p>However, hopefully, now we can see that a commitment to this explanatory condition leads to an unpalatable dilemma when it comes to the nature of the Good, at least in Spinoza, namely, that it couldn't be conceived except as infinitely relational.</p><p>The nature of the good in Spinoza's system is obviously a very complex topic, and my purpose here is hardly to give even a basic let alone an exhaustive account of it. Nonetheless, the scant few texts I have cited should allow me to make a couple of observations that are germane to the problem of the moral aspect of acosmism.</p><p>Spinoza can't be committed to the independence of some conception of the good that precedes, logically speaking, the system itself. Nor can he be committed to the entire dissolution of the idea of the good in either the unification of the individual with God (as in the early writings) or the intellectual love of God (in the later writings, which, as I have argued, are more ambiguous about the status of the subject). Somehow, we must avoid this Scylla and Charybdis and search for an alternative, one that allows us to maintain the paradox that we have discerned at the heart of the system. That is, we achieve the highest good when we realize that there is no ultimate good, that is, a good that is unqualified.</p><p>I said at the beginning that I thought we could use the logic of deterrence in <i>Dr. Strangelove</i> to help us understand some of the problems of acosmism. Let me now suggest in conclusion that we can use it as the blueprint for a solution to the moral problem. Let's call it the reverse Strangelove paradox: instead of saying that we need to threaten to destroy the world to save it, let us say that we need to embrace the world in order to destroy it. Or call it, if you'd like, the Parmenidean descent, which, as Della Rocca notes, is a possible translation of the Greek <i>katabasis</i>, though one he rejects for both rhetorical and philosophical reasons.<sup>22</sup> What we discover when we follow the PSR and ascend to the level of substance is that the world of finite beings is essential to the possibility of making sense of the highest good. And so we must, following the discovery of the logic of the Good, or what the PSR reveals about what the nature of the good is, namely, the endless recursive definition of it in terms of finite relations, descend back into the midst of endless relations precisely to find a reason to accept the One. Thus, contrary to Della Rocca's Wittgensteinian point, we cannot do away with the ladder. Rather, we must embrace it.</p><p>The good for any finite thing is always defined in relation to itself and to other finite things (even if we conflate them into an imaginative universal or discover some true property that they share in common). However, what we discover as we know the nature of God is that what is One, the infinite substance or nature or God, does not have any relations in its essence. For that reason, Spinoza thinks that substance is, as Nietzsche would later put it, “beyond good and evil.” But if we are to be motivated to pursue the demands of reason, we must seek the good for us, that is, as finite beings. So, instead of throwing away the ladder, and doing away with morality altogether, which Spinoza recognizes would be the case (and I don't know if Della Rocca thinks this or not), the paradoxical result is that we must cycle back from the One to the Many, which is the very source of the motivation to achieve this state of knowledge. If this is true of morality, then perhaps this dynamic might be true of every other domain as well. Instead of doing away with the many, the search for the One motivates us to return to our finite natures.<sup>23</sup> Whether we take this seriously or as yet another fictional satire, will be the subject of the sequel.<sup>24</sup></p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46958,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY\",\"volume\":\"33 1\",\"pages\":\"354-364\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2025-03-18\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13057\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13057\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13057","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

我想从一部电影开始:《奇爱博士》或《我如何学会停止担忧并爱上炸弹》。这部1964年的电影由斯坦利·库布里克执导,彼得·塞勒斯主演,讽刺了冷战时期的国防体制。影片讲述了基地指挥官杰克·d·里珀(Jack D. Ripper)将军(斯特林·海登(Sterling Hayden)饰演)的叛变故事,他利用通信系统故障,派遣他的B-52轰炸机中队攻击苏联。参谋长联席会议主席巴克·特吉德森将军(乔治·c·斯科特饰)向美国总统发出了这一可怕事态的警告,他试图与苏联总统基索夫总理达成协议,以获得有限的比例反应,但他惊讶地发现,他的顾问、前纳粹科学家奇爱博士告诉他,苏联最近启动了一个“世界末日”装置,其目的是通过立即引发一场毁灭整个世界的大火来阻止一次袭击。无论是来访的英国军官莱昂内尔·曼德拉克(Lionel Mandrake)上校,还是苏联防空系统,在试图阻止这次袭击失败后,聚集在作战室的国防官员们只能考虑他们唯一的选择,那就是把政府高官聚集在一个地下深处的掩蔽处,在那里他们将努力重新繁衍世界。最后,一架由t.j.“金刚”少校驾驶的轰炸机成功通过,运送了有效载荷,引发了世界末日。最后一幕是奇爱博士从轮椅上站起来,欣喜若狂地喊道:“我的爸爸,我能走路了!”然后切换到巨大的核蘑菇云在空中爆炸的场景,伴随着忧郁的歌曲“我们会再见面”。这是一部伟大的电影,毫无疑问是一部经典之作,如果你还没有看过,你应该去看看。但我为什么要在这里提出来?答案是,在我看来,它完美地说明了无宇宙论的本质。当我在读迈克尔·德拉·罗卡的新书《巴门尼德的崛起》时,我几乎立刻想到了这个故事。起初,我试图忽略它,认为这只是一种油嘴滑舌的联想,但当它再次出现时,我意识到我的哲学无意识在对我说话,也许我应该注意它。以下是一些比较点。重点是威慑的末日原则。半途而废的措施加起来并没有多大意义。如果你想保护世界,那么你必须威胁要彻底摧毁它。有一个疯狂的科学家,奇爱博士,他的名字就体现了这个悖论。他是体系本身的设计者之一,巴门尼德式的人物。值得注意的是,在电影中,这个角色有一个可疑的过去,作为一个极权帝国的仆人,也是一个软弱的角色。与头脑简单、大胆地执行毁灭世界任务的金刚大相反,在最后,当没有人能阻止叛变的炸弹手时,我们了解到,奇爱博士并没有完全遵守他所阐述的原则。他私下里是一个“驯服者”,即使世界上的其他地方都被摧毁了,他仍然相信一小群精英将在一个深矿中生存下来,这个深矿是为放射性未来的持续时间而储备的,其唯一目的是培育一个新的种族,重新繁衍世界。一个是煽动者杰克·d·里珀将军(General Jack D. Ripper),他对纯度的病态担忧引发了整个事件,主要原因是他害怕往水中添加氟化物。尽管他多疑,他还是很通情达理的。他会问正确的问题。如果我们投入了这么多时间和精力来开发这个项目,并且我们有一个有效的系统,那么为什么不使用它呢?现代理性主义者。开膛手的对手是队长莱昂内尔·曼德拉克,他试图用常识和开膛手讲道理。卓越的“驯兽师”,英国的常识哲学家。他注定无能为力。还有一位忠诚的士兵:金刚少校(Major T. J. King Kong),他指挥的B-52轰炸机避开了苏联的防空系统。金刚由著名的前牛仔表演者和西片明星“斯利姆”皮肯斯饰演,他一心一意地为自己的职责所驱使。当他驾驶的飞机的炸弹门卡住时,他下降到野兽的腹部来解决这个问题。他真的骑着炸弹冲向目标,高兴地大喊大叫,因为他开始了世界末日的场景和世界末日。这个形象是哲学家f·h·布拉德利(F.H. Bradley)给理想贴上的“快乐的思想自杀”的缩影。当然,影片中最重要的角色是炸弹,也就是PSR(充分理由原则)。技术不仅完成了工作,而且决定了系统的价值,它是系统的核心。 讽刺的目的是什么?让我们记住,尽管这部电影欢快地讲述了世界是如何被摧毁的,但该系统的目的是威慑,也就是说,保护世界。在影片的边缘,这部电影思考了一些明显而重要的问题:一个没有任何生物的世界会是什么样子?这样一个世界的价值是什么?不过,有些人可能会说,这些问题并不是这部电影真正的重点。真正的问题是要突出被选择用来保护世界的工具的无效。威慑的批评者和支持者都有同样的担忧。虽然批评者会指出威慑的愚蠢,因为它增加了我们想要保护的世界可能被摧毁的机会,但支持者只会说,基于同样的理由,我们只需要纠正和改进我们现有的系统。这是一场关于手段而非目的的辩论。当然,沿着这些思路,库布里克也想指出从体制中受益的人身上暴露出的虚伪。系统发明者的秘密驯服策略表明,他们确实关心有限的存在。问题在于,这表明他们只看重自己的生命,而不看重其他将要被毁灭的人的生命。但讽刺的颠覆性目的可能比质疑威慑体系的工具价值或指出其支持者的虚伪更为险恶。更确切地说,这部电影的重点是完全不同的,也就是说,系统的技术不再是维护其他一些价值观的工具——比如本世纪中叶美国资本主义的荣耀或苏联版的共产主义——而是系统本身的真正意义。我们需要一个精密的系统来维持核弹,但表面上武器的目的是防止战争,这与整个威慑原则的关键是破坏本身这一事实相违背。库布里克认为,这就是这个体系的终极价值,正如电影中真正的英雄在接受它时用他们的行动所展示的那样。黑格尔对斯宾诺莎的批判在形式上不是喜剧式的,而是直接的哲学式的。他的目的是表明斯宾诺莎的泛神论——认为自然和上帝是一体的观点——会导致一种反常的结果——否认世界上除了上帝之外的所有事物都是真实的——换句话说,无宇宙论。尽管如此,与库布里克电影的比较在两个方面是有用的。首先,这部电影,正如我所希望展示的,揭示了黑格尔论证的结构。另一方面,黑格尔的论点在依赖讽刺效果和隐含的道德和社会批判方面,分享了文学讽刺的一些元素。然而,与库布里克的《奇爱博士》相比,黑格尔版本的讽刺远没有那么凄凉。如果我把两种传统的讽刺作品区分开来,你就会明白我的意思了:一种是假设一种道德愿景,并为之服务;另一个则更为黑暗,对道德价值本身的可能性提出了质疑。黑格尔给出了第一个版本。正如伊扎克·梅拉米德(Yitzhak Melamed)提醒我们的,黑格尔对斯宾诺莎的解读依赖于弗里德里希·海因里希·雅柯比(Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi)的解读,但也截然不同(79)和黑格尔一样,雅可比想用斯宾诺莎的观点作为一种警告,尽管他的恐惧更为极端。雅可比认为,斯宾诺莎不仅抹杀了有限的东西(“因此,个别的事物,只要它们只存在于某一特定的规定性中,就是非一体的”[220]),而且抹杀了无限的东西,至少在雅可比看来,无限既不可能有智力也不可能有意志(222),与传统的上帝观念有任何相似之处,由此得出结论,斯宾诺莎不仅是一个无神论者(“斯宾诺莎主义是无神论”233),而且是一个虚无主义者相反,黑格尔认为斯宾诺莎是一种宗教思想家,尽管他犯了大错。正如他所写的,“无神论的指控,过去常常被用来反对哲学(认为它与上帝的关系太少),现在变得越来越少了;泛神论的指控越来越普遍,认为它与上帝的关系太多了。”对黑格尔来说,泛神论导致无宇宙论。许多学者对泛神论的问题进行了详细的讨论。简而言之,黑格尔认为,对斯宾诺莎来说,唯一实际存在的东西是一个单一的实体它是简单的,但包含思想和延伸。他所说的,在自身之内的实体有两种规定,一种是普遍的,自为存在,另一种是特殊的,只是以一种依赖的方式存在。黑格尔认为斯宾诺莎的许多区别——属性之间的区别以及属性与模式之间的区别——是没有理由的,而只是预设的。他似乎赞同“一切决定都是否定”这一基本原则,尽管它在斯宾诺莎体系中的应用方式和范围尚不清楚。 最关键的是,黑格尔认为斯宾诺莎没能解释有限是如何从无限推导出来的。不仅斯宾诺莎观点的结果有问题,其正当性也有问题。当然,对这些说法存在大量争论。一些学者不同意这种观点,认为这是对斯宾诺莎体系的讽刺,而另一些学者则认为这种观点有其可取之处。我想重点关注的一个指控,与他的道德形而上学有关。黑格尔对泛神论的批判背后和动机是他自己对道德形而上学基础的实质观点。当他通过展示无宇宙论(对有限主体的否定)如何由此产生而对泛神论进行批判时,他已经有了另一种道德概念,主要基于他对上帝和我们作为有限存在的主体性的概念,这是他的论点的依据。对于黑格尔来说,斯宾诺莎在这方面的问题在于,本体论的基本原则,实体,并没有表现出主体性原则。他对物质的概念是抽象的,不是有生命的和有生命的。需要澄清的是,我并不是说黑格尔只是有一些武断的道德立场,与斯宾诺莎的观点形成对比。他认为他对神圣和有限的主体性以及由此产生的道德和政治体系的观点有一个合理的解释。关键是,如果我们接受斯宾诺莎的观点,即理性将我们引向一个无差别的上帝,这破坏了有意义的道德生活的可能性,那么我们对理性本身或理性所发现的基本概念的看法肯定是不充分的。对黑格尔来说,解释的计划与它的道德内容从来没有区别。在这一点上,他明确地将斯宾诺莎的观点与“东方”思想和宗教进行了比较,并将其归类为一个例子正如保罗·弗兰克斯(Paul Franks)所说,贝尔已经将斯宾诺莎与东方联系在一起,并随后在其他思想家中成为一种司空见惯的现象(154)。在《逻辑学百科全书》中,据报道,黑格尔曾说:“斯宾诺莎是犹太人的后裔,在他的哲学中,以思维形式表现出来的东西,一般都是基于东方的直觉,根据这种直觉,一切有限的东西都只不过是暂时的东西,是正在消失的东西。”静止的和未分化的实体不是一个值得尊敬的上帝。相反,他是一个抽象版的暴君,把他的臣民当作工具或不存在的东西。被试者,反过来,有了这种奇怪的自我概念,就好像他们不存在一样,也就是说,就像奴隶一样。因此,对黑格尔来说,无宇宙论是对适当秩序的拙劣模仿。它是对一种宗教体系的恶搞,在这种体系中,上帝以天意指引世界;模仿:对一种哲学体系的模仿,其中的行为是通过主体的活动来决定的;以及对以自由为主导价值的道德和政治体系的拙劣模仿。诚然,斯宾诺莎声称他捍卫的是一个强大的自由概念,这是他体系的核心,但由于他对自由意志和神圣天意的攻击,他很难为自己辩护。这是一个很好的过渡点,回到对迈克尔·德拉·罗卡的书《巴门尼德的崛起》的讨论。德拉·罗卡和黑格尔有一些重要的共同点。德拉·罗卡和黑格尔都对斯宾诺莎和非宇宙论感兴趣。但它们在几个方面也有所不同。一方面,虽然德拉·罗卡是一位迷人的作家,但黑格尔写了很多浮夸的散文。更重要的是,德拉·罗卡几乎没有讽刺的意图。虽然他有很好的幽默感,这是他经常表现出来的,但他对非宇宙主义的拥抱是致命的认真。(有趣的是,尽管斯宾诺莎显然处于背景中,正如他在几处提到的那样,很少或根本没有对斯宾诺莎的系统讨论。这也许是因为,至少在他的阅读中,斯宾诺莎不是口译家中常见的驯服者之一。斯宾诺莎是唯一一个可以被解读为遵循自己原则的理性主义者,他不属于他给我们的失败名单。德拉·罗卡指出,正如f·h·布拉德利所理解的那样,这种失败的“症结”是“理性主义反对相关关系的现实,从而反对分化的实体、行动、知识或意义的现实”(xvi)。那么,这种观点是,如果我们遵循理性的要求,我们可以解释世界,而不依赖任何原语,不陷入无限的倒退,也不陷入恶性循环。通过消除所有关系以及由此产生的对世界的不同体验。事实上,他把它留到另一个场合,这表明他也意识到这个话题的重要性。我认为道德领域不仅仅是我们可以应用PSR的许多哲学问题之一,而且以一种特殊的方式与PSR本身的应用联系在一起。 这个答案是否足够——我怀疑德拉·罗卡并不这么认为——我会在最后再回到这个问题上。但现在提出这个问题的关键是,我认为斯宾诺莎确实认为这个问题是他研究的核心。在德拉·罗卡关于布拉德利的《表象与现实》的文章中,他确实把布拉德利和斯宾诺莎联系了起来,但除了指出斯宾诺莎似乎也赞同通过对“一”的认识来克服关系的观点外,他没有考虑布拉德利自己的道德哲学,也没有提出布拉德利的观点对他自己的影响我想说的是,除非我们提供一个项目本身的道德动机的解释,也就是PSR的道德内容,否则我们不能满足于这种扔掉梯子的姿态。现在让我们来谈谈斯宾诺莎。对斯宾诺莎的宇宙解读的兴趣已经复苏,并就其在斯宾诺莎体系中的应用程度进行了辩论。有些人主张系统中有限的个人是实在的,尽管是有限制的;另一些人则认为它最终是不真实的在这里,我想把重点放在宇宙解读的道德问题上。首先,我想谈谈斯宾诺莎体系的发展,以及它如何揭示他对最高善的本质的看法。然后我将转向他对善的意义的分析,以及它对最高善的本质的影响。过了一会儿,他宣布他有了真善的概念(§12),然后在下一节中,他分三步告诉我们这最高的善是什么。首先,我们必须认识到,“对事物的好与坏只是在某一方面说的”,从永恒的观点来看,没有事物本身是好或坏的其次,我们必须认识到,由于我们的软弱,我们没有把握永恒的观点,因此“人设想的人性比他自己的更强大、更持久”(《圣经》第13节)。(这一点的一个重要推论是,我们开始意识到我们可以获得这种天性,并且我们寻求这样做的方法。)第三,我们认识到这种理想的人性“是心灵与整个自然相结合的知识”(TdIE,§13)。在《伦理学》的后两部分,我们发现了一个明显类似的三方结构。首先,在第四部分的序言中,斯宾诺莎指出,“就善与恶而言,它们也没有在事物中表明任何积极的东西,就其本身而言,它们也不是别的,只不过是思维方式,或者是我们因为将事物相互比较而形成的概念”(E4pref)。第二,尽管存在这些限制,我们仍希望形成一种人性的模型,其目的就是提供一种共同的善的标准足够的这个模型的想法,一些人认为,可以在“自由的人”的讨论结束时IV.16一部分,然后这个模型中,反过来,是上帝的知识的基础,是斯宾诺莎的第五部分道德所说的我们的“幸福”【祝福】:“从这个我们清楚地理解所拯救,或幸福,或自由,包括viz.常数和永恒的爱的神,或者神的爱对男人”(E5p36c)。但在早期和后期的作品之间,无论是在细节上还是在更大的概念方案上,都有一些重要的区别。斯宾诺莎使用的语言不同。在TdIE中,它是“真正的善”,在伦理学中没有出现,而是“一定的善”。而且,尽管我们确实在两处都看到了“至善”(E5p19dem),但我们现在看到的对它的描述似乎更强调个人的精神状态,比如“至善”(E5p38s)或幸福,正如我们刚才看到的(E5p36c)。斯宾诺莎在TdIE中只使用了与上帝的“联合”这个词。在伦理学中,个人与自然之间没有这种明确的联系。我们确实发现了像“上帝对人的爱和心灵对上帝的理智的爱是同一的”这样的短语,有些人可能会认为这或多或少等同于一种结合的观念。正如我们所看到的,学者们对第三种知识的对象是有限本质还是无限本质存在分歧。然而,在这一点上,我们需要论证对最高善的解释,这一事实表明,任何基于个人解体的简单概念,至少都存在一个初步的问题。有限的个体和无限的个体之间的差距的持续存在,不仅体现在所使用的概念词汇略有不同,而且体现在缩小这一差距所需的工作量和种类上。在早期的文本中,斯宾诺莎采取了一种可能被认为是新斯多葛派的伦理生活方式,在这种方式中,我们主要通过纠正错误的判断来达到最高的善。 书中有对激情进行认知治疗的空间,他相当坚忍不拔地将其视为错误的观念,但书中很少或根本没有对社会和政治生活进行讨论当我们遇到政治语言,是作为一个隐喻为我们可怜的缺乏自主权,显然是看到神在短期专著,男人和他的幸福(科特Verhandeling或KV),他写道,“它遵循从这个(我们是自然的一部分,是由它的法律),我们是真正的上帝的servants-indeed,他的奴隶和我们最大的完美是这样一定”(KV,第2部分,ch。18.1;C127)。然而,正如我和其他人所争论的那样,斯宾诺莎对政治的参与,在TTP的组成和出版中表达出来,改变了他对伦理工程的概念斯宾诺莎不仅要求哲学家纠正自己的想法,对激情进行认知治疗,他还要求哲学家(我用性别术语来提醒我们,斯宾诺莎由于他的偏见,将女性作为理性的政治代理人排斥在外)作为伦理生活的条件,参与政治生活。我们可以从以下几个方面看到具体的例子:霍布斯的conatus概念(保存自我的愿望,E3p6),美德的基础是自我保存的主张(e4p18),自由人与国家交往的要求(e4p70,尤其是E4p73),以及倒数第二个命题中引人注目的主张,“即使我们不知道我们的心灵是永恒的,我们仍然会把道德、宗教、以及我们(在第四部分)所展示的与坚韧和高贵有关的所有东西”(E5p41)。这些观察结果很有趣,但它们只是暗示性的,对解释上的差异是开放的,而不是决定性的。在这里,我想对斯宾诺莎的善的概念提出一个哲学上的解读,把它更直接地放在宇宙传统中,但是,正如我们将看到的,有一个扭曲。其基本思想是,斯宾诺莎提出的善的观念,在根本上是相互关联的,但只有当我们理解了无限的观点,才有可能确切地理解这一事实,而无限本身就是非道德的。有三点可以支持这一观点:善不是独立于我们而存在的,无论是在上帝中,在自然界中,还是在某个第三领域中;相反,它是我们的欲望投射到世界上在这个层面上,我们理解的好会无休止的关系,由于我们将与外部世界的关系,甚至我们的关系转移到自我,这是远比我们想像得更不稳定或者it.202)试图地面这些个人,关系的概念在人性的一个模型,可以充分不充分或构思,添加一层确定性,特别是当它们足够了。当斯宾诺莎在第四部分开始定义善时,他写道:“通过善,我将理解我们当然知道对我们有用的东西”(E4d1)。同样,“然而,通过邪恶,我将理解我们当然知道阻止我们成为某些善的主人”(E4d2)。有用的东西可能就是我们所渴望的东西,因此这个定义与第三部分的欲望和价值本体论是一致的。斯宾诺莎知道,这是一个根本不稳定的定义,缺乏任何确定性,即使从个人的观点来看也是如此。因此,当他提供了一个额外的解释,并写道,“关于这些定义,参见前面的序言[208/18-22],”他把我们精确地引回到对人性模型的讨论,这些模型被认为为我们的价值判断提供了一个稳定的,因为主体间性的基础。然而,即使这些模型在某种意义上也是相互关联的。在一个不充分的人性模型的情况下,我们面临的问题是,我们只是把一系列特殊的经验和这些经验的想法合并成一个单一的想法,我们错误地贴上了“普遍”的标签(见E2p40s1)在适当的模型中,观念是更确定的,因为它是建立在理性所识别的部分和整体的性质上的,即共同的观念。尽管如此,这个想法仍然是相对于我们作为“人类”构建的自然属性的集合,而这些属性又相对于自然界中其他属性的分类。换句话说,一个有意义的、真正的人性观念,取决于特定属性的存在以及与世界上其他属性模式的差异,所有这些都引导我们考虑产生这种无限差异的自然本身的秩序和系统。3)我们可以通过理性来实现自然(或上帝)不包含任何内在价值。这种认识既有消极的一面,也有积极的一面。在《伦理学》第一部分的附录中,明确表达了否定的观点。 在书中,斯宾诺莎认为,我们对上帝的传统观念,他的属性,以及他与自然的关系,主要是由于我们错误的自我观念对自然秩序本身的拟人化投射。如果我们可以论证一个积极的上帝概念,它不包括这些拟人化的属性,那么我们不仅可以理解上帝没有这些属性,而且他也不可能拥有这些属性。《伦理学》中两个相邻的段落提供了斯宾诺莎有类似想法的最好证据。首先,斯宾诺莎写道:“从这一点(即,关于恶的知识是不充分的知识),可以得出结论,如果人类心灵只有足够的观念,就不会形成恶的概念”(E4p64c)。但这是不充分的,因为它与长期的神学和哲学传统是一致的,即把邪恶看作是一种缺失或根本没有现实的东西。因此,斯宾诺莎提出了第二个更全面的观点:“如果人类生而自由,那么只要他们保持自由,就不会形成善恶的概念”(E4p68)。那些理性的人质疑人类对自然的价值投射,他们知道,既然善的定义是关系的,一个没有关系的存在就不会有任何善的概念,然而我们也知道,从我们自己的经验开始,我们不可避免地形成了善与恶的概念,我们可以看到,在理性的基础上,这是我们的本性。当我们瞥见上帝的视角时,我们看到了无限的视角,只要我们使用各种各样的模型,善的递归本质。结论是,当我们明白我们自己的价值观是相互关联的,而上帝没有任何基本的价值观,这些价值观可能比我们在大自然中经历的复杂模式更深层地根植于它们,那么我们就可以接受一种无限限定的价值观,在这种价值观中,我们有时会设法达成一致,但更多的是不同意。换句话说,我们对道德世界有了解释。原因似乎是,解释的本质需要一个最终的“如何”,而无止境的回归原则上永远无法满足。然而,希望我们现在可以看到,对这个解释条件的承诺,导致了一个令人难以接受的困境,当涉及到善的本质时,至少在斯宾诺莎那里,也就是说,它只能被理解为无限的关系。在斯宾诺莎的体系中,善的本质显然是一个非常复杂的话题,我在这里的目的甚至很难给出一个基本的,更不用说详尽的描述了。尽管如此,我所引用的为数不多的几篇文章应该允许我对无宇宙论的道德方面的问题做出一些密切相关的观察。斯宾诺莎不能相信,某些先于体系本身的,善的概念是独立的。他也不能在个人与上帝的统一(如早期作品中)或对上帝的理智之爱(如我所论证的,在后期作品中,对主体的地位更为模糊)中,致力于善的观念的完全瓦解。无论如何,我们必须避开“锡拉”和“卡律布狄斯”寻找另一种选择,一种能让我们维持我们在系统中心发现的悖论的选择。也就是说,当我们意识到没有终极的善,即没有不合格的善时,我们就达到了最高的善。我一开始就说过,我认为我们可以用奇爱博士的威慑逻辑来帮助我们理解无宇宙论的一些问题。现在让我在结论中建议,我们可以把它作为解决道德问题的蓝图。让我们称之为反向奇爱悖论:与其说我们需要威胁要摧毁世界来拯救它,不如说我们需要拥抱世界来摧毁它。如果你愿意,也可以称之为巴门尼德血统,正如德拉·罗卡所指出的,这可能是希腊语katabasis的翻译,尽管他出于修辞和哲学的原因而拒绝了这个翻译当我们遵循PSR并提升到物质层面时,我们会发现,有限生命的世界对于理解最高善的可能性至关重要。因此,在发现了善的逻辑之后,或者在发现了《PSR》所揭示的善的本质之后,即在有限的关系中对善进行无穷无尽的递归定义之后,我们必须回到无穷无尽的关系中去寻找接受“一”的理由。因此,与德拉·罗卡的维特根斯坦观点相反,我们不能取消梯子。相反,我们必须拥抱它。任何有限事物的善总是根据它自身和其他有限事物的关系来规定的(即使我们把它们合并为一个想象的普遍,或发现它们共有的某种真正的性质)。 然而,当我们知道上帝的本性时,我们发现,那“一”,那无限的实体或自然或上帝,在本质上是没有任何关系的。因此,斯宾诺莎认为,正如尼采后来所说,物质是“超越善恶的”。但如果我们要被激励去追求理性的要求,我们就必须为我们自己,也就是作为有限生命,寻求好处。因此,与其抛弃梯子,抛弃道德,斯宾诺莎认为这是事实(我不知道德拉·罗卡是否这么认为),相反,矛盾的结果是,我们必须从“一”回到“多”,这是达到这种知识状态的动力源泉。如果道德是如此,那么这种动态可能也适用于其他领域。而不是放弃许多,寻找一个激励我们回到我们有限的本性不管我们是认真对待这件事,还是把它当作另一件虚构的讽刺作品,这都将是续集的主题
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Parmenides and Dr. Strangelove, Or How I Learned to Stop Worrying about Monism and Accept the World of Relations, at least for the sake of the Good

I want to start with a movie: Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb.1

This 1964 film, directed by Stanley Kubrick, and starring Peter Sellers in multiple roles, satirizes the Cold War defense establishment. It tells the story of a renegade base commander, General Jack D. Ripper, played by Sterling Hayden, who takes advantage of a malfunction in the communications system to send his wing of B-52 bombers to attack the Soviet Union. When the President of the United States is alerted to this dire state of affairs by the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, General Buck Turgidson, played by George C. Scott, he tries to make a deal with his Soviet counterpart, Premier Kissov, for a limited proportional response, but is startled to discover, as his advisor, the former Nazi scientist, Dr. Strangelove, informs him, that the Soviets have recently activated a “Doomsday” device, whose purpose is to deter a single attack by immediately triggering a conflagration that would destroy the entire world. After failed attempts to thwart the attack, whether by the visiting British officer, Group Captain Lionel Mandrake, at Burpelson Airbase, or by the Soviet Air Defense system, the defense officials gathered in the War Room are left to contemplate their only option, which is to gather top government officials in a deep underground shelter, where they will work to repopulate the world. At the end, one bomber, piloted by Major T. J. “King” Kong, manages to get through to deliver the payload and trigger Armageddon. The final scene is of Dr. Strangelove getting out of his wheelchair, exclaiming ecstatically, “Mein Führer, I can walk!,” which then cuts to scenes of giant nuclear mushroom clouds exploding in the air accompanied by the melancholy song, “We'll meet again.”

This is a great movie, undoubtedly a classic, and you should see it, if you haven't already. But why am I bringing it up here? The answer is that, in my view, it perfectly illustrates the nature of acosmism. As I was reading Michael Della Rocca's recent book, The Parmenidean Ascent, this was the story that almost immediately came to mind. At first, I tried to ignore it, thinking that it was just a glib association, but when it came back again, I realized that my philosophical unconscious was speaking to me and that perhaps I should pay attention to it. Here are some of the points of comparison.

The main point is the doomsday principle of deterrence. Half measures don't add up to much. If you want to preserve the world, then you must threaten to destroy it completely.

There is the mad scientist, Dr. Strangelove, whose very name embodies the paradox. He is one of the designers of the system itself, the Parmenides figure. One thing to note is that in the movie, this character has a dubious past, as a servant to a totalizing Reich, and also a weak character. In contrast to Major Kong, who has the simple-minded audacity to carry out his world-destroying duty, we learn in the end, when it becomes apparent that no-one can stop the renegade bomber, that Dr. Strangelove is not committed fully to the principle that he has articulated. He is secretly a “tamer” who, even as the rest of the world has been destroyed, embraces the idea that a small group of elites will survive in a deep mine, stocked for the duration of a radioactive future, whose only purpose will be to breed a new race of people to repopulate the world.

There is the instigator, General Jack D. Ripper: who unleashes the whole thing via a pathological concern for purity focused on his fear of fluoride being added to the water. Despite his paranoia, he can be quite reasonable. He asks the right questions. If we have devoted so much time and energy to developing this project, and we have a functioning system in place, then why not use it? The modern rationalist.

Ripper's counterpoint is the Group Captain Lionel Mandrake, who tries to reason with Gen. Ripper through appeals to common sense. The “tamer” par excellence, the British philosopher of common sense. He is doomed to be ineffectual.

Then there is the loyal soldier: Major T. J. “King” Kong, who commands the B-52 that eludes the Soviet air defense system. Played by the well-known former rodeo performer and star of Westerns, “Slim” Pickens, Kong is single-mindedly driven by his duty. When the bomb doors of the plane he is piloting become stuck, he descends into the belly of the beast to fix the problem. He literally rides the bomb to its target, whooping with joy, as he initiates the doomsday scenario and the end of the world. This image is the epitome of the “happy suicide of thought,” as the philosopher F.H. Bradley labeled the ideal.

The most important character of the film, of course, is the Bomb, a.k.a., the PSR (Principle of Sufficient Reason). It is the technology that not only gets the job done but determines the values of the system of which it is the heart.

What is the purpose of the satire? Let us remember that, although the movie gleefully recounts how the world is destroyed, that the purpose of the system was deterrence, that is, to preserve the world. At its margins, then, the film considers some obvious and important questions: What would a world without any living beings within it look like? What would the value of such a world be? Some would argue that these questions are not really the point of the film, though. The real issue is to highlight the inefficacy of the instrument chosen to protect the world. Both critics and proponents of deterrence share the same concerns. While a critic would point out the folies of deterrence, as it raises the chances that the very world we want to protect might be destroyed, a proponent would just say, on the very same grounds, that we simply need to correct and improve the systems that we have in place. It is a debate about the means and not the ends.

Of course, along these lines, Kubrick also wants to point out the hypocrisy, which is revealed among those that benefit from the system. The secret taming strategy of the inventors of the system reveals that they do care about finite existence. What is problematic about it is that it shows that they only value their own lives and not those of everyone else who will be destroyed.

But the subversive purpose of the satire might be something more sinister than either questioning the instrumental value of a system of deterrence or pointing out the hypocrisy of its advocates. Rather, the point of the film is something else entirely, namely, that the technology of the system is no longer an instrument to preserve some other set of values—say the glories of mid-century American capitalism or the Soviet version of communism—but itself the true meaning of the system. We need an elaborate system to maintain the bomb, but the ostensible purpose of the weapon—to prevent war—is belied by the fact that the key to the whole principle of deterrence is destruction itself. That, Kubrick suggests, is the ultimate value of the system, as the true heroes of the film demonstrate in their actions, when they embrace it.

Hegel's critique of Spinoza is not comedic in form but straightforwardly philosophical. He aims to show that Spinoza's pantheism—the view that nature and God are one—leads to a perverse effect—the denial that all things in the world except for God are real—in other words, acosmism. Nonetheless, the comparison to Kubrick's film is useful in two ways. For one thing, the film, as I hope to show, reveals something about the structure of Hegel's argument. For another, Hegel's argument shares some elements of literary satire in its reliance upon ironic effects and an implicit moral and social critique. In contrast to Kubrick's Dr. Strangelove, however, Hegel's version of satire is far less bleak. You might see what I mean if I distinguish between two traditional kinds of satire: one that assumes a moral vision and of which it is in service; and another one that is darker and calls into question the possibility of moral value itself. Hegel offers the first version. As Yitzhak Melamed reminds us, Hegel's reading of Spinoza depends on, but also starkly differs from that of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (79).2 Like Hegel, Jacobi wants to use Spinoza's views as a kind of warning, though his fear is more extreme. Jacobi thought that Spinoza had obliterated not only the finite (“Individual things, therefore, so far as they only exist in a certain determinate mode, are non-entia” [220]) but the infinite as well,3 at least in the sense that the infinite, which Jacobi thinks can have neither intellect nor will (222), has any resemblance to a traditional idea of God, which leads to the conclusion that Spinoza is not only an atheist (“Spinozism is atheism” 233) but also a nihilist.4 Hegel, in contrast, accepts Spinoza as a kind of religious thinker, albeit one who has gone horribly wrong. As he writes, “The charge of Atheism, which used often to be brought against philosophy (that it has too little of God), has grown rare: the more widespread grows the charge of Pantheism, that it has too much of him.”5 For Hegel, it is pantheism that leads to acosmism.

The problems with pantheism have been discussed in detail by many scholars. In a nutshell, Hegel thinks that for Spinoza the only thing that actually exists is a single substance.6 It is simple yet contains both thought and extension. There are, what he calls, two determinations of substance within itself, one that is universal and has being for itself, the other that is the particular and has being only in a dependent way. Hegel thinks that many of Spinoza's distinctions—among attributes and between attributes and modes—are not justified but only presupposed. He seems to endorse as a fundamental principle the notion that “all determination is negation,” even though it is unclear in the way and the extent of its application in Spinoza's system. Crucially, Hegel thinks that Spinoza fails to explain how the finite can be derived from the infinite. Not only are the consequences of Spinoza's view problematic, but so it its justification. Of course, there is a great deal of debate over these claims. Some scholars would disagree with them as a caricature of Spinoza's system, others would suggest that they have some merit. The one charge that I want to focus on, though, relates to the metaphysics of his morals.

What stands behind and motivates Hegel's critique of pantheism is his own substantive view of the metaphysical basis of morality. When he makes his critique of pantheism through showing how acosmism (the denial of finite subjects) results from it, he already has an alternative conception of morality, based primarily on his notion of subjectivity for God and for us, as finite beings, that is informing his arguments. For Hegel, the problem with Spinoza in this regard is that the fundamental ontological principle, substance, does not exhibit the principle of subjectivity. His idea of substance is abstract, not vital and alive (154). To be clear, I am not saying that Hegel simply has some arbitrary moral standpoint that he contrasts with that of Spinoza. He thinks that he has a rational justification for his view of divine and finite subjectivity and the moral and political system that follows from it. The point is that if we accept Spinoza's view, that reason leads us to an undifferentiated God, which undermines the possibility of meaningful moral life, then we must have an inadequate view either of reason itself or the fundamental concepts that reason has discovered. For Hegel, the project of explanation is never distinct from its moral content.

In this, he explicitly compares Spinoza's view to and categorizes it as an example of “Oriental” thought and religion.7 As Paul Franks remarks, Bayle had already made the association of Spinoza with the Orient, and it subsequently became a commonplace among other thinkers (154). In the Encyclopedia Logic, Hegel is reported to have said, “Spinoza was a Jew by descent, and what found expression in the form of thought in his philosophy is in general on the oriental intuition according to which everything finite appears merely as something transient, as something vanishing” (cited by Franks, 531). The static and undifferentiated substance is not a God to be venerated. Rather, he is an abstract version of a despot who treats his subjects either as tools or as non-existing. The subjects, in turn, with this strange conception of themselves act as if they don't exist, that is, as slaves.

Thus, for Hegel, acosmism is the parody of a proper order. It is the parody of a religious system, in which God directs the world providentially; the parody of a philosophical system in which actions are determined through the activity of subject; and the parody of a moral and political system, in which freedom is the reigning value. It is true that Spinoza claims that he defends a robust concept of freedom at the core of his system, but he has a hard time defending himself due to his attack on free-will and divine providence.

This is a good point to transition back to a discussion of Michael Della Rocca's book, The Parmenidean Ascent.8 Della Rocca and Hegel share some important features. Both Della Rocca and Hegel share an interest in Spinoza and Acosmism. But they also differ in several respects. For one thing, while Della Rocca is an engaging writer, Hegel produces a lot of turgid prose. More significantly, Della Rocca exhibits little or no satirical intent. Although he has a good sense of humor, which he frequently exhibits, he is deadly earnest in his embrace of Acosmism. (Interestingly, though Spinoza is clearly in the background, as he mentions in a couple of places, there is little or no systematic discussion of Spinoza. That is perhaps because, on his reading at least, Spinoza is not one of the tamers so common among interpreters. Spinoza is the only rationalist who could be read as living up to his own principles and doesn't belong among the list of failures that he gives us).

Della Rocca specifies that the “crux” of this failure, as F. H. Bradley understood, is the “rationalist argument against the reality of the relevant kind of relation, and hence against the reality of differentiated substance, action, knowledge, or meaning” (xvi). The idea, then, is that if we follow the demands of reason, we can explain the world without relying on any primitives, falling into an infinite regress, or getting trapped in a vicious circle, by doing away with all relations and the differentiated experience of the world that follows from them.

The fact that he has reserved it for another occasion is a sign that he is also aware of the importance of the topic. I would argue that the domain of the moral is not just one of many philosophical issues to which we can apply the PSR but connected in a special way to the employment of the PSR itself.

Whether this answer is sufficient—and I suspect that Della Rocca does not think that it is—is something that I return to at the end. But the point of bringing it up now is that I think that it is a problem that Spinoza does consider to be at the heart of his project. In Della Rocca's essay on Bradley's Appearance and Reality, he does link Bradley and Spinoza, but besides pointing out that Spinoza also seems to approve the idea of the overcoming of relations through knowledge of the One, he does not consider Bradley's own moral philosophy or suggest what the implications of Bradley's view might be for his own.9 I want to suggest that until we provide an account of the moral motivation of the project itself, that is, of the moral content of the PSR, then we cannot be satisfied with this gesture of throwing away the ladder.

Let us turn now to Spinoza. There has been a resurgence of interest in the acosmic reading of Spinoza and debates over the degree of its application within Spinoza's system. Some have argued for the reality, albeit qualified, of the finite individual in the system10; others for its ultimate unreality.11 Here I want to focus on the moral question of the acosmic reading. First, I want to say something about the development of Spinoza's system and how that sheds some light on how he conceives of the nature of the highest good. Then I will turn to his analysis of the meaning of the good and how that bears on the nature of the highest good.

Just a bit later, he announces that he has an idea of the true good (§12), and then in the following section he tells us in three steps in what this highest good consists. First, we have to realize that “good and bad are said of things only in a certain respect” and that from the point of view of the eternal nothing is in itself good or bad.14 Second, we must recognize that, due to our weakness, we do not grasp the point of view of the eternal, and hence “man conceives a human nature much stronger and more enduring than his own” (TdIE, §13). (An important corollary to this point is that we come to realize that we could acquire this nature and that we seek the means to do so.) Third, we realize that this ideal human nature “is the knowledge of the union that the mind has with the whole of Nature” (TdIE, §13).

We find an apparently similar tri-partite structure in the last two parts of the Ethics. First, in the preface of Part IV, Spinoza notes that, “As far as good and evil are concerned, they also indicate nothing positive in things, considered in themselves, nor are they anything other than modes of thinking, or notions we form because we compare things to one another” (E4pref). Second, despite these limitations, we desire to form a model of human nature, whose very purpose is to provide a common standard of good.15 An adequate idea of this model, some have argued, can be found in the discussion of the “free man” at the end of Part IV.16 And then this model, in turn, is a stepping stone to the knowledge of God that serves as the basis of what Spinoza in Part V of the Ethics calls our “blessedness” [beatitude]: “From this we clearly understand wherein our salvation, or blessedness, or Freedom, consists, viz. in a constant and eternal Love of God, or in God's Love for men” (E5p36c).

But there are also some important differences between the early and later works, both in fine details and in the larger conceptual scheme. The language that Spinoza uses differs. In the TdIE, it is “true good,” which doesn't appear in the Ethics, but rather “certain good.” And, although we do see the “highest good” (E5p19dem) mentioned in both places, we now see descriptions of it that seem to emphasize the individual state of mind, such as the “highest satisfaction” [summa acquiescentia] (E5p38s) or blessedness, as we just saw (E5p36c). Spinoza only uses the word “union” [unionis] with God in the TdIE. In the Ethics, there is no such explicit conjunction between the individual and nature. We do find phrases like “God's love of men and the mind's intellectual love of God are one and the same” (E5p36c), which some might argue is more or less equivalent with the idea of a union. As we have seen, scholars disagree over whether the object of the third kind of knowledge is a finite essence or an infinite essence. Yet the fact that we need to argue for an interpretation of the highest good at this point indicates that there is at least a prima facie problem with any simple conception based on the dissolution of the individual.

The persistence of a gap between the finite individual and the infinite is suggested not only in the slightly different conceptual vocabulary utilized, but also in the amount and kind of work that is required to close the gap. In the early texts, Spinoza takes what might be considered as a neo-Stoic approach to ethical life, in which we arrive at the highest good primarily through the correction of our false judgments. There is room for the cognitive therapy of the passions, which he treats rather stoically as mistaken ideas, but there is little or no discussion of social and political life.17 When we do come across political language, it is as a metaphor for our abject lack of autonomy, as is clearly seen in the Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being (Korte Verhandeling, or KV) where he writes, “it follows from this [the fact that we are part of nature and are determined by its laws] that we are truly God's servants—indeed, his slaves—and that our greatest perfection is to be such necessarily” (KV, Part 2, ch. 18.1; C127).

However, as I and others have argued, Spinoza's engagement with politics, expressed in the composition and publication of the TTP, changed his conception of the ethical project.18 Spinoza does not merely require the philosopher to correct his ideas and conduct a cognitive therapy of the passions, he also enjoins him [and I am using the gendered term to remind us that Spinoza due to his prejudice excluded women as rational political agents] to participate in political life as a condition of the ethical life. We see this concretely in the adoption of Hobbesian concepts of the conatus (the desire to preserve oneself, E3p6), the claim that the foundation of virtue is self-preservation (E4p18s), the requirement of the freeman to engage with the state (E4p70s and especially E4p73), and the striking claim in the penultimate proposition that, “Even if we did not know that our Mind is eternal, we would still regard as of the first importance Morality, Religion, and absolutely all the things we have shown (in Part IV) to be related to Tenacity and Nobility” (E5p41).

These observations are interesting, but they are only suggestive, open to interpretative differences, and hardly decisive. Here I want to propose a sketch of a philosophical reading of Spinoza's conception of the good that places it more squarely in the acosmic tradition, but, as we shall see, with a twist. The basic idea is that the idea of the good that Spinoza proposes is fundamentally relational, but that it is only possible to understand this fact with certainty once we understand the point of view of the infinite, which itself is amoral. There are three points that support this claim:

The good does not exist independently of us, whether in God, in nature, or in some third realm; rather, it is a projection of our desire onto the world.19 On this level, our understanding of the good will prove to be unendingly relational, due to our shifting relations with the external world and even our shifting relation to our self, which proves to be far less stable or given than we had imagined it.20

2) The attempts to ground these individual, relational conceptions of the good in a model of human nature, which can be either inadequately or adequately conceived, do add a layer of certainty, especially when they are adequate. When Spinoza defines the good at the beginning of Part IV, he writes, “By good I shall understand what we certainly know to be useful to us” (E4d1). Likewise, “By evil, however, I shall understand what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good” (E4d2). The useful could be just what we desire, hence the definition is consistent with the ontology of desire and value in Part III. Spinoza knows that this is a radically unstable definition, lacking any certainty, even from the point of view of the individual. Hence, when he provides an additional explanation, and writes, “On these definitions, see the preceding preface [208/18-22],” he refers us back precisely to the discussion of models of human nature, which are supposed to provide a stable, because intersubjective, basis for our value judgments.

However, even these models are always relational in some sense. In the case of an inadequate model of human nature, then we are faced with the problem that we are just conflating a set of particular experiences and the ideas of those experiences into a single idea that we falsely label as a “universal” (see E2p40s1).21 In the case of an adequate model, the idea is more certain because it is based on properties that reason discerns are in the part and whole, i.e., common notions. Nonetheless, the idea is still relative to the set of properties in nature that we construct as “human,” which in turn are relative to other classifications of properties in the natural world. In other words, a meaningful, true idea of human nature, depends on the existence of particular properties and the differences with other patterns of properties in the world, all of which leads us to consider the order and system of nature itself that produces this infinite differentiation.

3) We can come to the realization through reason that Nature (or God) does not contain any intrinsic value. There is both a negative and positive aspect of this realization. The negative view is expressed clearly in the appendix to Part 1 of the Ethics. There, Spinoza argues that our traditional conceptions of God, his attributes, and His relation to nature are mostly due to an anthropomorphic projection of our mostly mistaken self-conceptions onto the order of nature itself. If we can argue for a positive conception of God that does not include these anthropomorphic properties, then we can not only understand that God does not have these properties but that he cannot have them. Two adjacent passages in the Ethics provide the best evidence that Spinoza thought something like this. First, Spinoza writes that “from this [i.e., that knowledge of evil is inadequate knowledge], it follows that if the human mind had only adequate ideas, it would form no notion of evil” (E4p64c). But this is inadequate because it is consistent with the long theological and philosophical tradition of seeing evil as a lack or something that has no reality at all. Thus, Spinoza makes a second, more comprehensive point: “If men were born free, they would form no concept of good and evil so long as they remained free” (E4p68). Those who reason call into question the human projections of value onto nature and know that, since the definition of good is relational, a being that did not have relations would not have any conception of the good, and yet we also know, from the starting point of our own experience, that we inevitably form conceptions of good and evil, and we can see on the basis of reason that it is our nature to do so. When we glimpse the perspective of God, then we see the infinitely perspectival and, insofar as we use models of various kinds, the recursive nature of the good.

The conclusion is that when we understand that our own sense of value is relational and that God does not have any fundamental values that might ground them in any deeper sense than the complex patterns we experience in nature, then we can embrace the idea of an infinitely qualified sense of value, in which we sometimes manage to agree with one another but more often than not disagree. In other words, we have an explanation of our moral world.

The reason appears to be that the very nature of an explanation requires an ultimate how, which an endless regress can in principle simply never satisfy.

However, hopefully, now we can see that a commitment to this explanatory condition leads to an unpalatable dilemma when it comes to the nature of the Good, at least in Spinoza, namely, that it couldn't be conceived except as infinitely relational.

The nature of the good in Spinoza's system is obviously a very complex topic, and my purpose here is hardly to give even a basic let alone an exhaustive account of it. Nonetheless, the scant few texts I have cited should allow me to make a couple of observations that are germane to the problem of the moral aspect of acosmism.

Spinoza can't be committed to the independence of some conception of the good that precedes, logically speaking, the system itself. Nor can he be committed to the entire dissolution of the idea of the good in either the unification of the individual with God (as in the early writings) or the intellectual love of God (in the later writings, which, as I have argued, are more ambiguous about the status of the subject). Somehow, we must avoid this Scylla and Charybdis and search for an alternative, one that allows us to maintain the paradox that we have discerned at the heart of the system. That is, we achieve the highest good when we realize that there is no ultimate good, that is, a good that is unqualified.

I said at the beginning that I thought we could use the logic of deterrence in Dr. Strangelove to help us understand some of the problems of acosmism. Let me now suggest in conclusion that we can use it as the blueprint for a solution to the moral problem. Let's call it the reverse Strangelove paradox: instead of saying that we need to threaten to destroy the world to save it, let us say that we need to embrace the world in order to destroy it. Or call it, if you'd like, the Parmenidean descent, which, as Della Rocca notes, is a possible translation of the Greek katabasis, though one he rejects for both rhetorical and philosophical reasons.22 What we discover when we follow the PSR and ascend to the level of substance is that the world of finite beings is essential to the possibility of making sense of the highest good. And so we must, following the discovery of the logic of the Good, or what the PSR reveals about what the nature of the good is, namely, the endless recursive definition of it in terms of finite relations, descend back into the midst of endless relations precisely to find a reason to accept the One. Thus, contrary to Della Rocca's Wittgensteinian point, we cannot do away with the ladder. Rather, we must embrace it.

The good for any finite thing is always defined in relation to itself and to other finite things (even if we conflate them into an imaginative universal or discover some true property that they share in common). However, what we discover as we know the nature of God is that what is One, the infinite substance or nature or God, does not have any relations in its essence. For that reason, Spinoza thinks that substance is, as Nietzsche would later put it, “beyond good and evil.” But if we are to be motivated to pursue the demands of reason, we must seek the good for us, that is, as finite beings. So, instead of throwing away the ladder, and doing away with morality altogether, which Spinoza recognizes would be the case (and I don't know if Della Rocca thinks this or not), the paradoxical result is that we must cycle back from the One to the Many, which is the very source of the motivation to achieve this state of knowledge. If this is true of morality, then perhaps this dynamic might be true of every other domain as well. Instead of doing away with the many, the search for the One motivates us to return to our finite natures.23 Whether we take this seriously or as yet another fictional satire, will be the subject of the sequel.24

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
11.10%
发文量
82
期刊介绍: ''Founded by Mark Sacks in 1993, the European Journal of Philosophy has come to occupy a distinctive and highly valued place amongst the philosophical journals. The aim of EJP has been to bring together the best work from those working within the "analytic" and "continental" traditions, and to encourage connections between them, without diluting their respective priorities and concerns. This has enabled EJP to publish a wide range of material of the highest standard from philosophers across the world, reflecting the best thinking from a variety of philosophical perspectives, in a way that is accessible to all of them.''
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信