对社会不合理现象的理性批判。论法兰克福传统中的批判理论

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Rainer Forst
{"title":"对社会不合理现象的理性批判。论法兰克福传统中的批判理论","authors":"Rainer Forst","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12724","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>By “critical theory” in a general sense, we mean a unity of philosophical reflection and social scientific analysis informed by an interest in emancipation; all critical theories methodologically and normatively aim at uncovering forms of social domination and inquire into the possibilities of overcoming them. Critical theory in the tradition of what has been called the “Frankfurt School,” however, means something more specific: It develops a historically situated and normatively reflexive, systematic <i>rational</i> critique of existing forms of social <i>unreason</i> that are ideologically presented as forms of (individual and social) <i>rationality</i> — “the unreason of the dominant reason” (Adorno, <span>2005</span>/1962, p. 151). It explains why that is the case (that is, it unveils the <i>rationale</i> for such unreason) and it also conceives of a (more) <i>rational</i> form of a social and political order.<sup>1</sup> Specifically, it asks why the existing power relations within (and beyond) a society prevent the emergence of such an order. This is consistent with Horkheimer's (<span>2002</span>/1937, p. 199; tr. amended) original understanding of critical theory as “a theory guided at every turn by a concern for reasonable conditions of life.”</p><p>As the history of this demanding theoretical program demonstrates, it poses a multitude of difficult questions: How should the “interest in emancipation” be defined so that it is truly emancipation that is being sought and not just another desire to dominate? What kind of social theory (one that includes concepts of power and ideology) is available for the negative work of critique as well as for positively identifying potentials for progress? Most importantly: Which conception of reason should be used when what is at issue is both an existing “irrational” (though functionally rational) social and political order as well as the prospect for one that has a more “rational” form?</p><p>It is a characteristic of Frankfurt-type critical theory that, despite its numerous transformations, including the radical critique of reductive, one-sided instrumental rationality in the <i>Dialectic of Enlightenment</i>, it retains Horkheimer's original idea that the notion of reason developed in Kantian and Hegelian idealism had to be systematically connected to a structural-empirical (including psychological) analysis of social forces in order to identify the “rationality” of existing unreason. Social philosophy, Horkheimer (<span>1993b</span>/1931, p. 6) says in his programmatic speech from 1931, when he started the interdisciplinary program at the Institute for Social Research, searches to understand individual and social reality in a non-positivistic way, by seeking to include in its analysis “a higher, autonomous realm of being, or at least a realm of value or normativity in which transitory human beings have a share, but which is itself not reducible to mundane events.” For critical theory this is essential , since it was the idealist tradition that identified theoretical as well as practical reason with the faculty of principled critique and of moral-political autonomy as emancipation. In Horkheimer's words: “overcoming class domination (…) is, to put it abstractly, the materialist content of the idealist concept of reason” (Horkheimer 2002/1937, p.242: tr. amended).</p><p>To be sure, critical theory could not and cannot rely on an “objective” metaphysical theory of reason, as Horkheimer (<span>2004</span>/1947, p. 4) defined it in his <i>Eclipse of Reason</i>: “It aimed at evolving a comprehensive system, or hierarchy, of all beings, including man and his aims.” Therefore, if we want to hold onto the idea of a rational critique of social unreason and the corresponding idea of a (more) reasonable social and political order, and in this sense continue the Frankfurt program, we need to redefine reason in a self-critical, non-reductive as well as non-reifying, intersubjectivist way, that is, as more than mere instrumental or strategic rationality, to use the terms of Habermas' comprehensive effort to update the approach in his <i>Theory of Communicative Action</i>. For Frankfurt critical theory, such reduction was the main problem of modern notions of reason (especially in their capitalist form): they turned everything into a possible object for rational use. “For positivism, which has assumed the judicial office of enlightened reason, to speculate about intelligible worlds is no longer merely forbidden but senseless prattle” (Horkheimer &amp; Adorno, <span>2002</span>/1944, p. 19). Such thinking can no longer transcend the given, taking orientation from principles of reason—which is true of empiricist positivism as well as of any negativistic Nietzschean rejections of such principles. At the same time, given the imperative of self-criticism, charges of a possible cultural bias of such a program need to be taken seriously, radicalizing the search for justifiable grounds for critique.<sup>2</sup></p><p>In my view, the <i>systematic unity</i> of normative reflection and social-scientific analysis which is characteristic of critical theory requires <i>mediating terms</i> between “facts” and “norms,” i.e., between social reality and normative principles—terms that both convey the reality of “rational unreason” and unlock the potentials for social rationality, while exhibiting its basic principles. According to this idea of theoretical unity, the concepts used for the destructive as well as the constructive aspects of critique spring from a common source; the analysis of domination as well as non-domination, of unreason as well as reason, has to be carried out from within one overarching framework. In my own attempts to rethink critical theory, the concept of justification serves that role.<sup>3</sup> I interpret the question of a rational order normatively as the question of a <i>justifiable</i> order and, in the next step, I turn the notion of justification reflexively into a theoretical <i>and</i> a practical one and seek to analyze and find ways to transform existing <i>orders</i> and <i>relations of justification</i> such that those subject to them become their (equal) normative authorities. This approach allows for a <i>twofold</i> analysis of normative orders: First, it treats justifications that legitimize and constitute such orders as social facts for a critical examination of their emergence, stability, and function—i.e., their “rationality”; and, second, it takes a critical stance on these justifications by scrutinizing their rational justifiability (given certain criteria of justification). “Justifications” and corresponding “orders,” therefore, are the object, on the one hand, of a <i>descriptive</i> and critical analysis and, on the other, of <i>normative</i> critique. When we speak of “justifications,” in this twofold way, we are not only thinking of “good justifications” but also of ones which are socially effective as forms of power, even if (and perhaps because) they have an ideological character. <i>Ideology</i> is here defined negatively and quite simply: it justifies what cannot be justified and thus silences doubt and critique. In Adorno's words: “<i>Ideology is justification</i>” (Adorno <span>1979</span>/1954, p.465; tr. R.F.).</p><p>Such an approach requires a de-reification of conventional philosophical definitions of crucial concepts that suppress their practical, political, and emancipatory character. This is where critical and, if you will, “traditional” theories part company. First of all, it requires a reinterpretation of the theories of reason going back to Kant, as, correctly understood, his concept of reason remains the most radical one, identifying the voice of critical reason with the discursive, <i>autonomous</i> voice of all as justificatory equals bound only by principles of reasonable justification and mutual respect.<sup>4</sup> This voice, to be sure, is in reality never heard in purity, but it manifests itself in struggles for and achievements of emancipation. Emancipation means to “become what you are” as much as possible: a normative authority equal to others.</p><p>Reason, understood in this way, is the faculty of finding and being guided by proper reasons or justifications. A critical theory of reason thus analyzes the social causes of the lack of social reasoning through various methods of identifying “unreason” in the public sphere, in political discourses generally, in social structures but also in science as well as everyday communication (Forst, <span>2023</span>).<sup>5</sup> This allows for a distinction between powerful social “rationalities” and forms of reason that unveil these (possibly irrational) rationalities; both notions of rationality are of a discursive nature, but the first is sociological, the second of a normative kind. Both are essential for a practice of ideology critique that identifies those perversions of reason that turn concepts like “democracy” into an authoritarian means to deprive social groups of their basic rights, call self-absorbed arbitrariness and the economic exploitation of others “freedom,” or refer to a compensation for some of the worst forms of structural injustice as “justice,” while leaving these structures intact.</p><p>As Habermas taught us, a theory cannot claim to be “critical” unless it seeks explicit reassurance about its concept of reason.<sup>6</sup> For no matter how much critical theory opposes the “pathologies of reason” in modernity, it nevertheless always subjects, as Axel Honneth (<span>2009</span>, p. 28) emphasizes, claims to “universality—which should, at the same time, be both embodied by and realized through social cooperation—to the standards of rational justification.” There is only one faculty of critique, and it is that of reason (cf. Adorno, <span>2005</span>/1962, p. 158).</p><p>According to the twofold nature of normative orders, the question of justification always arises in concrete contexts and equally points beyond them. One can try to offer the best possible answer to a normative question within the conventional context of established norms and institutions. But one can also place these norms and institutions in question, whether immanently (do they fulfill their purpose?) or radically (is this purpose justifiable at all?). That is why the demand for justification cannot be restricted by appealing to a Hegelian form of <i>Sittlichkeit</i>. Justification practices have a historical apriori but are not determined by it; reason transcends its particular circumstances, though always in a situated way.</p><p>For example, who would want to suggest to critics of capitalist exploitation or of a caste system that they should please proceed in an “immanent” way? Are such practices and systems only unjust on the basis of their “own” principles, assuming there are any at hand that one can use for critique? Similarly, why remind a critic of patriarchy in a given society in which this was hardly ever challenged that she should not speak a “foreign language”? Would that not amount to ostracizing such critics from social discourses?<sup>7</sup> Radical criticism may be immanent <i>or</i> transcending so that it is no longer clear where the one form of criticism ends and the other begins—as, for example, when Luther described the Pope as the “Antichrist,” the Levellers declared the King to be the servant of the people “by the grace of God,” or Marx saw bourgeois society as the locus of modern slavery. Settled ethical life is the <i>object</i> of criticism, not its <i>ground</i> or <i>limit</i>. To recall the words of Adorno (<span>1973</span>/1966, p. 182): “The limit of immanent critique is that the law of the immanent context is ultimately one with the delusion that has to be overcome.” Critical theory knows of no imperative of “immanent” critique, for every such critique would have to provide an <i>independent</i> reason <i>which</i> “immanent” norms are right and <i>how</i> they ought to be interpreted. Recourse to mere historical-social facticity cannot be a rational ground for answering these questions; immanence is no criterion of reason.<sup>9</sup> In a given social situation, progressive as well as regressive values and norms are internal to the social horizon of justification; thus we are in need of other criteria of justification to distinguish the former from the latter. Only the principle of justification itself, as a principle of reason, can generate such criteria—in practical contexts where reciprocally and generally binding norms are at issue, reciprocity and generality are such criteria.</p><p>The perspective outlined enables us to define a conception of <i>progress</i> that cannot be suspected of disguising ethnocentrisms behind this claim.<sup>8</sup> Only those processes can count as progress that break open orders of justification in ways that make new forms of reciprocal and general justification possible, so that those affected <i>themselves</i> can autonomously determine in which direction their society should develop. A critical theory cannot dispense with such a notion of progress. In my <i>Toleration in Conflict</i> (2013), I reconstruct the history of struggles for toleration as a dialectical story: where emancipation was possible, “higher” forms of (reciprocally and generally) justifying toleration were achieved while facing various counter-narratives denying such forms or undermining them by using the language of toleration in a hierarchical, dominating way.</p><p>A broad series of basic concepts must be de-reified or re-politicized in the light of these orientations.</p><p>This is especially true of the concept of <i>justice</i>. The question of justice should not be answered in an apolitical way in terms of a false picture that looks at packages of goods or minimum standards of welfare (Forst, <span>2014a</span>, chap. 1). For these could just as well be conferred on “those in need” by a benevolent dictator or a correctly programmed distribution machine. Rather, political and social justice requires an <i>autonomous</i> collective process of establishing social and political conditions that aim to realize a basic structure of justification. Thus, the question of power, qua social and political power that shapes collective processes, is central to justice. Horkheimer (<span>1993a</span>/1933, p. 40) stresses the reflexivity of the concept: “That is the universal content of the concept of justice; according to this concept, the social inequality prevailing at any given time requires a rational justification. It ceases to be considered as a good, and becomes something that should be overcome.” Obviously, a critical account of justice needs to be of a transnational nature. Given the realities of past colonialism still present in global asymmetries of power, this has always been the case, though it has not always been taken into account (Forst, <span>2020</span>; Ibsen, <span>2023</span>).</p><p>Like the concept of justice, the concept of <i>power</i> also needs to be de-reified and redefined. Power should be understood in processual terms as the ability to determine, or even to close off (or also to open up) the space of reasons for others, whether based on a good argument, an ideological justification, or a threat. Social power does not have its primary “seat” in some material means or in institutions, but instead in the <i>noumenal</i> space of justifications in which struggles over meaning and hegemony take place (Forst, <span>2017a</span>, chaps. 2 and 3). The concept of power is neither positively nor negatively charged; only its modes of exercise, ranging from “empowerment” to domination and oppression, whether interpersonal or structural, must be differentiated and evaluated. Structural social power can be explained only by reconstructing the <i>justification narratives</i> that shape and in part constitute a normative order (and its subjects). Here a genealogy in the Foucauldian sense creates an important normative distance.<sup>10</sup> In this perspective, as suggested above, one can also develop an understanding of ideology that does not operate with problematic constructions of “genuine interests,” but instead proceeds on the basis of a right to justification that is falsely portrayed by ideologies either as non-existent or as already satisfied. The point of this perspective on critique is that <i>both</i> emancipatory and ideological uses of power ought to be analyzed as moves in the space of justifications. This is what the principle of the systematic unity of social and normative theory entails.</p><p>Another essential concept that must be de-reified is that of <i>democracy</i>. Democracy does not designate a fixed institutional model. Rather, it must be understood as a process of public criticism and justification, both within and outside of institutions, in which those who are subjected to rule progressively become the co-authors of their political order. Democracy on this conception is the political form of justice.</p><p>From here, further concepts in need of re-politicization also become accessible. <i>Human rights</i>, for example, are not a means of satisfying the pleas for help of beings in need but are instead rights to be involved in all aspects of the design of the social and political order to which one is subjected. Their core consists of the basic human right to justification and non-domination (Forst, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>The goal of a critical theory is to overcome this false, alienating form of rationality—that is, alienation from social reality (properly understood) and from the possibility of political intervention as a form of collective action. Social alienation consists in not seeing oneself and others as what one truly “is” (yet is not allowed to be): as socially, morally, and politically autonomous subjects of justification or as equal normative authorities within a normative order (Forst, <span>2017b</span>). It may also prevent them from living a “good life,” but that is a different story.</p><p>In this light, other normative terms can be reinterpreted. A critical theory of toleration, for example, as indicated above, unveils those forms of toleration in which dominant groups produce second-class groups who are merely “tolerated”—while toleration between normative equals who differ in their conceptions of the good life is a democratic alternative (Brown &amp; Forst, <span>2014</span>; Forst, <span>2013</span>).</p><p>In my view, then, critical theory must be reconfigured as a critique of relations of justification. This calls, on the one hand, for a critical social scientific analysis of social and political relations of <i>domination</i> that includes cultural and, not least, economic structures and relationships. In this regard, two dimensions of domination must be distinguished: subjugation to unjustifiable norms and institutions, and subjugation to conditions that prevent practices of justification. Such critical analysis must be combined with a discourse-theoretical, genealogical critique of the justifications and justification narratives that confer legitimacy on unjustifiable relations. On the other hand, we must pose the constructive question of how a “basic structure of justification” can be conceived as a requirement of fundamental justice and be realized in social practice—not as an ideal or a model to be imposed on societies, but as a normative order to be developed autonomously.</p><p>Essentially, a theory we call <i>critical</i> ought to be based on the <i>principle of criticism itself</i>. Its medium is reason striving for practices of autonomous justification among equals.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"30 4","pages":"395-400"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-12-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12724","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The rational critique of social unreason. On critical theory in the Frankfurt tradition\",\"authors\":\"Rainer Forst\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12724\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>By “critical theory” in a general sense, we mean a unity of philosophical reflection and social scientific analysis informed by an interest in emancipation; all critical theories methodologically and normatively aim at uncovering forms of social domination and inquire into the possibilities of overcoming them. Critical theory in the tradition of what has been called the “Frankfurt School,” however, means something more specific: It develops a historically situated and normatively reflexive, systematic <i>rational</i> critique of existing forms of social <i>unreason</i> that are ideologically presented as forms of (individual and social) <i>rationality</i> — “the unreason of the dominant reason” (Adorno, <span>2005</span>/1962, p. 151). It explains why that is the case (that is, it unveils the <i>rationale</i> for such unreason) and it also conceives of a (more) <i>rational</i> form of a social and political order.<sup>1</sup> Specifically, it asks why the existing power relations within (and beyond) a society prevent the emergence of such an order. This is consistent with Horkheimer's (<span>2002</span>/1937, p. 199; tr. amended) original understanding of critical theory as “a theory guided at every turn by a concern for reasonable conditions of life.”</p><p>As the history of this demanding theoretical program demonstrates, it poses a multitude of difficult questions: How should the “interest in emancipation” be defined so that it is truly emancipation that is being sought and not just another desire to dominate? What kind of social theory (one that includes concepts of power and ideology) is available for the negative work of critique as well as for positively identifying potentials for progress? Most importantly: Which conception of reason should be used when what is at issue is both an existing “irrational” (though functionally rational) social and political order as well as the prospect for one that has a more “rational” form?</p><p>It is a characteristic of Frankfurt-type critical theory that, despite its numerous transformations, including the radical critique of reductive, one-sided instrumental rationality in the <i>Dialectic of Enlightenment</i>, it retains Horkheimer's original idea that the notion of reason developed in Kantian and Hegelian idealism had to be systematically connected to a structural-empirical (including psychological) analysis of social forces in order to identify the “rationality” of existing unreason. Social philosophy, Horkheimer (<span>1993b</span>/1931, p. 6) says in his programmatic speech from 1931, when he started the interdisciplinary program at the Institute for Social Research, searches to understand individual and social reality in a non-positivistic way, by seeking to include in its analysis “a higher, autonomous realm of being, or at least a realm of value or normativity in which transitory human beings have a share, but which is itself not reducible to mundane events.” For critical theory this is essential , since it was the idealist tradition that identified theoretical as well as practical reason with the faculty of principled critique and of moral-political autonomy as emancipation. In Horkheimer's words: “overcoming class domination (…) is, to put it abstractly, the materialist content of the idealist concept of reason” (Horkheimer 2002/1937, p.242: tr. amended).</p><p>To be sure, critical theory could not and cannot rely on an “objective” metaphysical theory of reason, as Horkheimer (<span>2004</span>/1947, p. 4) defined it in his <i>Eclipse of Reason</i>: “It aimed at evolving a comprehensive system, or hierarchy, of all beings, including man and his aims.” Therefore, if we want to hold onto the idea of a rational critique of social unreason and the corresponding idea of a (more) reasonable social and political order, and in this sense continue the Frankfurt program, we need to redefine reason in a self-critical, non-reductive as well as non-reifying, intersubjectivist way, that is, as more than mere instrumental or strategic rationality, to use the terms of Habermas' comprehensive effort to update the approach in his <i>Theory of Communicative Action</i>. For Frankfurt critical theory, such reduction was the main problem of modern notions of reason (especially in their capitalist form): they turned everything into a possible object for rational use. “For positivism, which has assumed the judicial office of enlightened reason, to speculate about intelligible worlds is no longer merely forbidden but senseless prattle” (Horkheimer &amp; Adorno, <span>2002</span>/1944, p. 19). Such thinking can no longer transcend the given, taking orientation from principles of reason—which is true of empiricist positivism as well as of any negativistic Nietzschean rejections of such principles. At the same time, given the imperative of self-criticism, charges of a possible cultural bias of such a program need to be taken seriously, radicalizing the search for justifiable grounds for critique.<sup>2</sup></p><p>In my view, the <i>systematic unity</i> of normative reflection and social-scientific analysis which is characteristic of critical theory requires <i>mediating terms</i> between “facts” and “norms,” i.e., between social reality and normative principles—terms that both convey the reality of “rational unreason” and unlock the potentials for social rationality, while exhibiting its basic principles. According to this idea of theoretical unity, the concepts used for the destructive as well as the constructive aspects of critique spring from a common source; the analysis of domination as well as non-domination, of unreason as well as reason, has to be carried out from within one overarching framework. In my own attempts to rethink critical theory, the concept of justification serves that role.<sup>3</sup> I interpret the question of a rational order normatively as the question of a <i>justifiable</i> order and, in the next step, I turn the notion of justification reflexively into a theoretical <i>and</i> a practical one and seek to analyze and find ways to transform existing <i>orders</i> and <i>relations of justification</i> such that those subject to them become their (equal) normative authorities. This approach allows for a <i>twofold</i> analysis of normative orders: First, it treats justifications that legitimize and constitute such orders as social facts for a critical examination of their emergence, stability, and function—i.e., their “rationality”; and, second, it takes a critical stance on these justifications by scrutinizing their rational justifiability (given certain criteria of justification). “Justifications” and corresponding “orders,” therefore, are the object, on the one hand, of a <i>descriptive</i> and critical analysis and, on the other, of <i>normative</i> critique. When we speak of “justifications,” in this twofold way, we are not only thinking of “good justifications” but also of ones which are socially effective as forms of power, even if (and perhaps because) they have an ideological character. <i>Ideology</i> is here defined negatively and quite simply: it justifies what cannot be justified and thus silences doubt and critique. In Adorno's words: “<i>Ideology is justification</i>” (Adorno <span>1979</span>/1954, p.465; tr. R.F.).</p><p>Such an approach requires a de-reification of conventional philosophical definitions of crucial concepts that suppress their practical, political, and emancipatory character. This is where critical and, if you will, “traditional” theories part company. First of all, it requires a reinterpretation of the theories of reason going back to Kant, as, correctly understood, his concept of reason remains the most radical one, identifying the voice of critical reason with the discursive, <i>autonomous</i> voice of all as justificatory equals bound only by principles of reasonable justification and mutual respect.<sup>4</sup> This voice, to be sure, is in reality never heard in purity, but it manifests itself in struggles for and achievements of emancipation. Emancipation means to “become what you are” as much as possible: a normative authority equal to others.</p><p>Reason, understood in this way, is the faculty of finding and being guided by proper reasons or justifications. A critical theory of reason thus analyzes the social causes of the lack of social reasoning through various methods of identifying “unreason” in the public sphere, in political discourses generally, in social structures but also in science as well as everyday communication (Forst, <span>2023</span>).<sup>5</sup> This allows for a distinction between powerful social “rationalities” and forms of reason that unveil these (possibly irrational) rationalities; both notions of rationality are of a discursive nature, but the first is sociological, the second of a normative kind. Both are essential for a practice of ideology critique that identifies those perversions of reason that turn concepts like “democracy” into an authoritarian means to deprive social groups of their basic rights, call self-absorbed arbitrariness and the economic exploitation of others “freedom,” or refer to a compensation for some of the worst forms of structural injustice as “justice,” while leaving these structures intact.</p><p>As Habermas taught us, a theory cannot claim to be “critical” unless it seeks explicit reassurance about its concept of reason.<sup>6</sup> For no matter how much critical theory opposes the “pathologies of reason” in modernity, it nevertheless always subjects, as Axel Honneth (<span>2009</span>, p. 28) emphasizes, claims to “universality—which should, at the same time, be both embodied by and realized through social cooperation—to the standards of rational justification.” There is only one faculty of critique, and it is that of reason (cf. Adorno, <span>2005</span>/1962, p. 158).</p><p>According to the twofold nature of normative orders, the question of justification always arises in concrete contexts and equally points beyond them. One can try to offer the best possible answer to a normative question within the conventional context of established norms and institutions. But one can also place these norms and institutions in question, whether immanently (do they fulfill their purpose?) or radically (is this purpose justifiable at all?). That is why the demand for justification cannot be restricted by appealing to a Hegelian form of <i>Sittlichkeit</i>. Justification practices have a historical apriori but are not determined by it; reason transcends its particular circumstances, though always in a situated way.</p><p>For example, who would want to suggest to critics of capitalist exploitation or of a caste system that they should please proceed in an “immanent” way? Are such practices and systems only unjust on the basis of their “own” principles, assuming there are any at hand that one can use for critique? Similarly, why remind a critic of patriarchy in a given society in which this was hardly ever challenged that she should not speak a “foreign language”? Would that not amount to ostracizing such critics from social discourses?<sup>7</sup> Radical criticism may be immanent <i>or</i> transcending so that it is no longer clear where the one form of criticism ends and the other begins—as, for example, when Luther described the Pope as the “Antichrist,” the Levellers declared the King to be the servant of the people “by the grace of God,” or Marx saw bourgeois society as the locus of modern slavery. Settled ethical life is the <i>object</i> of criticism, not its <i>ground</i> or <i>limit</i>. To recall the words of Adorno (<span>1973</span>/1966, p. 182): “The limit of immanent critique is that the law of the immanent context is ultimately one with the delusion that has to be overcome.” Critical theory knows of no imperative of “immanent” critique, for every such critique would have to provide an <i>independent</i> reason <i>which</i> “immanent” norms are right and <i>how</i> they ought to be interpreted. Recourse to mere historical-social facticity cannot be a rational ground for answering these questions; immanence is no criterion of reason.<sup>9</sup> In a given social situation, progressive as well as regressive values and norms are internal to the social horizon of justification; thus we are in need of other criteria of justification to distinguish the former from the latter. Only the principle of justification itself, as a principle of reason, can generate such criteria—in practical contexts where reciprocally and generally binding norms are at issue, reciprocity and generality are such criteria.</p><p>The perspective outlined enables us to define a conception of <i>progress</i> that cannot be suspected of disguising ethnocentrisms behind this claim.<sup>8</sup> Only those processes can count as progress that break open orders of justification in ways that make new forms of reciprocal and general justification possible, so that those affected <i>themselves</i> can autonomously determine in which direction their society should develop. A critical theory cannot dispense with such a notion of progress. In my <i>Toleration in Conflict</i> (2013), I reconstruct the history of struggles for toleration as a dialectical story: where emancipation was possible, “higher” forms of (reciprocally and generally) justifying toleration were achieved while facing various counter-narratives denying such forms or undermining them by using the language of toleration in a hierarchical, dominating way.</p><p>A broad series of basic concepts must be de-reified or re-politicized in the light of these orientations.</p><p>This is especially true of the concept of <i>justice</i>. The question of justice should not be answered in an apolitical way in terms of a false picture that looks at packages of goods or minimum standards of welfare (Forst, <span>2014a</span>, chap. 1). For these could just as well be conferred on “those in need” by a benevolent dictator or a correctly programmed distribution machine. Rather, political and social justice requires an <i>autonomous</i> collective process of establishing social and political conditions that aim to realize a basic structure of justification. Thus, the question of power, qua social and political power that shapes collective processes, is central to justice. Horkheimer (<span>1993a</span>/1933, p. 40) stresses the reflexivity of the concept: “That is the universal content of the concept of justice; according to this concept, the social inequality prevailing at any given time requires a rational justification. It ceases to be considered as a good, and becomes something that should be overcome.” Obviously, a critical account of justice needs to be of a transnational nature. Given the realities of past colonialism still present in global asymmetries of power, this has always been the case, though it has not always been taken into account (Forst, <span>2020</span>; Ibsen, <span>2023</span>).</p><p>Like the concept of justice, the concept of <i>power</i> also needs to be de-reified and redefined. Power should be understood in processual terms as the ability to determine, or even to close off (or also to open up) the space of reasons for others, whether based on a good argument, an ideological justification, or a threat. Social power does not have its primary “seat” in some material means or in institutions, but instead in the <i>noumenal</i> space of justifications in which struggles over meaning and hegemony take place (Forst, <span>2017a</span>, chaps. 2 and 3). The concept of power is neither positively nor negatively charged; only its modes of exercise, ranging from “empowerment” to domination and oppression, whether interpersonal or structural, must be differentiated and evaluated. Structural social power can be explained only by reconstructing the <i>justification narratives</i> that shape and in part constitute a normative order (and its subjects). Here a genealogy in the Foucauldian sense creates an important normative distance.<sup>10</sup> In this perspective, as suggested above, one can also develop an understanding of ideology that does not operate with problematic constructions of “genuine interests,” but instead proceeds on the basis of a right to justification that is falsely portrayed by ideologies either as non-existent or as already satisfied. The point of this perspective on critique is that <i>both</i> emancipatory and ideological uses of power ought to be analyzed as moves in the space of justifications. This is what the principle of the systematic unity of social and normative theory entails.</p><p>Another essential concept that must be de-reified is that of <i>democracy</i>. Democracy does not designate a fixed institutional model. Rather, it must be understood as a process of public criticism and justification, both within and outside of institutions, in which those who are subjected to rule progressively become the co-authors of their political order. Democracy on this conception is the political form of justice.</p><p>From here, further concepts in need of re-politicization also become accessible. <i>Human rights</i>, for example, are not a means of satisfying the pleas for help of beings in need but are instead rights to be involved in all aspects of the design of the social and political order to which one is subjected. Their core consists of the basic human right to justification and non-domination (Forst, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>The goal of a critical theory is to overcome this false, alienating form of rationality—that is, alienation from social reality (properly understood) and from the possibility of political intervention as a form of collective action. Social alienation consists in not seeing oneself and others as what one truly “is” (yet is not allowed to be): as socially, morally, and politically autonomous subjects of justification or as equal normative authorities within a normative order (Forst, <span>2017b</span>). It may also prevent them from living a “good life,” but that is a different story.</p><p>In this light, other normative terms can be reinterpreted. A critical theory of toleration, for example, as indicated above, unveils those forms of toleration in which dominant groups produce second-class groups who are merely “tolerated”—while toleration between normative equals who differ in their conceptions of the good life is a democratic alternative (Brown &amp; Forst, <span>2014</span>; Forst, <span>2013</span>).</p><p>In my view, then, critical theory must be reconfigured as a critique of relations of justification. This calls, on the one hand, for a critical social scientific analysis of social and political relations of <i>domination</i> that includes cultural and, not least, economic structures and relationships. In this regard, two dimensions of domination must be distinguished: subjugation to unjustifiable norms and institutions, and subjugation to conditions that prevent practices of justification. Such critical analysis must be combined with a discourse-theoretical, genealogical critique of the justifications and justification narratives that confer legitimacy on unjustifiable relations. On the other hand, we must pose the constructive question of how a “basic structure of justification” can be conceived as a requirement of fundamental justice and be realized in social practice—not as an ideal or a model to be imposed on societies, but as a normative order to be developed autonomously.</p><p>Essentially, a theory we call <i>critical</i> ought to be based on the <i>principle of criticism itself</i>. Its medium is reason striving for practices of autonomous justification among equals.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"30 4\",\"pages\":\"395-400\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-12-19\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12724\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12724\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12724","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在我看来,规范性反思和社会科学分析的系统统一是批判理论的特征,它需要在“事实”和“规范”之间,即在社会现实和规范性原则之间进行中介——这些术语既传达了“理性的非理性”的现实,又揭示了社会理性的潜力,同时展示了其基本原则。根据这种理论统一性的观念,用于批判的破坏性和建设性方面的概念都有一个共同的来源;对统治和非统治的分析,对非理性和理性的分析,必须在一个总体框架内进行。在我自己重新思考批判理论的尝试中,证明的概念起到了这个作用我在规范上将理性秩序的问题解释为正当秩序的问题,在下一步中,我反身性地将正当化的概念转化为理论和实践的概念,并寻求分析和找到改造现有秩序和正当化关系的方法,使服从它们的人成为它们(平等的)规范权威。这种方法允许对规范秩序进行双重分析:首先,它将使这些秩序合法化并构成这些秩序的理由视为社会事实,以对它们的出现、稳定性和功能进行批判性检查。,他们的“合理性”;其次,它对这些理由采取批判的立场,通过审查它们的理性正当性(给定某些正当性标准)。因此,“证明”和相应的“秩序”,一方面是描述性和批判性分析的对象,另一方面是规范性批判的对象。当我们以这种双重方式谈论“辩护”时,我们不仅考虑到“好的辩护”,而且考虑到那些作为权力形式在社会上有效的辩护,即使(也许是因为)它们具有意识形态特征。在这里,意识形态的定义是消极的,而且相当简单:它为不能被证明的东西辩护,从而使怀疑和批判沉默。用阿多诺的话来说:“意识形态就是辩护”(阿多诺1979/1954,第465页;tr水)。这种方法需要对关键概念的传统哲学定义进行去物化,这些定义压制了它们的实践性、政治性和解放性。这就是批判理论和“传统”理论的不同之处。首先,它需要重新解释追溯到康德的理性理论,因为,正确地理解,他的理性概念仍然是最激进的理性概念,将批判理性的声音与所有人的话语、自主的声音等同起来,这些声音被合理的辩护和相互尊重的原则所约束诚然,这种声音在现实中从来没有纯粹地听到过,但它在争取解放的斗争和成就中表现出来。解放意味着尽可能“成为你自己”:成为与他人平等的规范权威。理性,从这个意义上说,是一种发现并受适当的理由或理由指导的能力。因此,理性批判理论通过在公共领域、一般的政治话语、社会结构以及科学和日常交流中识别“非理性”的各种方法,分析了缺乏社会推理的社会原因(Forst, 2023)这允许区分强大的社会“理性”和揭示这些(可能非理性的)理性的理性形式;理性的两个概念都是话语性质的,但第一个是社会学的,第二个是规范性的。两者对于意识形态批判的实践都是必不可少的,意识形态批判识别那些将“民主”等概念转变为剥夺社会群体基本权利的专制手段的理性曲解,将自私的专断和对他人的经济剥削称为“自由”,或将对某些最恶劣形式的结构性不公正的补偿称为“正义”,同时保持这些结构完好无损。正如哈贝马斯教导我们的那样,一个理论不能声称是“批判的”,除非它寻求对其理性概念的明确保证因为无论批判理论如何反对现代性中的“理性病理学”,正如阿克塞尔·霍尼特(Axel Honneth, 2009,第28页)所强调的那样,它总是将“普遍性——同时,它应该由社会合作体现并通过社会合作实现——置于理性辩护的标准之下。”批判的能力只有一种,那就是理性(参见阿多诺,2005/1962,第158页)。根据规范秩序的两面性,正当性的问题总是出现在具体的情境中,同样也出现在情境之外。人们可以尝试在既定规范和制度的传统背景下为规范性问题提供最好的答案。 社会权力的主要“席位”并不在某些物质手段或制度中,而是在为意义和霸权而斗争的正当性的本体空间中(Forst, 2017a,第7章)。2和3)。权力的概念既不带正电荷,也不带负电荷;只有它的行使模式,从“授权”到统治和压迫,无论是人际关系还是结构,必须加以区分和评估。结构性社会权力只能通过重构塑造并部分构成规范秩序(及其主体)的正当性叙事来解释。在这里,福柯式意义上的家谱创造了一个重要的规范距离从这个角度来看,如上所述,人们也可以发展一种对意识形态的理解,这种意识形态不以有问题的“真正利益”构建为基础,而是以一种被意识形态错误地描绘为不存在或已经满足的正当权利为基础。这种批判观点的要点是,对权力的解放和意识形态的使用都应该作为在辩护空间中的行动来分析。这就是社会理论和规范理论系统统一的原则所要求的。另一个必须去具体化的基本概念是民主。民主并不指定一种固定的制度模式。相反,它必须被理解为一个公共批评和辩护的过程,既存在于制度内部,也存在于制度外部,在这个过程中,那些受统治的人逐渐成为政治秩序的共同作者。在这个概念上,民主是正义的政治形式。从这里开始,需要重新政治化的进一步概念也变得容易理解。例如,人权不是满足有需要的人请求帮助的一种手段,而是参与设计一个人所服从的社会和政治秩序的所有方面的权利。其核心是基本人权的正当性和非支配性(Forst, 2010)。批判理论的目标是克服这种虚假的、异化的理性形式——即与社会现实(正确理解)和作为集体行动形式的政治干预的可能性的异化。社会异化包括不把自己和他人视为一个人真正的“是”(但不允许如此):作为社会、道德和政治上的辩护自主主体,或作为规范秩序中的平等规范权威(Forst, 2017b)。它也可能阻止他们过上“美好的生活”,但这是另一回事。从这个角度来看,其他规范性术语可以被重新解释。例如,如上所述,宽容的批判理论揭示了那些宽容的形式,在这些形式中,主导群体产生了仅仅是“被容忍”的二等群体——而在规范的平等群体之间,他们对美好生活的概念不同,而宽容是一种民主的选择(Brown &amp;弗斯特,2014;弗斯特,2013)。因此,在我看来,批判理论必须被重新配置为对正当性关系的批判。一方面,这要求对统治的社会和政治关系进行批判性的社会科学分析,其中包括文化,尤其是经济结构和关系。在这方面,必须区分统治的两个方面:屈从于不合理的规范和制度,以及屈从于阻止正当行为的条件。这种批判性分析必须与话语理论相结合,对正当性和正当性叙事进行谱系批判,这些正当性和叙事赋予了不正当性关系的合法性。另一方面,我们必须提出一个建设性的问题,即“正当性的基本结构”如何被视为基本正义的要求,并在社会实践中实现——不是作为一种强加于社会的理想或模式,而是作为一种自主发展的规范秩序。从本质上讲,我们称之为批判的理论应该建立在批判原则本身的基础上。它的媒介是理性在平等者之间寻求自主辩护的实践。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The rational critique of social unreason. On critical theory in the Frankfurt tradition

By “critical theory” in a general sense, we mean a unity of philosophical reflection and social scientific analysis informed by an interest in emancipation; all critical theories methodologically and normatively aim at uncovering forms of social domination and inquire into the possibilities of overcoming them. Critical theory in the tradition of what has been called the “Frankfurt School,” however, means something more specific: It develops a historically situated and normatively reflexive, systematic rational critique of existing forms of social unreason that are ideologically presented as forms of (individual and social) rationality — “the unreason of the dominant reason” (Adorno, 2005/1962, p. 151). It explains why that is the case (that is, it unveils the rationale for such unreason) and it also conceives of a (more) rational form of a social and political order.1 Specifically, it asks why the existing power relations within (and beyond) a society prevent the emergence of such an order. This is consistent with Horkheimer's (2002/1937, p. 199; tr. amended) original understanding of critical theory as “a theory guided at every turn by a concern for reasonable conditions of life.”

As the history of this demanding theoretical program demonstrates, it poses a multitude of difficult questions: How should the “interest in emancipation” be defined so that it is truly emancipation that is being sought and not just another desire to dominate? What kind of social theory (one that includes concepts of power and ideology) is available for the negative work of critique as well as for positively identifying potentials for progress? Most importantly: Which conception of reason should be used when what is at issue is both an existing “irrational” (though functionally rational) social and political order as well as the prospect for one that has a more “rational” form?

It is a characteristic of Frankfurt-type critical theory that, despite its numerous transformations, including the radical critique of reductive, one-sided instrumental rationality in the Dialectic of Enlightenment, it retains Horkheimer's original idea that the notion of reason developed in Kantian and Hegelian idealism had to be systematically connected to a structural-empirical (including psychological) analysis of social forces in order to identify the “rationality” of existing unreason. Social philosophy, Horkheimer (1993b/1931, p. 6) says in his programmatic speech from 1931, when he started the interdisciplinary program at the Institute for Social Research, searches to understand individual and social reality in a non-positivistic way, by seeking to include in its analysis “a higher, autonomous realm of being, or at least a realm of value or normativity in which transitory human beings have a share, but which is itself not reducible to mundane events.” For critical theory this is essential , since it was the idealist tradition that identified theoretical as well as practical reason with the faculty of principled critique and of moral-political autonomy as emancipation. In Horkheimer's words: “overcoming class domination (…) is, to put it abstractly, the materialist content of the idealist concept of reason” (Horkheimer 2002/1937, p.242: tr. amended).

To be sure, critical theory could not and cannot rely on an “objective” metaphysical theory of reason, as Horkheimer (2004/1947, p. 4) defined it in his Eclipse of Reason: “It aimed at evolving a comprehensive system, or hierarchy, of all beings, including man and his aims.” Therefore, if we want to hold onto the idea of a rational critique of social unreason and the corresponding idea of a (more) reasonable social and political order, and in this sense continue the Frankfurt program, we need to redefine reason in a self-critical, non-reductive as well as non-reifying, intersubjectivist way, that is, as more than mere instrumental or strategic rationality, to use the terms of Habermas' comprehensive effort to update the approach in his Theory of Communicative Action. For Frankfurt critical theory, such reduction was the main problem of modern notions of reason (especially in their capitalist form): they turned everything into a possible object for rational use. “For positivism, which has assumed the judicial office of enlightened reason, to speculate about intelligible worlds is no longer merely forbidden but senseless prattle” (Horkheimer & Adorno, 2002/1944, p. 19). Such thinking can no longer transcend the given, taking orientation from principles of reason—which is true of empiricist positivism as well as of any negativistic Nietzschean rejections of such principles. At the same time, given the imperative of self-criticism, charges of a possible cultural bias of such a program need to be taken seriously, radicalizing the search for justifiable grounds for critique.2

In my view, the systematic unity of normative reflection and social-scientific analysis which is characteristic of critical theory requires mediating terms between “facts” and “norms,” i.e., between social reality and normative principles—terms that both convey the reality of “rational unreason” and unlock the potentials for social rationality, while exhibiting its basic principles. According to this idea of theoretical unity, the concepts used for the destructive as well as the constructive aspects of critique spring from a common source; the analysis of domination as well as non-domination, of unreason as well as reason, has to be carried out from within one overarching framework. In my own attempts to rethink critical theory, the concept of justification serves that role.3 I interpret the question of a rational order normatively as the question of a justifiable order and, in the next step, I turn the notion of justification reflexively into a theoretical and a practical one and seek to analyze and find ways to transform existing orders and relations of justification such that those subject to them become their (equal) normative authorities. This approach allows for a twofold analysis of normative orders: First, it treats justifications that legitimize and constitute such orders as social facts for a critical examination of their emergence, stability, and function—i.e., their “rationality”; and, second, it takes a critical stance on these justifications by scrutinizing their rational justifiability (given certain criteria of justification). “Justifications” and corresponding “orders,” therefore, are the object, on the one hand, of a descriptive and critical analysis and, on the other, of normative critique. When we speak of “justifications,” in this twofold way, we are not only thinking of “good justifications” but also of ones which are socially effective as forms of power, even if (and perhaps because) they have an ideological character. Ideology is here defined negatively and quite simply: it justifies what cannot be justified and thus silences doubt and critique. In Adorno's words: “Ideology is justification” (Adorno 1979/1954, p.465; tr. R.F.).

Such an approach requires a de-reification of conventional philosophical definitions of crucial concepts that suppress their practical, political, and emancipatory character. This is where critical and, if you will, “traditional” theories part company. First of all, it requires a reinterpretation of the theories of reason going back to Kant, as, correctly understood, his concept of reason remains the most radical one, identifying the voice of critical reason with the discursive, autonomous voice of all as justificatory equals bound only by principles of reasonable justification and mutual respect.4 This voice, to be sure, is in reality never heard in purity, but it manifests itself in struggles for and achievements of emancipation. Emancipation means to “become what you are” as much as possible: a normative authority equal to others.

Reason, understood in this way, is the faculty of finding and being guided by proper reasons or justifications. A critical theory of reason thus analyzes the social causes of the lack of social reasoning through various methods of identifying “unreason” in the public sphere, in political discourses generally, in social structures but also in science as well as everyday communication (Forst, 2023).5 This allows for a distinction between powerful social “rationalities” and forms of reason that unveil these (possibly irrational) rationalities; both notions of rationality are of a discursive nature, but the first is sociological, the second of a normative kind. Both are essential for a practice of ideology critique that identifies those perversions of reason that turn concepts like “democracy” into an authoritarian means to deprive social groups of their basic rights, call self-absorbed arbitrariness and the economic exploitation of others “freedom,” or refer to a compensation for some of the worst forms of structural injustice as “justice,” while leaving these structures intact.

As Habermas taught us, a theory cannot claim to be “critical” unless it seeks explicit reassurance about its concept of reason.6 For no matter how much critical theory opposes the “pathologies of reason” in modernity, it nevertheless always subjects, as Axel Honneth (2009, p. 28) emphasizes, claims to “universality—which should, at the same time, be both embodied by and realized through social cooperation—to the standards of rational justification.” There is only one faculty of critique, and it is that of reason (cf. Adorno, 2005/1962, p. 158).

According to the twofold nature of normative orders, the question of justification always arises in concrete contexts and equally points beyond them. One can try to offer the best possible answer to a normative question within the conventional context of established norms and institutions. But one can also place these norms and institutions in question, whether immanently (do they fulfill their purpose?) or radically (is this purpose justifiable at all?). That is why the demand for justification cannot be restricted by appealing to a Hegelian form of Sittlichkeit. Justification practices have a historical apriori but are not determined by it; reason transcends its particular circumstances, though always in a situated way.

For example, who would want to suggest to critics of capitalist exploitation or of a caste system that they should please proceed in an “immanent” way? Are such practices and systems only unjust on the basis of their “own” principles, assuming there are any at hand that one can use for critique? Similarly, why remind a critic of patriarchy in a given society in which this was hardly ever challenged that she should not speak a “foreign language”? Would that not amount to ostracizing such critics from social discourses?7 Radical criticism may be immanent or transcending so that it is no longer clear where the one form of criticism ends and the other begins—as, for example, when Luther described the Pope as the “Antichrist,” the Levellers declared the King to be the servant of the people “by the grace of God,” or Marx saw bourgeois society as the locus of modern slavery. Settled ethical life is the object of criticism, not its ground or limit. To recall the words of Adorno (1973/1966, p. 182): “The limit of immanent critique is that the law of the immanent context is ultimately one with the delusion that has to be overcome.” Critical theory knows of no imperative of “immanent” critique, for every such critique would have to provide an independent reason which “immanent” norms are right and how they ought to be interpreted. Recourse to mere historical-social facticity cannot be a rational ground for answering these questions; immanence is no criterion of reason.9 In a given social situation, progressive as well as regressive values and norms are internal to the social horizon of justification; thus we are in need of other criteria of justification to distinguish the former from the latter. Only the principle of justification itself, as a principle of reason, can generate such criteria—in practical contexts where reciprocally and generally binding norms are at issue, reciprocity and generality are such criteria.

The perspective outlined enables us to define a conception of progress that cannot be suspected of disguising ethnocentrisms behind this claim.8 Only those processes can count as progress that break open orders of justification in ways that make new forms of reciprocal and general justification possible, so that those affected themselves can autonomously determine in which direction their society should develop. A critical theory cannot dispense with such a notion of progress. In my Toleration in Conflict (2013), I reconstruct the history of struggles for toleration as a dialectical story: where emancipation was possible, “higher” forms of (reciprocally and generally) justifying toleration were achieved while facing various counter-narratives denying such forms or undermining them by using the language of toleration in a hierarchical, dominating way.

A broad series of basic concepts must be de-reified or re-politicized in the light of these orientations.

This is especially true of the concept of justice. The question of justice should not be answered in an apolitical way in terms of a false picture that looks at packages of goods or minimum standards of welfare (Forst, 2014a, chap. 1). For these could just as well be conferred on “those in need” by a benevolent dictator or a correctly programmed distribution machine. Rather, political and social justice requires an autonomous collective process of establishing social and political conditions that aim to realize a basic structure of justification. Thus, the question of power, qua social and political power that shapes collective processes, is central to justice. Horkheimer (1993a/1933, p. 40) stresses the reflexivity of the concept: “That is the universal content of the concept of justice; according to this concept, the social inequality prevailing at any given time requires a rational justification. It ceases to be considered as a good, and becomes something that should be overcome.” Obviously, a critical account of justice needs to be of a transnational nature. Given the realities of past colonialism still present in global asymmetries of power, this has always been the case, though it has not always been taken into account (Forst, 2020; Ibsen, 2023).

Like the concept of justice, the concept of power also needs to be de-reified and redefined. Power should be understood in processual terms as the ability to determine, or even to close off (or also to open up) the space of reasons for others, whether based on a good argument, an ideological justification, or a threat. Social power does not have its primary “seat” in some material means or in institutions, but instead in the noumenal space of justifications in which struggles over meaning and hegemony take place (Forst, 2017a, chaps. 2 and 3). The concept of power is neither positively nor negatively charged; only its modes of exercise, ranging from “empowerment” to domination and oppression, whether interpersonal or structural, must be differentiated and evaluated. Structural social power can be explained only by reconstructing the justification narratives that shape and in part constitute a normative order (and its subjects). Here a genealogy in the Foucauldian sense creates an important normative distance.10 In this perspective, as suggested above, one can also develop an understanding of ideology that does not operate with problematic constructions of “genuine interests,” but instead proceeds on the basis of a right to justification that is falsely portrayed by ideologies either as non-existent or as already satisfied. The point of this perspective on critique is that both emancipatory and ideological uses of power ought to be analyzed as moves in the space of justifications. This is what the principle of the systematic unity of social and normative theory entails.

Another essential concept that must be de-reified is that of democracy. Democracy does not designate a fixed institutional model. Rather, it must be understood as a process of public criticism and justification, both within and outside of institutions, in which those who are subjected to rule progressively become the co-authors of their political order. Democracy on this conception is the political form of justice.

From here, further concepts in need of re-politicization also become accessible. Human rights, for example, are not a means of satisfying the pleas for help of beings in need but are instead rights to be involved in all aspects of the design of the social and political order to which one is subjected. Their core consists of the basic human right to justification and non-domination (Forst, 2010).

The goal of a critical theory is to overcome this false, alienating form of rationality—that is, alienation from social reality (properly understood) and from the possibility of political intervention as a form of collective action. Social alienation consists in not seeing oneself and others as what one truly “is” (yet is not allowed to be): as socially, morally, and politically autonomous subjects of justification or as equal normative authorities within a normative order (Forst, 2017b). It may also prevent them from living a “good life,” but that is a different story.

In this light, other normative terms can be reinterpreted. A critical theory of toleration, for example, as indicated above, unveils those forms of toleration in which dominant groups produce second-class groups who are merely “tolerated”—while toleration between normative equals who differ in their conceptions of the good life is a democratic alternative (Brown & Forst, 2014; Forst, 2013).

In my view, then, critical theory must be reconfigured as a critique of relations of justification. This calls, on the one hand, for a critical social scientific analysis of social and political relations of domination that includes cultural and, not least, economic structures and relationships. In this regard, two dimensions of domination must be distinguished: subjugation to unjustifiable norms and institutions, and subjugation to conditions that prevent practices of justification. Such critical analysis must be combined with a discourse-theoretical, genealogical critique of the justifications and justification narratives that confer legitimacy on unjustifiable relations. On the other hand, we must pose the constructive question of how a “basic structure of justification” can be conceived as a requirement of fundamental justice and be realized in social practice—not as an ideal or a model to be imposed on societies, but as a normative order to be developed autonomously.

Essentially, a theory we call critical ought to be based on the principle of criticism itself. Its medium is reason striving for practices of autonomous justification among equals.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信