民主自卫和公共领域机构

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Ludvig Norman, Ludvig Beckman
{"title":"民主自卫和公共领域机构","authors":"Ludvig Norman,&nbsp;Ludvig Beckman","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12737","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Contemporary concerns with democratic backsliding and contestation of democratic institutions, even in consolidated democracies, have reignited longstanding debates on how democratic societies should respond to perceived anti-democratic threats and what a principled “democratic self-defense” should look like (Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Norman, <span>2018</span>; cf. Loewenstein, <span>1937</span>). The core dilemma in these debates concerns the extent to which restrictions on anti-democratic speech, actors, and their associations can be justified in the interest of protecting the integrity of democratic institutions and strengthening democracy's guardrails.</p><p>Variations of this dilemma, traditionally concerned with the protection of democratic institutions, have increasingly come to the fore in other arenas of democratic societies. Public sphere institutions such as schools, universities, and public broadcasting organizations, as well as social media platforms have become deeply entangled in discussions on the limits of speech and political action. These institutions are expected, either by convention or legislation, to uphold and reproduce core liberal democratic values while also remaining open to a plurality of views, allowing for the free formation and expression of political ideas. Yet, the existing literature has had less to say about what values should guide decisions to restrict or call out speech deemed to challenge liberal democratic norms in the context of these public sphere institutions.</p><p>Our concern in this article is to clearly flesh out what core dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the public sphere consist of and theorize the democratic values at stake in this context. Seeing human dignity as a fundamental value for liberal democracy, we argue, helps us to more precisely identify the character of democratic threats in the public sphere, the various ways in which democratic values may be undermined, and in light of that, how public sphere institutions may respond to these challenges.</p><p>Crucially, the assumption that human dignity is a basic democratic value allows us to identify how legally protected speech can still be highly problematic from a democratic perspective. This is important, we argue, as many of the challenges to liberal democracy involve individual-level harms, instances where the human dignity of individual people is undermined. Key to this argument is theorizing the link between attacks on the equal dignity of citizens and attacks on democracy. We tie human dignity as a democratic value to the respect and status afforded to individuals as members of a political community. Paying attention to this link in the context of democracy helps highlight characteristics of speech that have not received sustained attention in current discussions on militant democracy and democratic self-defense.</p><p>Our argument emphasizes that some members of democratic society are more at risk than others by virtue of the fact that they already occupy precarious positions in terms of recognition of equal standing. Incorporating this insight should have repercussions for the strategies devised to combat anti-democratic threats at the “micro level” in democracies. This, finally, allows us to think anew regarding the strategies through which the dilemma can be approached by democratic actors. We consider both exclusionary and expressive strategies and discuss how they involve distinct trade-offs and dilemmas.</p><p>The article proceeds by first clarifying the theoretical starting point regarding anti-democratic challenges in the public sphere. We contrast our view with prevalent perspectives in democratic theory that have focused on democracy's protection. Next, we outline the significance of human dignity as a democratic value and define key ways in which dignity might be undermined in the public sphere. We illustrate our argument with discussions on dilemmas facing public broadcasting organizations, social media platforms and educational institutions. The final section outlines the menu of strategies available in pushing back anti-democratic threats in the public sphere, including both exclusionary and expressive actions. We present an argument in favor of expressive strategies while highlighting instances where both strategies may be employed, as well as instances where public sphere institutions should remain passive.</p><p>Our starting point is that contemporary threats to democracy require greater attention to the dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the public sphere. The public sphere can be defined as the “constellations of communicative spaces in society that permit the circulation of information, ideas and debates” (Dahlgren, <span>2005</span>). It is composed by formal and informal institutions including schools and universities (Holmwood, <span>2017</span>), public media institutions (Iosifidis, <span>2011</span>), museums (Barrett, <span>2011</span>) and increasingly, social media platforms (cf. Müller, <span>2019</span>). These are settings of key importance for a functioning democracy where individuals should be able to participate and deliberate about public issues on an equal basis. Our argument does not assume that the public sphere is uniquely concerned with “common interests” (Taylor, <span>1992</span>), or that it is necessarily “representative” and “inclusive” (Fraser, <span>1990</span>). Indeed, the public sphere can also provide oxygen for anti-democratic and extremist actors, and its institutions can become vehicles of autocratization (Arato &amp; Cohen, <span>2021</span>). For these reasons, teachers, journalists, editors, their boards and directors, are forced to make often difficult decisions on where the limits should be drawn regarding which actors and which views should be given room. There are thus good reasons to theorize how public sphere institutions should approach dilemmas related to where and how to draw limits with reference to what is tolerable in a democracy. These are dilemmas that parallel those theorized in the growing literature on democratic self-defense, but they take on a different guise when we consider public sphere institutions (cf. Müller, <span>2016</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Kirshner, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>In the wake of increasing digitalization, the rise of social media platforms and the decline of traditional print and broadcast media, there is a strong tendency toward a “breakdown of gatekeeping” (Farrell &amp; Schwartzberg, <span>2021</span>: 222). This also constitutes a shift whereby nonstate institutions in the public sphere increasingly have to undertake contentious and sometimes highly consequential decisions about the inclusion and exclusion of particular actions and messages, even in cases where they fall well within what is legal (Chambers &amp; Kopstein, <span>2022</span>). Decisions by some of the leading social media platforms, most notably what was then called Twitter, to suspend the account of then US president, Donald Trump, are illustrative (Twitter, <span>2021a</span>). The decision to ban Trump from Twitter, or indeed the decision to invite him back on the platform, was not taken by a public authority with reference to the breach of any laws. It was a decision taken by a private corporation with reference to its own policy against the glorification of violence (Twitter, <span>2021b</span>).</p><p>The dilemma of democratic self-defense does not only apply to social media platforms; it is ubiquitous in the public sphere of contemporary democratic societies. Decisions to suspend participants, censor users, or to flag or limit the distribution of content, as well as decisions to not take actions and include democratically questionable views, are regularly made by media outlets, schools, museums, universities and other institutions that provide arenas for public debate. The dilemmas that come to the fore in such settings increasingly permeate the every-day practices of democracy. However, they are clearly distinct from the dilemmas faced by the democratic state in relation to anti-democratic political parties and organizations.</p><p>Public sphere institutions are neither judicial nor legislative institutions; they are part of what Rawls termed as the “background culture”. In a free and democratic society, the background culture is the arena for free associational life that should largely remain unregulated by law (Rawls, <span>1997</span>). The public sphere thus provides ample occasions for the dilemma of democratic self-defense to materialize but where legislation does not, indeed should not, supply clear guidance. It is a dilemma that has less to do with the integrity of electoral institutions and procedures of political democracy and more with the extent to which the members of democratic societies are respected as equals. This comes with implications for how we understand how anti-democratic threats play out in these settings.</p><p>For the purposes of our argument, it is particularly important to challenge the assumption that such threats affect all citizens in a democracy equally. Rather, we assume that the burdens of anti-democratic rhetoric and actions are carried to a larger extent by some groups than by others, that they are unequally distributed. The increasing influence of political movements identified as potential threats to democracy, such as political parties with roots in the extreme right, are often theorized to pose an equally serious problem for <i>all</i> democratically minded citizens in a society. We agree that actual authoritarian governments do undermine the dignity of all their citizens in a fundamental sense. However, the belief that all citizens in an otherwise functioning democracy are equally affected by anti-democratic rhetoric obscures the fact that the key mechanism through which authoritarian politics gains traction in a democracy is by targeting often already marginalized groups (Tudor &amp; Slater, <span>2020</span>). Anti-democratic movements are never “just” anti-democratic in the sense of advocating for authoritarian forms of government. In general, these movements also target particular social, ethnic, linguistic groups in society, framing them in antagonistic terms, as enemies of the people, the state or the party. Anti-democratic movements often exploit pre-existing asymmetries in power and status in society.</p><p>In contemporary democracies, anti-democratic movements typically engage in continued rhetorical assaults on the status and rights of, in particular, immigrants, religious communities, women, members of the LBGTQ-community, indigenous peoples and minorities. Frustration, impatience, blame and indeed hatred directed at these groups is a fixture of the authoritarian playbook (Corrales &amp; Kiryk, <span>2023</span>; Lührmann et al., <span>2021</span>; Gricius, <span>2022</span>). Our argument builds on the premise that the primary target for contemporary perceived challengers of democracy, including the plethora of authoritarian populist parties in Europe, is the public status of specific groups and their individual members, rather than the integrity of democratic institutions and procedures as such. This observation does not exclude the possibility that, when in power, these parties would work to erode those institutions. Examples of this from the last decade are readily available in states like Hungary, Poland, and the United States.</p><p>However, beyond the most extreme fringe parties, such as neo-Nazis or revolutionary communists, parties marketing themselves in direct opposition to democracy as a form of government are rare. Targeting members of specific societal groups by identifying them as illegitimate or unwanted members of the political community is from this perspective a hallmark of contemporary anti-democratic politics. Anti-democratic movements in a democracy, while they may not attack democratic institutions as such, regularly work to denigrate the equal public status of some groups. This, we argue, is an affront to the human dignity of these individuals and as such in conflict with fundamental values in a democratic society. The type of anti-democratic threats that are our primary concern in this article thus start from the particular rather than the general; from targeted disdain, rather than from competing principles of government. Therefore, recognizing the unequal distribution of costs for assaults on democracy should inform attempts to theorize the dilemma of democratic self-defense. By contrast, public speech in a democracy that promotes anti-democratic forms of government, even if deemed offensive, is arguably less likely to have harmful effects in terms of undermining the dignity of particular citizens. Advocates of, for instance, military or expert rule, while clearly communicating support for anti-democratic principles, need not necessarily target the standing of particular individuals. Furthermore, the fact that we suspect that, given government power, critics of democracy would bring society in an authoritarian direction does not necessarily imply strong reasons for their blanket exclusion from public sphere arenas.</p><p>However, the contention that the first casualties of anti-democratic action are more likely to be members of particular groups prompts us to reconsider dominant themes in longstanding discussions on how to defend democracy against anti-democratic challengers. The theoretical tools developed in this literature are dominated by a concern with the preservation of democratic institutions and procedures, including the integrity of elections, basic political rights, and the balance of power between the executive, the legislature, and the judiciary (Abts &amp; Rummens, <span>2010</span>). These are concerns which we share. Questions concerning to what extent democracies should formally tolerate extremist and anti-democratic actors that rally under anti-democratic political programs or if such political actors should be confronted with repressive measures to protect democratic institutions remain important (Gutmann &amp; Voigt, <span>2021</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Kirshner, <span>2019</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>; Niesen, <span>2002</span>; Rijpkema, <span>2018</span>, <span>2019</span>; Sajo, <span>2004</span>; cf. Kelsen, <span>2006</span>; Vinx, <span>2020</span>). However, the predominant way anti-democratic threats are conceptualized in this literature limits its ability to accurately capture dilemmas and challenges of democratic self-defense in the public sphere.</p><p>The shadow of Karl Loewenstein—credited with coining the concept of “militant democracy”—looms large in its basic conceptualization of the dilemma of democratic self-defense (Loewenstein, <span>1937</span>). It is a perspective ultimately concerned with protecting the integrity of core democratic institutions and its decision-making procedures. The fundamental “Löwensteinian” concern is that democratic procedures are vulnerable and easily exploited for anti-democratic ends. References to the fall of the Weimar Republic are ubiquitous in the academic literature, and increasingly in contemporary public debate, serving as the paradigmatic example of a democratic system that lacked adequate constitutional mechanisms to protect itself against anti-democratic attacks (Abts &amp; Rummens, <span>2010</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Quong, <span>2004</span>; Rijpkema, <span>2018</span>; Vinx, <span>2020</span>).<sup>2</sup> Instead, the argument goes, anti-democrats were able to dismantle democracy “from within”.</p><p>A core idea is that the inherent openness of democratic institutions makes <i>pre-emptive</i> action permissible and sometimes necessary against political movements that can be suspected of subverting those institutions in the future. As Müller states, “a militant democracy does not wait until its enemies have gained majorities at the poll; it seeks to nip fundamental opposition to democracy in the bud” (Müller, <span>2016</span>: 250). Although conventionally less pronounced in a US constitutional tradition, it has been prevalent in post-war democratic constitutional debates in many European countries (Bourne, <span>2018</span>; Fox &amp; Nolte, <span>1995</span>; Norman, <span>2022</span>; Suteu, <span>2021</span>). Theorists of militant democracy are careful to distance themselves from many of the measures defended by Karl Löwenstein (Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>), and others have argued that the notion of a militant democracy is inherently tied to elitist and anti-participatory logics (Invernizzi Accetti &amp; Zuckerman, 2017; Malkopoulou &amp; Norman, <span>2018</span>). It is, moreover, increasingly recognized that contemporary anti-democrats rarely voice explicitly authoritarian or totalitarian political ideals. Rather, the political platforms of authoritarian populists in Europe, the United States, and Latin America, with some clear exceptions, tend to occupy the grey area between democratic and authoritarian politics (Malkopoulou &amp; Moffitt, <span>2023</span>). The point is that contemporary anti-democratic movements may fall well outside the scope of traditional militant measures such as restrictions on assembly, political organization and party funding that have dominated discussions on militant democracy (Rovira Kaltwasser, <span>2019</span>). This holds even if we observe how populist parties similar to those emerging in many consolidated democracies are instigating anti-democratic political developments elsewhere, where they may have gained government power. These observations further underpin the need to theorize the principles on which institutions in the public sphere should base their response to speech and agents perceived to challenge democratic values.</p><p>The answer, from our perspective, is not to advocate for more intrusive and repressive legal restrictions in the public sphere. Rather, we aim to highlight which values are at stake when public sphere institutions consider limits to public discourse. This leads us to theorize the nature of the threat to democracy in these settings. If, as we argued above, we are not primarily concerned with actions and forms of speech regulated by law, what is the basis for the dilemma and why is it a concern for democratic theory? How is democracy imperiled by systematic rhetorical attacks on the social and political status of particular groups? We propose that a focus on human dignity as a democratic value allows us to cut to the core of anti-democratic rhetoric and action. Indeed, these are values explicitly recognized by many militant democrats, including Loewenstein (<span>1937</span>, p. 658). Democratic institutions and procedures are from this perspective ultimately guarantors of human dignity, and this value should inform the protection of these institutions. Yet, we believe that the predominant focus on democratic institutions and procedures, specifically those related to electoral politics, tends to downplay both individual level and aggregated consequences of speech in the public sphere. For those reasons existing perspectives seem less well-suited to identify and address current anti-democratic challenges. By extending the analysis to public sphere institutions and by invoking the importance of human dignity to democracy, our approach offers the groundwork for a clearer discussion on the dilemmas that arise in efforts to defend democracy against such threats.</p><p>There is a dual relationship between the value of human dignity and democratic ideals. On the one hand, human dignity is the background norm—an abstract principle—that is frequently perceived as a justification for democratic rights of participation. On the other, human dignity signifies a particular social status—or social practice—that is arguably instrumental to active participation and the use of democratic rights. We discuss both these aspects of dignity as a vehicle to identify threats to democracy in the public sphere.</p><p>As a bedrock for normative claims and a social status worthy of protection, human dignity is bound up with a broader catalogue of liberal rights. Human dignity is typically incorporated as part of this catalogue and appears in written constitutions to differentiate the democratic political order from past authoritarian experiences. Human dignity emerged as the legal principle that provides the foundation for democratic and constitutional orders in post-war Europe (Dupré, <span>2013</span>). A similar pattern is visible in Latin America after the fall of the juntas and in Eastern Europe after the fall of Communist regimes (Barak, <span>2015</span>).<sup>3</sup></p><p>The principle of human dignity provides a justification for democratic institutions. This is, for instance, illustrated by the fact that it figures among the founding values of the Treaty on European Union (Article 2) and that it plays a key role in the 1949 constitution of Germany. It also undergirds important decisions in the jurisprudence of the US Supreme Court that has treated “dignity as a value underlying, or giving meaning to, existing constitutional rights and guarantees” (Goodman, <span>2005</span>, p. 743; cf. Kahn, <span>2015</span>; Simon, <span>2021</span>; Tremper, <span>1988</span>). Given that human dignity is widely recognized as a key value for democracy it might appear surprising that it has not been given more room in the literature on democratic self-defense.<sup>4</sup> To an extent, we believe that this has to do with the concept's pliability in terms of the different meanings to which it is associated in different literatures.</p><p>In fact, the relationship between human dignity and democracy remains contested (Baer, <span>2009</span>; Rosen, <span>2012</span>; Valentini, <span>2017</span>; Waldron, <span>2012</span>). There are conceptions of democracy where conceptions of human dignity play a limited, if any, role. For instance, justifications for democratic procedures as means for competitive but peaceful resolution of political conflict scarcely need appeal to values of equal dignity (Bobbio, <span>1984</span>; Popper, <span>1945</span>; Przeworski, <span>1999</span>; Schumpeter [1943] <span>2003</span>). This does not mean that such “minimalist” perspectives on democracy would necessarily deny that dignity is an important concern for human beings, only that it does not play into core justifications for democracy as a form of government. From a minimalist democratic perspective, even nondemocratic regimes have often done “very well in securing what most of us believe the democratic method should secure” including human dignity (Schumpeter [1943] <span>2003</span>, p. 246). A related and common objection to the concept is that human dignity fails to offer any clear normative direction at all (Seglow, <span>2016</span>). Others argue that human dignity may be more useful in other social and ethical contexts, for instance, as the basis for the protection of bodily integrity, privacy, or the right to life (Beyleveld &amp; Brownsword, <span>1993</span>).</p><p>We think, however, that the idea of human dignity as an important background value for democracy is useful to ground a discussion on democratic self-defense in the public sphere. Though human dignity refers to the inner human worth of individual beings, we shall here treat it as more or less coterminous with equal moral status and the moral claim that this status ought to be recognized by public institutions. Our point here is that a commitment to the principle of human dignity is fundamental not merely for liberals, but also for democrats (cf. Dworkin, <span>2011</span>).</p><p>To further specify the relevance of the principle of human dignity for discussions on democratic self-defense, we highlight two aspects. First, human dignity signifies a social status that is instrumental to democratic participation (Ober, <span>2012</span>). Human dignity is hence understood to require public recognition of the person as an equal member of society. A person who is publicly recognized as an equal is recognized as a person with human dignity. This overlaps with what is elsewhere termed social equality and rejects “hierarchies of social status” and “stigmatizing differences in status” (Fourie, <span>2012</span>). The respect required by human dignity is in this sense more demanding than protections of political equality. Arguably, the status of “public equality” is among the great benefits conferred to all members of a democratic society by virtue of their standing as political equals (Christiano, <span>2009</span>; Gonzalez-Ricoy &amp; Queralt, <span>2018</span>). The secure enjoyment of the social status associated with recognition of human dignity plays an important role in making available venues for participation. More specifically, related to the functioning of a democratic public sphere, it is a precondition for dialogue in public affairs for all members of the community.</p><p>Human dignity is, second, a basic claim about moral status that grounds a wide variety of rights, including rights to democratic participation (Rosen, <span>2012</span>).<sup>5</sup> The claim that all individuals share the same moral status, because of their human dignity, is intimately bound up with the justification of democracy as it allows us to regard the equal enjoyment and exercise of political rights as the full expression of our status as inviolable and dignified human beings (Baer, <span>2009</span>; Dworkin, <span>2006</span>). In the context of extremist threat to democracy, we thus believe the most illuminating aspect of dignity is that of a particular public status. This is consistent with the notion that it is a background value that makes democratic politics possible. The core meaning of human dignity is—we take it—that all members of the democratic community should be publicly affirmed as individuals of equal standing.</p><p>Human dignity as equal public status in a community is similar to the recognition of “the right to have rights” (Arendt, <span>1951</span>; Hann, <span>2016</span>; Isaac, <span>1996</span>). It avoids theoretical discussions on the contents of specific rights such as the right to freedom or the right to life and instead seeks to establish the fundamental condition for such rights, however they are defined, to be respected. Respect for dignity in this perspective serves a meta-function related to the recognition of full membership in a political community that is necessary for more specific rights to be respected, including democratic ones. Our thesis here is that dignity is a social status that depends on—and is therefore also vulnerable to—practices in the wider public sphere. To protect that status, theories of democratic self-defense need to ground themselves in a perspective that fleshes out what constitutes harms to equal dignity.</p><p>To concretize how the erosion of human dignity in the public sphere of democratic societies can manifest itself, we invoke a distinction from social-psychology and bioethics between two main ways in which speech may be contrary to the equal public status of others: <i>delegitimization</i> and <i>dehumanization</i>. These two concepts depict degrees to which the public standing of a person can be questioned or undermined by speech. They are related to the well-known category of “hate speech” that predominates in legal discourse. We believe, however, that the concepts proposed here open up for a more graded and nuanced discussion on which types of speech might work to undermine dignity, even when such speech falls within what is legally permitted.</p><p>Delegitimization is defined as efforts to fundamentally undermine an individual's status as legitimate member of a political community by reference to their association with a particular societal group and attributing deeply negative characteristics as intrinsic traits to that group (cf. Bar-Tal, <span>1989</span>). Delegitimization thus takes aim at individuals as members of groups rather than as representatives of particular political positions and it is characterized by implicit or explicit attempts to undermine the status of others as equal rights-holders and as equal contenders for political influence. Delegitimizing speech can be understood as intimately tied to exclusionary notions of “The People” and associated to understandings of the people's interests in fixed and holistic terms (Ochoa Espejo, <span>2017</span>; Urbinati, <span>2019</span>; Wolkenstein, <span>2019</span>). It includes statements that negate the equal public standing of individuals in that particular community. Yet, not every claim that seeks to delegitimize the equal public status of another person is necessarily an affront to the democratic value of human dignity.<sup>6</sup> Moreover, as outlined above, human dignity can also be undermined by measures that do not attack the equal public status of individuals as citizens.</p><p>Claims that some citizens be excluded from the moral, political or legal community may nevertheless constitute an attack on their equal public status and as such pave the way for infringements of their democratic rights as well as of other fundamental rights. The democratic significance of this point trades on an insight in the previous literature, which is that recognized membership in a political community is a precondition for secure enjoyment of basic political rights. As assaults on equal public status are instrumental in denying particular citizens their status as members of the political community, assaults on dignity also work to undermine basic political rights generally. This is what makes speech that attacks the public status of particular groups so insidious, and why it is inherently a concern for democracy.</p><p>Dehumanization is the category of speech with the most obvious and far-reaching implications in terms its potential to undermine the equal public status that is necessary for respecting the human dignity of all citizens. Delegitimization, deployed as a political strategy, may come with serious consequences, especially in terms of paving the way for the infringement of other fundamental rights of individuals. Dehumanization, however, cuts to the core of such infringements. The common denominator of speech that dehumanizes others is that it seeks to exclude them from membership in humanity by portraying them as “animal-like” or otherwise devoid of the traits that are uniquely human (Haslam, <span>2006</span>). It is thus more far-reaching in that it does not limit itself to questions of individual's legitimate right to participate in a particular community but works to undermine the status of individuals as human beings altogether. Historically, dehumanizing speech has been deployed to establish the inferiority of members of ethnic, linguistic, religious, and other social groups and has been part and parcel of violent persecution, slavery and genocide. In a US context, the historical legacy of slavery is illustrative for our argument, where recognition of human dignity was withheld on the basis of radical exclusion of certain groups from the category of humanity. The far-reaching denial of human dignity in this context is precisely evidenced not merely by the denial of slaves and their descendants as members of the political “people” but by the denial of them as members of the category of people <i>tout court</i> (Canovan, <span>2005</span>). Here, again, the problem was not that those in power were unable to conceptualize what particular rights entailed but that those rights emerged in a political context which rendered them null and void when considered in relation to parts of the population.</p><p>The underlying logic of speech that seeks to undermine the human dignity of others is instructive to the aim of theorizing how democratic values are at risk in the public sphere of democratic societies. Recent experimental studies in psychology indicate how dehumanization is associated with a permissive attitude toward harm with respect to targeted individuals and groups (Dalsklev &amp; Ronningsdalen Kunst, <span>2015</span>; Markowitz &amp; Slovic, <span>2020</span>; cf. Over, <span>2021</span>). The same attitudes are reinforced by, for instance, the depiction of undervalued minority groups as unhygienic, which has been shown to trigger feelings of disgust (Dalsklev &amp; Ronningsdalen Kunst, <span>2015</span>). Dehumanization comes close to what would in many cases count as hate speech, which is recognized as an offense by criminal law in many countries. However, as the examples above illustrate, speech that is not necessarily hate speech can still provide subtle cues instrumental for undermining human dignity. Like explicit anti-democratic positions, assaults on the dignity of other members are a form of extremism that prompts a response from democratic institutions also in the public sphere.</p><p>Once dignity is identified as a value to be preserved in the face of anti-democratic challenges, the sphere of concern expands to include institutions and practices in the public sphere generally, and not just the electoral arena. Here, the dilemma consists in how to safeguard democratic and inclusive arenas of opinion-formation while at the same time protect human dignity from the corrosive effects of delegitimizing or dehumanizing speech.</p><p>For the purpose of illustration, consider the cases of public media institutions, public schools and social media platforms. Public service broadcasting organizations are expected to adhere to ideals of inclusive representation in their coverage of politics. Truthful, impartial and objective reporting on political actors, public policy and law is a key role to be played by the public service in a liberal democracy (Goidel et al, <span>2017</span>; Newton, <span>2016</span>; Norris, <span>2000</span>). This is particularly the case in Europe where state funded public broadcasting organizations still hold important positions as public sphere institutions. There are strong and compelling reasons for these organizations to be as inclusive and pluralistic as possible. To that extent, public service media institutions should include political voices of any kind, even, it could be argued, those of actors engaging in delegitimizing speech. However, in order to protect the dignity of all citizens, there are good reasons for why public media institutions should take measures to protect both participants and audiences from attacks on their status as equal members of society. Thus, the best policy, all things considered, remains uncertain. Public broadcasting organizations often struggle to translate a principled commitment to democratic principles into a defensible response to speech deemed democratically problematic. Heated debates, in many European countries not least, have revolved around perceived biases of public broadcasting organizations on the one hand and, on the other, problems related to providing room for, and thus legitimizing, parties deemed by some to threaten democracy (Hien &amp; Norman, <span>2023</span>). The dilemma of democratic self-preservation facing public media institutions is that democratic values are potentially threatened whether speech that undermines the dignity of some is suppressed or not.</p><p>Similar conditions apply to public schools. Public schools in many countries organize mock elections as part of their civic education, often in election years, to foster citizens’ engagement in politics (Ohrvall &amp; Oskarsson, <span>2020</span>). By being inclusive with respect to political ideologies, schools can serve as a training ground for critical thinking and public deliberation. However, when radical political parties are invited, there is a risk that they will undermine the sense of equal worth and dignity among groups of students, again considering that such potential harms can be expected to be distributed unequally among the members of such groups. In order for public schools to take responsibility for democratic values they may need to take measures that protect students for particular egregious forms of political speech. The example of schools is instructive precisely because it clearly highlights the responsibility of the institution, especially as the audience in this setting are not fully formed members of the political community. Again, here emerges the dilemma of democratic self-preservation: there are democratic reasons for both including representatives of all political parties and for excluding at least some of them. Recently, in some contexts, for instance, in Scandinavian countries, schools have addressed the problem by discontinuing the practice of inviting political representatives. Although this might be a reasonable course of action it is also a solution that clearly limits the functioning of that part of the public sphere. A strategy of retreat replaces dealing head on with the difficult dilemma relating to the limits of permissible speech in political debate.</p><p>We mentioned social media platforms above and they exemplify clearly that this dilemma is not confined to institutions formally tied to the state. Although they are private corporations, dominant platforms have gained a prominent position as arenas for public debate. Exclusion from access to social media platforms may in some cases have more far-reaching consequences than exclusion from more conventional public sphere institutions, such as public service media outlets. In the United States, this came to a head with the post-election exclusion from these platforms by former president Donald Trump. The fact that platforms like Facebook, X, and YouTube have gained such prominent positions as vehicles of contemporary political debate has come with expectations that these companies should be “unbiased” in terms of the contents they allow. Due to these expectations and similar to public sphere institutions, dilemmas arise due to conflicting demands. On the one hand, there is the need to safeguard openness, inclusion, and pluralism, while on the other, there is a requirement to ensure safety, authenticity of published material, and in the case of Facebook's oversight board charter, to protect dignity of individuals (Facebook, <span>2021</span>).<sup>7</sup></p><p>To acknowledge the existence of dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the broader public sphere is to appreciate the need for a more graded and nuanced perspective than has often been the case in debates about democratic self-defense. This is particularly true when threats to equal dignity take the form of actions or speech that seek to either delegitimize or dehumanize specific members in society.</p><p>We consider two types of strategies for protecting the human dignity of participants in public sphere institutions from delegitimization and dehumanization: exclusion and expressive action. These strategies build on long-standing discussions on democratic self-defense, which have mainly focused on when it is legitimate for the state to respond with repressive measures. When transposing such considerations to public sphere institutions we think it is necessary to also discuss instances when these institutions should deviate from their role as impartial facilitators of public debate and use their expressive capabilities to push back at certain statements. Exclusion includes various degrees of denying individuals access to institutions as well as limiting the distribution of content and various forms of speech. Expressive action refers to how an institution may communicate how content and speech run contrary to specific democratic values. Of the two, exclusion from public sphere institutions tends to be more problematic. Excluding perceived anti-democratic agents risks undermining the respect required by democratic values for their equal participation in the public sphere. On a systemic level, it further risks introducing anti-participatory and elitist practices into the public sphere, similar to those highlighted by critics of the militant democratic tradition (Invernizzi Accetti &amp; Zuckerman, <span>2017</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Norman, <span>2018</span>; Norman, <span>2021</span>; Stahl &amp; Popp-Madsen, <span>2022</span>). However, expressive action, whether in the form of public endorsement or public condemnation of particular views, is not uncomplicated. It can have highly significant consequences for individuals and potentially stifle a climate of open debate.</p><p>In this context, various strategies analogous to those implied by classical dilemmas of democratic self-defense resurface, albeit in a new form. The dilemma revolves around the requirements for public sphere institutions to meet criteria of pluralism and promote the free exchange of ideas conducive to the formation of opinions, all while protecting the dignity of all individuals. Furthermore, the dilemma arises due to the potential costs incurred by individuals whose views are publicly denounced or excluded by an institution. When and to what extent is there a democratic justification for public sphere institutions to exclude political representatives, private citizens or specific content? When and to what extent should institutions in the public sphere engage in expressive action, by actively challenging or flagging speech that is perceived to undermine or attack the dignity of other citizens?</p><p>An expressive approach is analogous to Brettschneider's (<span>2016</span>) claim that the state should rely on its expressive powers to condemn “hateful viewpoints” by articulating the reasons and values that undergird democratic rights. However, as is regularly the case in the media, including social media, populist and far-right rhetoric does not necessarily meet the criteria for hate speech, even when it directly targets the public status of specific groups.</p><p>An alternative approach, therefore, is for public sphere institutions—schools, the public media, universities, museums, and social media platforms—to articulate the deeper justifications and reasons for their commitment to democratic values. In other words, they should publicly affirm the human dignity of all without denying anyone the democratic right to participate, speak, and be included in the public sphere. The basic idea is that respect for human dignity provides strong reasons for institutions in the public sphere to <i>challenge</i> content that seeks to delegitimize or dehumanize members of society. This includes a variety of possibilities, from discursive engagement to distancing, as acknowledged in the growing literature on counter-speech (e.g., Fumagalli, <span>2020</span>). The expressive strategy can also be pursued by means of “flagging” content that is considered suspect, unreliable or contrary to democratic values. Flagging is a well-established practice by social media providers, executed either manually, by scripts or self-learning algorithms. Though flagging is clearly a soft sanction, evidence suggests that it is effective in slowing the spread of problematic content (Mena, <span>2020</span>). Flagging is a measure that has been introduced, to a great degree, to cope with the sheer scale of content on social media apps and often contains little more than a reference to the platform's user agreement. Other institutions, such as universities or public broadcasting organizations, should be expected to provide elaborate justifications for flagging and other responses.</p><p>A benefit of the expressive approach is that it remains consistent with permissive norms of freedom of speech and freedom of association that also extend to anti-democratic rhetoric and actors. Expressive action is a form of reason-giving and is premised on the value of open debate. At the same time, it may also, to a degree, offset the often-unequal burden carried by those who are the explicit targets of efforts to delegitimize and dehumanize. The expressive strategy thus strikes a balance by offering a measure of protection while also trusting individuals, even those who might be targeted by efforts to undermine human dignity, to possess both the resilience and the agency to creatively engage in counterstrategies.</p><p>A commitment to a public sphere characterized by wide-ranging pluralism calls for tolerance and, therefore, for participants to be prepared to accept considerable discomfort or even offence. At a fundamental level it relies on a view of democracy that places trust in individuals to withstand offensive speech and to recognize the value of a permissive attitude toward speech as fundamental for democracy. We believe that norms against delegitimization and dehumanization can help distinguish speech that would necessitate an institutional response from speech that might be seen as offensive, uncivil or disrespectful but should not trigger such a response.</p><p>Far-reaching threats to the dignity of the members of society sometimes require exclusionary measures. The problems with exclusionary strategies are still numerous and mirror many of the concerns that might be raised against repressive responses, such as party bans in conventional notions of militant democracy. However, here it is also important to differentiate between various forms of exclusionary practices, each of which is associated to different problems that need to be mitigated in various ways and weighed against their possible gains.</p><p>Legal bans, such as those directed at anti-democratic parties in some democracies, are obviously beyond the reach for institutions in the public sphere. Yet, these institutions have the power to design their own formal or informal norms that exclude either actors or content in so far as they are consistent with the law. When implementing exclusionary measures aimed at content, private individuals, or organizations, there are well-known risks associated with infringements on the rights of those actors. If public sphere institutions are expected to reproduce norms of inclusiveness, impartiality, and openness and to safeguard individual rights such as freedom of speech, exclusionary practices become problematic. Apart from the democratic harms imposed on individuals there are systemic risks associated with the implementation of exclusionary measures. Chief among these might be that they short-circuit an important component of a vital public sphere, namely a principled level of trust extended to all members of society to process and respond to any viewpoints expressed in that sphere. A public sphere built on the notion of individuals’ inability to do so not only risks stifling public debate. It also comes with problematic implications in terms of infusing the public sphere with a paternalistic logic that goes against the grain of the democratic principle of self-government. Coercive measures, such as banning actors from participation and removing certain kinds of content should then be considered with great care before they are implemented.</p><p>To assess if exclusionary measures are justifiable from a democratic perspective, it is useful to think about exclusion in more differentiated terms than is conventionally the case. Here, considering the type of actor targeted by exclusionary measures, such as private individuals or organizations, might lead to different conclusions. To exclude representatives of groups, organizations or parties if they attack or undermine the dignity of other citizens, from spreading information in schools, public places, and social media platforms is not unproblematic. However, targeting actors in their capacity as private citizens, not only as representatives for political organizations, is more serious in terms of the risk of undermining the respect for human dignity of such individuals. As Kirshner (<span>2014</span>) has argued, the political interests and identities of anti-democrats, racists, and extremists are not solely determined by their hostility to democratic institutions and values. As private citizens, they may also have distinct political interests that deserve protection and inclusion in processes of collective will-formation. Blanket exclusions of private citizens from institutions in the public sphere thus represent a greater infringement of democratic norms than exclusions targeting representatives of organizations. Damages incurred by excluding representatives from particular settings also have broader implications as it excludes from discussion the views of a broader set of actors. Yet another aspect that brings nuance to the discussion on exclusionary measures is to consider time-limitations on sanctions rather than open-ended or indefinite ones. Such considerations were part of the stated reasons for the recent reinstatement of Donald Trump's Facebook and Instagram accounts by Meta (Meta, <span>2023</span>).<sup>8</sup></p><p>Exclusionary strategies can also be directed toward specific content or forms of speech. Again, militant democrats typically endorse legal bans on speech that attacks democratic institutions or elected representatives. Nazi ideology and propaganda have repeatedly been struck down by the European Court of Human Rights and many European constitutions either permit or require restrictions on “abuses” of freedom of speech that threaten the democratic system (Tsoumidis, <span>2021</span>). In the context of social media platforms this corresponds to the removal of content rather than “deplatforming”. One problem with the removal of content, often referred to as content moderation, is that the myriad of such decisions that are taken every day by the main social media platforms tend to be nontransparent and provide few means for appeal. Content moderation is thus facing specific challenges of democratic legitimacy. These challenges can be mitigated by expressive actions. The responsibility on the part of public sphere institutions to provide reasons for exclusion and to provide individuals with possibilities for appeal is important. Expressive action is thus a necessary aspect of any effort to implement exclusionary measures. Moreover, exclusionary measures have in themselves an expressive aspect that can be used to signal the limits of publicly acceptable political action to actors beyond those directly targeted.</p><p>Like all general principles, decisions on the application of the strategies outlined here need to take into account case-specific circumstances. Of key importance for such decisions is the historical legacy of power asymmetries and domination between different groups in particular societies. Historical legacies shape and give substance to what delegitimization and dehumanization is, and how the dignity of individuals is harmed by them, and must therefore inform the strategy that best serves to protect democratic values. Understanding such legacies will provide insights into the uneven distribution of threats to human dignity. Although the specific resolution of the dilemma we have discussed depends on the context in which it arises, we believe that the general conceptual tools developed here are essential for fully recognizing the stakes involved and for modeling a response that is appropriate for a democratic society.</p><p>In this article, we have offered the theoretical underpinnings for democracy's protection in the public sphere by elaborating on the democratic significance of human dignity. This shift in perspective was partially motivated by an empirical assessment of the types of anti-democratic threats facing contemporary democratic societies. Overt anti-democrats and outright extremist political movements still exist and should not be overlooked. However, we perceive a more acute problem among political actors who often remain broadly committed to a minimalist notion of democracy while trading on ideas, increasingly prevalent in the public sphere, which undermine the human dignity of particular societal groups. The analytical shift toward public sphere institutions, we argued, helps us reconsider the theoretical tools that we use to make sense of dilemmas of democracy's protection.</p><p>Focusing on human dignity as a fundamental democratic value highlights the unequal costs borne by already marginalized groups due to anti-democratic assaults. We illustrated this argument by discussing ways in which speech and other acts may undermine dignity by delegitimizing and dehumanizing members of particular social groups, undermining their claims to have their rights recognized, or, in the most egregious forms, denying them equal status as members of humanity. The choice between expressive actions or exclusions will always depend, in part, on factors specific to particular cases. However, we believe that the clear specification of a key value that underlie these democratic dilemmas, which we have attempted in this article, provides firmer theoretical grounding for such decisions.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"31 4","pages":"580-594"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2024-02-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12737","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Democratic self-defense and public sphere institutions\",\"authors\":\"Ludvig Norman,&nbsp;Ludvig Beckman\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12737\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Contemporary concerns with democratic backsliding and contestation of democratic institutions, even in consolidated democracies, have reignited longstanding debates on how democratic societies should respond to perceived anti-democratic threats and what a principled “democratic self-defense” should look like (Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Norman, <span>2018</span>; cf. Loewenstein, <span>1937</span>). The core dilemma in these debates concerns the extent to which restrictions on anti-democratic speech, actors, and their associations can be justified in the interest of protecting the integrity of democratic institutions and strengthening democracy's guardrails.</p><p>Variations of this dilemma, traditionally concerned with the protection of democratic institutions, have increasingly come to the fore in other arenas of democratic societies. Public sphere institutions such as schools, universities, and public broadcasting organizations, as well as social media platforms have become deeply entangled in discussions on the limits of speech and political action. These institutions are expected, either by convention or legislation, to uphold and reproduce core liberal democratic values while also remaining open to a plurality of views, allowing for the free formation and expression of political ideas. Yet, the existing literature has had less to say about what values should guide decisions to restrict or call out speech deemed to challenge liberal democratic norms in the context of these public sphere institutions.</p><p>Our concern in this article is to clearly flesh out what core dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the public sphere consist of and theorize the democratic values at stake in this context. Seeing human dignity as a fundamental value for liberal democracy, we argue, helps us to more precisely identify the character of democratic threats in the public sphere, the various ways in which democratic values may be undermined, and in light of that, how public sphere institutions may respond to these challenges.</p><p>Crucially, the assumption that human dignity is a basic democratic value allows us to identify how legally protected speech can still be highly problematic from a democratic perspective. This is important, we argue, as many of the challenges to liberal democracy involve individual-level harms, instances where the human dignity of individual people is undermined. Key to this argument is theorizing the link between attacks on the equal dignity of citizens and attacks on democracy. We tie human dignity as a democratic value to the respect and status afforded to individuals as members of a political community. Paying attention to this link in the context of democracy helps highlight characteristics of speech that have not received sustained attention in current discussions on militant democracy and democratic self-defense.</p><p>Our argument emphasizes that some members of democratic society are more at risk than others by virtue of the fact that they already occupy precarious positions in terms of recognition of equal standing. Incorporating this insight should have repercussions for the strategies devised to combat anti-democratic threats at the “micro level” in democracies. This, finally, allows us to think anew regarding the strategies through which the dilemma can be approached by democratic actors. We consider both exclusionary and expressive strategies and discuss how they involve distinct trade-offs and dilemmas.</p><p>The article proceeds by first clarifying the theoretical starting point regarding anti-democratic challenges in the public sphere. We contrast our view with prevalent perspectives in democratic theory that have focused on democracy's protection. Next, we outline the significance of human dignity as a democratic value and define key ways in which dignity might be undermined in the public sphere. We illustrate our argument with discussions on dilemmas facing public broadcasting organizations, social media platforms and educational institutions. The final section outlines the menu of strategies available in pushing back anti-democratic threats in the public sphere, including both exclusionary and expressive actions. We present an argument in favor of expressive strategies while highlighting instances where both strategies may be employed, as well as instances where public sphere institutions should remain passive.</p><p>Our starting point is that contemporary threats to democracy require greater attention to the dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the public sphere. The public sphere can be defined as the “constellations of communicative spaces in society that permit the circulation of information, ideas and debates” (Dahlgren, <span>2005</span>). It is composed by formal and informal institutions including schools and universities (Holmwood, <span>2017</span>), public media institutions (Iosifidis, <span>2011</span>), museums (Barrett, <span>2011</span>) and increasingly, social media platforms (cf. Müller, <span>2019</span>). These are settings of key importance for a functioning democracy where individuals should be able to participate and deliberate about public issues on an equal basis. Our argument does not assume that the public sphere is uniquely concerned with “common interests” (Taylor, <span>1992</span>), or that it is necessarily “representative” and “inclusive” (Fraser, <span>1990</span>). Indeed, the public sphere can also provide oxygen for anti-democratic and extremist actors, and its institutions can become vehicles of autocratization (Arato &amp; Cohen, <span>2021</span>). For these reasons, teachers, journalists, editors, their boards and directors, are forced to make often difficult decisions on where the limits should be drawn regarding which actors and which views should be given room. There are thus good reasons to theorize how public sphere institutions should approach dilemmas related to where and how to draw limits with reference to what is tolerable in a democracy. These are dilemmas that parallel those theorized in the growing literature on democratic self-defense, but they take on a different guise when we consider public sphere institutions (cf. Müller, <span>2016</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Kirshner, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>In the wake of increasing digitalization, the rise of social media platforms and the decline of traditional print and broadcast media, there is a strong tendency toward a “breakdown of gatekeeping” (Farrell &amp; Schwartzberg, <span>2021</span>: 222). This also constitutes a shift whereby nonstate institutions in the public sphere increasingly have to undertake contentious and sometimes highly consequential decisions about the inclusion and exclusion of particular actions and messages, even in cases where they fall well within what is legal (Chambers &amp; Kopstein, <span>2022</span>). Decisions by some of the leading social media platforms, most notably what was then called Twitter, to suspend the account of then US president, Donald Trump, are illustrative (Twitter, <span>2021a</span>). The decision to ban Trump from Twitter, or indeed the decision to invite him back on the platform, was not taken by a public authority with reference to the breach of any laws. It was a decision taken by a private corporation with reference to its own policy against the glorification of violence (Twitter, <span>2021b</span>).</p><p>The dilemma of democratic self-defense does not only apply to social media platforms; it is ubiquitous in the public sphere of contemporary democratic societies. Decisions to suspend participants, censor users, or to flag or limit the distribution of content, as well as decisions to not take actions and include democratically questionable views, are regularly made by media outlets, schools, museums, universities and other institutions that provide arenas for public debate. The dilemmas that come to the fore in such settings increasingly permeate the every-day practices of democracy. However, they are clearly distinct from the dilemmas faced by the democratic state in relation to anti-democratic political parties and organizations.</p><p>Public sphere institutions are neither judicial nor legislative institutions; they are part of what Rawls termed as the “background culture”. In a free and democratic society, the background culture is the arena for free associational life that should largely remain unregulated by law (Rawls, <span>1997</span>). The public sphere thus provides ample occasions for the dilemma of democratic self-defense to materialize but where legislation does not, indeed should not, supply clear guidance. It is a dilemma that has less to do with the integrity of electoral institutions and procedures of political democracy and more with the extent to which the members of democratic societies are respected as equals. This comes with implications for how we understand how anti-democratic threats play out in these settings.</p><p>For the purposes of our argument, it is particularly important to challenge the assumption that such threats affect all citizens in a democracy equally. Rather, we assume that the burdens of anti-democratic rhetoric and actions are carried to a larger extent by some groups than by others, that they are unequally distributed. The increasing influence of political movements identified as potential threats to democracy, such as political parties with roots in the extreme right, are often theorized to pose an equally serious problem for <i>all</i> democratically minded citizens in a society. We agree that actual authoritarian governments do undermine the dignity of all their citizens in a fundamental sense. However, the belief that all citizens in an otherwise functioning democracy are equally affected by anti-democratic rhetoric obscures the fact that the key mechanism through which authoritarian politics gains traction in a democracy is by targeting often already marginalized groups (Tudor &amp; Slater, <span>2020</span>). Anti-democratic movements are never “just” anti-democratic in the sense of advocating for authoritarian forms of government. In general, these movements also target particular social, ethnic, linguistic groups in society, framing them in antagonistic terms, as enemies of the people, the state or the party. Anti-democratic movements often exploit pre-existing asymmetries in power and status in society.</p><p>In contemporary democracies, anti-democratic movements typically engage in continued rhetorical assaults on the status and rights of, in particular, immigrants, religious communities, women, members of the LBGTQ-community, indigenous peoples and minorities. Frustration, impatience, blame and indeed hatred directed at these groups is a fixture of the authoritarian playbook (Corrales &amp; Kiryk, <span>2023</span>; Lührmann et al., <span>2021</span>; Gricius, <span>2022</span>). Our argument builds on the premise that the primary target for contemporary perceived challengers of democracy, including the plethora of authoritarian populist parties in Europe, is the public status of specific groups and their individual members, rather than the integrity of democratic institutions and procedures as such. This observation does not exclude the possibility that, when in power, these parties would work to erode those institutions. Examples of this from the last decade are readily available in states like Hungary, Poland, and the United States.</p><p>However, beyond the most extreme fringe parties, such as neo-Nazis or revolutionary communists, parties marketing themselves in direct opposition to democracy as a form of government are rare. Targeting members of specific societal groups by identifying them as illegitimate or unwanted members of the political community is from this perspective a hallmark of contemporary anti-democratic politics. Anti-democratic movements in a democracy, while they may not attack democratic institutions as such, regularly work to denigrate the equal public status of some groups. This, we argue, is an affront to the human dignity of these individuals and as such in conflict with fundamental values in a democratic society. The type of anti-democratic threats that are our primary concern in this article thus start from the particular rather than the general; from targeted disdain, rather than from competing principles of government. Therefore, recognizing the unequal distribution of costs for assaults on democracy should inform attempts to theorize the dilemma of democratic self-defense. By contrast, public speech in a democracy that promotes anti-democratic forms of government, even if deemed offensive, is arguably less likely to have harmful effects in terms of undermining the dignity of particular citizens. Advocates of, for instance, military or expert rule, while clearly communicating support for anti-democratic principles, need not necessarily target the standing of particular individuals. Furthermore, the fact that we suspect that, given government power, critics of democracy would bring society in an authoritarian direction does not necessarily imply strong reasons for their blanket exclusion from public sphere arenas.</p><p>However, the contention that the first casualties of anti-democratic action are more likely to be members of particular groups prompts us to reconsider dominant themes in longstanding discussions on how to defend democracy against anti-democratic challengers. The theoretical tools developed in this literature are dominated by a concern with the preservation of democratic institutions and procedures, including the integrity of elections, basic political rights, and the balance of power between the executive, the legislature, and the judiciary (Abts &amp; Rummens, <span>2010</span>). These are concerns which we share. Questions concerning to what extent democracies should formally tolerate extremist and anti-democratic actors that rally under anti-democratic political programs or if such political actors should be confronted with repressive measures to protect democratic institutions remain important (Gutmann &amp; Voigt, <span>2021</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Kirshner, <span>2019</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>; Niesen, <span>2002</span>; Rijpkema, <span>2018</span>, <span>2019</span>; Sajo, <span>2004</span>; cf. Kelsen, <span>2006</span>; Vinx, <span>2020</span>). However, the predominant way anti-democratic threats are conceptualized in this literature limits its ability to accurately capture dilemmas and challenges of democratic self-defense in the public sphere.</p><p>The shadow of Karl Loewenstein—credited with coining the concept of “militant democracy”—looms large in its basic conceptualization of the dilemma of democratic self-defense (Loewenstein, <span>1937</span>). It is a perspective ultimately concerned with protecting the integrity of core democratic institutions and its decision-making procedures. The fundamental “Löwensteinian” concern is that democratic procedures are vulnerable and easily exploited for anti-democratic ends. References to the fall of the Weimar Republic are ubiquitous in the academic literature, and increasingly in contemporary public debate, serving as the paradigmatic example of a democratic system that lacked adequate constitutional mechanisms to protect itself against anti-democratic attacks (Abts &amp; Rummens, <span>2010</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>; Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Quong, <span>2004</span>; Rijpkema, <span>2018</span>; Vinx, <span>2020</span>).<sup>2</sup> Instead, the argument goes, anti-democrats were able to dismantle democracy “from within”.</p><p>A core idea is that the inherent openness of democratic institutions makes <i>pre-emptive</i> action permissible and sometimes necessary against political movements that can be suspected of subverting those institutions in the future. As Müller states, “a militant democracy does not wait until its enemies have gained majorities at the poll; it seeks to nip fundamental opposition to democracy in the bud” (Müller, <span>2016</span>: 250). Although conventionally less pronounced in a US constitutional tradition, it has been prevalent in post-war democratic constitutional debates in many European countries (Bourne, <span>2018</span>; Fox &amp; Nolte, <span>1995</span>; Norman, <span>2022</span>; Suteu, <span>2021</span>). Theorists of militant democracy are careful to distance themselves from many of the measures defended by Karl Löwenstein (Kirshner, <span>2014</span>; Müller, <span>2016</span>), and others have argued that the notion of a militant democracy is inherently tied to elitist and anti-participatory logics (Invernizzi Accetti &amp; Zuckerman, 2017; Malkopoulou &amp; Norman, <span>2018</span>). It is, moreover, increasingly recognized that contemporary anti-democrats rarely voice explicitly authoritarian or totalitarian political ideals. Rather, the political platforms of authoritarian populists in Europe, the United States, and Latin America, with some clear exceptions, tend to occupy the grey area between democratic and authoritarian politics (Malkopoulou &amp; Moffitt, <span>2023</span>). The point is that contemporary anti-democratic movements may fall well outside the scope of traditional militant measures such as restrictions on assembly, political organization and party funding that have dominated discussions on militant democracy (Rovira Kaltwasser, <span>2019</span>). This holds even if we observe how populist parties similar to those emerging in many consolidated democracies are instigating anti-democratic political developments elsewhere, where they may have gained government power. These observations further underpin the need to theorize the principles on which institutions in the public sphere should base their response to speech and agents perceived to challenge democratic values.</p><p>The answer, from our perspective, is not to advocate for more intrusive and repressive legal restrictions in the public sphere. Rather, we aim to highlight which values are at stake when public sphere institutions consider limits to public discourse. This leads us to theorize the nature of the threat to democracy in these settings. If, as we argued above, we are not primarily concerned with actions and forms of speech regulated by law, what is the basis for the dilemma and why is it a concern for democratic theory? How is democracy imperiled by systematic rhetorical attacks on the social and political status of particular groups? We propose that a focus on human dignity as a democratic value allows us to cut to the core of anti-democratic rhetoric and action. Indeed, these are values explicitly recognized by many militant democrats, including Loewenstein (<span>1937</span>, p. 658). Democratic institutions and procedures are from this perspective ultimately guarantors of human dignity, and this value should inform the protection of these institutions. Yet, we believe that the predominant focus on democratic institutions and procedures, specifically those related to electoral politics, tends to downplay both individual level and aggregated consequences of speech in the public sphere. For those reasons existing perspectives seem less well-suited to identify and address current anti-democratic challenges. By extending the analysis to public sphere institutions and by invoking the importance of human dignity to democracy, our approach offers the groundwork for a clearer discussion on the dilemmas that arise in efforts to defend democracy against such threats.</p><p>There is a dual relationship between the value of human dignity and democratic ideals. On the one hand, human dignity is the background norm—an abstract principle—that is frequently perceived as a justification for democratic rights of participation. On the other, human dignity signifies a particular social status—or social practice—that is arguably instrumental to active participation and the use of democratic rights. We discuss both these aspects of dignity as a vehicle to identify threats to democracy in the public sphere.</p><p>As a bedrock for normative claims and a social status worthy of protection, human dignity is bound up with a broader catalogue of liberal rights. Human dignity is typically incorporated as part of this catalogue and appears in written constitutions to differentiate the democratic political order from past authoritarian experiences. Human dignity emerged as the legal principle that provides the foundation for democratic and constitutional orders in post-war Europe (Dupré, <span>2013</span>). A similar pattern is visible in Latin America after the fall of the juntas and in Eastern Europe after the fall of Communist regimes (Barak, <span>2015</span>).<sup>3</sup></p><p>The principle of human dignity provides a justification for democratic institutions. This is, for instance, illustrated by the fact that it figures among the founding values of the Treaty on European Union (Article 2) and that it plays a key role in the 1949 constitution of Germany. It also undergirds important decisions in the jurisprudence of the US Supreme Court that has treated “dignity as a value underlying, or giving meaning to, existing constitutional rights and guarantees” (Goodman, <span>2005</span>, p. 743; cf. Kahn, <span>2015</span>; Simon, <span>2021</span>; Tremper, <span>1988</span>). Given that human dignity is widely recognized as a key value for democracy it might appear surprising that it has not been given more room in the literature on democratic self-defense.<sup>4</sup> To an extent, we believe that this has to do with the concept's pliability in terms of the different meanings to which it is associated in different literatures.</p><p>In fact, the relationship between human dignity and democracy remains contested (Baer, <span>2009</span>; Rosen, <span>2012</span>; Valentini, <span>2017</span>; Waldron, <span>2012</span>). There are conceptions of democracy where conceptions of human dignity play a limited, if any, role. For instance, justifications for democratic procedures as means for competitive but peaceful resolution of political conflict scarcely need appeal to values of equal dignity (Bobbio, <span>1984</span>; Popper, <span>1945</span>; Przeworski, <span>1999</span>; Schumpeter [1943] <span>2003</span>). This does not mean that such “minimalist” perspectives on democracy would necessarily deny that dignity is an important concern for human beings, only that it does not play into core justifications for democracy as a form of government. From a minimalist democratic perspective, even nondemocratic regimes have often done “very well in securing what most of us believe the democratic method should secure” including human dignity (Schumpeter [1943] <span>2003</span>, p. 246). A related and common objection to the concept is that human dignity fails to offer any clear normative direction at all (Seglow, <span>2016</span>). Others argue that human dignity may be more useful in other social and ethical contexts, for instance, as the basis for the protection of bodily integrity, privacy, or the right to life (Beyleveld &amp; Brownsword, <span>1993</span>).</p><p>We think, however, that the idea of human dignity as an important background value for democracy is useful to ground a discussion on democratic self-defense in the public sphere. Though human dignity refers to the inner human worth of individual beings, we shall here treat it as more or less coterminous with equal moral status and the moral claim that this status ought to be recognized by public institutions. Our point here is that a commitment to the principle of human dignity is fundamental not merely for liberals, but also for democrats (cf. Dworkin, <span>2011</span>).</p><p>To further specify the relevance of the principle of human dignity for discussions on democratic self-defense, we highlight two aspects. First, human dignity signifies a social status that is instrumental to democratic participation (Ober, <span>2012</span>). Human dignity is hence understood to require public recognition of the person as an equal member of society. A person who is publicly recognized as an equal is recognized as a person with human dignity. This overlaps with what is elsewhere termed social equality and rejects “hierarchies of social status” and “stigmatizing differences in status” (Fourie, <span>2012</span>). The respect required by human dignity is in this sense more demanding than protections of political equality. Arguably, the status of “public equality” is among the great benefits conferred to all members of a democratic society by virtue of their standing as political equals (Christiano, <span>2009</span>; Gonzalez-Ricoy &amp; Queralt, <span>2018</span>). The secure enjoyment of the social status associated with recognition of human dignity plays an important role in making available venues for participation. More specifically, related to the functioning of a democratic public sphere, it is a precondition for dialogue in public affairs for all members of the community.</p><p>Human dignity is, second, a basic claim about moral status that grounds a wide variety of rights, including rights to democratic participation (Rosen, <span>2012</span>).<sup>5</sup> The claim that all individuals share the same moral status, because of their human dignity, is intimately bound up with the justification of democracy as it allows us to regard the equal enjoyment and exercise of political rights as the full expression of our status as inviolable and dignified human beings (Baer, <span>2009</span>; Dworkin, <span>2006</span>). In the context of extremist threat to democracy, we thus believe the most illuminating aspect of dignity is that of a particular public status. This is consistent with the notion that it is a background value that makes democratic politics possible. The core meaning of human dignity is—we take it—that all members of the democratic community should be publicly affirmed as individuals of equal standing.</p><p>Human dignity as equal public status in a community is similar to the recognition of “the right to have rights” (Arendt, <span>1951</span>; Hann, <span>2016</span>; Isaac, <span>1996</span>). It avoids theoretical discussions on the contents of specific rights such as the right to freedom or the right to life and instead seeks to establish the fundamental condition for such rights, however they are defined, to be respected. Respect for dignity in this perspective serves a meta-function related to the recognition of full membership in a political community that is necessary for more specific rights to be respected, including democratic ones. Our thesis here is that dignity is a social status that depends on—and is therefore also vulnerable to—practices in the wider public sphere. To protect that status, theories of democratic self-defense need to ground themselves in a perspective that fleshes out what constitutes harms to equal dignity.</p><p>To concretize how the erosion of human dignity in the public sphere of democratic societies can manifest itself, we invoke a distinction from social-psychology and bioethics between two main ways in which speech may be contrary to the equal public status of others: <i>delegitimization</i> and <i>dehumanization</i>. These two concepts depict degrees to which the public standing of a person can be questioned or undermined by speech. They are related to the well-known category of “hate speech” that predominates in legal discourse. We believe, however, that the concepts proposed here open up for a more graded and nuanced discussion on which types of speech might work to undermine dignity, even when such speech falls within what is legally permitted.</p><p>Delegitimization is defined as efforts to fundamentally undermine an individual's status as legitimate member of a political community by reference to their association with a particular societal group and attributing deeply negative characteristics as intrinsic traits to that group (cf. Bar-Tal, <span>1989</span>). Delegitimization thus takes aim at individuals as members of groups rather than as representatives of particular political positions and it is characterized by implicit or explicit attempts to undermine the status of others as equal rights-holders and as equal contenders for political influence. Delegitimizing speech can be understood as intimately tied to exclusionary notions of “The People” and associated to understandings of the people's interests in fixed and holistic terms (Ochoa Espejo, <span>2017</span>; Urbinati, <span>2019</span>; Wolkenstein, <span>2019</span>). It includes statements that negate the equal public standing of individuals in that particular community. Yet, not every claim that seeks to delegitimize the equal public status of another person is necessarily an affront to the democratic value of human dignity.<sup>6</sup> Moreover, as outlined above, human dignity can also be undermined by measures that do not attack the equal public status of individuals as citizens.</p><p>Claims that some citizens be excluded from the moral, political or legal community may nevertheless constitute an attack on their equal public status and as such pave the way for infringements of their democratic rights as well as of other fundamental rights. The democratic significance of this point trades on an insight in the previous literature, which is that recognized membership in a political community is a precondition for secure enjoyment of basic political rights. As assaults on equal public status are instrumental in denying particular citizens their status as members of the political community, assaults on dignity also work to undermine basic political rights generally. This is what makes speech that attacks the public status of particular groups so insidious, and why it is inherently a concern for democracy.</p><p>Dehumanization is the category of speech with the most obvious and far-reaching implications in terms its potential to undermine the equal public status that is necessary for respecting the human dignity of all citizens. Delegitimization, deployed as a political strategy, may come with serious consequences, especially in terms of paving the way for the infringement of other fundamental rights of individuals. Dehumanization, however, cuts to the core of such infringements. The common denominator of speech that dehumanizes others is that it seeks to exclude them from membership in humanity by portraying them as “animal-like” or otherwise devoid of the traits that are uniquely human (Haslam, <span>2006</span>). It is thus more far-reaching in that it does not limit itself to questions of individual's legitimate right to participate in a particular community but works to undermine the status of individuals as human beings altogether. Historically, dehumanizing speech has been deployed to establish the inferiority of members of ethnic, linguistic, religious, and other social groups and has been part and parcel of violent persecution, slavery and genocide. In a US context, the historical legacy of slavery is illustrative for our argument, where recognition of human dignity was withheld on the basis of radical exclusion of certain groups from the category of humanity. The far-reaching denial of human dignity in this context is precisely evidenced not merely by the denial of slaves and their descendants as members of the political “people” but by the denial of them as members of the category of people <i>tout court</i> (Canovan, <span>2005</span>). Here, again, the problem was not that those in power were unable to conceptualize what particular rights entailed but that those rights emerged in a political context which rendered them null and void when considered in relation to parts of the population.</p><p>The underlying logic of speech that seeks to undermine the human dignity of others is instructive to the aim of theorizing how democratic values are at risk in the public sphere of democratic societies. Recent experimental studies in psychology indicate how dehumanization is associated with a permissive attitude toward harm with respect to targeted individuals and groups (Dalsklev &amp; Ronningsdalen Kunst, <span>2015</span>; Markowitz &amp; Slovic, <span>2020</span>; cf. Over, <span>2021</span>). The same attitudes are reinforced by, for instance, the depiction of undervalued minority groups as unhygienic, which has been shown to trigger feelings of disgust (Dalsklev &amp; Ronningsdalen Kunst, <span>2015</span>). Dehumanization comes close to what would in many cases count as hate speech, which is recognized as an offense by criminal law in many countries. However, as the examples above illustrate, speech that is not necessarily hate speech can still provide subtle cues instrumental for undermining human dignity. Like explicit anti-democratic positions, assaults on the dignity of other members are a form of extremism that prompts a response from democratic institutions also in the public sphere.</p><p>Once dignity is identified as a value to be preserved in the face of anti-democratic challenges, the sphere of concern expands to include institutions and practices in the public sphere generally, and not just the electoral arena. Here, the dilemma consists in how to safeguard democratic and inclusive arenas of opinion-formation while at the same time protect human dignity from the corrosive effects of delegitimizing or dehumanizing speech.</p><p>For the purpose of illustration, consider the cases of public media institutions, public schools and social media platforms. Public service broadcasting organizations are expected to adhere to ideals of inclusive representation in their coverage of politics. Truthful, impartial and objective reporting on political actors, public policy and law is a key role to be played by the public service in a liberal democracy (Goidel et al, <span>2017</span>; Newton, <span>2016</span>; Norris, <span>2000</span>). This is particularly the case in Europe where state funded public broadcasting organizations still hold important positions as public sphere institutions. There are strong and compelling reasons for these organizations to be as inclusive and pluralistic as possible. To that extent, public service media institutions should include political voices of any kind, even, it could be argued, those of actors engaging in delegitimizing speech. However, in order to protect the dignity of all citizens, there are good reasons for why public media institutions should take measures to protect both participants and audiences from attacks on their status as equal members of society. Thus, the best policy, all things considered, remains uncertain. Public broadcasting organizations often struggle to translate a principled commitment to democratic principles into a defensible response to speech deemed democratically problematic. Heated debates, in many European countries not least, have revolved around perceived biases of public broadcasting organizations on the one hand and, on the other, problems related to providing room for, and thus legitimizing, parties deemed by some to threaten democracy (Hien &amp; Norman, <span>2023</span>). The dilemma of democratic self-preservation facing public media institutions is that democratic values are potentially threatened whether speech that undermines the dignity of some is suppressed or not.</p><p>Similar conditions apply to public schools. Public schools in many countries organize mock elections as part of their civic education, often in election years, to foster citizens’ engagement in politics (Ohrvall &amp; Oskarsson, <span>2020</span>). By being inclusive with respect to political ideologies, schools can serve as a training ground for critical thinking and public deliberation. However, when radical political parties are invited, there is a risk that they will undermine the sense of equal worth and dignity among groups of students, again considering that such potential harms can be expected to be distributed unequally among the members of such groups. In order for public schools to take responsibility for democratic values they may need to take measures that protect students for particular egregious forms of political speech. The example of schools is instructive precisely because it clearly highlights the responsibility of the institution, especially as the audience in this setting are not fully formed members of the political community. Again, here emerges the dilemma of democratic self-preservation: there are democratic reasons for both including representatives of all political parties and for excluding at least some of them. Recently, in some contexts, for instance, in Scandinavian countries, schools have addressed the problem by discontinuing the practice of inviting political representatives. Although this might be a reasonable course of action it is also a solution that clearly limits the functioning of that part of the public sphere. A strategy of retreat replaces dealing head on with the difficult dilemma relating to the limits of permissible speech in political debate.</p><p>We mentioned social media platforms above and they exemplify clearly that this dilemma is not confined to institutions formally tied to the state. Although they are private corporations, dominant platforms have gained a prominent position as arenas for public debate. Exclusion from access to social media platforms may in some cases have more far-reaching consequences than exclusion from more conventional public sphere institutions, such as public service media outlets. In the United States, this came to a head with the post-election exclusion from these platforms by former president Donald Trump. The fact that platforms like Facebook, X, and YouTube have gained such prominent positions as vehicles of contemporary political debate has come with expectations that these companies should be “unbiased” in terms of the contents they allow. Due to these expectations and similar to public sphere institutions, dilemmas arise due to conflicting demands. On the one hand, there is the need to safeguard openness, inclusion, and pluralism, while on the other, there is a requirement to ensure safety, authenticity of published material, and in the case of Facebook's oversight board charter, to protect dignity of individuals (Facebook, <span>2021</span>).<sup>7</sup></p><p>To acknowledge the existence of dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the broader public sphere is to appreciate the need for a more graded and nuanced perspective than has often been the case in debates about democratic self-defense. This is particularly true when threats to equal dignity take the form of actions or speech that seek to either delegitimize or dehumanize specific members in society.</p><p>We consider two types of strategies for protecting the human dignity of participants in public sphere institutions from delegitimization and dehumanization: exclusion and expressive action. These strategies build on long-standing discussions on democratic self-defense, which have mainly focused on when it is legitimate for the state to respond with repressive measures. When transposing such considerations to public sphere institutions we think it is necessary to also discuss instances when these institutions should deviate from their role as impartial facilitators of public debate and use their expressive capabilities to push back at certain statements. Exclusion includes various degrees of denying individuals access to institutions as well as limiting the distribution of content and various forms of speech. Expressive action refers to how an institution may communicate how content and speech run contrary to specific democratic values. Of the two, exclusion from public sphere institutions tends to be more problematic. Excluding perceived anti-democratic agents risks undermining the respect required by democratic values for their equal participation in the public sphere. On a systemic level, it further risks introducing anti-participatory and elitist practices into the public sphere, similar to those highlighted by critics of the militant democratic tradition (Invernizzi Accetti &amp; Zuckerman, <span>2017</span>; Malkopoulou &amp; Norman, <span>2018</span>; Norman, <span>2021</span>; Stahl &amp; Popp-Madsen, <span>2022</span>). However, expressive action, whether in the form of public endorsement or public condemnation of particular views, is not uncomplicated. It can have highly significant consequences for individuals and potentially stifle a climate of open debate.</p><p>In this context, various strategies analogous to those implied by classical dilemmas of democratic self-defense resurface, albeit in a new form. The dilemma revolves around the requirements for public sphere institutions to meet criteria of pluralism and promote the free exchange of ideas conducive to the formation of opinions, all while protecting the dignity of all individuals. Furthermore, the dilemma arises due to the potential costs incurred by individuals whose views are publicly denounced or excluded by an institution. When and to what extent is there a democratic justification for public sphere institutions to exclude political representatives, private citizens or specific content? When and to what extent should institutions in the public sphere engage in expressive action, by actively challenging or flagging speech that is perceived to undermine or attack the dignity of other citizens?</p><p>An expressive approach is analogous to Brettschneider's (<span>2016</span>) claim that the state should rely on its expressive powers to condemn “hateful viewpoints” by articulating the reasons and values that undergird democratic rights. However, as is regularly the case in the media, including social media, populist and far-right rhetoric does not necessarily meet the criteria for hate speech, even when it directly targets the public status of specific groups.</p><p>An alternative approach, therefore, is for public sphere institutions—schools, the public media, universities, museums, and social media platforms—to articulate the deeper justifications and reasons for their commitment to democratic values. In other words, they should publicly affirm the human dignity of all without denying anyone the democratic right to participate, speak, and be included in the public sphere. The basic idea is that respect for human dignity provides strong reasons for institutions in the public sphere to <i>challenge</i> content that seeks to delegitimize or dehumanize members of society. This includes a variety of possibilities, from discursive engagement to distancing, as acknowledged in the growing literature on counter-speech (e.g., Fumagalli, <span>2020</span>). The expressive strategy can also be pursued by means of “flagging” content that is considered suspect, unreliable or contrary to democratic values. Flagging is a well-established practice by social media providers, executed either manually, by scripts or self-learning algorithms. Though flagging is clearly a soft sanction, evidence suggests that it is effective in slowing the spread of problematic content (Mena, <span>2020</span>). Flagging is a measure that has been introduced, to a great degree, to cope with the sheer scale of content on social media apps and often contains little more than a reference to the platform's user agreement. Other institutions, such as universities or public broadcasting organizations, should be expected to provide elaborate justifications for flagging and other responses.</p><p>A benefit of the expressive approach is that it remains consistent with permissive norms of freedom of speech and freedom of association that also extend to anti-democratic rhetoric and actors. Expressive action is a form of reason-giving and is premised on the value of open debate. At the same time, it may also, to a degree, offset the often-unequal burden carried by those who are the explicit targets of efforts to delegitimize and dehumanize. The expressive strategy thus strikes a balance by offering a measure of protection while also trusting individuals, even those who might be targeted by efforts to undermine human dignity, to possess both the resilience and the agency to creatively engage in counterstrategies.</p><p>A commitment to a public sphere characterized by wide-ranging pluralism calls for tolerance and, therefore, for participants to be prepared to accept considerable discomfort or even offence. At a fundamental level it relies on a view of democracy that places trust in individuals to withstand offensive speech and to recognize the value of a permissive attitude toward speech as fundamental for democracy. We believe that norms against delegitimization and dehumanization can help distinguish speech that would necessitate an institutional response from speech that might be seen as offensive, uncivil or disrespectful but should not trigger such a response.</p><p>Far-reaching threats to the dignity of the members of society sometimes require exclusionary measures. The problems with exclusionary strategies are still numerous and mirror many of the concerns that might be raised against repressive responses, such as party bans in conventional notions of militant democracy. However, here it is also important to differentiate between various forms of exclusionary practices, each of which is associated to different problems that need to be mitigated in various ways and weighed against their possible gains.</p><p>Legal bans, such as those directed at anti-democratic parties in some democracies, are obviously beyond the reach for institutions in the public sphere. Yet, these institutions have the power to design their own formal or informal norms that exclude either actors or content in so far as they are consistent with the law. When implementing exclusionary measures aimed at content, private individuals, or organizations, there are well-known risks associated with infringements on the rights of those actors. If public sphere institutions are expected to reproduce norms of inclusiveness, impartiality, and openness and to safeguard individual rights such as freedom of speech, exclusionary practices become problematic. Apart from the democratic harms imposed on individuals there are systemic risks associated with the implementation of exclusionary measures. Chief among these might be that they short-circuit an important component of a vital public sphere, namely a principled level of trust extended to all members of society to process and respond to any viewpoints expressed in that sphere. A public sphere built on the notion of individuals’ inability to do so not only risks stifling public debate. It also comes with problematic implications in terms of infusing the public sphere with a paternalistic logic that goes against the grain of the democratic principle of self-government. Coercive measures, such as banning actors from participation and removing certain kinds of content should then be considered with great care before they are implemented.</p><p>To assess if exclusionary measures are justifiable from a democratic perspective, it is useful to think about exclusion in more differentiated terms than is conventionally the case. Here, considering the type of actor targeted by exclusionary measures, such as private individuals or organizations, might lead to different conclusions. To exclude representatives of groups, organizations or parties if they attack or undermine the dignity of other citizens, from spreading information in schools, public places, and social media platforms is not unproblematic. However, targeting actors in their capacity as private citizens, not only as representatives for political organizations, is more serious in terms of the risk of undermining the respect for human dignity of such individuals. As Kirshner (<span>2014</span>) has argued, the political interests and identities of anti-democrats, racists, and extremists are not solely determined by their hostility to democratic institutions and values. As private citizens, they may also have distinct political interests that deserve protection and inclusion in processes of collective will-formation. Blanket exclusions of private citizens from institutions in the public sphere thus represent a greater infringement of democratic norms than exclusions targeting representatives of organizations. Damages incurred by excluding representatives from particular settings also have broader implications as it excludes from discussion the views of a broader set of actors. Yet another aspect that brings nuance to the discussion on exclusionary measures is to consider time-limitations on sanctions rather than open-ended or indefinite ones. Such considerations were part of the stated reasons for the recent reinstatement of Donald Trump's Facebook and Instagram accounts by Meta (Meta, <span>2023</span>).<sup>8</sup></p><p>Exclusionary strategies can also be directed toward specific content or forms of speech. Again, militant democrats typically endorse legal bans on speech that attacks democratic institutions or elected representatives. Nazi ideology and propaganda have repeatedly been struck down by the European Court of Human Rights and many European constitutions either permit or require restrictions on “abuses” of freedom of speech that threaten the democratic system (Tsoumidis, <span>2021</span>). In the context of social media platforms this corresponds to the removal of content rather than “deplatforming”. One problem with the removal of content, often referred to as content moderation, is that the myriad of such decisions that are taken every day by the main social media platforms tend to be nontransparent and provide few means for appeal. Content moderation is thus facing specific challenges of democratic legitimacy. These challenges can be mitigated by expressive actions. The responsibility on the part of public sphere institutions to provide reasons for exclusion and to provide individuals with possibilities for appeal is important. Expressive action is thus a necessary aspect of any effort to implement exclusionary measures. Moreover, exclusionary measures have in themselves an expressive aspect that can be used to signal the limits of publicly acceptable political action to actors beyond those directly targeted.</p><p>Like all general principles, decisions on the application of the strategies outlined here need to take into account case-specific circumstances. Of key importance for such decisions is the historical legacy of power asymmetries and domination between different groups in particular societies. Historical legacies shape and give substance to what delegitimization and dehumanization is, and how the dignity of individuals is harmed by them, and must therefore inform the strategy that best serves to protect democratic values. Understanding such legacies will provide insights into the uneven distribution of threats to human dignity. Although the specific resolution of the dilemma we have discussed depends on the context in which it arises, we believe that the general conceptual tools developed here are essential for fully recognizing the stakes involved and for modeling a response that is appropriate for a democratic society.</p><p>In this article, we have offered the theoretical underpinnings for democracy's protection in the public sphere by elaborating on the democratic significance of human dignity. This shift in perspective was partially motivated by an empirical assessment of the types of anti-democratic threats facing contemporary democratic societies. Overt anti-democrats and outright extremist political movements still exist and should not be overlooked. However, we perceive a more acute problem among political actors who often remain broadly committed to a minimalist notion of democracy while trading on ideas, increasingly prevalent in the public sphere, which undermine the human dignity of particular societal groups. The analytical shift toward public sphere institutions, we argued, helps us reconsider the theoretical tools that we use to make sense of dilemmas of democracy's protection.</p><p>Focusing on human dignity as a fundamental democratic value highlights the unequal costs borne by already marginalized groups due to anti-democratic assaults. We illustrated this argument by discussing ways in which speech and other acts may undermine dignity by delegitimizing and dehumanizing members of particular social groups, undermining their claims to have their rights recognized, or, in the most egregious forms, denying them equal status as members of humanity. The choice between expressive actions or exclusions will always depend, in part, on factors specific to particular cases. However, we believe that the clear specification of a key value that underlie these democratic dilemmas, which we have attempted in this article, provides firmer theoretical grounding for such decisions.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"31 4\",\"pages\":\"580-594\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-02-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12737\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12737\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12737","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

当代对民主倒退和民主制度争论的关注,甚至在巩固的民主国家,重新引发了长期以来关于民主社会应如何应对感知到的反民主威胁以及原则性的“民主自卫”应该是什么样子的辩论(Kirshner, 2014;穆勒,2016;Malkopoulou,诺曼,2018;参见Loewenstein, 1937)。这些辩论的核心困境在于,为了保护民主制度的完整性和加强民主的护栏,对反民主言论、行动者及其协会的限制在多大程度上是合理的。这一传统上与保护民主体制有关的困境的各种形式,在民主社会的其他领域日益突出。公共领域机构,如学校、大学和公共广播组织,以及社交媒体平台,已经深深地卷入了关于言论和政治行动限制的讨论中。根据惯例或立法,人们期望这些机构维护和再现自由民主的核心价值,同时对多种观点保持开放,允许自由形成和表达政治思想。然而,在这些公共领域机构的背景下,哪些价值观应该指导限制或呼吁被视为挑战自由民主规范的言论的决定,现有的文献很少提及。我们在这篇文章中关注的是明确地充实公共领域民主自卫的核心困境,并将在此背景下岌岌可危的民主价值理论化。我们认为,将人的尊严视为自由民主的基本价值,有助于我们更准确地识别公共领域中民主威胁的特征,民主价值可能受到破坏的各种方式,以及据此,公共领域机构如何应对这些挑战。至关重要的是,人类尊严是一种基本民主价值的假设,使我们能够认识到,从民主的角度来看,受法律保护的言论如何仍然存在很大的问题。我们认为,这一点很重要,因为对自由民主的许多挑战涉及个人层面的伤害,即个人尊严受到损害的情况。这一论点的关键是将攻击公民平等尊严与攻击民主之间的联系理论化。我们把作为民主价值的人的尊严与作为政治共同体成员给予个人的尊重和地位联系起来。关注民主背景下的这种联系有助于突出在当前关于激进民主和民主自卫的讨论中没有得到持续关注的言论特征。我们的论点强调,民主社会的一些成员比其他人面临更大的风险,因为他们在承认平等地位方面已经处于不稳定的地位。纳入这一见解应对在民主国家“微观层面”打击反民主威胁的战略产生影响。最后,这使我们能够重新思考民主行动者可以通过哪些战略来解决这一困境。我们考虑排他性和表达性策略,并讨论它们如何涉及不同的权衡和困境。本文首先澄清了公共领域中反民主挑战的理论起点。我们将我们的观点与民主理论中关注民主保护的流行观点进行对比。接下来,我们概述了人类尊严作为一种民主价值的重要性,并定义了尊严在公共领域可能受到破坏的主要方式。我们通过讨论公共广播组织、社交媒体平台和教育机构所面临的困境来阐述我们的论点。最后一节概述了在公共领域击退反民主威胁的可用策略,包括排斥性和表达性行动。我们提出了一个支持表达策略的论点,同时强调了两种策略都可以使用的实例,以及公共领域机构应该保持被动的实例。我们的出发点是,当代对民主的威胁需要更多地关注公共领域中民主自卫的困境。公共领域可以被定义为“社会中允许信息、思想和辩论流通的交流空间的星座”(Dahlgren, 2005)。它由正式和非正式机构组成,包括学校和大学(Holmwood, 2017)、公共媒体机构(Iosifidis, 2011)、博物馆(Barrett, 2011)以及越来越多的社交媒体平台(cf. m<e:1>勒,2019)。 法律上的禁令,例如在某些民主国家针对反民主政党的禁令,显然超出了公共领域机构的能力范围。然而,这些机构有权设计自己的正式或非正式规范,在符合法律的情况下排除行为者或内容。在实施针对内容、个人或组织的排他性措施时,与侵犯这些行动者的权利有关的风险是众所周知的。如果期望公共领域机构再现包容、公正和开放的规范,并保障言论自由等个人权利,那么排他性做法就会成为问题。除了对个人造成的民主危害外,实施排他性措施还会带来系统性风险。其中最主要的可能是,它们使一个至关重要的公共领域的一个重要组成部分短路,即向社会所有成员提供原则性的信任,以处理和回应该领域所表达的任何观点。建立在个人无能的观念上的公共领域不仅有扼杀公共辩论的风险。它还带来了一些问题,比如在公共领域注入了一种与自治的民主原则背道而驰的家长式逻辑。强制措施,如禁止演员参与和删除某些类型的内容,在实施之前应该非常仔细地考虑。为了从民主的角度评估排斥性措施是否合理,从比传统情况更有区别的角度来考虑排斥性是有用的。在这里,考虑排他性措施所针对的行为者类型,例如私人或组织,可能会得出不同的结论。将攻击或损害其他公民尊严的团体、组织或政党的代表排除在学校、公共场所和社交媒体平台上传播信息并非没有问题。但是,针对作为普通公民而不仅仅是作为政治组织代表的行动者,就有破坏对这些个人的人的尊严的尊重的危险而言,是更为严重的。正如Kirshner(2014)所指出的那样,反民主主义者、种族主义者和极端主义者的政治利益和身份并不仅仅取决于他们对民主制度和价值观的敌意。作为普通公民,他们可能也有独特的政治利益,值得在集体意志形成过程中得到保护和包容。因此,将普通公民全面排除在公共领域的机构之外比将组织代表排除在外更严重地违反了民主规范。将代表排除在特定环境之外所造成的损害也具有更广泛的影响,因为它将更广泛的行为者的观点排除在讨论之外。然而,使关于排他性措施的讨论具有细微差别的另一个方面是考虑制裁的时限,而不是不限期限或无限期的。这些考虑是Meta最近恢复唐纳德·特朗普的Facebook和Instagram账户的部分原因(Meta, 2023)。排他策略也可以针对特定的言论内容或形式。同样,激进的民主人士通常支持法律禁止攻击民主机构或民选代表的言论。纳粹意识形态和宣传一再被欧洲人权法院驳回,许多欧洲宪法允许或要求限制威胁民主制度的“滥用”言论自由(Tsoumidis, 2021)。在社交媒体平台的背景下,这相当于删除内容,而不是“去平台化”。删除内容(通常被称为内容审核)的一个问题是,主要社交媒体平台每天做出的无数此类决定往往是不透明的,几乎没有提供上诉的手段。因此,内容节制正面临着民主合法性的具体挑战。这些挑战可以通过表达性的行动来缓解。公共领域机构有责任为排斥提供理由,并为个人提供申诉的可能性,这一点很重要。因此,表达性行动是实施排他性措施的必要方面。此外,排他性措施本身具有表达性,可用于表明公众可接受的政治行动对直接针对对象之外的行为者的限制。同所有一般原则一样,关于适用这里概述的战略的决定需要考虑到具体情况。 对于此类决策至关重要的是特定社会中不同群体之间权力不对称和统治的历史遗产。历史遗产塑造并赋予了什么是非合法化和非人性化,以及它们如何损害个人尊严的实质内容,因此必须为最有利于保护民主价值观的战略提供信息。了解这些遗产将有助于深入了解对人类尊严的威胁的不均衡分布。虽然我们所讨论的困境的具体解决办法取决于它产生的背景,但我们认为,这里发展的一般概念工具对于充分认识所涉及的利害关系和为适合民主社会的反应建模是必不可少的。在本文中,我们通过阐述人类尊严的民主意义,为在公共领域保护民主提供了理论基础。这种观点的转变部分是由于对当代民主社会所面临的各种反民主威胁进行了实证评估。公开的反民主和极端主义政治运动仍然存在,不应忽视。然而,我们在政治行为者中看到一个更严重的问题,他们往往仍然广泛地致力于最低限度的民主概念,同时利用在公共领域日益流行的损害特定社会群体的人的尊严的思想。我们认为,向公共领域制度的分析转变,有助于我们重新考虑我们用来理解民主保护困境的理论工具。把人的尊严作为一种基本的民主价值来强调,由于反民主的攻击,已经被边缘化的群体承担了不平等的代价。我们通过讨论言论和其他行为可能通过使特定社会群体的成员失去合法性和非人性化,破坏他们要求得到承认的权利,或者以最恶劣的形式否认他们作为人类成员的平等地位,从而损害尊严的方式来说明这一论点。在表达行为或排除之间的选择总是部分地取决于特定情况下的特定因素。然而,我们认为,我们在本文中试图明确说明构成这些民主困境的关键价值,为这些决定提供了更坚实的理论基础。 这些环境对于一个正常运作的民主制度至关重要,在民主制度下,个人应该能够平等地参与和审议公共问题。我们的论证并不假设公共领域只关注“共同利益”(Taylor, 1992),也不假设公共领域必然具有“代表性”和“包容性”(Fraser, 1990)。事实上,公共领域也可以为反民主和极端主义行为者提供氧气,其机构可以成为独裁的工具(阿拉托和;科恩,2021)。由于这些原因,教师、记者、编辑、他们的董事会和董事被迫做出往往困难的决定,决定哪些行为者和哪些观点应该得到尊重。因此,有很好的理由理论化公共领域机构应该如何处理与在哪里以及如何划定民主中可容忍的界限有关的困境。这些困境与越来越多的关于民主自卫的文献中理论化的困境相似,但当我们考虑公共领域机构时,它们就会呈现出不同的面貌(参见m<e:1>勒,2016;Malkopoulou,科什纳,2019)。随着数字化程度的提高,社交媒体平台的兴起以及传统印刷和广播媒体的衰落,出现了一种“守门人崩溃”的强烈趋势(法雷尔&;施瓦茨伯格,2021:222)。这也构成了一种转变,即公共领域的非国家机构越来越多地不得不就包括或排除特定行为和信息做出有争议的、有时是非常重要的决定,即使在这些行为和信息完全合法的情况下(钱伯斯和;Kopstein, 2022)。一些领先的社交媒体平台,尤其是当时被称为Twitter的平台,决定暂停当时美国总统唐纳德·特朗普(Donald Trump)的账户,这很能说明问题(Twitter, 2021a)。禁止特朗普使用Twitter的决定,或者实际上是邀请他重返该平台的决定,并不是由公共当局以违反任何法律为由做出的。这是一家私营公司根据其反对美化暴力的政策做出的决定(Twitter, 2021b)。民主自卫的困境不仅适用于社交媒体平台;它在当代民主社会的公共领域无处不在。媒体、学校、博物馆、大学和其他提供公共辩论场所的机构经常决定暂停参与者、审查用户、标记或限制内容的分发,以及决定不采取行动和包括民主上有问题的观点。在这种情况下出现的困境越来越多地渗透到民主的日常实践中。然而,它们与民主国家在反民主政党和组织方面所面临的困境明显不同。公共领域机构既不是司法机构,也不是立法机构;它们是罗尔斯所说的“背景文化”的一部分。在一个自由民主的社会中,背景文化是自由结社生活的舞台,这种生活在很大程度上应该不受法律的管制(罗尔斯,1997)。因此,公共领域为实现民主自卫的困境提供了充足的机会,但立法并没有,实际上也不应该提供明确的指导。这一困境与选举机构的完整性和政治民主程序的关系不大,而与民主社会的成员受到平等尊重的程度有关。这对我们如何理解反民主威胁在这些环境中如何发挥作用具有启示意义。为了我们论证的目的,特别重要的是要挑战这样一种假设,即这种威胁平等地影响民主国家的所有公民。相反,我们假设反民主言论和行动的负担在更大程度上由一些群体承担,而不是由其他群体承担,它们的分布是不平等的。被认为是对民主的潜在威胁的政治运动的影响越来越大,例如植根于极右翼的政党,通常被认为对一个社会中所有具有民主思想的公民构成同样严重的问题。我们同意,真正的威权政府确实从根本上损害了所有公民的尊严。然而,在一个正常运转的民主国家,所有公民都同样受到反民主言论的影响,这一信念掩盖了这样一个事实,即威权政治在民主国家获得动力的关键机制是针对通常已经被边缘化的群体(都多尔和;斯雷特,2020)。反民主运动从来都不是主张专制政府形式意义上的“正当”反民主。 魏玛共和国的垮台在学术文献中无处不在,在当代公共辩论中也越来越多地出现,这是一个民主制度缺乏足够的宪法机制来保护自己免受反民主攻击的范例(Abts &amp;Rummens, 2010;穆勒,2016;科什纳,2014;Quong, 2004;Rijpkema, 2018;Vinx, 2020)。2相反,他们认为,反民主人士能够“从内部”摧毁民主。一个核心思想是,民主体制固有的开放性使得对可能在未来颠覆这些体制的政治运动采取先发制人的行动是允许的,有时也是必要的。正如<s:1>勒女士所说,“一个激进的民主国家不会等到敌人在选举中获得多数;它试图将对民主的根本反对扼杀在萌芽状态”(m<s:1> ller, 2016: 250)。尽管在美国宪法传统中通常不那么明显,但在许多欧洲国家的战后民主宪法辩论中,它一直很普遍(Bourne, 2018;福克斯,诺尔特,1995;诺曼,2022;Suteu, 2021)。激进民主的理论家们小心翼翼地与卡尔Löwenstein所捍卫的许多措施保持距离(Kirshner, 2014;m<s:1> ller, 2016)和其他人认为,激进民主的概念本质上与精英主义和反参与逻辑有关(Invernizzi Accetti &amp;Zuckerman, 2017;Malkopoulou,诺曼,2018)。此外,人们越来越认识到,当代反民主主义者很少明确表达威权主义或极权主义的政治理想。相反,欧洲、美国和拉丁美洲的威权民粹主义者的政治纲领,除了一些明显的例外,往往占据民主政治和威权政治之间的灰色地带(Malkopoulou &amp;莫菲特,2023)。关键是,当代反民主运动可能远远超出了传统激进措施的范围,例如限制集会、政治组织和政党资金,这些措施主导了关于激进民主的讨论(Rovira Kaltwasser, 2019)。即使我们观察到与许多巩固的民主国家出现的民粹主义政党相似的民粹主义政党是如何在其他地方煽动反民主的政治发展的,这些政党可能已经获得了政府权力。这些观察结果进一步支持了将公共领域机构应对被视为挑战民主价值观的言论和代理人的反应所依据的原则理论化的必要性。从我们的角度来看,答案不是在公共领域提倡更具侵入性和压制性的法律限制。相反,我们的目标是强调当公共领域机构考虑对公共话语的限制时,哪些价值观处于危险之中。这使我们对这些情况下对民主的威胁的性质进行理论化。如果,正如我们上面所说的,我们主要关心的不是受法律约束的行为和言论形式,那么这种困境的基础是什么?为什么它是民主理论的关注点?对特定群体的社会和政治地位进行系统性的言辞攻击,是如何危及民主的?我们建议,把人的尊严作为一种民主价值的焦点,使我们能够切入反民主言论和行动的核心。事实上,这些是许多激进的民主人士明确承认的价值观,包括Loewenstein (1937, p. 658)。从这一角度看,民主体制和程序最终是人的尊严的保障,这种价值应当指导对这些体制的保护。然而,我们认为,对民主制度和程序的主要关注,特别是与选举政治有关的民主制度和程序,往往低估了公共领域言论的个人层面和总体后果。由于这些原因,现有的观点似乎不太适合识别和解决当前的反民主挑战。通过将分析扩展到公共领域机构,并通过援引人的尊严对民主的重要性,我们的方法为更清晰地讨论在捍卫民主免受这种威胁的努力中出现的困境提供了基础。人的尊严价值与民主理想之间存在着双重关系。一方面,人的尊严是一种背景规范——一种抽象原则——经常被视为民主参与权的正当理由。另一方面,人的尊严意味着一种特殊的社会地位或社会实践,这对于积极参与和使用民主权利是有争议的。我们讨论了尊严的这两个方面,作为确定公共领域对民主的威胁的工具。作为规范要求和值得保护的社会地位的基石,人类尊严与更广泛的自由权利目录紧密相连。 人类尊严通常被纳入这一目录,并出现在书面宪法中,以区分民主政治秩序与过去的专制经验。人的尊严作为法律原则出现,为战后欧洲的民主和宪法秩序提供了基础(dupreur, 2013)。在军政府倒台后的拉丁美洲和共产主义政权倒台后的东欧,也可以看到类似的模式(Barak, 2015)。人的尊严原则为民主制度提供了正当性。例如,它被列入《欧洲联盟条约》(第2条)的创始价值之一,并在1949年德国宪法中发挥了关键作用,这一事实说明了这一点。它也支持了美国最高法院的重要判例,将“尊严视为一种价值,或赋予现有宪法权利和保障以意义”(Goodman, 2005, p. 743;cf. Kahn, 2015;西蒙,2021;Tremper, 1988)。鉴于人的尊严被广泛认为是民主的一项关键价值,在关于民主自卫的文献中没有给予它更多的空间,这可能令人感到惊讶在某种程度上,我们认为这与这个概念的可塑性有关,因为它在不同的文献中有不同的含义。事实上,人的尊严和民主之间的关系仍然存在争议(Baer, 2009;罗森,2012;Valentini, 2017;沃尔德伦,2012)。在某些民主概念中,人类尊严的概念即使有作用,也起着有限的作用。例如,将民主程序作为竞争性但和平解决政治冲突的手段的理由几乎不需要诉诸平等尊严的价值观(博比奥,1984;波普尔,1945;Przeworski, 1999;熊彼特[1943]2003)。这并不意味着这种对民主的“极简主义”观点必然会否认尊严是人类的重要关切,只是它不会成为民主作为一种政府形式的核心理由。从极简主义民主的角度来看,即使是非民主的政权也常常“在确保我们大多数人认为民主方法应该确保的东西方面做得很好”,包括人的尊严(熊彼特[1943]2003,第246页)。对这一概念的一个相关且常见的反对意见是,人类尊严根本没有提供任何明确的规范方向(Seglow, 2016)。其他人则认为,人的尊严可能在其他社会和伦理背景下更有用,例如,作为保护身体完整、隐私或生命权的基础。Brownsword, 1993)。然而,我们认为,人类尊严作为民主的重要背景价值的观念,对于在公共领域讨论民主自卫是有用的。虽然人的尊严指的是个体的内在价值,但我们在这里将其或多或少地视为与平等的道德地位以及这种地位应该得到公共机构承认的道德要求相关。我们的观点是,对人类尊严原则的承诺不仅对自由主义者至关重要,对民主主义者也是如此(参见德沃金,2011)。为了进一步明确人的尊严原则与民主自卫讨论的相关性,我们强调两个方面。首先,人的尊严意味着一种有助于民主参与的社会地位(Ober, 2012)。因此,人的尊严被理解为要求公众承认人是社会的平等成员。一个被公众承认为平等的人被认为是一个有尊严的人。这与其他地方所谓的社会平等重叠,拒绝“社会地位等级”和“地位差异的污名化”(Fourie, 2012)。在这个意义上,人的尊严所要求的尊重比保护政治平等更为苛刻。可以说,“公共平等”的地位是民主社会所有成员因其政治平等地位而获得的巨大利益之一(Christiano, 2009;Gonzalez-Ricoy,Queralt, 2018)。有保障地享有与承认人的尊严有关的社会地位,在提供参与场所方面发挥着重要作用。更具体地说,与民主公共领域的运作有关,它是社会所有成员在公共事务中进行对话的先决条件。其次,人的尊严是一种关于道德地位的基本主张,它为包括民主参与权在内的各种权利奠定了基础(Rosen, 2012)。 5 .所有人因其人的尊严而享有同样的道德地位,这一主张与民主的正当性密切相关,因为民主使我们能够将平等享有和行使政治权利视为我们作为不可侵犯和有尊严的人的地位的充分表达(Baer, 2009;德沃金,2006)。因此,在极端主义威胁民主的背景下,我们认为尊严的最具启发性的方面是一种特殊的公共地位。这与使民主政治成为可能的背景价值的概念是一致的。我们认为,人类尊严的核心含义是,民主社会的所有成员都应该被公开确认为具有平等地位的个体。人的尊严作为社会中平等的公共地位,类似于对“拥有权利的权利”的承认(阿伦特,1951;损害,2016;以撒,1996)。它避免对诸如自由权或生命权等具体权利的内容进行理论上的讨论,而是力求确立尊重这些权利的基本条件,无论这些权利是如何定义的。从这个角度来看,尊重尊严是一种元功能,与承认政治共同体的正式成员资格有关,这是尊重更具体权利,包括民主权利所必需的。我们的论点是,尊严是一种社会地位,它依赖于——因此也容易受到——更广泛的公共领域的实践。为了保护这种地位,民主自卫理论需要立足于一个视角,即充实什么构成了对平等尊严的伤害。为了具体说明民主社会公共领域中人类尊严的侵蚀是如何表现出来的,我们援引社会心理学和生物伦理学对言论可能与他人平等公共地位相悖的两种主要方式的区分:非合法化和非人性化。这两个概念描述了一个人的公众地位受到言论质疑或破坏的程度。它们与众所周知的在法律话语中占主导地位的“仇恨言论”有关。然而,我们认为,这里提出的概念为更有层次和细致入微的讨论开辟了空间,讨论哪些类型的言论可能会损害尊严,即使这些言论是在法律允许的范围内。去合法化被定义为从根本上破坏个人作为政治社区合法成员的地位的努力,通过参考他们与特定社会群体的联系,并将深度负面特征归因于该群体的内在特征(参见Bar-Tal, 1989)。因此,非合法化针对的是作为群体成员的个人,而不是作为特定政治立场的代表,其特点是暗中或明确地企图破坏他人作为平等权利持有人和政治影响力平等竞争者的地位。非合法化言论可以被理解为与“人民”的排他性概念密切相关,并与以固定和整体的方式理解人民的利益相关(Ochoa Espejo, 2017;Urbinati, 2019;Wolkenstein, 2019)。它包括否定个人在该特定社区中的平等公共地位的言论。然而,并不是每一个试图使另一个人的平等公共地位不合法的主张都必然是对人类尊严的民主价值的侮辱此外,如上所述,不侵犯个人作为公民的平等公共地位的措施也会损害人的尊严。然而,声称某些公民被排除在道德、政治或法律界之外可能构成对其平等公共地位的攻击,从而为侵犯其民主权利和其他基本权利铺平道路。这一点的民主意义是基于以前文献的一种见解,即在一个政治共同体中得到承认的成员资格是确保享有基本政治权利的先决条件。由于对平等公共地位的攻击有助于剥夺特定公民作为政治团体成员的地位,对尊严的攻击也会损害基本的政治权利。这就是为什么攻击特定群体的公共地位的言论如此阴险,也是为什么它本质上是对民主的关注。非人性化是具有最明显和最深远影响的言论类别,因为它有可能破坏尊重所有公民的人类尊严所必需的平等公共地位。将非法化作为一种政治战略,可能带来严重后果,特别是为侵犯个人的其他基本权利铺平道路。然而,非人化却触及了这种侵权行为的核心。 将他人非人化的言论的共同点是,它试图通过将他们描绘成“动物一样”或缺乏人类特有的特征来将他们排除在人类之外(Haslam, 2006)。因此,它的影响更为深远,因为它不局限于个人参与某一特定社区的合法权利问题,而是致力于破坏个人作为人的整体地位。从历史上看,非人性化的言论被用来确立种族、语言、宗教和其他社会群体成员的劣等地位,是暴力迫害、奴役和种族灭绝的重要组成部分。在美国的背景下,奴隶制的历史遗产为我们的论点提供了例证,在那里,对人类尊严的承认是在将某些群体彻底排除在人类范畴之外的基础上被扣留的。在这种背景下,对人类尊严的深远否定不仅体现在否认奴隶及其后代是政治“人民”的成员,而且体现在否认他们是法庭上的人(Canovan, 2005)。在这里,问题不在于当权者不能将具体的权利概念化,而在于这些权利是在政治背景下产生的,当考虑到与部分人口的关系时,这些权利是无效的。试图破坏他人人格尊严的言论的潜在逻辑,对于将民主价值观如何在民主社会的公共领域面临风险的理论化具有指导意义。最近的心理学实验研究表明,非人化与对目标个人和群体的伤害的宽容态度是如何相关的(Dalsklev &amp;Ronningsdalen Kunst, 2015;马科维茨,Slovic, 2020;参见Over, 2021)。例如,将被低估的少数群体描述为不卫生的,这已被证明会引发厌恶的感觉,从而强化了同样的态度(Dalsklev &amp;Ronningsdalen Kunst, 2015)。在许多情况下,非人化接近于仇恨言论,在许多国家,仇恨言论被认定为刑事犯罪。然而,正如上面的例子所说明的那样,不一定是仇恨言论的言论仍然可以为破坏人类尊严提供微妙的线索。就像明确的反民主立场一样,攻击其他成员的尊严也是一种极端主义,会促使公共领域的民主机构做出回应。一旦尊严被确定为面对反民主挑战时要维护的一种价值,关注的范围就扩大到包括一般公共领域的机构和实践,而不仅仅是选举领域。在这里,困境在于如何维护民主和包容的舆论形成领域,同时保护人类尊严免受非法或非人性化言论的腐蚀影响。为了便于说明,请考虑公共媒体机构、公立学校和社交媒体平台的案例。公共广播机构在政治报道中应坚持包容性代表性的理念。对政治行为者、公共政策和法律进行真实、公正和客观的报道是公共服务在自由民主中发挥的关键作用(Goidel等人,2017;牛顿,2016;诺里斯,2000)。在欧洲尤其如此,国家资助的公共广播组织仍然作为公共领域机构占据重要地位。有充分和令人信服的理由使这些组织尽可能具有包容性和多元化。在这种程度上,公共服务媒体机构应该包括任何形式的政治声音,甚至可以争辩说,那些参与非法言论的行动者。然而,为了保护所有公民的尊严,公共媒体机构有充分的理由采取措施,保护参与者和受众,使他们作为社会平等成员的地位不受攻击。因此,从各方面考虑,最佳政策仍然是不确定的。公共广播机构往往难以将对民主原则的原则性承诺转化为对被认为存在民主问题的言论的辩护回应。尤其是在许多欧洲国家,激烈的辩论一方面围绕着公共广播组织的明显偏见,另一方面围绕着为某些人认为威胁民主的政党提供空间并因此合法化的问题(Hien &amp;诺曼,2023)。公共媒体机构面临的民主自我保护困境是,无论是否压制损害某些人尊严的言论,民主价值都可能受到威胁。类似的情况也适用于公立学校。 许多国家的公立学校经常在选举年组织模拟选举,作为公民教育的一部分,以促进公民对政治的参与。Oskarsson, 2020)。通过对政治意识形态的包容,学校可以成为批判性思维和公共审议的训练场。然而,当激进的政党被邀请时,有可能破坏学生群体的平等价值感和尊严感,再次考虑到这种潜在的危害可能会在这些群体的成员之间不平等地分配。为了让公立学校承担起民主价值观的责任,他们可能需要采取措施,保护学生免受特别恶劣形式的政治言论的侵害。学校的例子很有启发性,因为它清楚地强调了机构的责任,特别是在这种情况下,听众并不是政治社区的正式成员。这里再次出现了民主自我保护的困境:既有包括所有政党代表的民主理由,也有至少排除其中一些政党的民主理由。最近,在某些情况下,例如在斯堪的纳维亚国家,学校通过停止邀请政治代表的做法来解决这个问题。虽然这可能是一种合理的行动方针,但它也是一种明显限制这部分公共领域功能的解决办法。一种撤退策略取代了正面处理与政治辩论中允许言论的限制有关的困难困境。我们在上面提到了社交媒体平台,它们清楚地表明,这种困境并不局限于正式与国家联系在一起的机构。虽然它们是私营公司,但占主导地位的平台已经获得了作为公众辩论场所的突出地位。在某些情况下,被排除在社交媒体平台之外可能比被排除在更传统的公共领域机构(如公共服务媒体)之外产生更深远的影响。在美国,随着前总统唐纳德·特朗普(Donald Trump)在选举后将其排除在这些政纲之外,这一问题达到了顶峰。Facebook、X和YouTube等平台作为当代政治辩论的载体获得了如此突出的地位,这一事实伴随着人们对这些公司在允许的内容方面应该“公正”的期望。由于这些期望,与公共领域制度类似,由于需求冲突而产生困境。一方面,有必要维护开放性、包容性和多元化,而另一方面,有必要确保发布材料的安全性、真实性,并在Facebook的监督委员会章程的情况下,保护个人的尊严(Facebook, 2021)。承认在更广泛的公共领域存在民主自卫的困境,就是要认识到需要一个比在关于民主自卫的辩论中经常出现的情况更加分级和细致入微的观点。当对平等尊严的威胁采取行动或言论的形式,试图使社会中的特定成员失去合法性或非人化时,情况尤其如此。我们考虑两种类型的策略来保护公共领域机构中参与者的人类尊严,使其免于非法化和非人性化:排斥和表达行动。这些策略建立在关于民主自卫的长期讨论的基础上,这些讨论主要集中在国家何时可以合法地采取镇压措施。当将这些考虑转移到公共领域机构时,我们认为有必要讨论这些机构何时应该偏离其作为公共辩论的公正促进者的角色,并利用其表达能力来反击某些言论。排斥包括不同程度地拒绝个人进入机构以及限制内容和各种形式的言论的传播。表达行为指的是一个机构如何沟通内容和言论如何与特定的民主价值观相违背。在这两者中,被排除在公共领域机构之外的问题往往更大。排除被认为是反民主的行动者可能会破坏民主价值观所要求的对他们平等参与公共领域的尊重。在系统层面上,它进一步冒着将反参与和精英主义实践引入公共领域的风险,类似于激进民主传统的批评者所强调的那些(Invernizzi Accetti &amp;Zuckerman, 2017;Malkopoulou,诺曼,2018;诺曼,2021;斯特尔,Popp-Madsen, 2022)。然而,表达行为,无论是公开支持还是公开谴责特定观点,都不是简单的。 它可能对个人产生非常严重的后果,并可能扼杀公开辩论的气氛。在这种背景下,各种类似于民主自卫的经典困境所隐含的策略重新浮出水面,尽管是以一种新的形式。这一困境围绕着公共领域机构满足多元化标准的要求,并促进有利于形成意见的思想的自由交流,同时保护所有个人的尊严。此外,由于个人的观点被公开谴责或被一个机构排斥所带来的潜在成本,出现了这种困境。公共领域机构何时以及在何种程度上有民主理由排除政治代表、私人公民或特定内容?公共领域的机构应该在什么时候以及在多大程度上参与表达行动,积极挑战或抵制那些被认为破坏或攻击其他公民尊严的言论?表达方法类似于Brettschneider(2016)的主张,即国家应该依靠其表达能力,通过阐明支撑民主权利的理由和价值观来谴责“仇恨观点”。然而,正如媒体(包括社交媒体)经常出现的情况一样,民粹主义和极右翼言论不一定符合仇恨言论的标准,即使它直接针对特定群体的公众地位。因此,另一种方法是公共领域机构——学校、公共媒体、大学、博物馆和社交媒体平台——阐明他们致力于民主价值观的更深层次的理由和理由。换句话说,他们应该公开肯定所有人的人类尊严,而不否认任何人参与、发言和被纳入公共领域的民主权利。其基本思想是,对人类尊严的尊重为公共领域的机构提供了强有力的理由,以挑战那些试图使社会成员非法化或非人化的内容。这包括各种可能性,从话语参与到距离,正如越来越多的反言论文献所承认的那样(例如,Fumagalli, 2020)。表达策略也可以通过“标记”被认为是可疑的、不可靠的或与民主价值观相反的内容来实现。标记是社交媒体提供商的一种成熟做法,可以手动执行,也可以通过脚本或自学习算法执行。虽然标记显然是一种软制裁,但有证据表明,它可以有效减缓问题内容的传播(Mena, 2020)。标记在很大程度上是为了应对社交媒体应用上内容的庞大规模而引入的一种措施,通常只包含对平台用户协议的参考。其他机构,如大学或公共广播组织,应提供详细的理由,说明标记和其他回应的理由。表达方法的一个好处是,它与言论自由和结社自由的宽容规范保持一致,这些规范也延伸到反民主的言论和行为者。表达行为是一种给出理由的形式,以公开辩论的价值为前提。与此同时,它也可能在一定程度上抵消那些成为非法化和非人化努力的明确目标的人所承担的往往不平等的负担。因此,表达策略通过提供一定程度的保护,同时也信任个人,即使是那些可能成为破坏人类尊严的目标的人,同时拥有弹性和创造性地参与反策略的机构,从而达到一种平衡。对以广泛多元化为特征的公共领域的承诺要求容忍,因此要求参与者准备接受相当大的不适甚至冒犯。在基本层面上,它依赖于一种民主观点,即相信个人能够承受攻击性言论,并认识到对言论的宽容态度是民主的基础。我们认为,反对非合法化和非人性化的规范可以帮助区分需要制度性回应的言论,以及可能被视为冒犯性、不文明或不尊重但不应引发这种回应的言论。对社会成员尊严的深远威胁有时需要采取排他性措施。排他性策略的问题仍然很多,并且反映了许多可能对压制性反应提出的担忧,例如在传统的激进民主观念中禁止政党。然而,在这里,区分各种形式的排他性做法也很重要,每一种做法都与不同的问题有关,需要以各种方式加以缓解,并权衡其可能的收益。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Democratic self-defense and public sphere institutions

Contemporary concerns with democratic backsliding and contestation of democratic institutions, even in consolidated democracies, have reignited longstanding debates on how democratic societies should respond to perceived anti-democratic threats and what a principled “democratic self-defense” should look like (Kirshner, 2014; Müller, 2016; Malkopoulou & Norman, 2018; cf. Loewenstein, 1937). The core dilemma in these debates concerns the extent to which restrictions on anti-democratic speech, actors, and their associations can be justified in the interest of protecting the integrity of democratic institutions and strengthening democracy's guardrails.

Variations of this dilemma, traditionally concerned with the protection of democratic institutions, have increasingly come to the fore in other arenas of democratic societies. Public sphere institutions such as schools, universities, and public broadcasting organizations, as well as social media platforms have become deeply entangled in discussions on the limits of speech and political action. These institutions are expected, either by convention or legislation, to uphold and reproduce core liberal democratic values while also remaining open to a plurality of views, allowing for the free formation and expression of political ideas. Yet, the existing literature has had less to say about what values should guide decisions to restrict or call out speech deemed to challenge liberal democratic norms in the context of these public sphere institutions.

Our concern in this article is to clearly flesh out what core dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the public sphere consist of and theorize the democratic values at stake in this context. Seeing human dignity as a fundamental value for liberal democracy, we argue, helps us to more precisely identify the character of democratic threats in the public sphere, the various ways in which democratic values may be undermined, and in light of that, how public sphere institutions may respond to these challenges.

Crucially, the assumption that human dignity is a basic democratic value allows us to identify how legally protected speech can still be highly problematic from a democratic perspective. This is important, we argue, as many of the challenges to liberal democracy involve individual-level harms, instances where the human dignity of individual people is undermined. Key to this argument is theorizing the link between attacks on the equal dignity of citizens and attacks on democracy. We tie human dignity as a democratic value to the respect and status afforded to individuals as members of a political community. Paying attention to this link in the context of democracy helps highlight characteristics of speech that have not received sustained attention in current discussions on militant democracy and democratic self-defense.

Our argument emphasizes that some members of democratic society are more at risk than others by virtue of the fact that they already occupy precarious positions in terms of recognition of equal standing. Incorporating this insight should have repercussions for the strategies devised to combat anti-democratic threats at the “micro level” in democracies. This, finally, allows us to think anew regarding the strategies through which the dilemma can be approached by democratic actors. We consider both exclusionary and expressive strategies and discuss how they involve distinct trade-offs and dilemmas.

The article proceeds by first clarifying the theoretical starting point regarding anti-democratic challenges in the public sphere. We contrast our view with prevalent perspectives in democratic theory that have focused on democracy's protection. Next, we outline the significance of human dignity as a democratic value and define key ways in which dignity might be undermined in the public sphere. We illustrate our argument with discussions on dilemmas facing public broadcasting organizations, social media platforms and educational institutions. The final section outlines the menu of strategies available in pushing back anti-democratic threats in the public sphere, including both exclusionary and expressive actions. We present an argument in favor of expressive strategies while highlighting instances where both strategies may be employed, as well as instances where public sphere institutions should remain passive.

Our starting point is that contemporary threats to democracy require greater attention to the dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the public sphere. The public sphere can be defined as the “constellations of communicative spaces in society that permit the circulation of information, ideas and debates” (Dahlgren, 2005). It is composed by formal and informal institutions including schools and universities (Holmwood, 2017), public media institutions (Iosifidis, 2011), museums (Barrett, 2011) and increasingly, social media platforms (cf. Müller, 2019). These are settings of key importance for a functioning democracy where individuals should be able to participate and deliberate about public issues on an equal basis. Our argument does not assume that the public sphere is uniquely concerned with “common interests” (Taylor, 1992), or that it is necessarily “representative” and “inclusive” (Fraser, 1990). Indeed, the public sphere can also provide oxygen for anti-democratic and extremist actors, and its institutions can become vehicles of autocratization (Arato & Cohen, 2021). For these reasons, teachers, journalists, editors, their boards and directors, are forced to make often difficult decisions on where the limits should be drawn regarding which actors and which views should be given room. There are thus good reasons to theorize how public sphere institutions should approach dilemmas related to where and how to draw limits with reference to what is tolerable in a democracy. These are dilemmas that parallel those theorized in the growing literature on democratic self-defense, but they take on a different guise when we consider public sphere institutions (cf. Müller, 2016; Malkopoulou & Kirshner, 2019).

In the wake of increasing digitalization, the rise of social media platforms and the decline of traditional print and broadcast media, there is a strong tendency toward a “breakdown of gatekeeping” (Farrell & Schwartzberg, 2021: 222). This also constitutes a shift whereby nonstate institutions in the public sphere increasingly have to undertake contentious and sometimes highly consequential decisions about the inclusion and exclusion of particular actions and messages, even in cases where they fall well within what is legal (Chambers & Kopstein, 2022). Decisions by some of the leading social media platforms, most notably what was then called Twitter, to suspend the account of then US president, Donald Trump, are illustrative (Twitter, 2021a). The decision to ban Trump from Twitter, or indeed the decision to invite him back on the platform, was not taken by a public authority with reference to the breach of any laws. It was a decision taken by a private corporation with reference to its own policy against the glorification of violence (Twitter, 2021b).

The dilemma of democratic self-defense does not only apply to social media platforms; it is ubiquitous in the public sphere of contemporary democratic societies. Decisions to suspend participants, censor users, or to flag or limit the distribution of content, as well as decisions to not take actions and include democratically questionable views, are regularly made by media outlets, schools, museums, universities and other institutions that provide arenas for public debate. The dilemmas that come to the fore in such settings increasingly permeate the every-day practices of democracy. However, they are clearly distinct from the dilemmas faced by the democratic state in relation to anti-democratic political parties and organizations.

Public sphere institutions are neither judicial nor legislative institutions; they are part of what Rawls termed as the “background culture”. In a free and democratic society, the background culture is the arena for free associational life that should largely remain unregulated by law (Rawls, 1997). The public sphere thus provides ample occasions for the dilemma of democratic self-defense to materialize but where legislation does not, indeed should not, supply clear guidance. It is a dilemma that has less to do with the integrity of electoral institutions and procedures of political democracy and more with the extent to which the members of democratic societies are respected as equals. This comes with implications for how we understand how anti-democratic threats play out in these settings.

For the purposes of our argument, it is particularly important to challenge the assumption that such threats affect all citizens in a democracy equally. Rather, we assume that the burdens of anti-democratic rhetoric and actions are carried to a larger extent by some groups than by others, that they are unequally distributed. The increasing influence of political movements identified as potential threats to democracy, such as political parties with roots in the extreme right, are often theorized to pose an equally serious problem for all democratically minded citizens in a society. We agree that actual authoritarian governments do undermine the dignity of all their citizens in a fundamental sense. However, the belief that all citizens in an otherwise functioning democracy are equally affected by anti-democratic rhetoric obscures the fact that the key mechanism through which authoritarian politics gains traction in a democracy is by targeting often already marginalized groups (Tudor & Slater, 2020). Anti-democratic movements are never “just” anti-democratic in the sense of advocating for authoritarian forms of government. In general, these movements also target particular social, ethnic, linguistic groups in society, framing them in antagonistic terms, as enemies of the people, the state or the party. Anti-democratic movements often exploit pre-existing asymmetries in power and status in society.

In contemporary democracies, anti-democratic movements typically engage in continued rhetorical assaults on the status and rights of, in particular, immigrants, religious communities, women, members of the LBGTQ-community, indigenous peoples and minorities. Frustration, impatience, blame and indeed hatred directed at these groups is a fixture of the authoritarian playbook (Corrales & Kiryk, 2023; Lührmann et al., 2021; Gricius, 2022). Our argument builds on the premise that the primary target for contemporary perceived challengers of democracy, including the plethora of authoritarian populist parties in Europe, is the public status of specific groups and their individual members, rather than the integrity of democratic institutions and procedures as such. This observation does not exclude the possibility that, when in power, these parties would work to erode those institutions. Examples of this from the last decade are readily available in states like Hungary, Poland, and the United States.

However, beyond the most extreme fringe parties, such as neo-Nazis or revolutionary communists, parties marketing themselves in direct opposition to democracy as a form of government are rare. Targeting members of specific societal groups by identifying them as illegitimate or unwanted members of the political community is from this perspective a hallmark of contemporary anti-democratic politics. Anti-democratic movements in a democracy, while they may not attack democratic institutions as such, regularly work to denigrate the equal public status of some groups. This, we argue, is an affront to the human dignity of these individuals and as such in conflict with fundamental values in a democratic society. The type of anti-democratic threats that are our primary concern in this article thus start from the particular rather than the general; from targeted disdain, rather than from competing principles of government. Therefore, recognizing the unequal distribution of costs for assaults on democracy should inform attempts to theorize the dilemma of democratic self-defense. By contrast, public speech in a democracy that promotes anti-democratic forms of government, even if deemed offensive, is arguably less likely to have harmful effects in terms of undermining the dignity of particular citizens. Advocates of, for instance, military or expert rule, while clearly communicating support for anti-democratic principles, need not necessarily target the standing of particular individuals. Furthermore, the fact that we suspect that, given government power, critics of democracy would bring society in an authoritarian direction does not necessarily imply strong reasons for their blanket exclusion from public sphere arenas.

However, the contention that the first casualties of anti-democratic action are more likely to be members of particular groups prompts us to reconsider dominant themes in longstanding discussions on how to defend democracy against anti-democratic challengers. The theoretical tools developed in this literature are dominated by a concern with the preservation of democratic institutions and procedures, including the integrity of elections, basic political rights, and the balance of power between the executive, the legislature, and the judiciary (Abts & Rummens, 2010). These are concerns which we share. Questions concerning to what extent democracies should formally tolerate extremist and anti-democratic actors that rally under anti-democratic political programs or if such political actors should be confronted with repressive measures to protect democratic institutions remain important (Gutmann & Voigt, 2021; Kirshner, 2014; Malkopoulou & Kirshner, 2019; Müller, 2016; Niesen, 2002; Rijpkema, 2018, 2019; Sajo, 2004; cf. Kelsen, 2006; Vinx, 2020). However, the predominant way anti-democratic threats are conceptualized in this literature limits its ability to accurately capture dilemmas and challenges of democratic self-defense in the public sphere.

The shadow of Karl Loewenstein—credited with coining the concept of “militant democracy”—looms large in its basic conceptualization of the dilemma of democratic self-defense (Loewenstein, 1937). It is a perspective ultimately concerned with protecting the integrity of core democratic institutions and its decision-making procedures. The fundamental “Löwensteinian” concern is that democratic procedures are vulnerable and easily exploited for anti-democratic ends. References to the fall of the Weimar Republic are ubiquitous in the academic literature, and increasingly in contemporary public debate, serving as the paradigmatic example of a democratic system that lacked adequate constitutional mechanisms to protect itself against anti-democratic attacks (Abts & Rummens, 2010; Müller, 2016; Kirshner, 2014; Quong, 2004; Rijpkema, 2018; Vinx, 2020).2 Instead, the argument goes, anti-democrats were able to dismantle democracy “from within”.

A core idea is that the inherent openness of democratic institutions makes pre-emptive action permissible and sometimes necessary against political movements that can be suspected of subverting those institutions in the future. As Müller states, “a militant democracy does not wait until its enemies have gained majorities at the poll; it seeks to nip fundamental opposition to democracy in the bud” (Müller, 2016: 250). Although conventionally less pronounced in a US constitutional tradition, it has been prevalent in post-war democratic constitutional debates in many European countries (Bourne, 2018; Fox & Nolte, 1995; Norman, 2022; Suteu, 2021). Theorists of militant democracy are careful to distance themselves from many of the measures defended by Karl Löwenstein (Kirshner, 2014; Müller, 2016), and others have argued that the notion of a militant democracy is inherently tied to elitist and anti-participatory logics (Invernizzi Accetti & Zuckerman, 2017; Malkopoulou & Norman, 2018). It is, moreover, increasingly recognized that contemporary anti-democrats rarely voice explicitly authoritarian or totalitarian political ideals. Rather, the political platforms of authoritarian populists in Europe, the United States, and Latin America, with some clear exceptions, tend to occupy the grey area between democratic and authoritarian politics (Malkopoulou & Moffitt, 2023). The point is that contemporary anti-democratic movements may fall well outside the scope of traditional militant measures such as restrictions on assembly, political organization and party funding that have dominated discussions on militant democracy (Rovira Kaltwasser, 2019). This holds even if we observe how populist parties similar to those emerging in many consolidated democracies are instigating anti-democratic political developments elsewhere, where they may have gained government power. These observations further underpin the need to theorize the principles on which institutions in the public sphere should base their response to speech and agents perceived to challenge democratic values.

The answer, from our perspective, is not to advocate for more intrusive and repressive legal restrictions in the public sphere. Rather, we aim to highlight which values are at stake when public sphere institutions consider limits to public discourse. This leads us to theorize the nature of the threat to democracy in these settings. If, as we argued above, we are not primarily concerned with actions and forms of speech regulated by law, what is the basis for the dilemma and why is it a concern for democratic theory? How is democracy imperiled by systematic rhetorical attacks on the social and political status of particular groups? We propose that a focus on human dignity as a democratic value allows us to cut to the core of anti-democratic rhetoric and action. Indeed, these are values explicitly recognized by many militant democrats, including Loewenstein (1937, p. 658). Democratic institutions and procedures are from this perspective ultimately guarantors of human dignity, and this value should inform the protection of these institutions. Yet, we believe that the predominant focus on democratic institutions and procedures, specifically those related to electoral politics, tends to downplay both individual level and aggregated consequences of speech in the public sphere. For those reasons existing perspectives seem less well-suited to identify and address current anti-democratic challenges. By extending the analysis to public sphere institutions and by invoking the importance of human dignity to democracy, our approach offers the groundwork for a clearer discussion on the dilemmas that arise in efforts to defend democracy against such threats.

There is a dual relationship between the value of human dignity and democratic ideals. On the one hand, human dignity is the background norm—an abstract principle—that is frequently perceived as a justification for democratic rights of participation. On the other, human dignity signifies a particular social status—or social practice—that is arguably instrumental to active participation and the use of democratic rights. We discuss both these aspects of dignity as a vehicle to identify threats to democracy in the public sphere.

As a bedrock for normative claims and a social status worthy of protection, human dignity is bound up with a broader catalogue of liberal rights. Human dignity is typically incorporated as part of this catalogue and appears in written constitutions to differentiate the democratic political order from past authoritarian experiences. Human dignity emerged as the legal principle that provides the foundation for democratic and constitutional orders in post-war Europe (Dupré, 2013). A similar pattern is visible in Latin America after the fall of the juntas and in Eastern Europe after the fall of Communist regimes (Barak, 2015).3

The principle of human dignity provides a justification for democratic institutions. This is, for instance, illustrated by the fact that it figures among the founding values of the Treaty on European Union (Article 2) and that it plays a key role in the 1949 constitution of Germany. It also undergirds important decisions in the jurisprudence of the US Supreme Court that has treated “dignity as a value underlying, or giving meaning to, existing constitutional rights and guarantees” (Goodman, 2005, p. 743; cf. Kahn, 2015; Simon, 2021; Tremper, 1988). Given that human dignity is widely recognized as a key value for democracy it might appear surprising that it has not been given more room in the literature on democratic self-defense.4 To an extent, we believe that this has to do with the concept's pliability in terms of the different meanings to which it is associated in different literatures.

In fact, the relationship between human dignity and democracy remains contested (Baer, 2009; Rosen, 2012; Valentini, 2017; Waldron, 2012). There are conceptions of democracy where conceptions of human dignity play a limited, if any, role. For instance, justifications for democratic procedures as means for competitive but peaceful resolution of political conflict scarcely need appeal to values of equal dignity (Bobbio, 1984; Popper, 1945; Przeworski, 1999; Schumpeter [1943] 2003). This does not mean that such “minimalist” perspectives on democracy would necessarily deny that dignity is an important concern for human beings, only that it does not play into core justifications for democracy as a form of government. From a minimalist democratic perspective, even nondemocratic regimes have often done “very well in securing what most of us believe the democratic method should secure” including human dignity (Schumpeter [1943] 2003, p. 246). A related and common objection to the concept is that human dignity fails to offer any clear normative direction at all (Seglow, 2016). Others argue that human dignity may be more useful in other social and ethical contexts, for instance, as the basis for the protection of bodily integrity, privacy, or the right to life (Beyleveld & Brownsword, 1993).

We think, however, that the idea of human dignity as an important background value for democracy is useful to ground a discussion on democratic self-defense in the public sphere. Though human dignity refers to the inner human worth of individual beings, we shall here treat it as more or less coterminous with equal moral status and the moral claim that this status ought to be recognized by public institutions. Our point here is that a commitment to the principle of human dignity is fundamental not merely for liberals, but also for democrats (cf. Dworkin, 2011).

To further specify the relevance of the principle of human dignity for discussions on democratic self-defense, we highlight two aspects. First, human dignity signifies a social status that is instrumental to democratic participation (Ober, 2012). Human dignity is hence understood to require public recognition of the person as an equal member of society. A person who is publicly recognized as an equal is recognized as a person with human dignity. This overlaps with what is elsewhere termed social equality and rejects “hierarchies of social status” and “stigmatizing differences in status” (Fourie, 2012). The respect required by human dignity is in this sense more demanding than protections of political equality. Arguably, the status of “public equality” is among the great benefits conferred to all members of a democratic society by virtue of their standing as political equals (Christiano, 2009; Gonzalez-Ricoy & Queralt, 2018). The secure enjoyment of the social status associated with recognition of human dignity plays an important role in making available venues for participation. More specifically, related to the functioning of a democratic public sphere, it is a precondition for dialogue in public affairs for all members of the community.

Human dignity is, second, a basic claim about moral status that grounds a wide variety of rights, including rights to democratic participation (Rosen, 2012).5 The claim that all individuals share the same moral status, because of their human dignity, is intimately bound up with the justification of democracy as it allows us to regard the equal enjoyment and exercise of political rights as the full expression of our status as inviolable and dignified human beings (Baer, 2009; Dworkin, 2006). In the context of extremist threat to democracy, we thus believe the most illuminating aspect of dignity is that of a particular public status. This is consistent with the notion that it is a background value that makes democratic politics possible. The core meaning of human dignity is—we take it—that all members of the democratic community should be publicly affirmed as individuals of equal standing.

Human dignity as equal public status in a community is similar to the recognition of “the right to have rights” (Arendt, 1951; Hann, 2016; Isaac, 1996). It avoids theoretical discussions on the contents of specific rights such as the right to freedom or the right to life and instead seeks to establish the fundamental condition for such rights, however they are defined, to be respected. Respect for dignity in this perspective serves a meta-function related to the recognition of full membership in a political community that is necessary for more specific rights to be respected, including democratic ones. Our thesis here is that dignity is a social status that depends on—and is therefore also vulnerable to—practices in the wider public sphere. To protect that status, theories of democratic self-defense need to ground themselves in a perspective that fleshes out what constitutes harms to equal dignity.

To concretize how the erosion of human dignity in the public sphere of democratic societies can manifest itself, we invoke a distinction from social-psychology and bioethics between two main ways in which speech may be contrary to the equal public status of others: delegitimization and dehumanization. These two concepts depict degrees to which the public standing of a person can be questioned or undermined by speech. They are related to the well-known category of “hate speech” that predominates in legal discourse. We believe, however, that the concepts proposed here open up for a more graded and nuanced discussion on which types of speech might work to undermine dignity, even when such speech falls within what is legally permitted.

Delegitimization is defined as efforts to fundamentally undermine an individual's status as legitimate member of a political community by reference to their association with a particular societal group and attributing deeply negative characteristics as intrinsic traits to that group (cf. Bar-Tal, 1989). Delegitimization thus takes aim at individuals as members of groups rather than as representatives of particular political positions and it is characterized by implicit or explicit attempts to undermine the status of others as equal rights-holders and as equal contenders for political influence. Delegitimizing speech can be understood as intimately tied to exclusionary notions of “The People” and associated to understandings of the people's interests in fixed and holistic terms (Ochoa Espejo, 2017; Urbinati, 2019; Wolkenstein, 2019). It includes statements that negate the equal public standing of individuals in that particular community. Yet, not every claim that seeks to delegitimize the equal public status of another person is necessarily an affront to the democratic value of human dignity.6 Moreover, as outlined above, human dignity can also be undermined by measures that do not attack the equal public status of individuals as citizens.

Claims that some citizens be excluded from the moral, political or legal community may nevertheless constitute an attack on their equal public status and as such pave the way for infringements of their democratic rights as well as of other fundamental rights. The democratic significance of this point trades on an insight in the previous literature, which is that recognized membership in a political community is a precondition for secure enjoyment of basic political rights. As assaults on equal public status are instrumental in denying particular citizens their status as members of the political community, assaults on dignity also work to undermine basic political rights generally. This is what makes speech that attacks the public status of particular groups so insidious, and why it is inherently a concern for democracy.

Dehumanization is the category of speech with the most obvious and far-reaching implications in terms its potential to undermine the equal public status that is necessary for respecting the human dignity of all citizens. Delegitimization, deployed as a political strategy, may come with serious consequences, especially in terms of paving the way for the infringement of other fundamental rights of individuals. Dehumanization, however, cuts to the core of such infringements. The common denominator of speech that dehumanizes others is that it seeks to exclude them from membership in humanity by portraying them as “animal-like” or otherwise devoid of the traits that are uniquely human (Haslam, 2006). It is thus more far-reaching in that it does not limit itself to questions of individual's legitimate right to participate in a particular community but works to undermine the status of individuals as human beings altogether. Historically, dehumanizing speech has been deployed to establish the inferiority of members of ethnic, linguistic, religious, and other social groups and has been part and parcel of violent persecution, slavery and genocide. In a US context, the historical legacy of slavery is illustrative for our argument, where recognition of human dignity was withheld on the basis of radical exclusion of certain groups from the category of humanity. The far-reaching denial of human dignity in this context is precisely evidenced not merely by the denial of slaves and their descendants as members of the political “people” but by the denial of them as members of the category of people tout court (Canovan, 2005). Here, again, the problem was not that those in power were unable to conceptualize what particular rights entailed but that those rights emerged in a political context which rendered them null and void when considered in relation to parts of the population.

The underlying logic of speech that seeks to undermine the human dignity of others is instructive to the aim of theorizing how democratic values are at risk in the public sphere of democratic societies. Recent experimental studies in psychology indicate how dehumanization is associated with a permissive attitude toward harm with respect to targeted individuals and groups (Dalsklev & Ronningsdalen Kunst, 2015; Markowitz & Slovic, 2020; cf. Over, 2021). The same attitudes are reinforced by, for instance, the depiction of undervalued minority groups as unhygienic, which has been shown to trigger feelings of disgust (Dalsklev & Ronningsdalen Kunst, 2015). Dehumanization comes close to what would in many cases count as hate speech, which is recognized as an offense by criminal law in many countries. However, as the examples above illustrate, speech that is not necessarily hate speech can still provide subtle cues instrumental for undermining human dignity. Like explicit anti-democratic positions, assaults on the dignity of other members are a form of extremism that prompts a response from democratic institutions also in the public sphere.

Once dignity is identified as a value to be preserved in the face of anti-democratic challenges, the sphere of concern expands to include institutions and practices in the public sphere generally, and not just the electoral arena. Here, the dilemma consists in how to safeguard democratic and inclusive arenas of opinion-formation while at the same time protect human dignity from the corrosive effects of delegitimizing or dehumanizing speech.

For the purpose of illustration, consider the cases of public media institutions, public schools and social media platforms. Public service broadcasting organizations are expected to adhere to ideals of inclusive representation in their coverage of politics. Truthful, impartial and objective reporting on political actors, public policy and law is a key role to be played by the public service in a liberal democracy (Goidel et al, 2017; Newton, 2016; Norris, 2000). This is particularly the case in Europe where state funded public broadcasting organizations still hold important positions as public sphere institutions. There are strong and compelling reasons for these organizations to be as inclusive and pluralistic as possible. To that extent, public service media institutions should include political voices of any kind, even, it could be argued, those of actors engaging in delegitimizing speech. However, in order to protect the dignity of all citizens, there are good reasons for why public media institutions should take measures to protect both participants and audiences from attacks on their status as equal members of society. Thus, the best policy, all things considered, remains uncertain. Public broadcasting organizations often struggle to translate a principled commitment to democratic principles into a defensible response to speech deemed democratically problematic. Heated debates, in many European countries not least, have revolved around perceived biases of public broadcasting organizations on the one hand and, on the other, problems related to providing room for, and thus legitimizing, parties deemed by some to threaten democracy (Hien & Norman, 2023). The dilemma of democratic self-preservation facing public media institutions is that democratic values are potentially threatened whether speech that undermines the dignity of some is suppressed or not.

Similar conditions apply to public schools. Public schools in many countries organize mock elections as part of their civic education, often in election years, to foster citizens’ engagement in politics (Ohrvall & Oskarsson, 2020). By being inclusive with respect to political ideologies, schools can serve as a training ground for critical thinking and public deliberation. However, when radical political parties are invited, there is a risk that they will undermine the sense of equal worth and dignity among groups of students, again considering that such potential harms can be expected to be distributed unequally among the members of such groups. In order for public schools to take responsibility for democratic values they may need to take measures that protect students for particular egregious forms of political speech. The example of schools is instructive precisely because it clearly highlights the responsibility of the institution, especially as the audience in this setting are not fully formed members of the political community. Again, here emerges the dilemma of democratic self-preservation: there are democratic reasons for both including representatives of all political parties and for excluding at least some of them. Recently, in some contexts, for instance, in Scandinavian countries, schools have addressed the problem by discontinuing the practice of inviting political representatives. Although this might be a reasonable course of action it is also a solution that clearly limits the functioning of that part of the public sphere. A strategy of retreat replaces dealing head on with the difficult dilemma relating to the limits of permissible speech in political debate.

We mentioned social media platforms above and they exemplify clearly that this dilemma is not confined to institutions formally tied to the state. Although they are private corporations, dominant platforms have gained a prominent position as arenas for public debate. Exclusion from access to social media platforms may in some cases have more far-reaching consequences than exclusion from more conventional public sphere institutions, such as public service media outlets. In the United States, this came to a head with the post-election exclusion from these platforms by former president Donald Trump. The fact that platforms like Facebook, X, and YouTube have gained such prominent positions as vehicles of contemporary political debate has come with expectations that these companies should be “unbiased” in terms of the contents they allow. Due to these expectations and similar to public sphere institutions, dilemmas arise due to conflicting demands. On the one hand, there is the need to safeguard openness, inclusion, and pluralism, while on the other, there is a requirement to ensure safety, authenticity of published material, and in the case of Facebook's oversight board charter, to protect dignity of individuals (Facebook, 2021).7

To acknowledge the existence of dilemmas of democratic self-defense in the broader public sphere is to appreciate the need for a more graded and nuanced perspective than has often been the case in debates about democratic self-defense. This is particularly true when threats to equal dignity take the form of actions or speech that seek to either delegitimize or dehumanize specific members in society.

We consider two types of strategies for protecting the human dignity of participants in public sphere institutions from delegitimization and dehumanization: exclusion and expressive action. These strategies build on long-standing discussions on democratic self-defense, which have mainly focused on when it is legitimate for the state to respond with repressive measures. When transposing such considerations to public sphere institutions we think it is necessary to also discuss instances when these institutions should deviate from their role as impartial facilitators of public debate and use their expressive capabilities to push back at certain statements. Exclusion includes various degrees of denying individuals access to institutions as well as limiting the distribution of content and various forms of speech. Expressive action refers to how an institution may communicate how content and speech run contrary to specific democratic values. Of the two, exclusion from public sphere institutions tends to be more problematic. Excluding perceived anti-democratic agents risks undermining the respect required by democratic values for their equal participation in the public sphere. On a systemic level, it further risks introducing anti-participatory and elitist practices into the public sphere, similar to those highlighted by critics of the militant democratic tradition (Invernizzi Accetti & Zuckerman, 2017; Malkopoulou & Norman, 2018; Norman, 2021; Stahl & Popp-Madsen, 2022). However, expressive action, whether in the form of public endorsement or public condemnation of particular views, is not uncomplicated. It can have highly significant consequences for individuals and potentially stifle a climate of open debate.

In this context, various strategies analogous to those implied by classical dilemmas of democratic self-defense resurface, albeit in a new form. The dilemma revolves around the requirements for public sphere institutions to meet criteria of pluralism and promote the free exchange of ideas conducive to the formation of opinions, all while protecting the dignity of all individuals. Furthermore, the dilemma arises due to the potential costs incurred by individuals whose views are publicly denounced or excluded by an institution. When and to what extent is there a democratic justification for public sphere institutions to exclude political representatives, private citizens or specific content? When and to what extent should institutions in the public sphere engage in expressive action, by actively challenging or flagging speech that is perceived to undermine or attack the dignity of other citizens?

An expressive approach is analogous to Brettschneider's (2016) claim that the state should rely on its expressive powers to condemn “hateful viewpoints” by articulating the reasons and values that undergird democratic rights. However, as is regularly the case in the media, including social media, populist and far-right rhetoric does not necessarily meet the criteria for hate speech, even when it directly targets the public status of specific groups.

An alternative approach, therefore, is for public sphere institutions—schools, the public media, universities, museums, and social media platforms—to articulate the deeper justifications and reasons for their commitment to democratic values. In other words, they should publicly affirm the human dignity of all without denying anyone the democratic right to participate, speak, and be included in the public sphere. The basic idea is that respect for human dignity provides strong reasons for institutions in the public sphere to challenge content that seeks to delegitimize or dehumanize members of society. This includes a variety of possibilities, from discursive engagement to distancing, as acknowledged in the growing literature on counter-speech (e.g., Fumagalli, 2020). The expressive strategy can also be pursued by means of “flagging” content that is considered suspect, unreliable or contrary to democratic values. Flagging is a well-established practice by social media providers, executed either manually, by scripts or self-learning algorithms. Though flagging is clearly a soft sanction, evidence suggests that it is effective in slowing the spread of problematic content (Mena, 2020). Flagging is a measure that has been introduced, to a great degree, to cope with the sheer scale of content on social media apps and often contains little more than a reference to the platform's user agreement. Other institutions, such as universities or public broadcasting organizations, should be expected to provide elaborate justifications for flagging and other responses.

A benefit of the expressive approach is that it remains consistent with permissive norms of freedom of speech and freedom of association that also extend to anti-democratic rhetoric and actors. Expressive action is a form of reason-giving and is premised on the value of open debate. At the same time, it may also, to a degree, offset the often-unequal burden carried by those who are the explicit targets of efforts to delegitimize and dehumanize. The expressive strategy thus strikes a balance by offering a measure of protection while also trusting individuals, even those who might be targeted by efforts to undermine human dignity, to possess both the resilience and the agency to creatively engage in counterstrategies.

A commitment to a public sphere characterized by wide-ranging pluralism calls for tolerance and, therefore, for participants to be prepared to accept considerable discomfort or even offence. At a fundamental level it relies on a view of democracy that places trust in individuals to withstand offensive speech and to recognize the value of a permissive attitude toward speech as fundamental for democracy. We believe that norms against delegitimization and dehumanization can help distinguish speech that would necessitate an institutional response from speech that might be seen as offensive, uncivil or disrespectful but should not trigger such a response.

Far-reaching threats to the dignity of the members of society sometimes require exclusionary measures. The problems with exclusionary strategies are still numerous and mirror many of the concerns that might be raised against repressive responses, such as party bans in conventional notions of militant democracy. However, here it is also important to differentiate between various forms of exclusionary practices, each of which is associated to different problems that need to be mitigated in various ways and weighed against their possible gains.

Legal bans, such as those directed at anti-democratic parties in some democracies, are obviously beyond the reach for institutions in the public sphere. Yet, these institutions have the power to design their own formal or informal norms that exclude either actors or content in so far as they are consistent with the law. When implementing exclusionary measures aimed at content, private individuals, or organizations, there are well-known risks associated with infringements on the rights of those actors. If public sphere institutions are expected to reproduce norms of inclusiveness, impartiality, and openness and to safeguard individual rights such as freedom of speech, exclusionary practices become problematic. Apart from the democratic harms imposed on individuals there are systemic risks associated with the implementation of exclusionary measures. Chief among these might be that they short-circuit an important component of a vital public sphere, namely a principled level of trust extended to all members of society to process and respond to any viewpoints expressed in that sphere. A public sphere built on the notion of individuals’ inability to do so not only risks stifling public debate. It also comes with problematic implications in terms of infusing the public sphere with a paternalistic logic that goes against the grain of the democratic principle of self-government. Coercive measures, such as banning actors from participation and removing certain kinds of content should then be considered with great care before they are implemented.

To assess if exclusionary measures are justifiable from a democratic perspective, it is useful to think about exclusion in more differentiated terms than is conventionally the case. Here, considering the type of actor targeted by exclusionary measures, such as private individuals or organizations, might lead to different conclusions. To exclude representatives of groups, organizations or parties if they attack or undermine the dignity of other citizens, from spreading information in schools, public places, and social media platforms is not unproblematic. However, targeting actors in their capacity as private citizens, not only as representatives for political organizations, is more serious in terms of the risk of undermining the respect for human dignity of such individuals. As Kirshner (2014) has argued, the political interests and identities of anti-democrats, racists, and extremists are not solely determined by their hostility to democratic institutions and values. As private citizens, they may also have distinct political interests that deserve protection and inclusion in processes of collective will-formation. Blanket exclusions of private citizens from institutions in the public sphere thus represent a greater infringement of democratic norms than exclusions targeting representatives of organizations. Damages incurred by excluding representatives from particular settings also have broader implications as it excludes from discussion the views of a broader set of actors. Yet another aspect that brings nuance to the discussion on exclusionary measures is to consider time-limitations on sanctions rather than open-ended or indefinite ones. Such considerations were part of the stated reasons for the recent reinstatement of Donald Trump's Facebook and Instagram accounts by Meta (Meta, 2023).8

Exclusionary strategies can also be directed toward specific content or forms of speech. Again, militant democrats typically endorse legal bans on speech that attacks democratic institutions or elected representatives. Nazi ideology and propaganda have repeatedly been struck down by the European Court of Human Rights and many European constitutions either permit or require restrictions on “abuses” of freedom of speech that threaten the democratic system (Tsoumidis, 2021). In the context of social media platforms this corresponds to the removal of content rather than “deplatforming”. One problem with the removal of content, often referred to as content moderation, is that the myriad of such decisions that are taken every day by the main social media platforms tend to be nontransparent and provide few means for appeal. Content moderation is thus facing specific challenges of democratic legitimacy. These challenges can be mitigated by expressive actions. The responsibility on the part of public sphere institutions to provide reasons for exclusion and to provide individuals with possibilities for appeal is important. Expressive action is thus a necessary aspect of any effort to implement exclusionary measures. Moreover, exclusionary measures have in themselves an expressive aspect that can be used to signal the limits of publicly acceptable political action to actors beyond those directly targeted.

Like all general principles, decisions on the application of the strategies outlined here need to take into account case-specific circumstances. Of key importance for such decisions is the historical legacy of power asymmetries and domination between different groups in particular societies. Historical legacies shape and give substance to what delegitimization and dehumanization is, and how the dignity of individuals is harmed by them, and must therefore inform the strategy that best serves to protect democratic values. Understanding such legacies will provide insights into the uneven distribution of threats to human dignity. Although the specific resolution of the dilemma we have discussed depends on the context in which it arises, we believe that the general conceptual tools developed here are essential for fully recognizing the stakes involved and for modeling a response that is appropriate for a democratic society.

In this article, we have offered the theoretical underpinnings for democracy's protection in the public sphere by elaborating on the democratic significance of human dignity. This shift in perspective was partially motivated by an empirical assessment of the types of anti-democratic threats facing contemporary democratic societies. Overt anti-democrats and outright extremist political movements still exist and should not be overlooked. However, we perceive a more acute problem among political actors who often remain broadly committed to a minimalist notion of democracy while trading on ideas, increasingly prevalent in the public sphere, which undermine the human dignity of particular societal groups. The analytical shift toward public sphere institutions, we argued, helps us reconsider the theoretical tools that we use to make sense of dilemmas of democracy's protection.

Focusing on human dignity as a fundamental democratic value highlights the unequal costs borne by already marginalized groups due to anti-democratic assaults. We illustrated this argument by discussing ways in which speech and other acts may undermine dignity by delegitimizing and dehumanizing members of particular social groups, undermining their claims to have their rights recognized, or, in the most egregious forms, denying them equal status as members of humanity. The choice between expressive actions or exclusions will always depend, in part, on factors specific to particular cases. However, we believe that the clear specification of a key value that underlie these democratic dilemmas, which we have attempted in this article, provides firmer theoretical grounding for such decisions.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信