慈善与民主:两种权威

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Matthieu Debief
{"title":"慈善与民主:两种权威","authors":"Matthieu Debief","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12759","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In 2000, the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation tackled an issue concerning the American education system: unsatisfactory high school graduation rates and college entry rates, especially in urban school districts (Ravitch, <span>2011</span>). Between 2000 and 2008, this foundation donated more than $2 billion to 2600 schools across 45 US states. Bill and Melinda Gates's aim was clearly spelled out: they saw the K−12<sup>1</sup> education system as “obsolete”<sup>2</sup> and in need of drastic reforms (Ravitch, <span>2011</span>). The Gates Foundation's leaders observed that some schools in the United States could host up to 4000 or 5000 pupils, leading to the neglect of a portion of students who needed extra attention. Based on contemporary research and already-existing movements in civil society,<sup>3</sup> they concluded that smaller schools were the key to students’ success.</p><p>In a context of public budget cuts, not many school boards could refuse a multimillion-dollar philanthropic donation. Hence, the Gates Foundation started to distribute money all over the United States, tying its gifts to conditions that would promote an effectiveness-based conception of education. At first, schools were asked to restructure and split themselves into independent units of no more than 400 students. Later, performance-based pay for teachers and national-standards tests, serving as effectiveness yardsticks, became mandatory for funding.</p><p>Although this system benefited some schools, it created more problems than it solved in the great majority of cases. For example, the fragmentation of large schools into small autonomous units increased conflict and competition for resources and deprived students of a significant range of activities that were only provided in larger institutions. Praised in the beginning, the Gates program was sharply criticized in 2005 when the first evaluations came out. In 2008, the foundation's directors recognized the bad start of their program and mostly put the blame on the lack of receptivity of the schools they helped or on teachers’ lack of competence. A few months later, the foundation decided to all but shut the program down.</p><p>In a democracy, there are good reasons to believe that the making of collectively binding decisions about such public goods as school infrastructures, education programs, and teachers’ salary should be carried out by citizens or people who speak in their name. However, the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation's case shows a sense in which some people or organizations, by virtue of their private resources, have an additional and sometimes larger say on such questions. This raises the question whether the logics of democracy and philanthropy are compatible. The question is more pressing because philanthropic donations are generally tax subsidized, representing therefore a redirection of public money (Pevnick, <span>2013</span>) toward aims likely to advance donors’ personal interests.</p><p>Political philosophers have debated the role that philanthropy should have in liberal democratic states. On the one hand, a good amount of work argues that philanthropy should not assume a role in distributive justice, as private and voluntary redistribution of basic goods is too unreliable (Beerbohm, <span>2016</span>), might affect egalitarian values (Cordelli, <span>2012</span>), reinforces power asymmetries (Lechterman, <span>2021</span>), and constitutes a paternalistic type of assistance (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>). On the other hand, philanthropy may help promote social innovations (Reich, <span>2018</span>), foster a vibrant cultural life (Pevnick, <span>2013</span>), serve as a means for intergenerational justice (Cordelli &amp; Reich, <span>2016</span>), uphold public institutional action (Ceva, <span>2021</span>), or supplement the provision of goods unrequired by justice (Lechterman, <span>2021</span>). All in all, philanthropic actions have been praised for allowing a variety of interests to be included in collective decision-making while being criticized for the unequal manner by which it includes them (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>).</p><p>While many political philosophers have thus discussed the <i>normative</i> question of why philanthropy might or might not be desirable in a democracy, few have paused to address the prior and more fundamental <i>analytical</i> question of what, if anything, makes philanthropy inherently specific in such a way that it may raise issues of compatibility with democracy. I argue in this paper that, although philanthropy and democracy aim at the same goal, they instantiate two distinct forms of political authority. Political authority is the morally and legally legitimate power of an individual or institution to give direction to public action.<sup>4</sup> In a democratic society, such a direction-giving activity (the practice of authority) is carried out by collectively binding decision-making. I show how, while democratic practices enable people to make mutually binding decisions together, philanthropic acts allow them to give direction to public decisions and actions based on their own unilateral preferences. Building on this basic observation, I argue that philanthropic donations may be vectors of power, and when they are, they carry a specific form of authority that differs from that underpinning the democratic logic of authority.</p><p>This paper unfolds in the following way. I start with a brief sketch of democracy as a practice of authority (Section 2). I then offer a conceptual analysis of philanthropy, showing how it can be conceived of as an authority practice (Section 3). I then provide an overview of how we can conceive of the relationship between philanthropy and democracy (Section 4). Finally, I develop my account of philanthropy as an authority-constituting practice defined by the three constitutive rules of unilateralism; first &amp; third personality, and externality of currency (Section 5).</p><p>The aim of this work is primarily analytical. Hence, when I point to a divergent relation between the democratic and philanthropic logics of authority, I do not defend one practice against the other. Of course, as is often the case in political theory, my analytical and conceptual work may serve to elucidate further normative issues. For example, my discussion suggests that the analytical distinction that philanthropy and democracy are different decision-making tools, which can inform the normative question of what tool a polity should choose, knowing that the choice would change, for better or worse, the nature of the relationship between those implicated in those decisions. In this sense, while my primary interest in the paper is analytical, the distinction I shall draw can usefully inform future normative appraisals of the role of philanthropy in a democracy.</p><p>This paper inquiries into philanthropy within a particular mode of social and political organization: democracy. To gain a clear idea of what I mean when I point to a divergent relation between the democratic and philanthropic logics of authority, I briefly introduce the former concept. To do so, I build on Ceva and Ottonelli's (<span>2021</span>) paper “Second-Personal Authority and the Practice of Democracy”, which offers a descriptive (nonnormative) account of democracy.</p><p>Ceva and Ottonelli identify the basic features of the practice of democracy. They do not offer reasons why we should prefer democracy over other types of political organization, nor do they concern themselves with defining democracy. Their aim is rather to understand what making democratic decisions and living under these decisions involve. For Ceva and Ottonelli (<span>2021</span>), democracy is a rule-based social and political practice. That means that democratic practices are defined by a set of rules that instantiate special actions and relations that exist only within these rules. It also means that those who engage in the democratic practices are assigned specific rights in the form of normative power and roles in a way that is particular to this set of rules (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>).</p><p>One of the specific roles instantiated by democratic practices is that of maker of collectively binding decisions (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>). Democratic actors (i.e., citizens) wield the authority to make decisions together, either directly (e.g., through referenda) or indirectly (e.g., by electing representatives), and those decisions bind citizens according to a specific relationship of rights and duties. What characterizes and differentiates this authority from other types of decision-making power (such as monarchic or oligarchic) is the set of rules that constitute the logic of the democratic practice.</p><p>In Ceva and Ottonelli's paper, these constitutive rules are twofold. First, democratic authority is mutual (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>). Mutuality refers to how the democratic authority is <i>exercised</i>. It means that the democratic authority, and the decisions that result from it, is exercised jointly by all decision-makers. Eric Beerbohm (<span>2012</span>) suggests that this mutualism is what makes citizens both “cosubjects of the law and coauthors” (Beerbohm, <span>2012</span>, p. 44). This contrasts, for example, with the power of a queen, who can unilaterally enact laws that will constrain her people but not herself.</p><p>Second, democratic practices are also second-personal (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>). The notion of personality invoked here refers to the <i>source</i> of an authority, that is, the reasons that triggers person X's action. Second- personality is the idea that what triggers X's action is person Y's reasons, as in an I–you relationship (Darwall, <span>2006</span>). Democracy involves second-personality because of the specific type of rights that are instantiated during this practice. Democracy generates what are called <i>claim-rights</i>. Following a Hohfeldian analysis, those who hold this kind of right can claim (i.e., they are the source of) certain treatment from specific individuals: the duty bearers (Hohfeld, <span>1919</span>).</p><p>Say, for example, that I make an oral agreement (instantiating this specific type of aforementioned relationship between claim-rights and duties) with a friend giving him the right to use my guitar for a gig. By that agreement, my friend becomes bound by a duty to give me back my guitar at the end of the concert. Moreover, I will have the right to reclaim my guitar, and my friend will be the only person allowed to fulfill the duty. What triggers my friend's duty—his reason to give me back my guitar—is my claim-right. The practice of democracy binds citizens in their use of power in the same way. As all democratic citizens are claim-right holders, they also are duty bearers. This means that, for example, when citizens vote directly on a given topic,<sup>5</sup> it gives them the authority to collectively decide the content of a law and it binds those citizens to respect the content of the newly decided law because each of them has a claim-right and a duty toward the others. Thus, by virtue of their participating in the democratic practice, citizens become the owners and sources of each other's rights and duties. This leads Ceva and Ottonelli (<span>2021</span>) to note that “the relations between democratic voters constitute a new ‘we,’ a collective of rights holders who, in that very capacity and no other, jointly recognize each other as the final authorities on their reciprocal claims and duties” (p. 6).</p><p>Mutualism hence enacts how the democratic authority is exercised (jointly by all decision-makers), while second-personality underlines the source of citizens’ reason for action (their reciprocal claim-rights and duties). I suggest adding a third constitutive rule of democratic authority to mutuality (<i>exercise</i>) and second-personality (<i>source</i>); it concerns the authority's <i>currency</i>. This rule concerns what gives an authority its effective action-power. By currency, I refer to the resources that empower the authority bearer in the making of collectively binding decisions. It is helpful to think about the currency of an authority as a token. In a democracy, citizens may only make use of one specific type of token. This token, which is at the root of all democratic decisions, is the democratic vote.<sup>6</sup> When citizens enter the democratic decision-making process, they are granted voting rights.</p><p>Voting rights as tokens reflect the basic idea of a one-person, one-vote system: they are at the same time unique and similar. They are unique because each citizen disposes of their own single token. But all tokens are similar in the sense that they are worth the exact same amount of power. When a citizen casts a vote, they exercise no more authority than any of their co-citizens. Moreover, these tokens only exist (i.e., have currency) within the democratic decision-making process. They do not exist prior to, after, or outside the democratic institution. Friends do not have this type of authority over each other, nor is this kind of authority possessed by virtue of citizenship relationships alone. For example, it is not enough that a group of friends democratically vote in favor of building a new theater for asking other people in the neighborhood to contribute to the project. Voting acquires its binding capacity on a given constituency only if carried out within a special institutional settings; it is democratic when this setting implicates every other citizen, as they are engaged in mutual and second-personal relationships.</p><p>I revisit the constitutive rules of democracy in Section 5 when I discuss their differences from those of philanthropy. Before I do that, I must characterize the practice of philanthropy.</p><p>Now that the background of this work has been set, I proceed with a conceptual analysis of philanthropy. This section allows me to introduce the conception of philanthropy as a social and political practice.</p><p>An unanimously accepted definition of philanthropy does not exist. Various terms, such as charity, nonprofit sector, third sector, benevolence, eleemosynary acts, and alms, describe the action or context of giving. For Jenny Harrow and Siobhan Daly, this is because philanthropy is a clustered and essentially contested concept. It is clustered because it is “capable of being multiply defined by multiple stakeholders, so that parallel understandings of its nature and purpose coexist in research” (Harrow, <span>2010</span>,p. 123), while its essential contestability is reflected by the internal complexity, diverse describability, the multidimensionality, as well as the continuous competition that exist between the different normative conceptualization of philanthropy (Daly, <span>2012</span>).</p><p>One of the many conceptions of philanthropy views it as a practice: “the voluntary contribution of private resources (usually money, but also in-kind goods or time) for broadly public purposes, and for which the giver does not receive payment in the ordinary sense (though she may receive inducements, thank-you gifts, or special consideration of other kinds, e.g., access to concert tickets). Such voluntary contributions may be made by groups or legal entities like corporations as well as by individuals” (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2019</span>, p. 1). More simply put, philanthropy can be outlined as the <i>voluntary commitment of private property for public purposes</i> (Ostrower, <span>1997</span>), as a social and political practice that is regulated by formal and informal rules (Lechterman, <span>2021</span>). From this perspective, philanthropy allows private individuals to have a say in what is considered of public interest.</p><p>Following this conception, I highlight four defining features of philanthropic practice. First, it can only be exercised by private individuals or organizations; it cannot be exercised by the state or its representative. A government can incentivize philanthropic actions, but it cannot give money or in-kind goods away in a philanthropic way. Let us imagine that, following a pandemic, elected officials decide to provide an exceptional grant, allocating money to their country's worst off. To fund this grant, the government decides to collect extra taxes from the richest 5%. It cannot be said that the people targeted by this grant benefited from charity from the richest 5%. They receive this money because, following a decision made with democratic logic, they have a claim-right to it, which triggers a second-personal reason for action by the taxpayers. This also differentiates philanthropy from actions exercised by public international organizations such as development-aid agencies, as in this case also the decision to provide resources emerges from public decisions. While states can be authors and recipients of charitable donations, only private individuals and organizations can make <i>philanthropic</i> donations.</p><p>Second, to be described as philanthropic, an action must aim at public purposes. For present purposes, I leave this concept somewhat open, as a public purpose can take many forms. However, not just any purpose can be considered as public. Following Lechterman (<span>2021</span>) “Public” can mean “open to all” (in the way that a “pub” is open to any customer with the means to pay for a drink), “universal” (in the way that “public utilities” are meant to cover all residents of a region), as well as “collectively authorized,” “collectively beneficial,” and “governmental.”<sup>7</sup> Consequently, “private” would rather refer to acts benefiting definite individuals. In this sense, nonpublic or private purposes would include market exchanges, parents’ inheritance to their children, gifts one makes to one of his or her friends, or again donations to clubs of which one is a member. The necessary condition of publicity is that any philanthropic act aims at virtually benefiting the greatest number, where “virtually” means that it should be accessible to anyone. Obviously, cases like donations to research against orphan disease, which may concern a very restricted number of patients, would still count as philanthropic under this framework. Similar conceptualizations of accessibility may be found in the Anglo-American context where it is stated that philanthropy should benefit an indefinite number.</p><p>Third, philanthropy must be voluntary, understood as not being coercively imposed. Taxes cannot be considered as philanthropy because the state uses its coercive power to force citizens to pay what they must and what they are duty bound to pay (Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2002</span>).</p><p>Fourth, philanthropy is concerned with the transfer of private property. If money is the first type of resource that comes to mind when one thinks about philanthropic donations, it is far from being the only one. Time, goods, and services may all be donated as well. While elite philanthropy is often characterized by the amount of money that flows through organizations such as foundations (MacKenzie, <span>2021</span>), cash is rarely the final contribution of these institutions. To be provided on a large scale, medical aid, new buildings, counseling, legal assistance, and water distribution may require a lot of money, but their recipients are not directly given cash.</p><p>In summary, philanthropy can be conceived of as a social and political practice, defined as being only exercised by private actors, aiming at a public purpose, being voluntary, and being concerned with the transfer of private property.</p><p>Before going further, it is important to clarify a point. It is often noted that the word <i>philanthropy</i> derives from the Greek for “love of humanity.” This etymology points to the conception of philanthropy as a motivation: “the love of humanity or concern for the common good (whether of humanity in general or of a more circumscribed group)” (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2019</span>, p. 1). Following this, as long as donors act with certain motives, they are acting philanthropically. However, I want to argue that the motives as well as moral standards underlying giving are not relevant to a political examination of philanthropy. Individuals have their own reasons for acting in a generous way. Maybe they do it because they think it is morally important, maybe simply because their pockets are too heavy, maybe to show the world that they are good human beings, or maybe to change society. What is crucial, however, is that whether the decision is made for X or Y reason does not substantially alter the kind of power one has when exercising authority derived from philanthropic acts.</p><p>In the case of the Gates Foundation, it has been demonstrated that its generous donation served to promote businesslike organization and new-public-management methods in schools (Ravitch, <span>2011</span>; Saltman, <span>2011</span>). After all, it is well known that philanthropy does not only derive from altruistic feelings (Andreoni, <span>1990</span>) but may be an instrument of private political advocacy or agenda setting (Reich, <span>2018</span>). However, this feature of philanthropy should not be seen as fundamentally problematic in liberal democracies. The Gateses’ program, after all, probably reflected a conception of education that was shared by many other US citizens at that time. And as citizens themselves, the Gateses are free to advocate for their preferred conception of education. Nevertheless, the tension raised by this case stems from the <i>way</i> this specific conception of education was conveyed to the public: it is one thing to cast a vote for businesslike organization in the education system, and another to bypass democratic processes by defining and setting the political agenda of a nation's education just because one has the resources to do so, as Bill and Melinda Gates did. But whatever the reasons one may have to practice philanthropy, the kind of authority that will emerge from it will remain the same.<sup>8</sup></p><p>One crucial point that the conceptual analysis of philanthropy as a practice exposed is that philanthropy and democracy are, to some extent, both pursuing public causes. They are both tools to give direction to concrete actions that may advance social justice, foster a vibrant cultural life, fund basic and higher education, nurture democratic innovation, advocate visions of a better society, or tackle health-related issues. Hence, philanthropy and democracy can be interpreted as different and possibly competing decision-making tools for public causes. One way to interpret the competition is that democratic societies in nonideal contexts may face scarcity of resources, and a choice may have to be made between public and private funding of goods and services. A second way, the one I am interested in here, concerns the different implications of philanthropy and democracy for the making of collectively binding decisions.</p><p>For many scholars, the most striking feature of philanthropy is that it allows donors to exercise a form of power that revolves around material resources (Beerbohm, <span>2016</span>; Cordelli, <span>2016, 2020</span>; Cordelli &amp; Reich, <span>2016</span>; Lambelet et al., <span>2019</span>; Lechterman, <span>2021</span>; Lechterman &amp; Reich, <span>2020</span>; Reich, <span>2018</span>; Saunders-Hastings, <span>2018, 2019</span>). Given that feature, most of them argue that philanthropy is at odds in democratic societies where decisions should, in principle, be taken collectively and equally. For Emma Saunders-Hastings, philanthropy “gives donors influence and authority, in public life and over particular beneficiaries. It shapes public options and the choices available to individuals” (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>, p. 5). Philanthropic foundations are, according to Rob Reich (<span>2018</span>), “institutional oddities in a democracy,” (p. 144) as they represent plutocratic, unaccountable, and nontransparent vehicle of political power, while, for Lechterman (<span>2021</span>), philanthropy is a form of private power with plutocratic tendencies.</p><p>These observations have flourished in a myriad of interesting normative propositions.<sup>9</sup> However, the issue lies in the fact that the aforementioned authors do not adequately inform us about what inherently distinguishes philanthropy in a way that might raise concerns regarding its compatibility with democracy. What remains lacking is a systematic analytical framework that delineates the fundamental differences between philanthropy and democracy concerning their roles in making collectively binding decisions.</p><p>Ryan Pevnick has taken an initial step in this direction. In his work “Philanthropy and Democratic Ideals,” while acknowledging the discomfort that philanthropy often experiences within democratic regimes, he expresses his aim: “My goal in this chapter is conceptual. I seek to move beyond the initial tension between philanthropy and democracy by providing a careful account of the role philanthropy might properly claim in a well-functioning democracy” (Pevnick, <span>2016</span>, p. 227). He accomplishes this by comparing the potential role of philanthropy in two distinct ideals of democracy: market democracy and democratic equality.</p><p>Market democracy and democratic equality, both grounded in fundamental liberal principles, diverge in their conceptions of individual citizens, governance, and justice. These differing conceptions yield contrasting assessments of the role philanthropy should assume within these democratic systems. Market democracies view individuals as responsible self-authors, governance revolves around a minimal government, and justice leans toward respecting market outcomes due to reasons of desert and efficiency (Pevnick, <span>2016</span>). Advocates of market democracy thus see philanthropy as pivotal in providing noncoercive aid and fostering self-governance. Conversely, democratic equality emphasizes individual citizens as equal participants in a cooperative scheme, features a deliberative democracy, and champions justice marked by liberal egalitarianism. While proponents of this democratic ideal might view philanthropy skeptically, fearing it might undermine the idea of a community governed by equality, Pevnick argues that democratic equality should endorse philanthropic support for cultural projects.</p><p>This comparison has the merit to suggest that although philanthropy and democracy may appear in tension within democratic societies, this does not automatically render them incompatible. The degree of compatibility hinges on the specific type of democracy, such as its conception of freedom or equality. However, while this work acknowledges the difference between philanthropy and democracy without asserting inherent contradiction, it falls short in providing a robust analytical account of what fundamentally distinguishes the two. This shortfall arises because Pevnick's conceptual differentiation relies on normative ideals of democracy.</p><p>One approach to circumvent this issue could involve creating a taxonomy that catalogs every conceivable ideal of democracy, studying the role philanthropy should play in each, and identifying recurring themes. Another option might involve a descriptive (nonnormative) analysis of democracy followed by a comparative analytical study of philanthropy.</p><p>Emanuela Ceva and Valeria Ottonelli's characterization of democracy serves this purpose and is therefore the basis for my proposal of a conceptual analysis of philanthropy as an authoritative practice defined by constitutive rules.</p><p>One advantage of this analytical approach to philanthropy lies in its ability to make sense of the diverse philanthropic practices that exist. For instance, a difficulty that political theorists might encounter concerns the distinction between small-scale and large-scale (or elite) manifestations of philanthropy. Saunders-Hastings (<span>2018</span>) acknowledges this disparity in the following way: “Compared with ordinary donors, the very wealthy can influence the behavior of recipient organizations in more significant, sustained, and structured ways. This is especially true where they manage giving through their own institutions, of which the private foundation is the most important.” (p. 151) This is also reaffirmed when she states that ‘‘Mass philanthropy can be undemocratic or inegalitarian in its aggregate effects’’ (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>, p. 122). Thus, she admits that while philanthropy generally conflicts with democracy, she perceives more issues in massive philanthropic donations compared to smaller, individual gifts.</p><p>While I also believe that that mass philanthropy, when aggregated, may present as many issues as elite philanthropy, my idea is that any kind of philanthropic action (whatever their amplitude) lacks basic democratic credentials. For sure, to differentiate between the consequences of small and big philanthropy is relevant, yet it is relevant only because of the exponential nature of the plutocratic form of authority that philanthropy exercises.</p><p>In a pure plutocracy, in which the wealthy rule, the more one owns, the more powerful one is. And Bill and Melinda Gates's potential power is unmistakably greater than that of a taxi driver who gives 100 Swiss francs to the local migrant associations every month. But looking only at who enjoys the most power neglects the full picture of the relationship between democracy and philanthropy. The fundamental difference between philanthropy and democracy concerns <i>how</i> someone acquires and exercises authority—that is, how they give direction to political action and how they do it. As authority is acquired and exercised in the form of donations, the logic of this authority will always be different from that which underpins democratic decision-making, which is mutual and second personal and in which currency is external to the decision-making process.</p><p>Obviously, when one donates 10 Swiss francs to a local school foundation, one may very well exercise less power than one who votes in an election. But this authority is still different from democratic authority. In this sense, although a small donation does not concretely change the state of affair of a society, they nevertheless carry the logic of authority that allow them to give direction to what is of public interest (and therefore to change the nature of the relationship between those implicated in those decisions) in a way that diverges from a democratic way of taking decisions.</p><p>Another advantage of my analytical approach lies in its ability to distinguish between two methods for making collectively binding decisions, which in practice are closely interlinked and often overlap. Consider, for instance, the cases involving tax incentives for philanthropy. One issue with such incentives is that they tend to blur the distinction between public and private actions.</p><p>Tax incentives are utilized by governments to encourage taxpayers to contribute philanthropically to causes deemed publicly valuable. When individuals donate money to these specific causes or institutions like philanthropic foundations engaged in such causes, they are permitted to deduct a portion or the entirety of their donations from what would have been their income tax obligations. The rationale behind these tax exemptions varies, but political theorists generally agree that donors are entitled to a tax reduction in order to ‘‘decentralize the process of producing social goods and promoting the pluralism of associational life by diminishing state orthodoxy in defining its contours’’ (Reich, <span>2018</span>, p. 158). Consequently, it becomes challenging to argue that philanthropy represents a strictly distinct form of private power from democratic practices when incentivized by public institutions firmly rooted in democracy.</p><p>However, despite tax incentives publicly indicating which philanthropic practices are favored, they do not render philanthropy more democratic in terms of exercising an authority that is mutual, second-personal, and whose currency is internal to the decision-making process. For instance, an incentive can, at best, be interpreted as an encouragement to exercise one's liberty or as a form of supererogatory duty. Therefore, incentives do not evoke a relationship of rights and duties between two parties, as is observed in relationships characterized by second-personality.</p><p>Thus, even if philanthropic acts are particularly incentivized by public entities, they remain fundamentally distinct from democratic practices. This differentiation arises due to a crucial aspect of constitutive rules, which is their creation of a unique relationship among those implicated by them. This relationship exists exclusively within their defined boundaries and defines the activity as long as these rules remain unchanged (Rawls, <span>1955</span>). Altering even one of the constitutive rules of democracy, even slightly, would significantly modify the interactions individuals experience within the authoritative practice. In essence, democracy maintains its democratic nature only when the type of authority exercised by every citizen remains simultaneously strictly second-personal, mutual, and an internal currency.</p><p>To understand how philanthropic authority differs from democratic authority in this manner, I now turn to the constitutive rules that underpin the logic of philanthropic practice.</p><p>In the two previous sections, I presented a conceptual analysis of the practice of philanthropy and a characterization of democracy defined as a practice with a form of authority whose currency is internal. In this section, I characterize the practice of philanthropy as authority conferring and distinguished by a set of constitutive rules. In this sense, by showing how the constitutive rules of the practice of philanthropy differ from those of the practice of democracy, I argue that the difference between philanthropy and democracy is that they instantiate two different logics for the making of collectively binding decisions.</p><p>Philanthropy's three constitutive rules are: (1) its authority is exercised <i>unilaterally</i>, (2) its source of authority is at the same time <i>first-personal</i> and <i>third-personal</i>, and (3) its authority's currency (which materializes its action-power) is <i>external to the practice of decision-making</i>.</p><p>Consider the first claim: philanthropic authority is unilateral. Philanthropy can be viewed as a specific form of plutocratic and dictatorial authority, understood as authority that is imposable on others. As a donor, and at least in the first instance, one exercises their authority in the form of donating without having to consult with or gather the opinions of those who will be subject to the decision (Table 1). Returning to the Gates Foundation example, Bill and Melinda Gates made a series of decisions in a way that could have never happened under a democratic process of decision-making. For example, all by themselves, they targeted the American education system and defined what its aim should be and what tools they would use to achieve it. More than that, the foundation has also defined conditions that schools must accept in order to receive funding. In this sense, Bill and Melinda Gates unilaterally exercised their authority. That, as Ravitch (<span>2011</span>) notes, the Gateses have been advised by well-trained experts does not change the unilateral nature of their acts. What make their acts different from democratic ones is that the final decision was in their hands alone. And this would have remained true even if the Gateses had consulted teachers, students, or even elected officials. However, as this paper aims at being purely descriptive, I do not discuss whether the Gateses had legitimate business in deciding how to use their money, provided that the purported aims were not against the law or general morality nor relied on stolen money.</p><p>This is thus what I mean by unilateral authority: rather than being mutually considered, shared, and taken, decisions flow from one individual or a group of individuals to another. This goes against the logic of democracy, in which no wielder of democratic authority can impose their own decisions on others, as the democratic collective body is self-legislating: the rulers are also the ruled. Or in Ceva and Ottonelli's (<span>2021</span>) words, “[…] when citizens vote, they do not make an individual final decision, but activate their portion of normative powers that will only contribute to the final decision in combination with the same kind of acts by other voters” (p. 5).</p><p>This is not to say that decisions made within a philanthropic context are never jointly taken. For example, foundations as big as the Gates Foundation may have internal mechanisms that ensure that the final decisions are the result of an equal balance of power between all members of the board. Bill and Melinda Gates may have had the same decision-making power as the researchers who suggested how to reform the American school system. But as close to democratic as they may be, these mechanisms remain internal to the institution, making their authority similar to that of a jury or a cardinal council in the Catholic Church.</p><p>Unilateralism highlights a fundamental, perhaps commonsensical, feature of any private practice aimed at guiding the making of collectively binding decisions: private individuals and institutions express, promote and act in ways that reflect their own conception of society. As Barkan (<span>2013</span>) says about philanthropists, “They may act with good intentions, but they define ‘good’.” (p. 636) However, this is an important point to raise, as it helps us to understand how these private entities can influence public action. Philanthropists, by definition, act for public purposes. However, unilateralism teaches us that this greater good is defined by the small number of individuals who participate in these practices, and not by the public as a whole.</p><p>The second constitutive rule of the practice of philanthropy is the first- and third-personal nature of its authority. To gain greater precision, let us turn to an example of Stephen Darwall (<span>2006</span>). Imagine that someone, named Jackie, is stepping on your feet and that you are trying to find <i>normative reasons</i> (i.e., reasons that give her reasons <i>for action</i>) for her to stop doing so. One way to do it would be to appeal to reasons that are internal to Jackie's moral conscience. For example, you could convince Jackie that stepping on your feet hurts and that she herself would never want to feel this pain. This discussion might strike Jackie and make her think that yes, she should not be acting like that. This is a <i>first</i>-personal reason in the sense that it appeals to Jackie's inner morality to decide whether to do something. Another way would be to appeal to external reasons to act or not act. For example, you could draw a knife from your pocket and threaten to stab Jackie if she does not take her feet off yours immediately. If she decides to comply because of your threat, she is compelled by a reason that is primarily external to her own choice. Call it a <i>third</i>-personal reason. Interpreting this case from a second-personal perspective, you could ask Jackie to remove her feet because, based on your relationship, you have an appropriate claim on her to do so. In doing so, you would give Jackie a valid reason to comply. This reason is second-personal because it takes another agent's reason, yours, as a reason for action. In this case, the source of normativity is neither Jackie's own reason for action nor an external rule but the relation between you and Jackie. Thus, where a second-personal source of normativity is relational, first- and third-personalities are, respectively, internal and external.</p><p>Now that we have a clearer picture of the different sources of normativity, let us return to the philanthropic form of authority. Philanthropy is both first- and third-personal. This authority triggers these two forms of normativity, and not the second-personal one, because the philanthropic practice is a different type of Hohfeldian right from the claim-right. It can be viewed as a <i>privilege-</i>right (Hohfeld, <span>1919</span>). It relates to first-personal reasons because, when donors decide to act for a public purpose, they are referring to reasons that are internal to themselves. Such reasons can take many forms: providing better education for people in impoverished regions of the world and saving the ocean from pollution or again stimulating cultural activities. What is specific with these internal reasons is that through their donations, a philanthropist fond of ecological conservation is not answering to the claim-right of whales to have clean oceans because humans are polluting them. Put into the democratic vocabulary, this means that Bill and Melinda Gateses’ source of authority is nowhere to be found in their co-citizens’ demands, that is, they did not act because they were legitimately asked to do so. As Darwall (<span>2006</span>) would put, they decided to reform the American school system based on their “state of the world regarding” (p. 6) reasons, on their very own conception of the good.</p><p>Philanthropic authority is also third-personal: it applies an external source of normativity to those who will be subject to it. By making donations, one imposes—based on their own will—on others their vision of how public purposes should be arranged. By giving money to put forward a certain conception of how to organize the school system, Bill and Melinda Gates gave third-personal reasons for parent–teacher associations and students to act in a certain way. The resources they gave, tied to a number of clauses, transformed the living conditions of those involved in those schools by defining how to work, how to learn, and what is worth learning. Importantly for my comparison with the second-personal form of authority, these changes happened for normative reasons that were unrelated to the relation shared by those affected by the Gateses’ decision. In contrast, saying that democracy instantiates second-personal relations means that citizens recognize the special authority to hold other citizens accountable for what is done to them. Hence, the philanthropic mode of decision-making alters this relation of joint recognition as the final authority over their reciprocal claims and duties.</p><p>To summarize this second constitutive rule, philanthropy is at the same time first- and third-personal, as a philanthropist's reasons for action originate in their internal reasons and as those reasons create, for citizens, external obligations that do not rest on their interactions. As stated in the previous section, these constitutive rules also help to understand why publicly encouraged act of philanthropy such as those encouraged by tax incentives does not make philanthropic authority less distinct from democratic one. Although incentivized philanthropy answers to what could be conceived as a state's call, the source of their authority remains first- and third-personal. It remains first-personal because philanthropists make use of their own internal reasons for actions, in the sense that it is not a duty trigger by citizens’ claim-rights. It is also third-personal in the sense that the way philanthropists give direction to public activities are not anchored in a mechanism of joint recognition of authority.</p><p>This constitutive rule highlights the type of relationship that philanthropy establishes within a polity. Philanthropy offers donors the opportunity to give direction to society on the basis of their own reasons for actions. However, philanthropy's third-personal authority also risks changing the lives of citizens for reasons that are external to them. Second-order reasons for action, as found in democratic decision-making, may be demanding because of their relationship of rights and duties, nevertheless they bind citizens in a different way than philanthropy does. Second personality guarantee citizens that each decision and public action is implemented for reasons with which they are associated.</p><p>The distinction between first- and third-personalities and second-personality could be stated as follows: Who should decide how public purposes are pursued? Individuals acting voluntarily out of their love for humanity, or all citizens acting through a collective system based on interrelations of accountability?</p><p>Focusing on the source of authority also allows to show how interrelation changes in function of the preferred practice. For example, one redistributive system based on taxes and another one based on voluntary donations do not share the same implications and social meanings, even if the outcome is identical. In the first case, the state redistributes resources from those who have benefited more from social cooperation to those who benefited less. There is the idea that some citizens owe something to others. In the second situation, we are appealing to the generosity (in opposition to their obligation) of individuals to make the world more just.</p><p>Finally, philanthropy's third constitutive rule concerns the currency of its authority. Recall that by <i>currency</i>, I refer to the resources that empower the authority bearer to make collectively binding decisions. In the case of philanthropy, its currency consists in external resources. Philanthropic donations can take the form of money, time, and services (Figure 1). This is why philanthropy is generally seen as a form of plutocratic power: the currency of its authority is derived from concrete resources. This makes plutocracy different from aristocracy, which used to derive its power from social resources such as titles of nobility and social status.</p><p>Unlike democracy, what gives philanthropy its substantive action-power exists prior to and outside its decision-making process. Money, for example, is a resource that individuals gather and possess before they even decide to act in a philanthropic manner. This is fundamentally different from what happens in a democracy. Imagine that instead of having one token each, citizens have unequal amount of tokens. By taking as legitimate the authority derived from material resources, philanthropy creates a fundamentally asymmetric form of decision-making, as the source of this authority—wealth or time—is unequally distributed. Since some individuals have more of these resources than others, poorer individuals must accept the decisions of richer ones. And since philanthropic resources exist prior to and after the decision-making process, the tokens may be used with much more flexibility than democratic ones. Instead of waiting on elected official's decision or popular votations, philanthropy might offer my friend and I two options for the creating a new theater: First, we could pool our money and fund it ourselves. Second, we could use our resources to advocate that theaters are an important part of a rich cultural life and that the local government should fund one. The options are not strictly the same, as the first one would probably leave the philanthropist with more decision-making power over the theater's activities, but the example nevertheless shows the impact of authority based on external resources. In both options, calling on philanthropic resources allows us to realize public purposes rather than relying on the democratic process.</p><p>Disparities between large and small philanthropic foundations clearly illustrate how difference in resources shape philanthropy's action power. It is clear that the Bill and Melinda Gates’ foundation disposed of much more resources to shape the American system than a smaller local philanthropic organization. However, conceptually, it should not be assumed that the political authority derived from these entities are more or less distinct from democratic authority solely based on the tangible impact they have on policy-making or public decision-making. Democracy is democratic as long as the kind of authority exercised by every citizen remains at the same time strictly second-personal, mutual and its currency is external. Even the slightest number of external resources aimed at giving direction to public decisions and actions will be incompatible will change the nature of relationships instantiate by such democratic forms of collectively-binding decision-making.</p><p>In this section, I have explained that philanthropy embodies a specific logic of authority. Philanthropic authority is <i>unilaterally</i> exercised, allowing the donor to have a direct and individual say in public decisions. It takes its normativity from a mix of <i>first-personality</i> and <i>third-personality</i>, appealing to reasons that are not linked to any relations of claim-rights between decision-makers. And the currency of philanthropy—what materializes its action-power—is <i>external</i> to the decision-making process rather than being internally created as in a one-person, one-vote system. Given these constitutive rules, authority emerging from philanthropic practices is fundamentally different from that emerging from democratic ones, which is characterized by the rules of mutualism, second-personality, and externality of currency.</p><p>My characterization of philanthropic authority is important in at least two manners. First, it allows us to clearly understand what philanthropy involves for public decisions and how it relates to democracy. This characterization thus shows what should be taken into consideration when determining which kind of decision-making tool should be employed for public decisions. Clarifying how these two logics of authority differ seems to indicate how difficult it might be to reconcile them. Introducing philanthropy in a democracy changes, for better or worse, the relations of accountability shared by citizens. My characterization of philanthropy points to its inherently political nature. It emphasizes that philanthropy is not purely benevolent (as it can be used as a tool to affect the making of public decision) without assuming that it is always aimed at secretly pulling the strings of government.</p><p>A second manner in which this characterization is significant is that of making sense of the numerous philanthropic practices that exist. Focusing on the kind of authority that emanates from philanthropy allows us to gain a clear account of what different forms of philanthropy share, from the smallest donation to the largest sum given by the richest individual. This paper shows that giving is not voting, and even if the final result of these two decision-making methods may be the same, or even if their action power is weaker, the methods nevertheless change the nature of the relationship between those affected by the decisions.</p><p>Similarly, my characterization enables an understanding of mixed or in-between cases, such as when philanthropy is encouraged publicly through tax incentives. Constitutive rules teach us that practices characterized by them cannot be changed, even by a little, without risking the nature of that practice. In this sense, it is not possible to make philanthropy analytically more democratic by giving it a public varnish. Public incentives or public–private partnerships<sup>10</sup> represent normative positions concerning philanthropy within a democracy. They articulate the types of philanthropic practices deemed desirable or valuable in a democratic society. Such desirability can itself be democratically established through specific policies. For instance, the very existence of philanthropy is contingent on its democratic authorization. However, the normative reasons guiding our encouragement or discouragement of philanthropy in a democracy do not alter the analytical characterization of the practice itself. Philanthropic authority is exercised unilaterally, originating from first and third-personal reasons for actions, and its currency is external to the collectively binding decision-making process it initiates.</p><p>Furthermore, discerning the differentiation between philanthropic authority and other forms of private practice might seem challenging. For instance, consider a scenario where a friend and I opt to establish a for-profit corporation instead of choosing philanthropy to construct a new theater. The authority exercised as a corporation could mirror that of philanthropy: unilateral decision-making (our choice to build the theater and determine the show), rooted in our personal reasons for action, and with an external impact on citizens through the currency (money). It appears that philanthropic and for-profit activities share similarities, but their substantive difference lies in their directed objectives: public purposes, as oppose to for-profit ones. However, delineating between for-profit and nonprofit actions was beyond the scope of this paper.</p><p>Lastly, I wish to emphasize a central implication stemming from my characterization of philanthropy. Asserting that philanthropy and democracy represent two distinct forms of authority does not inherently favor or oppose philanthropic actions in public spheres. My aim in characterizing philanthropy is to highlight the nature of making collectively binding decisions using this practice and its implications for democracy. Consequently, my intention is not to argue for or against the various normative values of philanthropy, as presented by the political theorists referenced in this paper. Depending on preferred democratic ideals, some might find the unilateral nature of philanthropy advantageous. Supporters of this view often commend the efficacy of philanthropy over public actions. Others might believe that philanthropy, by utilizing external resources, offers a wide range of possibilities potentially unavailable to the state. This aligns with Rob Reich's defense of the discovery argument for philanthropic foundations. However, other scholars may contend that the first and third-personal nature of philanthropy risks subjecting citizens to the goodwill of their benefactors.</p><p>I have argued that there is a constitutive difference between philanthropy and democracy. Understood as two tools for the making of collectively binding decisions, they instantiate two forms of authority differentiated by their constitutive rules. First, where democracy's exercise of authority is mutual, and its citizens are co-subject and coauthor of laws, philanthropic authority is unilateral in the sense of being imposable on others. Second, the source of democratic authority is second-personal, anchoring citizens’ reasons for action in the interpersonal relationship they all share. In contrast, philanthropy is first- and third-personal, so that philanthropists’ reasons for action are internal to themselves while instantiating an external source of normativity in relation to those who will be subject to it. Finally, where democracy's currency of authority is created within the decision-making process, philanthropy takes its authority from resources that are external to the process and unequally distributed.</p><p>This paper shed light on how philanthropy and democracy differ as forms of authority even if they aim at the same public purposes. My analytical characterization of philanthropy showed what features of the practice should be taken into consideration in normative discussions of the kind of decision-making tools to deploy for making collectively binding decisions. The encompassing focus of this work also allowed us to gain a clear account of what different forms of philanthropy share, from the smallest donation to the largest donations.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"32 1","pages":"33-46"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2024-09-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12759","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Philanthropy and democracy: Two kinds of authority\",\"authors\":\"Matthieu Debief\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12759\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>In 2000, the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation tackled an issue concerning the American education system: unsatisfactory high school graduation rates and college entry rates, especially in urban school districts (Ravitch, <span>2011</span>). Between 2000 and 2008, this foundation donated more than $2 billion to 2600 schools across 45 US states. Bill and Melinda Gates's aim was clearly spelled out: they saw the K−12<sup>1</sup> education system as “obsolete”<sup>2</sup> and in need of drastic reforms (Ravitch, <span>2011</span>). The Gates Foundation's leaders observed that some schools in the United States could host up to 4000 or 5000 pupils, leading to the neglect of a portion of students who needed extra attention. Based on contemporary research and already-existing movements in civil society,<sup>3</sup> they concluded that smaller schools were the key to students’ success.</p><p>In a context of public budget cuts, not many school boards could refuse a multimillion-dollar philanthropic donation. Hence, the Gates Foundation started to distribute money all over the United States, tying its gifts to conditions that would promote an effectiveness-based conception of education. At first, schools were asked to restructure and split themselves into independent units of no more than 400 students. Later, performance-based pay for teachers and national-standards tests, serving as effectiveness yardsticks, became mandatory for funding.</p><p>Although this system benefited some schools, it created more problems than it solved in the great majority of cases. For example, the fragmentation of large schools into small autonomous units increased conflict and competition for resources and deprived students of a significant range of activities that were only provided in larger institutions. Praised in the beginning, the Gates program was sharply criticized in 2005 when the first evaluations came out. In 2008, the foundation's directors recognized the bad start of their program and mostly put the blame on the lack of receptivity of the schools they helped or on teachers’ lack of competence. A few months later, the foundation decided to all but shut the program down.</p><p>In a democracy, there are good reasons to believe that the making of collectively binding decisions about such public goods as school infrastructures, education programs, and teachers’ salary should be carried out by citizens or people who speak in their name. However, the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation's case shows a sense in which some people or organizations, by virtue of their private resources, have an additional and sometimes larger say on such questions. This raises the question whether the logics of democracy and philanthropy are compatible. The question is more pressing because philanthropic donations are generally tax subsidized, representing therefore a redirection of public money (Pevnick, <span>2013</span>) toward aims likely to advance donors’ personal interests.</p><p>Political philosophers have debated the role that philanthropy should have in liberal democratic states. On the one hand, a good amount of work argues that philanthropy should not assume a role in distributive justice, as private and voluntary redistribution of basic goods is too unreliable (Beerbohm, <span>2016</span>), might affect egalitarian values (Cordelli, <span>2012</span>), reinforces power asymmetries (Lechterman, <span>2021</span>), and constitutes a paternalistic type of assistance (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>). On the other hand, philanthropy may help promote social innovations (Reich, <span>2018</span>), foster a vibrant cultural life (Pevnick, <span>2013</span>), serve as a means for intergenerational justice (Cordelli &amp; Reich, <span>2016</span>), uphold public institutional action (Ceva, <span>2021</span>), or supplement the provision of goods unrequired by justice (Lechterman, <span>2021</span>). All in all, philanthropic actions have been praised for allowing a variety of interests to be included in collective decision-making while being criticized for the unequal manner by which it includes them (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>).</p><p>While many political philosophers have thus discussed the <i>normative</i> question of why philanthropy might or might not be desirable in a democracy, few have paused to address the prior and more fundamental <i>analytical</i> question of what, if anything, makes philanthropy inherently specific in such a way that it may raise issues of compatibility with democracy. I argue in this paper that, although philanthropy and democracy aim at the same goal, they instantiate two distinct forms of political authority. Political authority is the morally and legally legitimate power of an individual or institution to give direction to public action.<sup>4</sup> In a democratic society, such a direction-giving activity (the practice of authority) is carried out by collectively binding decision-making. I show how, while democratic practices enable people to make mutually binding decisions together, philanthropic acts allow them to give direction to public decisions and actions based on their own unilateral preferences. Building on this basic observation, I argue that philanthropic donations may be vectors of power, and when they are, they carry a specific form of authority that differs from that underpinning the democratic logic of authority.</p><p>This paper unfolds in the following way. I start with a brief sketch of democracy as a practice of authority (Section 2). I then offer a conceptual analysis of philanthropy, showing how it can be conceived of as an authority practice (Section 3). I then provide an overview of how we can conceive of the relationship between philanthropy and democracy (Section 4). Finally, I develop my account of philanthropy as an authority-constituting practice defined by the three constitutive rules of unilateralism; first &amp; third personality, and externality of currency (Section 5).</p><p>The aim of this work is primarily analytical. Hence, when I point to a divergent relation between the democratic and philanthropic logics of authority, I do not defend one practice against the other. Of course, as is often the case in political theory, my analytical and conceptual work may serve to elucidate further normative issues. For example, my discussion suggests that the analytical distinction that philanthropy and democracy are different decision-making tools, which can inform the normative question of what tool a polity should choose, knowing that the choice would change, for better or worse, the nature of the relationship between those implicated in those decisions. In this sense, while my primary interest in the paper is analytical, the distinction I shall draw can usefully inform future normative appraisals of the role of philanthropy in a democracy.</p><p>This paper inquiries into philanthropy within a particular mode of social and political organization: democracy. To gain a clear idea of what I mean when I point to a divergent relation between the democratic and philanthropic logics of authority, I briefly introduce the former concept. To do so, I build on Ceva and Ottonelli's (<span>2021</span>) paper “Second-Personal Authority and the Practice of Democracy”, which offers a descriptive (nonnormative) account of democracy.</p><p>Ceva and Ottonelli identify the basic features of the practice of democracy. They do not offer reasons why we should prefer democracy over other types of political organization, nor do they concern themselves with defining democracy. Their aim is rather to understand what making democratic decisions and living under these decisions involve. For Ceva and Ottonelli (<span>2021</span>), democracy is a rule-based social and political practice. That means that democratic practices are defined by a set of rules that instantiate special actions and relations that exist only within these rules. It also means that those who engage in the democratic practices are assigned specific rights in the form of normative power and roles in a way that is particular to this set of rules (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>).</p><p>One of the specific roles instantiated by democratic practices is that of maker of collectively binding decisions (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>). Democratic actors (i.e., citizens) wield the authority to make decisions together, either directly (e.g., through referenda) or indirectly (e.g., by electing representatives), and those decisions bind citizens according to a specific relationship of rights and duties. What characterizes and differentiates this authority from other types of decision-making power (such as monarchic or oligarchic) is the set of rules that constitute the logic of the democratic practice.</p><p>In Ceva and Ottonelli's paper, these constitutive rules are twofold. First, democratic authority is mutual (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>). Mutuality refers to how the democratic authority is <i>exercised</i>. It means that the democratic authority, and the decisions that result from it, is exercised jointly by all decision-makers. Eric Beerbohm (<span>2012</span>) suggests that this mutualism is what makes citizens both “cosubjects of the law and coauthors” (Beerbohm, <span>2012</span>, p. 44). This contrasts, for example, with the power of a queen, who can unilaterally enact laws that will constrain her people but not herself.</p><p>Second, democratic practices are also second-personal (Ceva &amp; Ottonelli, <span>2021</span>). The notion of personality invoked here refers to the <i>source</i> of an authority, that is, the reasons that triggers person X's action. Second- personality is the idea that what triggers X's action is person Y's reasons, as in an I–you relationship (Darwall, <span>2006</span>). Democracy involves second-personality because of the specific type of rights that are instantiated during this practice. Democracy generates what are called <i>claim-rights</i>. Following a Hohfeldian analysis, those who hold this kind of right can claim (i.e., they are the source of) certain treatment from specific individuals: the duty bearers (Hohfeld, <span>1919</span>).</p><p>Say, for example, that I make an oral agreement (instantiating this specific type of aforementioned relationship between claim-rights and duties) with a friend giving him the right to use my guitar for a gig. By that agreement, my friend becomes bound by a duty to give me back my guitar at the end of the concert. Moreover, I will have the right to reclaim my guitar, and my friend will be the only person allowed to fulfill the duty. What triggers my friend's duty—his reason to give me back my guitar—is my claim-right. The practice of democracy binds citizens in their use of power in the same way. As all democratic citizens are claim-right holders, they also are duty bearers. This means that, for example, when citizens vote directly on a given topic,<sup>5</sup> it gives them the authority to collectively decide the content of a law and it binds those citizens to respect the content of the newly decided law because each of them has a claim-right and a duty toward the others. Thus, by virtue of their participating in the democratic practice, citizens become the owners and sources of each other's rights and duties. This leads Ceva and Ottonelli (<span>2021</span>) to note that “the relations between democratic voters constitute a new ‘we,’ a collective of rights holders who, in that very capacity and no other, jointly recognize each other as the final authorities on their reciprocal claims and duties” (p. 6).</p><p>Mutualism hence enacts how the democratic authority is exercised (jointly by all decision-makers), while second-personality underlines the source of citizens’ reason for action (their reciprocal claim-rights and duties). I suggest adding a third constitutive rule of democratic authority to mutuality (<i>exercise</i>) and second-personality (<i>source</i>); it concerns the authority's <i>currency</i>. This rule concerns what gives an authority its effective action-power. By currency, I refer to the resources that empower the authority bearer in the making of collectively binding decisions. It is helpful to think about the currency of an authority as a token. In a democracy, citizens may only make use of one specific type of token. This token, which is at the root of all democratic decisions, is the democratic vote.<sup>6</sup> When citizens enter the democratic decision-making process, they are granted voting rights.</p><p>Voting rights as tokens reflect the basic idea of a one-person, one-vote system: they are at the same time unique and similar. They are unique because each citizen disposes of their own single token. But all tokens are similar in the sense that they are worth the exact same amount of power. When a citizen casts a vote, they exercise no more authority than any of their co-citizens. Moreover, these tokens only exist (i.e., have currency) within the democratic decision-making process. They do not exist prior to, after, or outside the democratic institution. Friends do not have this type of authority over each other, nor is this kind of authority possessed by virtue of citizenship relationships alone. For example, it is not enough that a group of friends democratically vote in favor of building a new theater for asking other people in the neighborhood to contribute to the project. Voting acquires its binding capacity on a given constituency only if carried out within a special institutional settings; it is democratic when this setting implicates every other citizen, as they are engaged in mutual and second-personal relationships.</p><p>I revisit the constitutive rules of democracy in Section 5 when I discuss their differences from those of philanthropy. Before I do that, I must characterize the practice of philanthropy.</p><p>Now that the background of this work has been set, I proceed with a conceptual analysis of philanthropy. This section allows me to introduce the conception of philanthropy as a social and political practice.</p><p>An unanimously accepted definition of philanthropy does not exist. Various terms, such as charity, nonprofit sector, third sector, benevolence, eleemosynary acts, and alms, describe the action or context of giving. For Jenny Harrow and Siobhan Daly, this is because philanthropy is a clustered and essentially contested concept. It is clustered because it is “capable of being multiply defined by multiple stakeholders, so that parallel understandings of its nature and purpose coexist in research” (Harrow, <span>2010</span>,p. 123), while its essential contestability is reflected by the internal complexity, diverse describability, the multidimensionality, as well as the continuous competition that exist between the different normative conceptualization of philanthropy (Daly, <span>2012</span>).</p><p>One of the many conceptions of philanthropy views it as a practice: “the voluntary contribution of private resources (usually money, but also in-kind goods or time) for broadly public purposes, and for which the giver does not receive payment in the ordinary sense (though she may receive inducements, thank-you gifts, or special consideration of other kinds, e.g., access to concert tickets). Such voluntary contributions may be made by groups or legal entities like corporations as well as by individuals” (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2019</span>, p. 1). More simply put, philanthropy can be outlined as the <i>voluntary commitment of private property for public purposes</i> (Ostrower, <span>1997</span>), as a social and political practice that is regulated by formal and informal rules (Lechterman, <span>2021</span>). From this perspective, philanthropy allows private individuals to have a say in what is considered of public interest.</p><p>Following this conception, I highlight four defining features of philanthropic practice. First, it can only be exercised by private individuals or organizations; it cannot be exercised by the state or its representative. A government can incentivize philanthropic actions, but it cannot give money or in-kind goods away in a philanthropic way. Let us imagine that, following a pandemic, elected officials decide to provide an exceptional grant, allocating money to their country's worst off. To fund this grant, the government decides to collect extra taxes from the richest 5%. It cannot be said that the people targeted by this grant benefited from charity from the richest 5%. They receive this money because, following a decision made with democratic logic, they have a claim-right to it, which triggers a second-personal reason for action by the taxpayers. This also differentiates philanthropy from actions exercised by public international organizations such as development-aid agencies, as in this case also the decision to provide resources emerges from public decisions. While states can be authors and recipients of charitable donations, only private individuals and organizations can make <i>philanthropic</i> donations.</p><p>Second, to be described as philanthropic, an action must aim at public purposes. For present purposes, I leave this concept somewhat open, as a public purpose can take many forms. However, not just any purpose can be considered as public. Following Lechterman (<span>2021</span>) “Public” can mean “open to all” (in the way that a “pub” is open to any customer with the means to pay for a drink), “universal” (in the way that “public utilities” are meant to cover all residents of a region), as well as “collectively authorized,” “collectively beneficial,” and “governmental.”<sup>7</sup> Consequently, “private” would rather refer to acts benefiting definite individuals. In this sense, nonpublic or private purposes would include market exchanges, parents’ inheritance to their children, gifts one makes to one of his or her friends, or again donations to clubs of which one is a member. The necessary condition of publicity is that any philanthropic act aims at virtually benefiting the greatest number, where “virtually” means that it should be accessible to anyone. Obviously, cases like donations to research against orphan disease, which may concern a very restricted number of patients, would still count as philanthropic under this framework. Similar conceptualizations of accessibility may be found in the Anglo-American context where it is stated that philanthropy should benefit an indefinite number.</p><p>Third, philanthropy must be voluntary, understood as not being coercively imposed. Taxes cannot be considered as philanthropy because the state uses its coercive power to force citizens to pay what they must and what they are duty bound to pay (Murphy &amp; Nagel, <span>2002</span>).</p><p>Fourth, philanthropy is concerned with the transfer of private property. If money is the first type of resource that comes to mind when one thinks about philanthropic donations, it is far from being the only one. Time, goods, and services may all be donated as well. While elite philanthropy is often characterized by the amount of money that flows through organizations such as foundations (MacKenzie, <span>2021</span>), cash is rarely the final contribution of these institutions. To be provided on a large scale, medical aid, new buildings, counseling, legal assistance, and water distribution may require a lot of money, but their recipients are not directly given cash.</p><p>In summary, philanthropy can be conceived of as a social and political practice, defined as being only exercised by private actors, aiming at a public purpose, being voluntary, and being concerned with the transfer of private property.</p><p>Before going further, it is important to clarify a point. It is often noted that the word <i>philanthropy</i> derives from the Greek for “love of humanity.” This etymology points to the conception of philanthropy as a motivation: “the love of humanity or concern for the common good (whether of humanity in general or of a more circumscribed group)” (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2019</span>, p. 1). Following this, as long as donors act with certain motives, they are acting philanthropically. However, I want to argue that the motives as well as moral standards underlying giving are not relevant to a political examination of philanthropy. Individuals have their own reasons for acting in a generous way. Maybe they do it because they think it is morally important, maybe simply because their pockets are too heavy, maybe to show the world that they are good human beings, or maybe to change society. What is crucial, however, is that whether the decision is made for X or Y reason does not substantially alter the kind of power one has when exercising authority derived from philanthropic acts.</p><p>In the case of the Gates Foundation, it has been demonstrated that its generous donation served to promote businesslike organization and new-public-management methods in schools (Ravitch, <span>2011</span>; Saltman, <span>2011</span>). After all, it is well known that philanthropy does not only derive from altruistic feelings (Andreoni, <span>1990</span>) but may be an instrument of private political advocacy or agenda setting (Reich, <span>2018</span>). However, this feature of philanthropy should not be seen as fundamentally problematic in liberal democracies. The Gateses’ program, after all, probably reflected a conception of education that was shared by many other US citizens at that time. And as citizens themselves, the Gateses are free to advocate for their preferred conception of education. Nevertheless, the tension raised by this case stems from the <i>way</i> this specific conception of education was conveyed to the public: it is one thing to cast a vote for businesslike organization in the education system, and another to bypass democratic processes by defining and setting the political agenda of a nation's education just because one has the resources to do so, as Bill and Melinda Gates did. But whatever the reasons one may have to practice philanthropy, the kind of authority that will emerge from it will remain the same.<sup>8</sup></p><p>One crucial point that the conceptual analysis of philanthropy as a practice exposed is that philanthropy and democracy are, to some extent, both pursuing public causes. They are both tools to give direction to concrete actions that may advance social justice, foster a vibrant cultural life, fund basic and higher education, nurture democratic innovation, advocate visions of a better society, or tackle health-related issues. Hence, philanthropy and democracy can be interpreted as different and possibly competing decision-making tools for public causes. One way to interpret the competition is that democratic societies in nonideal contexts may face scarcity of resources, and a choice may have to be made between public and private funding of goods and services. A second way, the one I am interested in here, concerns the different implications of philanthropy and democracy for the making of collectively binding decisions.</p><p>For many scholars, the most striking feature of philanthropy is that it allows donors to exercise a form of power that revolves around material resources (Beerbohm, <span>2016</span>; Cordelli, <span>2016, 2020</span>; Cordelli &amp; Reich, <span>2016</span>; Lambelet et al., <span>2019</span>; Lechterman, <span>2021</span>; Lechterman &amp; Reich, <span>2020</span>; Reich, <span>2018</span>; Saunders-Hastings, <span>2018, 2019</span>). Given that feature, most of them argue that philanthropy is at odds in democratic societies where decisions should, in principle, be taken collectively and equally. For Emma Saunders-Hastings, philanthropy “gives donors influence and authority, in public life and over particular beneficiaries. It shapes public options and the choices available to individuals” (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>, p. 5). Philanthropic foundations are, according to Rob Reich (<span>2018</span>), “institutional oddities in a democracy,” (p. 144) as they represent plutocratic, unaccountable, and nontransparent vehicle of political power, while, for Lechterman (<span>2021</span>), philanthropy is a form of private power with plutocratic tendencies.</p><p>These observations have flourished in a myriad of interesting normative propositions.<sup>9</sup> However, the issue lies in the fact that the aforementioned authors do not adequately inform us about what inherently distinguishes philanthropy in a way that might raise concerns regarding its compatibility with democracy. What remains lacking is a systematic analytical framework that delineates the fundamental differences between philanthropy and democracy concerning their roles in making collectively binding decisions.</p><p>Ryan Pevnick has taken an initial step in this direction. In his work “Philanthropy and Democratic Ideals,” while acknowledging the discomfort that philanthropy often experiences within democratic regimes, he expresses his aim: “My goal in this chapter is conceptual. I seek to move beyond the initial tension between philanthropy and democracy by providing a careful account of the role philanthropy might properly claim in a well-functioning democracy” (Pevnick, <span>2016</span>, p. 227). He accomplishes this by comparing the potential role of philanthropy in two distinct ideals of democracy: market democracy and democratic equality.</p><p>Market democracy and democratic equality, both grounded in fundamental liberal principles, diverge in their conceptions of individual citizens, governance, and justice. These differing conceptions yield contrasting assessments of the role philanthropy should assume within these democratic systems. Market democracies view individuals as responsible self-authors, governance revolves around a minimal government, and justice leans toward respecting market outcomes due to reasons of desert and efficiency (Pevnick, <span>2016</span>). Advocates of market democracy thus see philanthropy as pivotal in providing noncoercive aid and fostering self-governance. Conversely, democratic equality emphasizes individual citizens as equal participants in a cooperative scheme, features a deliberative democracy, and champions justice marked by liberal egalitarianism. While proponents of this democratic ideal might view philanthropy skeptically, fearing it might undermine the idea of a community governed by equality, Pevnick argues that democratic equality should endorse philanthropic support for cultural projects.</p><p>This comparison has the merit to suggest that although philanthropy and democracy may appear in tension within democratic societies, this does not automatically render them incompatible. The degree of compatibility hinges on the specific type of democracy, such as its conception of freedom or equality. However, while this work acknowledges the difference between philanthropy and democracy without asserting inherent contradiction, it falls short in providing a robust analytical account of what fundamentally distinguishes the two. This shortfall arises because Pevnick's conceptual differentiation relies on normative ideals of democracy.</p><p>One approach to circumvent this issue could involve creating a taxonomy that catalogs every conceivable ideal of democracy, studying the role philanthropy should play in each, and identifying recurring themes. Another option might involve a descriptive (nonnormative) analysis of democracy followed by a comparative analytical study of philanthropy.</p><p>Emanuela Ceva and Valeria Ottonelli's characterization of democracy serves this purpose and is therefore the basis for my proposal of a conceptual analysis of philanthropy as an authoritative practice defined by constitutive rules.</p><p>One advantage of this analytical approach to philanthropy lies in its ability to make sense of the diverse philanthropic practices that exist. For instance, a difficulty that political theorists might encounter concerns the distinction between small-scale and large-scale (or elite) manifestations of philanthropy. Saunders-Hastings (<span>2018</span>) acknowledges this disparity in the following way: “Compared with ordinary donors, the very wealthy can influence the behavior of recipient organizations in more significant, sustained, and structured ways. This is especially true where they manage giving through their own institutions, of which the private foundation is the most important.” (p. 151) This is also reaffirmed when she states that ‘‘Mass philanthropy can be undemocratic or inegalitarian in its aggregate effects’’ (Saunders-Hastings, <span>2022</span>, p. 122). Thus, she admits that while philanthropy generally conflicts with democracy, she perceives more issues in massive philanthropic donations compared to smaller, individual gifts.</p><p>While I also believe that that mass philanthropy, when aggregated, may present as many issues as elite philanthropy, my idea is that any kind of philanthropic action (whatever their amplitude) lacks basic democratic credentials. For sure, to differentiate between the consequences of small and big philanthropy is relevant, yet it is relevant only because of the exponential nature of the plutocratic form of authority that philanthropy exercises.</p><p>In a pure plutocracy, in which the wealthy rule, the more one owns, the more powerful one is. And Bill and Melinda Gates's potential power is unmistakably greater than that of a taxi driver who gives 100 Swiss francs to the local migrant associations every month. But looking only at who enjoys the most power neglects the full picture of the relationship between democracy and philanthropy. The fundamental difference between philanthropy and democracy concerns <i>how</i> someone acquires and exercises authority—that is, how they give direction to political action and how they do it. As authority is acquired and exercised in the form of donations, the logic of this authority will always be different from that which underpins democratic decision-making, which is mutual and second personal and in which currency is external to the decision-making process.</p><p>Obviously, when one donates 10 Swiss francs to a local school foundation, one may very well exercise less power than one who votes in an election. But this authority is still different from democratic authority. In this sense, although a small donation does not concretely change the state of affair of a society, they nevertheless carry the logic of authority that allow them to give direction to what is of public interest (and therefore to change the nature of the relationship between those implicated in those decisions) in a way that diverges from a democratic way of taking decisions.</p><p>Another advantage of my analytical approach lies in its ability to distinguish between two methods for making collectively binding decisions, which in practice are closely interlinked and often overlap. Consider, for instance, the cases involving tax incentives for philanthropy. One issue with such incentives is that they tend to blur the distinction between public and private actions.</p><p>Tax incentives are utilized by governments to encourage taxpayers to contribute philanthropically to causes deemed publicly valuable. When individuals donate money to these specific causes or institutions like philanthropic foundations engaged in such causes, they are permitted to deduct a portion or the entirety of their donations from what would have been their income tax obligations. The rationale behind these tax exemptions varies, but political theorists generally agree that donors are entitled to a tax reduction in order to ‘‘decentralize the process of producing social goods and promoting the pluralism of associational life by diminishing state orthodoxy in defining its contours’’ (Reich, <span>2018</span>, p. 158). Consequently, it becomes challenging to argue that philanthropy represents a strictly distinct form of private power from democratic practices when incentivized by public institutions firmly rooted in democracy.</p><p>However, despite tax incentives publicly indicating which philanthropic practices are favored, they do not render philanthropy more democratic in terms of exercising an authority that is mutual, second-personal, and whose currency is internal to the decision-making process. For instance, an incentive can, at best, be interpreted as an encouragement to exercise one's liberty or as a form of supererogatory duty. Therefore, incentives do not evoke a relationship of rights and duties between two parties, as is observed in relationships characterized by second-personality.</p><p>Thus, even if philanthropic acts are particularly incentivized by public entities, they remain fundamentally distinct from democratic practices. This differentiation arises due to a crucial aspect of constitutive rules, which is their creation of a unique relationship among those implicated by them. This relationship exists exclusively within their defined boundaries and defines the activity as long as these rules remain unchanged (Rawls, <span>1955</span>). Altering even one of the constitutive rules of democracy, even slightly, would significantly modify the interactions individuals experience within the authoritative practice. In essence, democracy maintains its democratic nature only when the type of authority exercised by every citizen remains simultaneously strictly second-personal, mutual, and an internal currency.</p><p>To understand how philanthropic authority differs from democratic authority in this manner, I now turn to the constitutive rules that underpin the logic of philanthropic practice.</p><p>In the two previous sections, I presented a conceptual analysis of the practice of philanthropy and a characterization of democracy defined as a practice with a form of authority whose currency is internal. In this section, I characterize the practice of philanthropy as authority conferring and distinguished by a set of constitutive rules. In this sense, by showing how the constitutive rules of the practice of philanthropy differ from those of the practice of democracy, I argue that the difference between philanthropy and democracy is that they instantiate two different logics for the making of collectively binding decisions.</p><p>Philanthropy's three constitutive rules are: (1) its authority is exercised <i>unilaterally</i>, (2) its source of authority is at the same time <i>first-personal</i> and <i>third-personal</i>, and (3) its authority's currency (which materializes its action-power) is <i>external to the practice of decision-making</i>.</p><p>Consider the first claim: philanthropic authority is unilateral. Philanthropy can be viewed as a specific form of plutocratic and dictatorial authority, understood as authority that is imposable on others. As a donor, and at least in the first instance, one exercises their authority in the form of donating without having to consult with or gather the opinions of those who will be subject to the decision (Table 1). Returning to the Gates Foundation example, Bill and Melinda Gates made a series of decisions in a way that could have never happened under a democratic process of decision-making. For example, all by themselves, they targeted the American education system and defined what its aim should be and what tools they would use to achieve it. More than that, the foundation has also defined conditions that schools must accept in order to receive funding. In this sense, Bill and Melinda Gates unilaterally exercised their authority. That, as Ravitch (<span>2011</span>) notes, the Gateses have been advised by well-trained experts does not change the unilateral nature of their acts. What make their acts different from democratic ones is that the final decision was in their hands alone. And this would have remained true even if the Gateses had consulted teachers, students, or even elected officials. However, as this paper aims at being purely descriptive, I do not discuss whether the Gateses had legitimate business in deciding how to use their money, provided that the purported aims were not against the law or general morality nor relied on stolen money.</p><p>This is thus what I mean by unilateral authority: rather than being mutually considered, shared, and taken, decisions flow from one individual or a group of individuals to another. This goes against the logic of democracy, in which no wielder of democratic authority can impose their own decisions on others, as the democratic collective body is self-legislating: the rulers are also the ruled. Or in Ceva and Ottonelli's (<span>2021</span>) words, “[…] when citizens vote, they do not make an individual final decision, but activate their portion of normative powers that will only contribute to the final decision in combination with the same kind of acts by other voters” (p. 5).</p><p>This is not to say that decisions made within a philanthropic context are never jointly taken. For example, foundations as big as the Gates Foundation may have internal mechanisms that ensure that the final decisions are the result of an equal balance of power between all members of the board. Bill and Melinda Gates may have had the same decision-making power as the researchers who suggested how to reform the American school system. But as close to democratic as they may be, these mechanisms remain internal to the institution, making their authority similar to that of a jury or a cardinal council in the Catholic Church.</p><p>Unilateralism highlights a fundamental, perhaps commonsensical, feature of any private practice aimed at guiding the making of collectively binding decisions: private individuals and institutions express, promote and act in ways that reflect their own conception of society. As Barkan (<span>2013</span>) says about philanthropists, “They may act with good intentions, but they define ‘good’.” (p. 636) However, this is an important point to raise, as it helps us to understand how these private entities can influence public action. Philanthropists, by definition, act for public purposes. However, unilateralism teaches us that this greater good is defined by the small number of individuals who participate in these practices, and not by the public as a whole.</p><p>The second constitutive rule of the practice of philanthropy is the first- and third-personal nature of its authority. To gain greater precision, let us turn to an example of Stephen Darwall (<span>2006</span>). Imagine that someone, named Jackie, is stepping on your feet and that you are trying to find <i>normative reasons</i> (i.e., reasons that give her reasons <i>for action</i>) for her to stop doing so. One way to do it would be to appeal to reasons that are internal to Jackie's moral conscience. For example, you could convince Jackie that stepping on your feet hurts and that she herself would never want to feel this pain. This discussion might strike Jackie and make her think that yes, she should not be acting like that. This is a <i>first</i>-personal reason in the sense that it appeals to Jackie's inner morality to decide whether to do something. Another way would be to appeal to external reasons to act or not act. For example, you could draw a knife from your pocket and threaten to stab Jackie if she does not take her feet off yours immediately. If she decides to comply because of your threat, she is compelled by a reason that is primarily external to her own choice. Call it a <i>third</i>-personal reason. Interpreting this case from a second-personal perspective, you could ask Jackie to remove her feet because, based on your relationship, you have an appropriate claim on her to do so. In doing so, you would give Jackie a valid reason to comply. This reason is second-personal because it takes another agent's reason, yours, as a reason for action. In this case, the source of normativity is neither Jackie's own reason for action nor an external rule but the relation between you and Jackie. Thus, where a second-personal source of normativity is relational, first- and third-personalities are, respectively, internal and external.</p><p>Now that we have a clearer picture of the different sources of normativity, let us return to the philanthropic form of authority. Philanthropy is both first- and third-personal. This authority triggers these two forms of normativity, and not the second-personal one, because the philanthropic practice is a different type of Hohfeldian right from the claim-right. It can be viewed as a <i>privilege-</i>right (Hohfeld, <span>1919</span>). It relates to first-personal reasons because, when donors decide to act for a public purpose, they are referring to reasons that are internal to themselves. Such reasons can take many forms: providing better education for people in impoverished regions of the world and saving the ocean from pollution or again stimulating cultural activities. What is specific with these internal reasons is that through their donations, a philanthropist fond of ecological conservation is not answering to the claim-right of whales to have clean oceans because humans are polluting them. Put into the democratic vocabulary, this means that Bill and Melinda Gateses’ source of authority is nowhere to be found in their co-citizens’ demands, that is, they did not act because they were legitimately asked to do so. As Darwall (<span>2006</span>) would put, they decided to reform the American school system based on their “state of the world regarding” (p. 6) reasons, on their very own conception of the good.</p><p>Philanthropic authority is also third-personal: it applies an external source of normativity to those who will be subject to it. By making donations, one imposes—based on their own will—on others their vision of how public purposes should be arranged. By giving money to put forward a certain conception of how to organize the school system, Bill and Melinda Gates gave third-personal reasons for parent–teacher associations and students to act in a certain way. The resources they gave, tied to a number of clauses, transformed the living conditions of those involved in those schools by defining how to work, how to learn, and what is worth learning. Importantly for my comparison with the second-personal form of authority, these changes happened for normative reasons that were unrelated to the relation shared by those affected by the Gateses’ decision. In contrast, saying that democracy instantiates second-personal relations means that citizens recognize the special authority to hold other citizens accountable for what is done to them. Hence, the philanthropic mode of decision-making alters this relation of joint recognition as the final authority over their reciprocal claims and duties.</p><p>To summarize this second constitutive rule, philanthropy is at the same time first- and third-personal, as a philanthropist's reasons for action originate in their internal reasons and as those reasons create, for citizens, external obligations that do not rest on their interactions. As stated in the previous section, these constitutive rules also help to understand why publicly encouraged act of philanthropy such as those encouraged by tax incentives does not make philanthropic authority less distinct from democratic one. Although incentivized philanthropy answers to what could be conceived as a state's call, the source of their authority remains first- and third-personal. It remains first-personal because philanthropists make use of their own internal reasons for actions, in the sense that it is not a duty trigger by citizens’ claim-rights. It is also third-personal in the sense that the way philanthropists give direction to public activities are not anchored in a mechanism of joint recognition of authority.</p><p>This constitutive rule highlights the type of relationship that philanthropy establishes within a polity. Philanthropy offers donors the opportunity to give direction to society on the basis of their own reasons for actions. However, philanthropy's third-personal authority also risks changing the lives of citizens for reasons that are external to them. Second-order reasons for action, as found in democratic decision-making, may be demanding because of their relationship of rights and duties, nevertheless they bind citizens in a different way than philanthropy does. Second personality guarantee citizens that each decision and public action is implemented for reasons with which they are associated.</p><p>The distinction between first- and third-personalities and second-personality could be stated as follows: Who should decide how public purposes are pursued? Individuals acting voluntarily out of their love for humanity, or all citizens acting through a collective system based on interrelations of accountability?</p><p>Focusing on the source of authority also allows to show how interrelation changes in function of the preferred practice. For example, one redistributive system based on taxes and another one based on voluntary donations do not share the same implications and social meanings, even if the outcome is identical. In the first case, the state redistributes resources from those who have benefited more from social cooperation to those who benefited less. There is the idea that some citizens owe something to others. In the second situation, we are appealing to the generosity (in opposition to their obligation) of individuals to make the world more just.</p><p>Finally, philanthropy's third constitutive rule concerns the currency of its authority. Recall that by <i>currency</i>, I refer to the resources that empower the authority bearer to make collectively binding decisions. In the case of philanthropy, its currency consists in external resources. Philanthropic donations can take the form of money, time, and services (Figure 1). This is why philanthropy is generally seen as a form of plutocratic power: the currency of its authority is derived from concrete resources. This makes plutocracy different from aristocracy, which used to derive its power from social resources such as titles of nobility and social status.</p><p>Unlike democracy, what gives philanthropy its substantive action-power exists prior to and outside its decision-making process. Money, for example, is a resource that individuals gather and possess before they even decide to act in a philanthropic manner. This is fundamentally different from what happens in a democracy. Imagine that instead of having one token each, citizens have unequal amount of tokens. By taking as legitimate the authority derived from material resources, philanthropy creates a fundamentally asymmetric form of decision-making, as the source of this authority—wealth or time—is unequally distributed. Since some individuals have more of these resources than others, poorer individuals must accept the decisions of richer ones. And since philanthropic resources exist prior to and after the decision-making process, the tokens may be used with much more flexibility than democratic ones. Instead of waiting on elected official's decision or popular votations, philanthropy might offer my friend and I two options for the creating a new theater: First, we could pool our money and fund it ourselves. Second, we could use our resources to advocate that theaters are an important part of a rich cultural life and that the local government should fund one. The options are not strictly the same, as the first one would probably leave the philanthropist with more decision-making power over the theater's activities, but the example nevertheless shows the impact of authority based on external resources. In both options, calling on philanthropic resources allows us to realize public purposes rather than relying on the democratic process.</p><p>Disparities between large and small philanthropic foundations clearly illustrate how difference in resources shape philanthropy's action power. It is clear that the Bill and Melinda Gates’ foundation disposed of much more resources to shape the American system than a smaller local philanthropic organization. However, conceptually, it should not be assumed that the political authority derived from these entities are more or less distinct from democratic authority solely based on the tangible impact they have on policy-making or public decision-making. Democracy is democratic as long as the kind of authority exercised by every citizen remains at the same time strictly second-personal, mutual and its currency is external. Even the slightest number of external resources aimed at giving direction to public decisions and actions will be incompatible will change the nature of relationships instantiate by such democratic forms of collectively-binding decision-making.</p><p>In this section, I have explained that philanthropy embodies a specific logic of authority. Philanthropic authority is <i>unilaterally</i> exercised, allowing the donor to have a direct and individual say in public decisions. It takes its normativity from a mix of <i>first-personality</i> and <i>third-personality</i>, appealing to reasons that are not linked to any relations of claim-rights between decision-makers. And the currency of philanthropy—what materializes its action-power—is <i>external</i> to the decision-making process rather than being internally created as in a one-person, one-vote system. Given these constitutive rules, authority emerging from philanthropic practices is fundamentally different from that emerging from democratic ones, which is characterized by the rules of mutualism, second-personality, and externality of currency.</p><p>My characterization of philanthropic authority is important in at least two manners. First, it allows us to clearly understand what philanthropy involves for public decisions and how it relates to democracy. This characterization thus shows what should be taken into consideration when determining which kind of decision-making tool should be employed for public decisions. Clarifying how these two logics of authority differ seems to indicate how difficult it might be to reconcile them. Introducing philanthropy in a democracy changes, for better or worse, the relations of accountability shared by citizens. My characterization of philanthropy points to its inherently political nature. It emphasizes that philanthropy is not purely benevolent (as it can be used as a tool to affect the making of public decision) without assuming that it is always aimed at secretly pulling the strings of government.</p><p>A second manner in which this characterization is significant is that of making sense of the numerous philanthropic practices that exist. Focusing on the kind of authority that emanates from philanthropy allows us to gain a clear account of what different forms of philanthropy share, from the smallest donation to the largest sum given by the richest individual. This paper shows that giving is not voting, and even if the final result of these two decision-making methods may be the same, or even if their action power is weaker, the methods nevertheless change the nature of the relationship between those affected by the decisions.</p><p>Similarly, my characterization enables an understanding of mixed or in-between cases, such as when philanthropy is encouraged publicly through tax incentives. Constitutive rules teach us that practices characterized by them cannot be changed, even by a little, without risking the nature of that practice. In this sense, it is not possible to make philanthropy analytically more democratic by giving it a public varnish. Public incentives or public–private partnerships<sup>10</sup> represent normative positions concerning philanthropy within a democracy. They articulate the types of philanthropic practices deemed desirable or valuable in a democratic society. Such desirability can itself be democratically established through specific policies. For instance, the very existence of philanthropy is contingent on its democratic authorization. However, the normative reasons guiding our encouragement or discouragement of philanthropy in a democracy do not alter the analytical characterization of the practice itself. Philanthropic authority is exercised unilaterally, originating from first and third-personal reasons for actions, and its currency is external to the collectively binding decision-making process it initiates.</p><p>Furthermore, discerning the differentiation between philanthropic authority and other forms of private practice might seem challenging. For instance, consider a scenario where a friend and I opt to establish a for-profit corporation instead of choosing philanthropy to construct a new theater. The authority exercised as a corporation could mirror that of philanthropy: unilateral decision-making (our choice to build the theater and determine the show), rooted in our personal reasons for action, and with an external impact on citizens through the currency (money). It appears that philanthropic and for-profit activities share similarities, but their substantive difference lies in their directed objectives: public purposes, as oppose to for-profit ones. However, delineating between for-profit and nonprofit actions was beyond the scope of this paper.</p><p>Lastly, I wish to emphasize a central implication stemming from my characterization of philanthropy. Asserting that philanthropy and democracy represent two distinct forms of authority does not inherently favor or oppose philanthropic actions in public spheres. My aim in characterizing philanthropy is to highlight the nature of making collectively binding decisions using this practice and its implications for democracy. Consequently, my intention is not to argue for or against the various normative values of philanthropy, as presented by the political theorists referenced in this paper. Depending on preferred democratic ideals, some might find the unilateral nature of philanthropy advantageous. Supporters of this view often commend the efficacy of philanthropy over public actions. Others might believe that philanthropy, by utilizing external resources, offers a wide range of possibilities potentially unavailable to the state. This aligns with Rob Reich's defense of the discovery argument for philanthropic foundations. However, other scholars may contend that the first and third-personal nature of philanthropy risks subjecting citizens to the goodwill of their benefactors.</p><p>I have argued that there is a constitutive difference between philanthropy and democracy. Understood as two tools for the making of collectively binding decisions, they instantiate two forms of authority differentiated by their constitutive rules. First, where democracy's exercise of authority is mutual, and its citizens are co-subject and coauthor of laws, philanthropic authority is unilateral in the sense of being imposable on others. Second, the source of democratic authority is second-personal, anchoring citizens’ reasons for action in the interpersonal relationship they all share. In contrast, philanthropy is first- and third-personal, so that philanthropists’ reasons for action are internal to themselves while instantiating an external source of normativity in relation to those who will be subject to it. Finally, where democracy's currency of authority is created within the decision-making process, philanthropy takes its authority from resources that are external to the process and unequally distributed.</p><p>This paper shed light on how philanthropy and democracy differ as forms of authority even if they aim at the same public purposes. My analytical characterization of philanthropy showed what features of the practice should be taken into consideration in normative discussions of the kind of decision-making tools to deploy for making collectively binding decisions. The encompassing focus of this work also allowed us to gain a clear account of what different forms of philanthropy share, from the smallest donation to the largest donations.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"32 1\",\"pages\":\"33-46\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-09-04\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12759\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12759\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12759","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

2000年,比尔和梅林达·盖茨基金会解决了一个与美国教育系统有关的问题:令人不满意的高中毕业率和大学入学率,特别是在城市学区(Ravitch, 2011)。2000年至2008年间,该基金会向美国45个州的2600所学校捐赠了20多亿美元。比尔和梅琳达·盖茨的目标是明确的:他们认为K - 121教育系统是“过时的”,需要进行彻底的改革(Ravitch, 2011)。盖茨基金会的领导人注意到,美国的一些学校可以容纳多达4000或5000名学生,导致一部分需要额外关注的学生被忽视。基于当代研究和公民社会已经存在的运动,他们得出结论,较小的学校是学生成功的关键。在公共预算削减的背景下,没有多少学校董事会会拒绝数百万美元的慈善捐赠。因此,盖茨基金会开始在美国各地分发资金,并将其捐赠与能够促进以效率为基础的教育理念的条件联系起来。起初,学校被要求重组,分成独立的单元,每个单元不超过400名学生。后来,教师的绩效工资和国家标准测试,作为有效性的衡量标准,成为资金的强制性标准。虽然这一制度使一些学校受益,但在大多数情况下,它产生的问题比解决的问题要多。例如,将大型学校分割成小型自治单位增加了冲突和争夺资源的竞争,并剥夺了学生参加一系列只有大型学校才提供的活动的机会。盖茨项目在一开始受到称赞,但在2005年第一次评估出来时,遭到了严厉的批评。2008年,基金会的董事们认识到他们项目的糟糕开端,他们大多把责任归咎于他们所帮助的学校缺乏接受能力,或者教师缺乏能力。几个月后,基金会决定关闭这个项目。在一个民主国家,我们有充分的理由相信,关于学校基础设施、教育项目和教师工资等公共产品的集体约束性决策应该由公民或代表他们的人来执行。然而,比尔和梅琳达·盖茨基金会的案例表明,一些人或组织凭借其私人资源,在这些问题上拥有额外的、有时甚至更大的发言权。这就提出了民主和慈善的逻辑是否相容的问题。这个问题更为紧迫,因为慈善捐赠通常是由税收补贴的,因此代表了公共资金的重新定向(Pevnick, 2013),其目标可能是促进捐赠者的个人利益。政治哲学家们一直在争论慈善事业在自由民主国家中应该扮演的角色。一方面,大量的研究认为慈善事业不应该在分配正义中发挥作用,因为基本商品的私人和自愿再分配太不可靠(Beerbohm, 2016),可能会影响平等主义价值观(Cordelli, 2012),强化权力不对称(Lechterman, 2021),并构成一种家长式的援助(Saunders-Hastings, 2022)。另一方面,慈善事业可能有助于促进社会创新(Reich, 2018),培养充满活力的文化生活(Pevnick, 2013),作为代际正义的手段(Cordelli &amp;Reich, 2016),维护公共机构行动(Ceva, 2021),或补充提供司法不需要的商品(Lechterman, 2021)。总而言之,慈善行为因允许各种利益被纳入集体决策而受到赞扬,同时因其包括它们的不平等方式而受到批评(Saunders-Hastings, 2022)。虽然许多政治哲学家因此讨论了为什么慈善事业在民主中可能或可能不可取的规范性问题,但很少有人停下来解决先前和更基本的分析问题,即如果有的话,是什么使慈善事业在某种程度上具有特殊性,从而可能引发与民主相容的问题。我在本文中认为,尽管慈善和民主的目标相同,但它们体现了两种截然不同的政治权威形式。政治权威是个人或机构在道德上和法律上的合法权力,用于指导公共行为在民主社会中,这种指示活动(权威的实践)是通过具有集体约束力的决策来实现的。我展示了,虽然民主实践使人们能够共同做出相互约束的决定,但慈善行为使他们能够根据自己的单方面偏好为公共决策和行动提供方向。 基于这一基本观察,我认为慈善捐赠可能是权力的载体,当它们是,它们带有一种特定形式的权威,不同于支撑权威的民主逻辑。本文是这样展开的。首先,我简要介绍了作为权威实践的民主(第2节)。然后,我对慈善事业进行了概念分析,展示了如何将其视为一种权威实践(第3节)。然后,我概述了我们如何构想慈善事业与民主之间的关系(第4节)。最后,我将慈善事业描述为一种权威构成实践,该实践由单边主义的三个构成规则定义;第一,第三人格,以及货币的外部性(第5节)。这项工作的目的主要是分析性的。因此,当我指出权威的民主逻辑和博爱逻辑之间的不同关系时,我并不是在为一种实践辩护,而反对另一种实践。当然,正如政治理论中经常出现的情况一样,我的分析性和概念性工作可能有助于阐明进一步的规范性问题。例如,我的讨论表明,慈善和民主是不同决策工具的分析区别,可以告知一个政体应该选择什么工具的规范性问题,知道选择会改变,无论好坏,涉及这些决策的人之间关系的性质。从这个意义上说,虽然我对本文的主要兴趣是分析性的,但我将得出的区别可以有效地为未来对慈善事业在民主中的作用的规范性评估提供信息。本文探讨了社会和政治组织的一种特殊模式:民主。当我指出权威的民主逻辑和博爱逻辑之间的分歧关系时,为了清楚地理解我的意思,我简要地介绍了前者的概念。为此,我借鉴了Ceva和Ottonelli(2021)的论文《第二个人权威与民主实践》(Second-Personal Authority and Practice of Democracy),该论文对民主进行了描述性(非规范性)描述。Ceva和Ottonelli指出了民主实践的基本特征。他们没有提供理由说明为什么我们应该更喜欢民主而不是其他类型的政治组织,他们也不关心民主的定义。他们的目的是了解做出民主决策和在这些决策下生活的含义。对于Ceva和Ottonelli(2021)来说,民主是一种基于规则的社会和政治实践。这意味着民主实践是由一套规则定义的,这些规则实例化了只存在于这些规则中的特殊行为和关系。这也意味着那些参与民主实践的人被赋予了特定的权利,以规范性权力和角色的形式,以一种特定于这套规则的方式(Ceva &amp;Ottonelli, 2021)。民主实践所体现的一个具体角色是具有集体约束力的决策的制定者(Ceva &amp;Ottonelli, 2021)。民主行为体(即公民)行使权力共同作出决定,直接(如通过公民投票)或间接(如通过选举代表),这些决定根据特定的权利和义务关系约束公民。这种权力与其他类型的决策权(如君主制或寡头制)的特征和区别在于构成民主实践逻辑的一套规则。在Ceva和Ottonelli的论文中,这些本构规则是双重的。首先,民主权威是相互的(Ceva &amp;Ottonelli, 2021)。相互性指的是民主权力如何行使。这意味着民主权威以及由此产生的决定由所有决策者共同行使。Eric Beerbohm(2012)认为,正是这种互惠主义使公民既是“法律的共同主体,也是共同作者”(Beerbohm, 2012,第44页)。例如,这与女王的权力形成鲜明对比,女王可以单方面制定法律,约束她的人民,而不是她自己。其次,民主实践也是第二个人(Ceva &amp;Ottonelli, 2021)。这里提到的人格概念指的是权威的来源,也就是触发X人行为的原因。第二人格是指触发X行为的是Y人的原因,就像我和你的关系一样(Darwall, 2006)。民主涉及第二人格,因为在这种实践中具体体现的权利类型。民主产生了所谓的主张权利。根据Hohfeld的分析,那些拥有这种权利的人可以要求(即,他们是某种待遇的来源)来自特定的个人:义务承担者(Hohfeld, 1919)。 比如说,我和一个朋友达成了一个口头协议(举例说明前面提到的这种权利与义务之间的特殊关系),让他有权在演出中使用我的吉他。根据这项协议,我的朋友有义务在音乐会结束时把吉他还给我。此外,我将有权收回我的吉他,我的朋友将是唯一被允许履行义务的人。是什么触发了我朋友的责任——他把吉他还给我的理由——是我的索取权。民主的实践以同样的方式约束公民使用权力。由于所有民主公民都是主张权利的持有者,他们也是义务的承担者。这意味着,例如,当公民直接就某一议题投票时,5这就赋予了他们集体决定法律内容的权力,并使这些公民有义务尊重新决定的法律的内容,因为他们每个人都对其他人有要求权利和义务。因此,公民通过参与民主实践,成为彼此权利义务的所有者和来源。这导致Ceva和Ottonelli(2021)注意到“民主选民之间的关系构成了一个新的‘我们’,一个权利所有者的集体,他们以这种身份而不是其他身份,共同承认彼此是他们相互要求和义务的最终权威”(第6页)。因此,互惠主义制定了民主权威如何被行使(由所有决策者共同行使)。而第二人格则强调了公民行为理由的来源(他们的相互要求-权利和义务)。我建议在互性(行使)和第二人格(来源)之外增加第三条民主权威的构成规则;它涉及当局的货币。这条规则涉及到是什么赋予了当局有效的行动权力。通过货币,我指的是在制定具有集体约束力的决策时赋予权力的资源。将权威的货币视为令牌是有帮助的。在民主国家,公民只能使用一种特定类型的代币。这个标志是民主投票,它是所有民主决定的基础当公民参与民主决策过程时,他们被赋予投票权。作为代币的投票权反映了一人一票制度的基本思想:它们同时具有独特性和相似性。它们是独一无二的,因为每个公民都有自己的代币。但所有代币都是相似的,因为它们的价值完全相同。当公民投票时,他们并不比其他公民行使更多的权力。此外,这些代币只存在于民主决策过程中(即具有货币)。它们不存在于民主制度之前、之后,也不存在于民主制度之外。朋友之间没有这种权威,这种权威也不仅仅是由于公民关系而拥有的。例如,一群朋友民主地投票赞成建造一个新剧院,要求附近的其他人为这个项目做出贡献是不够的。投票只有在特殊的体制环境中进行,才对某一特定选民具有约束力;当这种环境涉及到其他每一个公民时,它就是民主的,因为他们参与了相互的和第二个人的关系。当我在第5节讨论民主与慈善的区别时,我重新审视了民主的构成规则。在此之前,我必须描述一下慈善事业的特点。既然这项工作的背景已经确定,我就开始对慈善事业进行概念分析。这一节允许我介绍慈善作为一种社会和政治实践的概念。一个被一致接受的慈善定义并不存在。各种各样的术语,如慈善、非营利部门、第三部门、慈善、慈善行为和施舍,都描述了给予的行为或背景。对珍妮·哈罗(Jenny Harrow)和西沃恩·戴利(Siobhan Daly)来说,这是因为慈善是一个集群的、本质上有争议的概念。它是集群的,因为它“能够被多个利益相关者多重定义,因此对其性质和目的的平行理解在研究中共存”(Harrow, 2010,p。123),而其本质的可竞争性体现在其内部的复杂性、多样化的可描述性、多维性以及存在于不同规范的慈善概念之间的持续竞争(Daly, 2012)。在众多关于慈善事业的概念中,有一种将其视为一种实践:“为广泛的公共目的自愿贡献私人资源(通常是金钱,但也包括实物物品或时间),捐赠人不会因此而获得一般意义上的报酬(尽管她可能会收到诱惑、感谢礼物或其他形式的特殊报酬,例如: (获得音乐会门票)。这种自愿捐款可以由团体或法人实体(如公司)以及个人做出”(Saunders-Hastings, 2019, p. 1)。更简单地说,慈善事业可以被概括为为公共目的自愿承诺私有财产(Ostrower, 1997),作为一种受正式和非正式规则约束的社会和政治实践(Lechterman, 2021)。从这个角度来看,慈善事业允许个人在被认为是公共利益的事情上有发言权。根据这一概念,我强调了慈善实践的四个特征。首先,它只能由个人或私人组织行使;它不能由国家或其代表行使。政府可以激励慈善行为,但它不能以慈善的方式提供金钱或实物。让我们想象一下,在一场大流行之后,民选官员决定提供一笔特别赠款,将资金分配给他们国家最贫困的人。为了资助这笔拨款,政府决定向最富有的5%的人征收额外的税。不能说这笔赠款的目标人群受益于最富有的5%的慈善事业。他们得到这笔钱是因为,按照民主逻辑做出的决定,他们有权利要求得到这笔钱,这引发了纳税人采取行动的第二个个人原因。这也将慈善事业与公共国际组织(如发展援助机构)的行动区分开来,因为在这种情况下,提供资源的决定也来自公共决策。虽然国家可以是慈善捐赠的发起者和接受者,但只有私人和组织才能进行慈善捐赠。第二,慈善行为必须以公共目的为目标。出于目前的目的,我把这个概念留得有点开放,因为公共目的可以有多种形式。然而,并不是所有的目的都可以被认为是公共的。继Lechterman(2021)之后,“公共”可以指“向所有人开放”(就像“酒吧”向任何有能力支付饮料的顾客开放一样),“普遍”(就像“公用事业”意味着覆盖一个地区的所有居民一样),以及“集体授权”,“集体受益”和“政府”。因此,“私人”一词更倾向于指对特定个人有利的行为。从这个意义上说,非公共或私人目的将包括市场交换,父母给子女的遗产,一个人给他或她的一个朋友的礼物,或者再次向自己是会员的俱乐部捐款。宣传的必要条件是,任何慈善行为的目的都是实际上使最大多数人受益,这里的“实际上”意味着任何人都应该可以获得。显然,在这个框架下,像对孤儿病研究的捐赠这样的情况,可能只涉及非常有限的患者数量,仍然可以算作慈善。类似的可及性概念可以在英美语境中找到,在英美语境中,慈善事业应该使无限数量的人受益。第三,慈善必须是自愿的,被理解为不是强制性的。税收不能被认为是慈善事业,因为国家使用其强制性权力迫使公民支付他们必须支付的和他们有义务支付的(墨菲&;内格尔,2002)。第四,慈善事业涉及私有财产的转移。如果金钱是人们想到慈善捐赠时首先想到的资源,那么它远不是唯一的资源。时间、物品和服务都可以捐赠。虽然精英慈善事业的特点往往是通过基金会等组织流动的资金数量(MacKenzie, 2021),但现金很少是这些机构的最终贡献。大规模提供的医疗援助、新建筑、咨询、法律援助和水分配可能需要大量资金,但它们的接受者不会直接获得现金。总之,慈善可以被视为一种社会和政治实践,定义为只能由私人行为者行使,以公共目的为目标,是自愿的,与私有财产的转移有关。在进一步讨论之前,有必要澄清一点。人们经常注意到,慈善这个词来源于希腊语,意思是“对人类的爱”。这个词源指出了慈善事业作为一种动机的概念:“对人类的爱或对共同利益的关注(无论是对一般人类还是对更有限的群体)”(Saunders-Hastings, 2019,第1页)。在此之后,只要捐赠者有一定的动机,他们就是在做慈善。然而,我想说的是,捐赠背后的动机和道德标准与慈善事业的政治审查无关。每个人都有自己慷慨的理由。 也许他们这样做是因为他们认为这在道德上很重要,也许仅仅是因为他们的口袋太重了,也许是为了向世界展示他们是好人,或者也许是为了改变社会。然而,至关重要的是,无论这个决定是出于某种原因还是出于某种原因,都不会从本质上改变一个人在行使源于慈善行为的权力时所拥有的那种权力。在盖茨基金会的案例中,事实证明,它的慷慨捐赠有助于促进学校的商业组织和新的公共管理方法(Ravitch, 2011;索特曼,2011)。毕竟,众所周知,慈善事业不仅源于利他的感觉(Andreoni, 1990),而且可能是私人政治倡导或议程设置的工具(Reich, 2018)。然而,在自由民主国家,慈善事业的这一特征不应被视为根本问题。毕竟,盖茨的计划可能反映了当时许多其他美国公民所共有的教育观念。作为公民,盖茨夫妇可以自由地倡导他们喜欢的教育理念。然而,这个案例引发的紧张源于这种特定的教育概念向公众传达的方式:在教育系统中投票支持商业组织是一回事,而仅仅因为有资源就通过定义和设定一个国家教育的政治议程来绕过民主程序是另一回事,就像比尔和梅林达·盖茨所做的那样。但是,无论一个人从事慈善事业的原因是什么,从中产生的那种权威将保持不变。慈善作为一种实践的概念分析揭示的一个关键点是,慈善和民主在某种程度上都是追求公共事业。它们都是指导具体行动的工具,可以促进社会正义,促进充满活力的文化生活,资助基础教育和高等教育,培育民主创新,倡导更美好社会的愿景,或解决与健康有关的问题。因此,慈善和民主可以被解释为不同的,甚至可能是相互竞争的公共事业决策工具。对这种竞争的一种解释是,在非理想环境下的民主社会可能面临资源短缺,因此可能不得不在公共和私人资助的商品和服务之间做出选择。第二种方式,也是我在这里感兴趣的,是关于慈善和民主对集体约束决策的不同影响。对于许多学者来说,慈善事业最显著的特征是它允许捐赠者行使一种围绕物质资源的权力形式(Beerbohm, 2016;Cordelli, 2016, 2020;Cordelli,帝国,2016;Lambelet et al., 2019;Lechterman, 2021;Lechterman,帝国,2020;帝国,2018;Saunders-Hastings, 2018, 2019)。鉴于这一特点,他们中的大多数人认为,在民主社会中,慈善事业是不一致的,原则上,民主社会的决策应该是集体平等地做出的。对艾玛·桑德斯-黑斯廷斯(Emma Saunders-Hastings)来说,慈善事业“赋予捐赠者在公共生活和特定受益人方面的影响力和权威。”它塑造了公共选择和个人可获得的选择”(Saunders-Hastings, 2022,第5页)。根据罗布·赖克(Rob Reich, 2018)的说法,慈善基金会是“民主制度中的怪异现象”(第144页),因为它们代表了富豪、不负责任和不透明的政治权力工具,而对莱奇特曼(Lechterman, 2021)来说,慈善是一种具有富豪倾向的私人权力形式。这些观察在无数有趣的规范命题中蓬勃发展然而,问题在于上述作者没有充分地告诉我们,慈善事业的内在区别是什么,这可能会引起人们对其与民主的兼容性的担忧。目前还缺乏一个系统的分析框架,来描述慈善与民主在做出具有集体约束力的决策时所扮演的角色之间的根本区别。瑞安·佩夫尼克已经朝这个方向迈出了第一步。在他的著作《慈善与民主理想》(Philanthropy and Democratic Ideals)中,他承认慈善事业在民主政权中经常遇到的不适,但他表达了自己的目标:“我在这一章中的目标是概念性的。我试图超越慈善与民主之间最初的紧张关系,对慈善在一个运作良好的民主中可能正确主张的角色进行仔细的描述”(Pevnick, 2016,第227页)。他通过比较慈善在两种截然不同的民主理想(市场民主和民主平等)中的潜在作用来实现这一点。市场民主和民主平等都建立在基本的自由主义原则基础上,但它们在公民个人、治理和正义的概念上存在分歧。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。

Philanthropy and democracy: Two kinds of authority

Philanthropy and democracy: Two kinds of authority

In 2000, the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation tackled an issue concerning the American education system: unsatisfactory high school graduation rates and college entry rates, especially in urban school districts (Ravitch, 2011). Between 2000 and 2008, this foundation donated more than $2 billion to 2600 schools across 45 US states. Bill and Melinda Gates's aim was clearly spelled out: they saw the K−121 education system as “obsolete”2 and in need of drastic reforms (Ravitch, 2011). The Gates Foundation's leaders observed that some schools in the United States could host up to 4000 or 5000 pupils, leading to the neglect of a portion of students who needed extra attention. Based on contemporary research and already-existing movements in civil society,3 they concluded that smaller schools were the key to students’ success.

In a context of public budget cuts, not many school boards could refuse a multimillion-dollar philanthropic donation. Hence, the Gates Foundation started to distribute money all over the United States, tying its gifts to conditions that would promote an effectiveness-based conception of education. At first, schools were asked to restructure and split themselves into independent units of no more than 400 students. Later, performance-based pay for teachers and national-standards tests, serving as effectiveness yardsticks, became mandatory for funding.

Although this system benefited some schools, it created more problems than it solved in the great majority of cases. For example, the fragmentation of large schools into small autonomous units increased conflict and competition for resources and deprived students of a significant range of activities that were only provided in larger institutions. Praised in the beginning, the Gates program was sharply criticized in 2005 when the first evaluations came out. In 2008, the foundation's directors recognized the bad start of their program and mostly put the blame on the lack of receptivity of the schools they helped or on teachers’ lack of competence. A few months later, the foundation decided to all but shut the program down.

In a democracy, there are good reasons to believe that the making of collectively binding decisions about such public goods as school infrastructures, education programs, and teachers’ salary should be carried out by citizens or people who speak in their name. However, the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation's case shows a sense in which some people or organizations, by virtue of their private resources, have an additional and sometimes larger say on such questions. This raises the question whether the logics of democracy and philanthropy are compatible. The question is more pressing because philanthropic donations are generally tax subsidized, representing therefore a redirection of public money (Pevnick, 2013) toward aims likely to advance donors’ personal interests.

Political philosophers have debated the role that philanthropy should have in liberal democratic states. On the one hand, a good amount of work argues that philanthropy should not assume a role in distributive justice, as private and voluntary redistribution of basic goods is too unreliable (Beerbohm, 2016), might affect egalitarian values (Cordelli, 2012), reinforces power asymmetries (Lechterman, 2021), and constitutes a paternalistic type of assistance (Saunders-Hastings, 2022). On the other hand, philanthropy may help promote social innovations (Reich, 2018), foster a vibrant cultural life (Pevnick, 2013), serve as a means for intergenerational justice (Cordelli & Reich, 2016), uphold public institutional action (Ceva, 2021), or supplement the provision of goods unrequired by justice (Lechterman, 2021). All in all, philanthropic actions have been praised for allowing a variety of interests to be included in collective decision-making while being criticized for the unequal manner by which it includes them (Saunders-Hastings, 2022).

While many political philosophers have thus discussed the normative question of why philanthropy might or might not be desirable in a democracy, few have paused to address the prior and more fundamental analytical question of what, if anything, makes philanthropy inherently specific in such a way that it may raise issues of compatibility with democracy. I argue in this paper that, although philanthropy and democracy aim at the same goal, they instantiate two distinct forms of political authority. Political authority is the morally and legally legitimate power of an individual or institution to give direction to public action.4 In a democratic society, such a direction-giving activity (the practice of authority) is carried out by collectively binding decision-making. I show how, while democratic practices enable people to make mutually binding decisions together, philanthropic acts allow them to give direction to public decisions and actions based on their own unilateral preferences. Building on this basic observation, I argue that philanthropic donations may be vectors of power, and when they are, they carry a specific form of authority that differs from that underpinning the democratic logic of authority.

This paper unfolds in the following way. I start with a brief sketch of democracy as a practice of authority (Section 2). I then offer a conceptual analysis of philanthropy, showing how it can be conceived of as an authority practice (Section 3). I then provide an overview of how we can conceive of the relationship between philanthropy and democracy (Section 4). Finally, I develop my account of philanthropy as an authority-constituting practice defined by the three constitutive rules of unilateralism; first & third personality, and externality of currency (Section 5).

The aim of this work is primarily analytical. Hence, when I point to a divergent relation between the democratic and philanthropic logics of authority, I do not defend one practice against the other. Of course, as is often the case in political theory, my analytical and conceptual work may serve to elucidate further normative issues. For example, my discussion suggests that the analytical distinction that philanthropy and democracy are different decision-making tools, which can inform the normative question of what tool a polity should choose, knowing that the choice would change, for better or worse, the nature of the relationship between those implicated in those decisions. In this sense, while my primary interest in the paper is analytical, the distinction I shall draw can usefully inform future normative appraisals of the role of philanthropy in a democracy.

This paper inquiries into philanthropy within a particular mode of social and political organization: democracy. To gain a clear idea of what I mean when I point to a divergent relation between the democratic and philanthropic logics of authority, I briefly introduce the former concept. To do so, I build on Ceva and Ottonelli's (2021) paper “Second-Personal Authority and the Practice of Democracy”, which offers a descriptive (nonnormative) account of democracy.

Ceva and Ottonelli identify the basic features of the practice of democracy. They do not offer reasons why we should prefer democracy over other types of political organization, nor do they concern themselves with defining democracy. Their aim is rather to understand what making democratic decisions and living under these decisions involve. For Ceva and Ottonelli (2021), democracy is a rule-based social and political practice. That means that democratic practices are defined by a set of rules that instantiate special actions and relations that exist only within these rules. It also means that those who engage in the democratic practices are assigned specific rights in the form of normative power and roles in a way that is particular to this set of rules (Ceva & Ottonelli, 2021).

One of the specific roles instantiated by democratic practices is that of maker of collectively binding decisions (Ceva & Ottonelli, 2021). Democratic actors (i.e., citizens) wield the authority to make decisions together, either directly (e.g., through referenda) or indirectly (e.g., by electing representatives), and those decisions bind citizens according to a specific relationship of rights and duties. What characterizes and differentiates this authority from other types of decision-making power (such as monarchic or oligarchic) is the set of rules that constitute the logic of the democratic practice.

In Ceva and Ottonelli's paper, these constitutive rules are twofold. First, democratic authority is mutual (Ceva & Ottonelli, 2021). Mutuality refers to how the democratic authority is exercised. It means that the democratic authority, and the decisions that result from it, is exercised jointly by all decision-makers. Eric Beerbohm (2012) suggests that this mutualism is what makes citizens both “cosubjects of the law and coauthors” (Beerbohm, 2012, p. 44). This contrasts, for example, with the power of a queen, who can unilaterally enact laws that will constrain her people but not herself.

Second, democratic practices are also second-personal (Ceva & Ottonelli, 2021). The notion of personality invoked here refers to the source of an authority, that is, the reasons that triggers person X's action. Second- personality is the idea that what triggers X's action is person Y's reasons, as in an I–you relationship (Darwall, 2006). Democracy involves second-personality because of the specific type of rights that are instantiated during this practice. Democracy generates what are called claim-rights. Following a Hohfeldian analysis, those who hold this kind of right can claim (i.e., they are the source of) certain treatment from specific individuals: the duty bearers (Hohfeld, 1919).

Say, for example, that I make an oral agreement (instantiating this specific type of aforementioned relationship between claim-rights and duties) with a friend giving him the right to use my guitar for a gig. By that agreement, my friend becomes bound by a duty to give me back my guitar at the end of the concert. Moreover, I will have the right to reclaim my guitar, and my friend will be the only person allowed to fulfill the duty. What triggers my friend's duty—his reason to give me back my guitar—is my claim-right. The practice of democracy binds citizens in their use of power in the same way. As all democratic citizens are claim-right holders, they also are duty bearers. This means that, for example, when citizens vote directly on a given topic,5 it gives them the authority to collectively decide the content of a law and it binds those citizens to respect the content of the newly decided law because each of them has a claim-right and a duty toward the others. Thus, by virtue of their participating in the democratic practice, citizens become the owners and sources of each other's rights and duties. This leads Ceva and Ottonelli (2021) to note that “the relations between democratic voters constitute a new ‘we,’ a collective of rights holders who, in that very capacity and no other, jointly recognize each other as the final authorities on their reciprocal claims and duties” (p. 6).

Mutualism hence enacts how the democratic authority is exercised (jointly by all decision-makers), while second-personality underlines the source of citizens’ reason for action (their reciprocal claim-rights and duties). I suggest adding a third constitutive rule of democratic authority to mutuality (exercise) and second-personality (source); it concerns the authority's currency. This rule concerns what gives an authority its effective action-power. By currency, I refer to the resources that empower the authority bearer in the making of collectively binding decisions. It is helpful to think about the currency of an authority as a token. In a democracy, citizens may only make use of one specific type of token. This token, which is at the root of all democratic decisions, is the democratic vote.6 When citizens enter the democratic decision-making process, they are granted voting rights.

Voting rights as tokens reflect the basic idea of a one-person, one-vote system: they are at the same time unique and similar. They are unique because each citizen disposes of their own single token. But all tokens are similar in the sense that they are worth the exact same amount of power. When a citizen casts a vote, they exercise no more authority than any of their co-citizens. Moreover, these tokens only exist (i.e., have currency) within the democratic decision-making process. They do not exist prior to, after, or outside the democratic institution. Friends do not have this type of authority over each other, nor is this kind of authority possessed by virtue of citizenship relationships alone. For example, it is not enough that a group of friends democratically vote in favor of building a new theater for asking other people in the neighborhood to contribute to the project. Voting acquires its binding capacity on a given constituency only if carried out within a special institutional settings; it is democratic when this setting implicates every other citizen, as they are engaged in mutual and second-personal relationships.

I revisit the constitutive rules of democracy in Section 5 when I discuss their differences from those of philanthropy. Before I do that, I must characterize the practice of philanthropy.

Now that the background of this work has been set, I proceed with a conceptual analysis of philanthropy. This section allows me to introduce the conception of philanthropy as a social and political practice.

An unanimously accepted definition of philanthropy does not exist. Various terms, such as charity, nonprofit sector, third sector, benevolence, eleemosynary acts, and alms, describe the action or context of giving. For Jenny Harrow and Siobhan Daly, this is because philanthropy is a clustered and essentially contested concept. It is clustered because it is “capable of being multiply defined by multiple stakeholders, so that parallel understandings of its nature and purpose coexist in research” (Harrow, 2010,p. 123), while its essential contestability is reflected by the internal complexity, diverse describability, the multidimensionality, as well as the continuous competition that exist between the different normative conceptualization of philanthropy (Daly, 2012).

One of the many conceptions of philanthropy views it as a practice: “the voluntary contribution of private resources (usually money, but also in-kind goods or time) for broadly public purposes, and for which the giver does not receive payment in the ordinary sense (though she may receive inducements, thank-you gifts, or special consideration of other kinds, e.g., access to concert tickets). Such voluntary contributions may be made by groups or legal entities like corporations as well as by individuals” (Saunders-Hastings, 2019, p. 1). More simply put, philanthropy can be outlined as the voluntary commitment of private property for public purposes (Ostrower, 1997), as a social and political practice that is regulated by formal and informal rules (Lechterman, 2021). From this perspective, philanthropy allows private individuals to have a say in what is considered of public interest.

Following this conception, I highlight four defining features of philanthropic practice. First, it can only be exercised by private individuals or organizations; it cannot be exercised by the state or its representative. A government can incentivize philanthropic actions, but it cannot give money or in-kind goods away in a philanthropic way. Let us imagine that, following a pandemic, elected officials decide to provide an exceptional grant, allocating money to their country's worst off. To fund this grant, the government decides to collect extra taxes from the richest 5%. It cannot be said that the people targeted by this grant benefited from charity from the richest 5%. They receive this money because, following a decision made with democratic logic, they have a claim-right to it, which triggers a second-personal reason for action by the taxpayers. This also differentiates philanthropy from actions exercised by public international organizations such as development-aid agencies, as in this case also the decision to provide resources emerges from public decisions. While states can be authors and recipients of charitable donations, only private individuals and organizations can make philanthropic donations.

Second, to be described as philanthropic, an action must aim at public purposes. For present purposes, I leave this concept somewhat open, as a public purpose can take many forms. However, not just any purpose can be considered as public. Following Lechterman (2021) “Public” can mean “open to all” (in the way that a “pub” is open to any customer with the means to pay for a drink), “universal” (in the way that “public utilities” are meant to cover all residents of a region), as well as “collectively authorized,” “collectively beneficial,” and “governmental.”7 Consequently, “private” would rather refer to acts benefiting definite individuals. In this sense, nonpublic or private purposes would include market exchanges, parents’ inheritance to their children, gifts one makes to one of his or her friends, or again donations to clubs of which one is a member. The necessary condition of publicity is that any philanthropic act aims at virtually benefiting the greatest number, where “virtually” means that it should be accessible to anyone. Obviously, cases like donations to research against orphan disease, which may concern a very restricted number of patients, would still count as philanthropic under this framework. Similar conceptualizations of accessibility may be found in the Anglo-American context where it is stated that philanthropy should benefit an indefinite number.

Third, philanthropy must be voluntary, understood as not being coercively imposed. Taxes cannot be considered as philanthropy because the state uses its coercive power to force citizens to pay what they must and what they are duty bound to pay (Murphy & Nagel, 2002).

Fourth, philanthropy is concerned with the transfer of private property. If money is the first type of resource that comes to mind when one thinks about philanthropic donations, it is far from being the only one. Time, goods, and services may all be donated as well. While elite philanthropy is often characterized by the amount of money that flows through organizations such as foundations (MacKenzie, 2021), cash is rarely the final contribution of these institutions. To be provided on a large scale, medical aid, new buildings, counseling, legal assistance, and water distribution may require a lot of money, but their recipients are not directly given cash.

In summary, philanthropy can be conceived of as a social and political practice, defined as being only exercised by private actors, aiming at a public purpose, being voluntary, and being concerned with the transfer of private property.

Before going further, it is important to clarify a point. It is often noted that the word philanthropy derives from the Greek for “love of humanity.” This etymology points to the conception of philanthropy as a motivation: “the love of humanity or concern for the common good (whether of humanity in general or of a more circumscribed group)” (Saunders-Hastings, 2019, p. 1). Following this, as long as donors act with certain motives, they are acting philanthropically. However, I want to argue that the motives as well as moral standards underlying giving are not relevant to a political examination of philanthropy. Individuals have their own reasons for acting in a generous way. Maybe they do it because they think it is morally important, maybe simply because their pockets are too heavy, maybe to show the world that they are good human beings, or maybe to change society. What is crucial, however, is that whether the decision is made for X or Y reason does not substantially alter the kind of power one has when exercising authority derived from philanthropic acts.

In the case of the Gates Foundation, it has been demonstrated that its generous donation served to promote businesslike organization and new-public-management methods in schools (Ravitch, 2011; Saltman, 2011). After all, it is well known that philanthropy does not only derive from altruistic feelings (Andreoni, 1990) but may be an instrument of private political advocacy or agenda setting (Reich, 2018). However, this feature of philanthropy should not be seen as fundamentally problematic in liberal democracies. The Gateses’ program, after all, probably reflected a conception of education that was shared by many other US citizens at that time. And as citizens themselves, the Gateses are free to advocate for their preferred conception of education. Nevertheless, the tension raised by this case stems from the way this specific conception of education was conveyed to the public: it is one thing to cast a vote for businesslike organization in the education system, and another to bypass democratic processes by defining and setting the political agenda of a nation's education just because one has the resources to do so, as Bill and Melinda Gates did. But whatever the reasons one may have to practice philanthropy, the kind of authority that will emerge from it will remain the same.8

One crucial point that the conceptual analysis of philanthropy as a practice exposed is that philanthropy and democracy are, to some extent, both pursuing public causes. They are both tools to give direction to concrete actions that may advance social justice, foster a vibrant cultural life, fund basic and higher education, nurture democratic innovation, advocate visions of a better society, or tackle health-related issues. Hence, philanthropy and democracy can be interpreted as different and possibly competing decision-making tools for public causes. One way to interpret the competition is that democratic societies in nonideal contexts may face scarcity of resources, and a choice may have to be made between public and private funding of goods and services. A second way, the one I am interested in here, concerns the different implications of philanthropy and democracy for the making of collectively binding decisions.

For many scholars, the most striking feature of philanthropy is that it allows donors to exercise a form of power that revolves around material resources (Beerbohm, 2016; Cordelli, 2016, 2020; Cordelli & Reich, 2016; Lambelet et al., 2019; Lechterman, 2021; Lechterman & Reich, 2020; Reich, 2018; Saunders-Hastings, 2018, 2019). Given that feature, most of them argue that philanthropy is at odds in democratic societies where decisions should, in principle, be taken collectively and equally. For Emma Saunders-Hastings, philanthropy “gives donors influence and authority, in public life and over particular beneficiaries. It shapes public options and the choices available to individuals” (Saunders-Hastings, 2022, p. 5). Philanthropic foundations are, according to Rob Reich (2018), “institutional oddities in a democracy,” (p. 144) as they represent plutocratic, unaccountable, and nontransparent vehicle of political power, while, for Lechterman (2021), philanthropy is a form of private power with plutocratic tendencies.

These observations have flourished in a myriad of interesting normative propositions.9 However, the issue lies in the fact that the aforementioned authors do not adequately inform us about what inherently distinguishes philanthropy in a way that might raise concerns regarding its compatibility with democracy. What remains lacking is a systematic analytical framework that delineates the fundamental differences between philanthropy and democracy concerning their roles in making collectively binding decisions.

Ryan Pevnick has taken an initial step in this direction. In his work “Philanthropy and Democratic Ideals,” while acknowledging the discomfort that philanthropy often experiences within democratic regimes, he expresses his aim: “My goal in this chapter is conceptual. I seek to move beyond the initial tension between philanthropy and democracy by providing a careful account of the role philanthropy might properly claim in a well-functioning democracy” (Pevnick, 2016, p. 227). He accomplishes this by comparing the potential role of philanthropy in two distinct ideals of democracy: market democracy and democratic equality.

Market democracy and democratic equality, both grounded in fundamental liberal principles, diverge in their conceptions of individual citizens, governance, and justice. These differing conceptions yield contrasting assessments of the role philanthropy should assume within these democratic systems. Market democracies view individuals as responsible self-authors, governance revolves around a minimal government, and justice leans toward respecting market outcomes due to reasons of desert and efficiency (Pevnick, 2016). Advocates of market democracy thus see philanthropy as pivotal in providing noncoercive aid and fostering self-governance. Conversely, democratic equality emphasizes individual citizens as equal participants in a cooperative scheme, features a deliberative democracy, and champions justice marked by liberal egalitarianism. While proponents of this democratic ideal might view philanthropy skeptically, fearing it might undermine the idea of a community governed by equality, Pevnick argues that democratic equality should endorse philanthropic support for cultural projects.

This comparison has the merit to suggest that although philanthropy and democracy may appear in tension within democratic societies, this does not automatically render them incompatible. The degree of compatibility hinges on the specific type of democracy, such as its conception of freedom or equality. However, while this work acknowledges the difference between philanthropy and democracy without asserting inherent contradiction, it falls short in providing a robust analytical account of what fundamentally distinguishes the two. This shortfall arises because Pevnick's conceptual differentiation relies on normative ideals of democracy.

One approach to circumvent this issue could involve creating a taxonomy that catalogs every conceivable ideal of democracy, studying the role philanthropy should play in each, and identifying recurring themes. Another option might involve a descriptive (nonnormative) analysis of democracy followed by a comparative analytical study of philanthropy.

Emanuela Ceva and Valeria Ottonelli's characterization of democracy serves this purpose and is therefore the basis for my proposal of a conceptual analysis of philanthropy as an authoritative practice defined by constitutive rules.

One advantage of this analytical approach to philanthropy lies in its ability to make sense of the diverse philanthropic practices that exist. For instance, a difficulty that political theorists might encounter concerns the distinction between small-scale and large-scale (or elite) manifestations of philanthropy. Saunders-Hastings (2018) acknowledges this disparity in the following way: “Compared with ordinary donors, the very wealthy can influence the behavior of recipient organizations in more significant, sustained, and structured ways. This is especially true where they manage giving through their own institutions, of which the private foundation is the most important.” (p. 151) This is also reaffirmed when she states that ‘‘Mass philanthropy can be undemocratic or inegalitarian in its aggregate effects’’ (Saunders-Hastings, 2022, p. 122). Thus, she admits that while philanthropy generally conflicts with democracy, she perceives more issues in massive philanthropic donations compared to smaller, individual gifts.

While I also believe that that mass philanthropy, when aggregated, may present as many issues as elite philanthropy, my idea is that any kind of philanthropic action (whatever their amplitude) lacks basic democratic credentials. For sure, to differentiate between the consequences of small and big philanthropy is relevant, yet it is relevant only because of the exponential nature of the plutocratic form of authority that philanthropy exercises.

In a pure plutocracy, in which the wealthy rule, the more one owns, the more powerful one is. And Bill and Melinda Gates's potential power is unmistakably greater than that of a taxi driver who gives 100 Swiss francs to the local migrant associations every month. But looking only at who enjoys the most power neglects the full picture of the relationship between democracy and philanthropy. The fundamental difference between philanthropy and democracy concerns how someone acquires and exercises authority—that is, how they give direction to political action and how they do it. As authority is acquired and exercised in the form of donations, the logic of this authority will always be different from that which underpins democratic decision-making, which is mutual and second personal and in which currency is external to the decision-making process.

Obviously, when one donates 10 Swiss francs to a local school foundation, one may very well exercise less power than one who votes in an election. But this authority is still different from democratic authority. In this sense, although a small donation does not concretely change the state of affair of a society, they nevertheless carry the logic of authority that allow them to give direction to what is of public interest (and therefore to change the nature of the relationship between those implicated in those decisions) in a way that diverges from a democratic way of taking decisions.

Another advantage of my analytical approach lies in its ability to distinguish between two methods for making collectively binding decisions, which in practice are closely interlinked and often overlap. Consider, for instance, the cases involving tax incentives for philanthropy. One issue with such incentives is that they tend to blur the distinction between public and private actions.

Tax incentives are utilized by governments to encourage taxpayers to contribute philanthropically to causes deemed publicly valuable. When individuals donate money to these specific causes or institutions like philanthropic foundations engaged in such causes, they are permitted to deduct a portion or the entirety of their donations from what would have been their income tax obligations. The rationale behind these tax exemptions varies, but political theorists generally agree that donors are entitled to a tax reduction in order to ‘‘decentralize the process of producing social goods and promoting the pluralism of associational life by diminishing state orthodoxy in defining its contours’’ (Reich, 2018, p. 158). Consequently, it becomes challenging to argue that philanthropy represents a strictly distinct form of private power from democratic practices when incentivized by public institutions firmly rooted in democracy.

However, despite tax incentives publicly indicating which philanthropic practices are favored, they do not render philanthropy more democratic in terms of exercising an authority that is mutual, second-personal, and whose currency is internal to the decision-making process. For instance, an incentive can, at best, be interpreted as an encouragement to exercise one's liberty or as a form of supererogatory duty. Therefore, incentives do not evoke a relationship of rights and duties between two parties, as is observed in relationships characterized by second-personality.

Thus, even if philanthropic acts are particularly incentivized by public entities, they remain fundamentally distinct from democratic practices. This differentiation arises due to a crucial aspect of constitutive rules, which is their creation of a unique relationship among those implicated by them. This relationship exists exclusively within their defined boundaries and defines the activity as long as these rules remain unchanged (Rawls, 1955). Altering even one of the constitutive rules of democracy, even slightly, would significantly modify the interactions individuals experience within the authoritative practice. In essence, democracy maintains its democratic nature only when the type of authority exercised by every citizen remains simultaneously strictly second-personal, mutual, and an internal currency.

To understand how philanthropic authority differs from democratic authority in this manner, I now turn to the constitutive rules that underpin the logic of philanthropic practice.

In the two previous sections, I presented a conceptual analysis of the practice of philanthropy and a characterization of democracy defined as a practice with a form of authority whose currency is internal. In this section, I characterize the practice of philanthropy as authority conferring and distinguished by a set of constitutive rules. In this sense, by showing how the constitutive rules of the practice of philanthropy differ from those of the practice of democracy, I argue that the difference between philanthropy and democracy is that they instantiate two different logics for the making of collectively binding decisions.

Philanthropy's three constitutive rules are: (1) its authority is exercised unilaterally, (2) its source of authority is at the same time first-personal and third-personal, and (3) its authority's currency (which materializes its action-power) is external to the practice of decision-making.

Consider the first claim: philanthropic authority is unilateral. Philanthropy can be viewed as a specific form of plutocratic and dictatorial authority, understood as authority that is imposable on others. As a donor, and at least in the first instance, one exercises their authority in the form of donating without having to consult with or gather the opinions of those who will be subject to the decision (Table 1). Returning to the Gates Foundation example, Bill and Melinda Gates made a series of decisions in a way that could have never happened under a democratic process of decision-making. For example, all by themselves, they targeted the American education system and defined what its aim should be and what tools they would use to achieve it. More than that, the foundation has also defined conditions that schools must accept in order to receive funding. In this sense, Bill and Melinda Gates unilaterally exercised their authority. That, as Ravitch (2011) notes, the Gateses have been advised by well-trained experts does not change the unilateral nature of their acts. What make their acts different from democratic ones is that the final decision was in their hands alone. And this would have remained true even if the Gateses had consulted teachers, students, or even elected officials. However, as this paper aims at being purely descriptive, I do not discuss whether the Gateses had legitimate business in deciding how to use their money, provided that the purported aims were not against the law or general morality nor relied on stolen money.

This is thus what I mean by unilateral authority: rather than being mutually considered, shared, and taken, decisions flow from one individual or a group of individuals to another. This goes against the logic of democracy, in which no wielder of democratic authority can impose their own decisions on others, as the democratic collective body is self-legislating: the rulers are also the ruled. Or in Ceva and Ottonelli's (2021) words, “[…] when citizens vote, they do not make an individual final decision, but activate their portion of normative powers that will only contribute to the final decision in combination with the same kind of acts by other voters” (p. 5).

This is not to say that decisions made within a philanthropic context are never jointly taken. For example, foundations as big as the Gates Foundation may have internal mechanisms that ensure that the final decisions are the result of an equal balance of power between all members of the board. Bill and Melinda Gates may have had the same decision-making power as the researchers who suggested how to reform the American school system. But as close to democratic as they may be, these mechanisms remain internal to the institution, making their authority similar to that of a jury or a cardinal council in the Catholic Church.

Unilateralism highlights a fundamental, perhaps commonsensical, feature of any private practice aimed at guiding the making of collectively binding decisions: private individuals and institutions express, promote and act in ways that reflect their own conception of society. As Barkan (2013) says about philanthropists, “They may act with good intentions, but they define ‘good’.” (p. 636) However, this is an important point to raise, as it helps us to understand how these private entities can influence public action. Philanthropists, by definition, act for public purposes. However, unilateralism teaches us that this greater good is defined by the small number of individuals who participate in these practices, and not by the public as a whole.

The second constitutive rule of the practice of philanthropy is the first- and third-personal nature of its authority. To gain greater precision, let us turn to an example of Stephen Darwall (2006). Imagine that someone, named Jackie, is stepping on your feet and that you are trying to find normative reasons (i.e., reasons that give her reasons for action) for her to stop doing so. One way to do it would be to appeal to reasons that are internal to Jackie's moral conscience. For example, you could convince Jackie that stepping on your feet hurts and that she herself would never want to feel this pain. This discussion might strike Jackie and make her think that yes, she should not be acting like that. This is a first-personal reason in the sense that it appeals to Jackie's inner morality to decide whether to do something. Another way would be to appeal to external reasons to act or not act. For example, you could draw a knife from your pocket and threaten to stab Jackie if she does not take her feet off yours immediately. If she decides to comply because of your threat, she is compelled by a reason that is primarily external to her own choice. Call it a third-personal reason. Interpreting this case from a second-personal perspective, you could ask Jackie to remove her feet because, based on your relationship, you have an appropriate claim on her to do so. In doing so, you would give Jackie a valid reason to comply. This reason is second-personal because it takes another agent's reason, yours, as a reason for action. In this case, the source of normativity is neither Jackie's own reason for action nor an external rule but the relation between you and Jackie. Thus, where a second-personal source of normativity is relational, first- and third-personalities are, respectively, internal and external.

Now that we have a clearer picture of the different sources of normativity, let us return to the philanthropic form of authority. Philanthropy is both first- and third-personal. This authority triggers these two forms of normativity, and not the second-personal one, because the philanthropic practice is a different type of Hohfeldian right from the claim-right. It can be viewed as a privilege-right (Hohfeld, 1919). It relates to first-personal reasons because, when donors decide to act for a public purpose, they are referring to reasons that are internal to themselves. Such reasons can take many forms: providing better education for people in impoverished regions of the world and saving the ocean from pollution or again stimulating cultural activities. What is specific with these internal reasons is that through their donations, a philanthropist fond of ecological conservation is not answering to the claim-right of whales to have clean oceans because humans are polluting them. Put into the democratic vocabulary, this means that Bill and Melinda Gateses’ source of authority is nowhere to be found in their co-citizens’ demands, that is, they did not act because they were legitimately asked to do so. As Darwall (2006) would put, they decided to reform the American school system based on their “state of the world regarding” (p. 6) reasons, on their very own conception of the good.

Philanthropic authority is also third-personal: it applies an external source of normativity to those who will be subject to it. By making donations, one imposes—based on their own will—on others their vision of how public purposes should be arranged. By giving money to put forward a certain conception of how to organize the school system, Bill and Melinda Gates gave third-personal reasons for parent–teacher associations and students to act in a certain way. The resources they gave, tied to a number of clauses, transformed the living conditions of those involved in those schools by defining how to work, how to learn, and what is worth learning. Importantly for my comparison with the second-personal form of authority, these changes happened for normative reasons that were unrelated to the relation shared by those affected by the Gateses’ decision. In contrast, saying that democracy instantiates second-personal relations means that citizens recognize the special authority to hold other citizens accountable for what is done to them. Hence, the philanthropic mode of decision-making alters this relation of joint recognition as the final authority over their reciprocal claims and duties.

To summarize this second constitutive rule, philanthropy is at the same time first- and third-personal, as a philanthropist's reasons for action originate in their internal reasons and as those reasons create, for citizens, external obligations that do not rest on their interactions. As stated in the previous section, these constitutive rules also help to understand why publicly encouraged act of philanthropy such as those encouraged by tax incentives does not make philanthropic authority less distinct from democratic one. Although incentivized philanthropy answers to what could be conceived as a state's call, the source of their authority remains first- and third-personal. It remains first-personal because philanthropists make use of their own internal reasons for actions, in the sense that it is not a duty trigger by citizens’ claim-rights. It is also third-personal in the sense that the way philanthropists give direction to public activities are not anchored in a mechanism of joint recognition of authority.

This constitutive rule highlights the type of relationship that philanthropy establishes within a polity. Philanthropy offers donors the opportunity to give direction to society on the basis of their own reasons for actions. However, philanthropy's third-personal authority also risks changing the lives of citizens for reasons that are external to them. Second-order reasons for action, as found in democratic decision-making, may be demanding because of their relationship of rights and duties, nevertheless they bind citizens in a different way than philanthropy does. Second personality guarantee citizens that each decision and public action is implemented for reasons with which they are associated.

The distinction between first- and third-personalities and second-personality could be stated as follows: Who should decide how public purposes are pursued? Individuals acting voluntarily out of their love for humanity, or all citizens acting through a collective system based on interrelations of accountability?

Focusing on the source of authority also allows to show how interrelation changes in function of the preferred practice. For example, one redistributive system based on taxes and another one based on voluntary donations do not share the same implications and social meanings, even if the outcome is identical. In the first case, the state redistributes resources from those who have benefited more from social cooperation to those who benefited less. There is the idea that some citizens owe something to others. In the second situation, we are appealing to the generosity (in opposition to their obligation) of individuals to make the world more just.

Finally, philanthropy's third constitutive rule concerns the currency of its authority. Recall that by currency, I refer to the resources that empower the authority bearer to make collectively binding decisions. In the case of philanthropy, its currency consists in external resources. Philanthropic donations can take the form of money, time, and services (Figure 1). This is why philanthropy is generally seen as a form of plutocratic power: the currency of its authority is derived from concrete resources. This makes plutocracy different from aristocracy, which used to derive its power from social resources such as titles of nobility and social status.

Unlike democracy, what gives philanthropy its substantive action-power exists prior to and outside its decision-making process. Money, for example, is a resource that individuals gather and possess before they even decide to act in a philanthropic manner. This is fundamentally different from what happens in a democracy. Imagine that instead of having one token each, citizens have unequal amount of tokens. By taking as legitimate the authority derived from material resources, philanthropy creates a fundamentally asymmetric form of decision-making, as the source of this authority—wealth or time—is unequally distributed. Since some individuals have more of these resources than others, poorer individuals must accept the decisions of richer ones. And since philanthropic resources exist prior to and after the decision-making process, the tokens may be used with much more flexibility than democratic ones. Instead of waiting on elected official's decision or popular votations, philanthropy might offer my friend and I two options for the creating a new theater: First, we could pool our money and fund it ourselves. Second, we could use our resources to advocate that theaters are an important part of a rich cultural life and that the local government should fund one. The options are not strictly the same, as the first one would probably leave the philanthropist with more decision-making power over the theater's activities, but the example nevertheless shows the impact of authority based on external resources. In both options, calling on philanthropic resources allows us to realize public purposes rather than relying on the democratic process.

Disparities between large and small philanthropic foundations clearly illustrate how difference in resources shape philanthropy's action power. It is clear that the Bill and Melinda Gates’ foundation disposed of much more resources to shape the American system than a smaller local philanthropic organization. However, conceptually, it should not be assumed that the political authority derived from these entities are more or less distinct from democratic authority solely based on the tangible impact they have on policy-making or public decision-making. Democracy is democratic as long as the kind of authority exercised by every citizen remains at the same time strictly second-personal, mutual and its currency is external. Even the slightest number of external resources aimed at giving direction to public decisions and actions will be incompatible will change the nature of relationships instantiate by such democratic forms of collectively-binding decision-making.

In this section, I have explained that philanthropy embodies a specific logic of authority. Philanthropic authority is unilaterally exercised, allowing the donor to have a direct and individual say in public decisions. It takes its normativity from a mix of first-personality and third-personality, appealing to reasons that are not linked to any relations of claim-rights between decision-makers. And the currency of philanthropy—what materializes its action-power—is external to the decision-making process rather than being internally created as in a one-person, one-vote system. Given these constitutive rules, authority emerging from philanthropic practices is fundamentally different from that emerging from democratic ones, which is characterized by the rules of mutualism, second-personality, and externality of currency.

My characterization of philanthropic authority is important in at least two manners. First, it allows us to clearly understand what philanthropy involves for public decisions and how it relates to democracy. This characterization thus shows what should be taken into consideration when determining which kind of decision-making tool should be employed for public decisions. Clarifying how these two logics of authority differ seems to indicate how difficult it might be to reconcile them. Introducing philanthropy in a democracy changes, for better or worse, the relations of accountability shared by citizens. My characterization of philanthropy points to its inherently political nature. It emphasizes that philanthropy is not purely benevolent (as it can be used as a tool to affect the making of public decision) without assuming that it is always aimed at secretly pulling the strings of government.

A second manner in which this characterization is significant is that of making sense of the numerous philanthropic practices that exist. Focusing on the kind of authority that emanates from philanthropy allows us to gain a clear account of what different forms of philanthropy share, from the smallest donation to the largest sum given by the richest individual. This paper shows that giving is not voting, and even if the final result of these two decision-making methods may be the same, or even if their action power is weaker, the methods nevertheless change the nature of the relationship between those affected by the decisions.

Similarly, my characterization enables an understanding of mixed or in-between cases, such as when philanthropy is encouraged publicly through tax incentives. Constitutive rules teach us that practices characterized by them cannot be changed, even by a little, without risking the nature of that practice. In this sense, it is not possible to make philanthropy analytically more democratic by giving it a public varnish. Public incentives or public–private partnerships10 represent normative positions concerning philanthropy within a democracy. They articulate the types of philanthropic practices deemed desirable or valuable in a democratic society. Such desirability can itself be democratically established through specific policies. For instance, the very existence of philanthropy is contingent on its democratic authorization. However, the normative reasons guiding our encouragement or discouragement of philanthropy in a democracy do not alter the analytical characterization of the practice itself. Philanthropic authority is exercised unilaterally, originating from first and third-personal reasons for actions, and its currency is external to the collectively binding decision-making process it initiates.

Furthermore, discerning the differentiation between philanthropic authority and other forms of private practice might seem challenging. For instance, consider a scenario where a friend and I opt to establish a for-profit corporation instead of choosing philanthropy to construct a new theater. The authority exercised as a corporation could mirror that of philanthropy: unilateral decision-making (our choice to build the theater and determine the show), rooted in our personal reasons for action, and with an external impact on citizens through the currency (money). It appears that philanthropic and for-profit activities share similarities, but their substantive difference lies in their directed objectives: public purposes, as oppose to for-profit ones. However, delineating between for-profit and nonprofit actions was beyond the scope of this paper.

Lastly, I wish to emphasize a central implication stemming from my characterization of philanthropy. Asserting that philanthropy and democracy represent two distinct forms of authority does not inherently favor or oppose philanthropic actions in public spheres. My aim in characterizing philanthropy is to highlight the nature of making collectively binding decisions using this practice and its implications for democracy. Consequently, my intention is not to argue for or against the various normative values of philanthropy, as presented by the political theorists referenced in this paper. Depending on preferred democratic ideals, some might find the unilateral nature of philanthropy advantageous. Supporters of this view often commend the efficacy of philanthropy over public actions. Others might believe that philanthropy, by utilizing external resources, offers a wide range of possibilities potentially unavailable to the state. This aligns with Rob Reich's defense of the discovery argument for philanthropic foundations. However, other scholars may contend that the first and third-personal nature of philanthropy risks subjecting citizens to the goodwill of their benefactors.

I have argued that there is a constitutive difference between philanthropy and democracy. Understood as two tools for the making of collectively binding decisions, they instantiate two forms of authority differentiated by their constitutive rules. First, where democracy's exercise of authority is mutual, and its citizens are co-subject and coauthor of laws, philanthropic authority is unilateral in the sense of being imposable on others. Second, the source of democratic authority is second-personal, anchoring citizens’ reasons for action in the interpersonal relationship they all share. In contrast, philanthropy is first- and third-personal, so that philanthropists’ reasons for action are internal to themselves while instantiating an external source of normativity in relation to those who will be subject to it. Finally, where democracy's currency of authority is created within the decision-making process, philanthropy takes its authority from resources that are external to the process and unequally distributed.

This paper shed light on how philanthropy and democracy differ as forms of authority even if they aim at the same public purposes. My analytical characterization of philanthropy showed what features of the practice should be taken into consideration in normative discussions of the kind of decision-making tools to deploy for making collectively binding decisions. The encompassing focus of this work also allowed us to gain a clear account of what different forms of philanthropy share, from the smallest donation to the largest donations.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信