作为批判理论的社会理论:霍克海默的纲领及其在当今的现实意义

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Maeve Cooke
{"title":"作为批判理论的社会理论:霍克海默的纲领及其在当今的现实意义","authors":"Maeve Cooke","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12722","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>More than 90 years later, it is fascinating and encouraging to read Horkheimer's inaugural address as the second director of the Institute for Social Research. Social philosophy, as depicted in his lecture, had not yet found its specific articulation as critical theory. However, in setting out the Institute's tasks as a center for social philosophy, the key components of his emerging idea of critical theory are already visible. These will be elaborated in his programmatic essay on traditional and critical theory, which appeared in 1937 (Horkheimer, <span>1973</span>). The fundamental elements of the early Horkheimer's view of social philosophy/critical theory seem to me as pertinent as ever. This is how I understand them:</p><p>First, social philosophy's aim is to interpret philosophically “the fate of humans” (Horkheimer, <span>1988</span>, p. 20).<sup>1</sup> It must do so within a framework in which the individual and social whole exist in a dynamic relationship of mutual self-constitution (p. 20), which is in turn part of a dynamic interplay between fact and value or, as he writes, “mind” and “reality” (p. 32). We can infer from this that “the fate of humans” has a material basis and is socially produced. This calls for attentiveness to the actual facts of existing social reality. However, social philosophy must not lose sight of “the great principal questions”—questions about the relationship of the individual to society, the meaning of culture, the formation of communities, and the development of history as a whole (p. 28). In the same vein, though it must start from the concrete pressing philosophical questions of the times, it must endeavor always to keep the universal in view (p. 29).</p><p>Second, social philosophy's interpretative efforts must be based on collective inquiry in multiple areas that has an empirical component. Accordingly, it must organize investigations in which philosophers, sociologists, economists, historians, and psychologists work together with the aid of the most precise scientific methods, revising the concrete philosophical questions driving its interpretative efforts and rendering them more exact; it must also develop new methods in the course of such work. Social philosophical questions thereby become part of a dialectical movement, in which they are drawn into the empirical scientific process, which affects their character (p. 30); presumably they in turn impact the empirical process of inquiry. While Horkheimer does not say so explicitly in his lecture, his 1937 essay criticizes theories that hypostatize the facts, treating them as extrinsic to the human mind. He contrasts such hypostatization with critical theory's view that facts are “products which in principle should be under human control” (Horkheimer, <span>1973</span>, p. 209). In this way, “objective realities” lose the character of “pure factuality” (p. 209). In other words, critical theory recognizes the importance of a fact-driven, empirically based inquiry, provided it is conducted within a context of critical engagement with questions of meaning and value and motivated by a concrete practical concern to bring about social change for the better. It seems clear, therefore, that for Horkheimer mind in the form of social philosophy impacts reality as investigated by the empirically based sciences, just as reality impacts mind. In other words, there is a feedback loop between critical theory and scientific findings.</p><p>Third, social philosophy is concerned with knowing the true value and content of the meaning of human existence. Horkheimer attributes this view of social philosophy to Hegel and describes it as problematic (p. 21). However, to all appearances he distances himself only from Hegel's idealist view that such knowledge is solely a matter of philosophical insight and that it can be established once and for all, thereby closing the dialectical process. There is no indication that he rejects Hegel's commitment to determining the value and content of human existence as it takes shape in historical reality and some hints that he endorses it. Indeed, providing we leave aside his objections to Hegel's idealism and closure of the dialectic, his citation of him fits well with his opening remarks on social philosophy's concern to interpret the fate of humans within a value-imbued social context. His citation of Hegel could also be said to anticipate his 1937 essay, where he tells us that critical theory “constructs a developing picture of society as a whole, an existential judgment with a historical dimension” (Horkheimer, <span>1973</span>, p. 239; see Cooke, <span>2023</span>).</p><p>In Horkheimer's inaugural address, the second of the three elements is foregrounded. He criticizes abstract theorizing, be it Spinozist, Hegelian, or Marxian, for splitting off mind and reality (p. 32) and underscores the need for social theory to remain in constant connection with its material: It must develop its philosophical questions through “work on the object” (p. 28), according to the matter at hand as opposed to its own wishes. This calls on it to develop the most varied methods of investigation (p. 33). If it does not, it runs the risk of losing sight of the first core element; in addition, it is also likely to sink into dogmatic rigidity, advancing theses that are fundamentally immune from external control (pp. 32–33). In his 1937 essay, Horkheimer expands on this point, observing that social philosophy (now called critical theory) can avoid dogmatic rigidity only if it is based on a concern for social transformation that arises ever anew from the prevailing social injustice. Importantly, the concrete concern for social transformation must manifest itself in theoretically informed political action (<i>praxis</i>).<sup>2</sup> Whereas in this essay, Horkheimer seems in the first instance to have the enlightening powers of critical theory in mind, in his 1931 lecture, his emphasis is on the scientific evidence provided by traditional theory, especially empirical-based scientific inquiry in multiple disciplines. There is no suggestion, however, that he sees any conflict between the two.</p><p>In the 1937 essay, more clearly than in the 1931 lecture, Horkheimer draws attention to the mutual learning involved in the interactions between mind (in the sense of critical theory) and reality (in the double sense of empirically based scientific research and <i>praxis</i>). On the one hand, critical theory, due to its concrete concern for social transformation, must be ready to modify its values, and accordingly its substantive content, in response to the prevailing injustice; here, the theory must learn from scientific findings about social reality. On the other hand, the values and substantive content of critical theory must shape and guide its empirically informed, practical efforts to overcome the prevailing injustice through concrete transformative proposals; <i>praxis</i> cannot rely solely on scientific evidence but must also learn from the value-driven insights of critical theory.</p><p>In the 1930s, in sum, Horkheimer's idea of critical theory, and of the tasks of a research institute that would foster such theorizing, displays a concrete concern for social transformation in response to the pressing philosophical problems of the time. In its attentiveness to social reality, it loses sight neither of more general questions of meaning and value nor of its task of interpreting the (materially based, socially produced) fate of humans, while maintaining a dynamic relationship between mind and reality.</p><p>I will leave open the question of whether critical theory as it subsequently developed in the Frankfurt School tradition has succeeded in realizing the early Horkheimer's program. My question in the following is what it implies for contemporary critical theory. To focus my discussion, I consider some challenges arising from anthropogenic ecological devastation on a global scale.<sup>3</sup> Of the many concrete and pressing philosophical questions that confront critical theories today, the meaning and value of human life in the context of global anthropogenic ecological destruction is indisputably one of them.</p><p>In addressing this question, Horkheimer's call for a dynamic relationship between fact and value, mind and reality, is highly relevant. The importance of the reality side is obvious. It is immediately evident that the scale of ecological devastation, together with the rapidity at which it has happened and continues to happen, means that any attempt philosophically to interpret its implications must go together with multiple strands of empirical investigation. It must incorporate “work on the object,” preferably cooperative work, conducted in the areas mentioned by Horkheimer: sociology, economics, history, and psychology. We can add to this list just about all other disciplines in the human sciences, for example, ethnography, science and technology studies, archaeology and geography, and the entire palette of research areas in the natural sciences. Furthermore, the urgent imperative to halt ecological devastation, and where possible, to remedy its worst effects, calls for <i>praxis</i>: theoretically guided social transformation aimed at bringing about change for the better.</p><p>But the mind side of the relationship is just as relevant. One reason for this is the contemporary “post-truth” culture, which undermines truth claims made by the empirical sciences, with knock-on effects for the validity claims of any philosophical or social theory. Widespread feelings of disorientation are a consequence of this. Disorientation leads easily to apathy when it comes to possibilities for socially transformative action. Critical theory's tasks of orientation and guidance acquire special importance in such circumstances. Although Horkheimer does not include these tasks explicitly in his account of social philosophy, they are implicit in the interpretative aim he attributes to it: its concern to interpret the (materially based, socially produced) “fate of humans” from the point of view of the “true value and content of human existence.” A danger here, however, is that social philosophy's concern to orient and guide may be authoritarian. Clearly, this is a problem for critical theory in the Marxist tradition, which connects human emancipation with the free development of individuals in association with others (Marx &amp; Engels, <span>1848</span>). Accordingly, critical theory's orientation and guidance should foster such development, which means, at a minimum, that it must always be open to critical questioning by those it addresses and, in this sense, non-authoritarian (Cooke, <span>2005</span>). In his political writings of the late 1960s, Theodor W. Adorno, Horkheimer's collaborator and colleague at the Institute, draws a link between (what I call) an authoritarian conception of theory and a kind of political activism he calls “actionism” (Adorno, <span>2005</span>). In my reading of Adorno, he acknowledges that actionists may initially be theoretically motivated. However, due to a fixation on action, they subsequently leave to one side the question of the theory's validity, deeming it irrelevant to the fundamental social transformation the objective facts of the situation demand. This leaves no room for critical interrogation of the theory's analyses of what is wrong with existing social and political reality and of its (usually tacit) projections of a better alternative. Adorno offers a trenchant critique of this action-fixation (see Cooke, <span>2020b</span>, pp. 585–591). As he describes it, actionism serves to distract from the only kind of genuinely transformative <i>praxis</i> possible in the social conditions of the time, which is resistance to the power of the totality in the form of unrelenting, unsparing self-reflection, coupled with reflection based on a theoretically guided interpretation of the causes of the current catastrophe. Actionism works against the required transformation, since it generates the false belief that resistance of this kind is not necessary; it thereby not only serves the power of the oppressive totality but also strengthens it. This is why, in my terms, critical theory today must offer authoritative, yet non-authoritarian diagnoses of social reality and utopian projections of better alternatives.<sup>4</sup> By this I mean that its guidance and orientation must be authoritative in the sense of having the power to move the hearts and minds of its addressees, giving them reason to feel that it is “advice that they may not safely ignore” (Mommsen, <span>1888</span>, cited in Arendt, <span>1977</span>)<sup>5</sup>; yet, at the same time, it must be non-authoritarian by acknowledging its own inherent contestability and opening its prescriptions and recommendations to critical challenge by everyone affected by them (Cooke, <span>2020c</span>).</p><p>Human-induced ecological devastation on a global scale poses many other difficulties for contemporary critical theory. A particular challenge is how to reconcile the need for ecological sustainability with critical theory's projections of an emancipated social condition, since it is hard to imagine how an emancipatory aim such as the free development of each individual could be achieved without a significant material impact on the earth's ecosystems. However, here too Horkheimer's programmatic writings from the 1930s, with their emphasis on the dynamic interplay between mind and reality, between the material and spiritual dimensions of human life, seem to me a fruitful starting point. They remind us that the concrete material impact of humans on earth is not a given but something that demands ongoing critical attention through reference to scientific findings, while keeping in view the importance of achieving a good life on this planet for each human individual within a corresponding good society.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"30 4","pages":"384-389"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-12-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12722","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Social theory as critical theory: Horkheimer's program and its relevance today\",\"authors\":\"Maeve Cooke\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12722\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>More than 90 years later, it is fascinating and encouraging to read Horkheimer's inaugural address as the second director of the Institute for Social Research. Social philosophy, as depicted in his lecture, had not yet found its specific articulation as critical theory. However, in setting out the Institute's tasks as a center for social philosophy, the key components of his emerging idea of critical theory are already visible. These will be elaborated in his programmatic essay on traditional and critical theory, which appeared in 1937 (Horkheimer, <span>1973</span>). The fundamental elements of the early Horkheimer's view of social philosophy/critical theory seem to me as pertinent as ever. This is how I understand them:</p><p>First, social philosophy's aim is to interpret philosophically “the fate of humans” (Horkheimer, <span>1988</span>, p. 20).<sup>1</sup> It must do so within a framework in which the individual and social whole exist in a dynamic relationship of mutual self-constitution (p. 20), which is in turn part of a dynamic interplay between fact and value or, as he writes, “mind” and “reality” (p. 32). We can infer from this that “the fate of humans” has a material basis and is socially produced. This calls for attentiveness to the actual facts of existing social reality. However, social philosophy must not lose sight of “the great principal questions”—questions about the relationship of the individual to society, the meaning of culture, the formation of communities, and the development of history as a whole (p. 28). In the same vein, though it must start from the concrete pressing philosophical questions of the times, it must endeavor always to keep the universal in view (p. 29).</p><p>Second, social philosophy's interpretative efforts must be based on collective inquiry in multiple areas that has an empirical component. Accordingly, it must organize investigations in which philosophers, sociologists, economists, historians, and psychologists work together with the aid of the most precise scientific methods, revising the concrete philosophical questions driving its interpretative efforts and rendering them more exact; it must also develop new methods in the course of such work. Social philosophical questions thereby become part of a dialectical movement, in which they are drawn into the empirical scientific process, which affects their character (p. 30); presumably they in turn impact the empirical process of inquiry. While Horkheimer does not say so explicitly in his lecture, his 1937 essay criticizes theories that hypostatize the facts, treating them as extrinsic to the human mind. He contrasts such hypostatization with critical theory's view that facts are “products which in principle should be under human control” (Horkheimer, <span>1973</span>, p. 209). In this way, “objective realities” lose the character of “pure factuality” (p. 209). In other words, critical theory recognizes the importance of a fact-driven, empirically based inquiry, provided it is conducted within a context of critical engagement with questions of meaning and value and motivated by a concrete practical concern to bring about social change for the better. It seems clear, therefore, that for Horkheimer mind in the form of social philosophy impacts reality as investigated by the empirically based sciences, just as reality impacts mind. In other words, there is a feedback loop between critical theory and scientific findings.</p><p>Third, social philosophy is concerned with knowing the true value and content of the meaning of human existence. Horkheimer attributes this view of social philosophy to Hegel and describes it as problematic (p. 21). However, to all appearances he distances himself only from Hegel's idealist view that such knowledge is solely a matter of philosophical insight and that it can be established once and for all, thereby closing the dialectical process. There is no indication that he rejects Hegel's commitment to determining the value and content of human existence as it takes shape in historical reality and some hints that he endorses it. Indeed, providing we leave aside his objections to Hegel's idealism and closure of the dialectic, his citation of him fits well with his opening remarks on social philosophy's concern to interpret the fate of humans within a value-imbued social context. His citation of Hegel could also be said to anticipate his 1937 essay, where he tells us that critical theory “constructs a developing picture of society as a whole, an existential judgment with a historical dimension” (Horkheimer, <span>1973</span>, p. 239; see Cooke, <span>2023</span>).</p><p>In Horkheimer's inaugural address, the second of the three elements is foregrounded. He criticizes abstract theorizing, be it Spinozist, Hegelian, or Marxian, for splitting off mind and reality (p. 32) and underscores the need for social theory to remain in constant connection with its material: It must develop its philosophical questions through “work on the object” (p. 28), according to the matter at hand as opposed to its own wishes. This calls on it to develop the most varied methods of investigation (p. 33). If it does not, it runs the risk of losing sight of the first core element; in addition, it is also likely to sink into dogmatic rigidity, advancing theses that are fundamentally immune from external control (pp. 32–33). In his 1937 essay, Horkheimer expands on this point, observing that social philosophy (now called critical theory) can avoid dogmatic rigidity only if it is based on a concern for social transformation that arises ever anew from the prevailing social injustice. Importantly, the concrete concern for social transformation must manifest itself in theoretically informed political action (<i>praxis</i>).<sup>2</sup> Whereas in this essay, Horkheimer seems in the first instance to have the enlightening powers of critical theory in mind, in his 1931 lecture, his emphasis is on the scientific evidence provided by traditional theory, especially empirical-based scientific inquiry in multiple disciplines. There is no suggestion, however, that he sees any conflict between the two.</p><p>In the 1937 essay, more clearly than in the 1931 lecture, Horkheimer draws attention to the mutual learning involved in the interactions between mind (in the sense of critical theory) and reality (in the double sense of empirically based scientific research and <i>praxis</i>). On the one hand, critical theory, due to its concrete concern for social transformation, must be ready to modify its values, and accordingly its substantive content, in response to the prevailing injustice; here, the theory must learn from scientific findings about social reality. On the other hand, the values and substantive content of critical theory must shape and guide its empirically informed, practical efforts to overcome the prevailing injustice through concrete transformative proposals; <i>praxis</i> cannot rely solely on scientific evidence but must also learn from the value-driven insights of critical theory.</p><p>In the 1930s, in sum, Horkheimer's idea of critical theory, and of the tasks of a research institute that would foster such theorizing, displays a concrete concern for social transformation in response to the pressing philosophical problems of the time. In its attentiveness to social reality, it loses sight neither of more general questions of meaning and value nor of its task of interpreting the (materially based, socially produced) fate of humans, while maintaining a dynamic relationship between mind and reality.</p><p>I will leave open the question of whether critical theory as it subsequently developed in the Frankfurt School tradition has succeeded in realizing the early Horkheimer's program. My question in the following is what it implies for contemporary critical theory. To focus my discussion, I consider some challenges arising from anthropogenic ecological devastation on a global scale.<sup>3</sup> Of the many concrete and pressing philosophical questions that confront critical theories today, the meaning and value of human life in the context of global anthropogenic ecological destruction is indisputably one of them.</p><p>In addressing this question, Horkheimer's call for a dynamic relationship between fact and value, mind and reality, is highly relevant. The importance of the reality side is obvious. It is immediately evident that the scale of ecological devastation, together with the rapidity at which it has happened and continues to happen, means that any attempt philosophically to interpret its implications must go together with multiple strands of empirical investigation. It must incorporate “work on the object,” preferably cooperative work, conducted in the areas mentioned by Horkheimer: sociology, economics, history, and psychology. We can add to this list just about all other disciplines in the human sciences, for example, ethnography, science and technology studies, archaeology and geography, and the entire palette of research areas in the natural sciences. Furthermore, the urgent imperative to halt ecological devastation, and where possible, to remedy its worst effects, calls for <i>praxis</i>: theoretically guided social transformation aimed at bringing about change for the better.</p><p>But the mind side of the relationship is just as relevant. One reason for this is the contemporary “post-truth” culture, which undermines truth claims made by the empirical sciences, with knock-on effects for the validity claims of any philosophical or social theory. Widespread feelings of disorientation are a consequence of this. Disorientation leads easily to apathy when it comes to possibilities for socially transformative action. Critical theory's tasks of orientation and guidance acquire special importance in such circumstances. Although Horkheimer does not include these tasks explicitly in his account of social philosophy, they are implicit in the interpretative aim he attributes to it: its concern to interpret the (materially based, socially produced) “fate of humans” from the point of view of the “true value and content of human existence.” A danger here, however, is that social philosophy's concern to orient and guide may be authoritarian. Clearly, this is a problem for critical theory in the Marxist tradition, which connects human emancipation with the free development of individuals in association with others (Marx &amp; Engels, <span>1848</span>). Accordingly, critical theory's orientation and guidance should foster such development, which means, at a minimum, that it must always be open to critical questioning by those it addresses and, in this sense, non-authoritarian (Cooke, <span>2005</span>). In his political writings of the late 1960s, Theodor W. Adorno, Horkheimer's collaborator and colleague at the Institute, draws a link between (what I call) an authoritarian conception of theory and a kind of political activism he calls “actionism” (Adorno, <span>2005</span>). In my reading of Adorno, he acknowledges that actionists may initially be theoretically motivated. However, due to a fixation on action, they subsequently leave to one side the question of the theory's validity, deeming it irrelevant to the fundamental social transformation the objective facts of the situation demand. This leaves no room for critical interrogation of the theory's analyses of what is wrong with existing social and political reality and of its (usually tacit) projections of a better alternative. Adorno offers a trenchant critique of this action-fixation (see Cooke, <span>2020b</span>, pp. 585–591). As he describes it, actionism serves to distract from the only kind of genuinely transformative <i>praxis</i> possible in the social conditions of the time, which is resistance to the power of the totality in the form of unrelenting, unsparing self-reflection, coupled with reflection based on a theoretically guided interpretation of the causes of the current catastrophe. Actionism works against the required transformation, since it generates the false belief that resistance of this kind is not necessary; it thereby not only serves the power of the oppressive totality but also strengthens it. This is why, in my terms, critical theory today must offer authoritative, yet non-authoritarian diagnoses of social reality and utopian projections of better alternatives.<sup>4</sup> By this I mean that its guidance and orientation must be authoritative in the sense of having the power to move the hearts and minds of its addressees, giving them reason to feel that it is “advice that they may not safely ignore” (Mommsen, <span>1888</span>, cited in Arendt, <span>1977</span>)<sup>5</sup>; yet, at the same time, it must be non-authoritarian by acknowledging its own inherent contestability and opening its prescriptions and recommendations to critical challenge by everyone affected by them (Cooke, <span>2020c</span>).</p><p>Human-induced ecological devastation on a global scale poses many other difficulties for contemporary critical theory. A particular challenge is how to reconcile the need for ecological sustainability with critical theory's projections of an emancipated social condition, since it is hard to imagine how an emancipatory aim such as the free development of each individual could be achieved without a significant material impact on the earth's ecosystems. However, here too Horkheimer's programmatic writings from the 1930s, with their emphasis on the dynamic interplay between mind and reality, between the material and spiritual dimensions of human life, seem to me a fruitful starting point. They remind us that the concrete material impact of humans on earth is not a given but something that demands ongoing critical attention through reference to scientific findings, while keeping in view the importance of achieving a good life on this planet for each human individual within a corresponding good society.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"30 4\",\"pages\":\"384-389\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-12-21\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12722\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12722\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12722","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

90多年后的今天,读到霍克海默作为社会研究所第二任所长的就职演说,既令人着迷又令人鼓舞。正如他在演讲中所描述的那样,社会哲学还没有找到作为批判理论的具体表述。然而,在确定研究所作为社会哲学中心的任务时,他新兴的批判理论思想的关键组成部分已经可见。这些将在他1937年发表的关于传统和批判理论的纲领性论文中加以阐述(霍克海默,1973)。在我看来,霍克海默早期社会哲学/批判理论观点的基本要素一如既往地相关。我是这样理解它们的:首先,社会哲学的目的是哲学地解释“人类的命运”(霍克海默,1988,第20页)它必须在一个框架内这样做,在这个框架中,个人和社会整体存在于相互自我构成的动态关系中(第20页),这反过来又是事实与价值之间动态相互作用的一部分,或者正如他所写的那样,“思想”与“现实”(第32页)。由此我们可以推断,“人类的命运”是有物质基础的,是社会生产出来的。这就要求注意现有社会现实的实际情况。然而,社会哲学不能忽视“重大的主要问题”——关于个人与社会的关系、文化的意义、社区的形成以及作为一个整体的历史发展的问题。同样地,虽然它必须从具体而紧迫的时代哲学问题出发,但它必须始终努力保持对普遍的看法。其次,社会哲学的解释性努力必须建立在具有经验成分的多个领域的集体探究的基础上。因此,它必须组织调查,让哲学家、社会学家、经济学家、历史学家和心理学家在最精确的科学方法的帮助下共同努力,修正推动其解释努力的具体哲学问题,使其更加准确;它还必须在这项工作中发展新的方法。社会哲学问题因此成为辩证运动的一部分,在辩证运动中,社会哲学问题被卷入了影响其性质的经验科学过程;据推测,它们反过来又影响了调查的实证过程。虽然霍克海默在他的演讲中没有明确地说,但他在1937年的文章中批评了那些将事实物化的理论,将它们视为人类思维的外在因素。他将这种实体化与批判理论的观点进行了对比,批判理论认为事实是“原则上应该在人类控制之下的产品”(霍克海默,1973年,第209页)。这样,“客观现实”就失去了“纯粹事实”的性质(第209页)。换句话说,批判理论认识到事实驱动的、基于经验的探究的重要性,前提是它是在与意义和价值问题进行批判性接触的背景下进行的,并受到具体实践关注的推动,以实现更好的社会变革。因此,很明显,对于霍克海默来说,社会哲学形式的思维影响着现实正如经验科学所研究的那样,正如现实影响着思维一样。换句话说,在批判理论和科学发现之间存在一个反馈循环。第三,社会哲学关注的是认识人类存在意义的真正价值和内容。霍克海默将这种社会哲学观点归因于黑格尔,并将其描述为有问题的(第21页)。但是,从各方面看来,他只是把自己同黑格尔的唯心主义观点划清界限,黑格尔的唯心主义观点认为,这种认识仅仅是一种哲学洞察力的问题,它可以一劳永逸地确立起来,从而结束辩证过程。没有迹象表明他反对黑格尔的承诺,即决定人类存在的价值和内容,因为它是在历史现实中形成的,有些迹象表明他赞同这一点。事实上,如果我们撇开他对黑格尔唯心主义和辩证法的终结的反对,他对黑格尔的引用与他对社会哲学在价值灌输的社会背景下解释人类命运的关注的开场白非常吻合。他对黑格尔的引用也可以说是对他1937年论文的预测,他在论文中告诉我们,批判理论“构建了一个整体社会的发展图景,一个具有历史维度的存在主义判断”(霍克海默,1973年,第239页;参见Cooke, 2023)。在霍克海默的就职演说中,这三个要素中的第二个是突出的。他批评抽象的理论化,无论是斯宾诺莎的,黑格尔的,还是马克思的,因为他们把思想和现实分开了(第32页),并强调社会理论需要与它的材料保持不断的联系:它必须通过“对对象的研究”来发展它的哲学问题(第32页)。 28),根据手头的事情而不是自己的意愿。这就要求它发展最多样化的调查方法(第33页)。如果不这样做,它就有可能忽视第一个核心元素;此外,它也可能陷入教条主义的僵化,提出从根本上不受外部控制的论点(第32-33页)。在他1937年的文章中,霍克海默扩展了这一点,观察到社会哲学(现在被称为批判理论)只有建立在对社会转型的关注基础上,才能避免教条的僵化,这种转型是从普遍存在的社会不公正中不断产生的。重要的是,对社会转型的具体关注必须体现在理论上知情的政治行动(实践)中虽然在这篇文章中,霍克海默似乎首先想到了批判理论的启蒙力量,但在他1931年的演讲中,他强调的是传统理论提供的科学证据,特别是在多学科中基于经验的科学探究。然而,没有迹象表明他认为这两者之间有任何冲突。在1937年的文章中,霍克海默比1931年的演讲更清楚地将注意力集中在思想(在批判理论的意义上)和现实(在以经验为基础的科学研究和实践的双重意义上)之间相互作用的相互学习上。一方面,批判理论由于其对社会转型的具体关注,必须随时准备修改其价值,并相应地修改其实质内容,以回应普遍存在的不公正;在这里,理论必须借鉴有关社会现实的科学发现。另一方面,批判理论的价值和实质内容必须塑造和指导其经验丰富的实践努力,通过具体的变革建议来克服普遍存在的不公正;实践不能仅仅依赖科学证据,还必须从批判理论的价值驱动的见解中学习。总而言之,在20世纪30年代,霍克海默的批判理论思想,以及促进这种理论化的研究机构的任务,表现出对社会转型的具体关注,以回应当时紧迫的哲学问题。在关注社会现实的过程中,它既没有忽视意义和价值等更普遍的问题,也没有忽视解释(以物质为基础的、社会产生的)人类命运的任务,同时又保持了精神与现实之间的动态关系。我将留下一个开放的问题,即批判理论是否在法兰克福学派传统中发展,成功地实现了早期霍克海默的计划。我接下来的问题是,这对当代批判理论意味着什么。为了使我的讨论集中起来,我考虑了全球范围内人为生态破坏所带来的一些挑战在当今批判理论面临的许多具体而紧迫的哲学问题中,人类生命在全球人为生态破坏背景下的意义和价值无疑是其中之一。在解决这个问题时,霍克海默对事实与价值、思想与现实之间动态关系的呼吁是非常相关的。现实一面的重要性是显而易见的。显而易见的是,生态破坏的规模,以及它已经发生和继续发生的速度,意味着任何从哲学上解释其含义的尝试都必须与多种经验调查相结合。它必须包含“对目标的工作”,最好是在霍克海默提到的领域进行的合作工作:社会学、经济学、历史学和心理学。我们还可以在这个列表中加上人文科学的所有其他学科,例如,人种学、科学技术研究、考古学和地理学,以及自然科学的整个研究领域。此外,迫切需要制止生态破坏,并在可能的情况下补救其最坏的影响,这就要求以实践为指导的社会变革,旨在带来更好的变化。但这种关系的精神层面同样重要。其中一个原因是当代的“后真理”文化,它破坏了经验科学提出的真理主张,对任何哲学或社会理论的有效性主张产生了连锁反应。这导致了广泛的迷失感。当涉及到社会变革行动的可能性时,迷失方向很容易导致冷漠。批判理论的定位和指导任务在这种情况下显得尤为重要。 虽然霍克海默没有在他的社会哲学论述中明确地包括这些任务,但它们隐含在他赋予社会哲学的解释目标中:从“人类存在的真正价值和内容”的角度来解释(以物质为基础的、社会生产的)“人类的命运”。然而,这里的一个危险是,社会哲学对定向和引导的关注可能是专制的。显然,这是马克思主义传统中批判理论的一个问题,马克思主义传统将人的解放与个人在与他人的联系中自由发展联系起来(马克思和;恩格斯,1848)。因此,批判理论的取向和指导应该促进这种发展,这意味着,至少,它必须始终对它所解决的人的批判性质疑持开放态度,从这个意义上说,非威权主义(Cooke, 2005)。霍克海默在研究所的合作者和同事西奥多·阿多诺(Theodor W. Adorno)在他20世纪60年代后期的政治著作中,将(我称之为)威权主义理论概念与一种他称之为“行动主义”的政治激进主义(Adorno, 2005)联系起来。在我对阿多诺的解读中,他承认行动主义者最初可能是受到理论激励的。然而,由于对行动的执着,他们随后将理论的有效性问题搁置一边,认为它与客观情况所要求的基本社会变革无关。这就没有给该理论对现有社会和政治现实问题的分析以及(通常是心照不宣的)更好替代方案的预测留下批判性质疑的空间。阿多诺对这种对行动的迷恋提出了尖锐的批评(参见Cooke, 2020b,第585-591页)。正如他所描述的那样,行动主义分散了人们对当时社会条件下唯一可能的真正变革实践的注意力,这种实践是以无情的、毫不留情的自我反思的形式对整体力量的抵抗,以及基于对当前灾难原因的理论指导解释的反思。行动主义反对所需的转变,因为它产生了一种错误的信念,认为这种抵抗是不必要的;因此,它不仅为压迫性总体的权力服务,而且还加强了它。这就是为什么,用我的话说,今天的批判理论必须提供权威的,但非权威的社会现实诊断和更好的替代方案的乌托邦式预测我的意思是,它的指导和方向必须是权威的,因为它有能力打动受众的心灵和思想,让他们有理由觉得这是“他们可能不会安全地忽视的建议”(Mommsen, 1888,引自阿伦特,1977)5;然而,与此同时,它必须是非专制的,承认其自身固有的可争议性,并开放其处方和建议,以应对受其影响的每个人的关键挑战(Cooke, 2020c)。人类在全球范围内造成的生态破坏给当代批判理论带来了许多其他困难。一个特别的挑战是如何调和对生态可持续性的需求与批判理论对一个解放的社会条件的预测,因为很难想象一个解放的目标,如每个人的自由发展,如何能够在不对地球生态系统产生重大物质影响的情况下实现。然而,这里也霍克的程序化的著作从1930年代,他们强调思想和现实之间的动态相互作用,在人类生活的物质和精神维度之间,在我看来一个卓有成效的起点。它们提醒我们,人类对地球的具体物质影响不是给定的,而是需要通过参考科学发现来持续关注的东西,同时要考虑到在这个星球上为每个人在相应的良好社会中实现良好生活的重要性。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Social theory as critical theory: Horkheimer's program and its relevance today

More than 90 years later, it is fascinating and encouraging to read Horkheimer's inaugural address as the second director of the Institute for Social Research. Social philosophy, as depicted in his lecture, had not yet found its specific articulation as critical theory. However, in setting out the Institute's tasks as a center for social philosophy, the key components of his emerging idea of critical theory are already visible. These will be elaborated in his programmatic essay on traditional and critical theory, which appeared in 1937 (Horkheimer, 1973). The fundamental elements of the early Horkheimer's view of social philosophy/critical theory seem to me as pertinent as ever. This is how I understand them:

First, social philosophy's aim is to interpret philosophically “the fate of humans” (Horkheimer, 1988, p. 20).1 It must do so within a framework in which the individual and social whole exist in a dynamic relationship of mutual self-constitution (p. 20), which is in turn part of a dynamic interplay between fact and value or, as he writes, “mind” and “reality” (p. 32). We can infer from this that “the fate of humans” has a material basis and is socially produced. This calls for attentiveness to the actual facts of existing social reality. However, social philosophy must not lose sight of “the great principal questions”—questions about the relationship of the individual to society, the meaning of culture, the formation of communities, and the development of history as a whole (p. 28). In the same vein, though it must start from the concrete pressing philosophical questions of the times, it must endeavor always to keep the universal in view (p. 29).

Second, social philosophy's interpretative efforts must be based on collective inquiry in multiple areas that has an empirical component. Accordingly, it must organize investigations in which philosophers, sociologists, economists, historians, and psychologists work together with the aid of the most precise scientific methods, revising the concrete philosophical questions driving its interpretative efforts and rendering them more exact; it must also develop new methods in the course of such work. Social philosophical questions thereby become part of a dialectical movement, in which they are drawn into the empirical scientific process, which affects their character (p. 30); presumably they in turn impact the empirical process of inquiry. While Horkheimer does not say so explicitly in his lecture, his 1937 essay criticizes theories that hypostatize the facts, treating them as extrinsic to the human mind. He contrasts such hypostatization with critical theory's view that facts are “products which in principle should be under human control” (Horkheimer, 1973, p. 209). In this way, “objective realities” lose the character of “pure factuality” (p. 209). In other words, critical theory recognizes the importance of a fact-driven, empirically based inquiry, provided it is conducted within a context of critical engagement with questions of meaning and value and motivated by a concrete practical concern to bring about social change for the better. It seems clear, therefore, that for Horkheimer mind in the form of social philosophy impacts reality as investigated by the empirically based sciences, just as reality impacts mind. In other words, there is a feedback loop between critical theory and scientific findings.

Third, social philosophy is concerned with knowing the true value and content of the meaning of human existence. Horkheimer attributes this view of social philosophy to Hegel and describes it as problematic (p. 21). However, to all appearances he distances himself only from Hegel's idealist view that such knowledge is solely a matter of philosophical insight and that it can be established once and for all, thereby closing the dialectical process. There is no indication that he rejects Hegel's commitment to determining the value and content of human existence as it takes shape in historical reality and some hints that he endorses it. Indeed, providing we leave aside his objections to Hegel's idealism and closure of the dialectic, his citation of him fits well with his opening remarks on social philosophy's concern to interpret the fate of humans within a value-imbued social context. His citation of Hegel could also be said to anticipate his 1937 essay, where he tells us that critical theory “constructs a developing picture of society as a whole, an existential judgment with a historical dimension” (Horkheimer, 1973, p. 239; see Cooke, 2023).

In Horkheimer's inaugural address, the second of the three elements is foregrounded. He criticizes abstract theorizing, be it Spinozist, Hegelian, or Marxian, for splitting off mind and reality (p. 32) and underscores the need for social theory to remain in constant connection with its material: It must develop its philosophical questions through “work on the object” (p. 28), according to the matter at hand as opposed to its own wishes. This calls on it to develop the most varied methods of investigation (p. 33). If it does not, it runs the risk of losing sight of the first core element; in addition, it is also likely to sink into dogmatic rigidity, advancing theses that are fundamentally immune from external control (pp. 32–33). In his 1937 essay, Horkheimer expands on this point, observing that social philosophy (now called critical theory) can avoid dogmatic rigidity only if it is based on a concern for social transformation that arises ever anew from the prevailing social injustice. Importantly, the concrete concern for social transformation must manifest itself in theoretically informed political action (praxis).2 Whereas in this essay, Horkheimer seems in the first instance to have the enlightening powers of critical theory in mind, in his 1931 lecture, his emphasis is on the scientific evidence provided by traditional theory, especially empirical-based scientific inquiry in multiple disciplines. There is no suggestion, however, that he sees any conflict between the two.

In the 1937 essay, more clearly than in the 1931 lecture, Horkheimer draws attention to the mutual learning involved in the interactions between mind (in the sense of critical theory) and reality (in the double sense of empirically based scientific research and praxis). On the one hand, critical theory, due to its concrete concern for social transformation, must be ready to modify its values, and accordingly its substantive content, in response to the prevailing injustice; here, the theory must learn from scientific findings about social reality. On the other hand, the values and substantive content of critical theory must shape and guide its empirically informed, practical efforts to overcome the prevailing injustice through concrete transformative proposals; praxis cannot rely solely on scientific evidence but must also learn from the value-driven insights of critical theory.

In the 1930s, in sum, Horkheimer's idea of critical theory, and of the tasks of a research institute that would foster such theorizing, displays a concrete concern for social transformation in response to the pressing philosophical problems of the time. In its attentiveness to social reality, it loses sight neither of more general questions of meaning and value nor of its task of interpreting the (materially based, socially produced) fate of humans, while maintaining a dynamic relationship between mind and reality.

I will leave open the question of whether critical theory as it subsequently developed in the Frankfurt School tradition has succeeded in realizing the early Horkheimer's program. My question in the following is what it implies for contemporary critical theory. To focus my discussion, I consider some challenges arising from anthropogenic ecological devastation on a global scale.3 Of the many concrete and pressing philosophical questions that confront critical theories today, the meaning and value of human life in the context of global anthropogenic ecological destruction is indisputably one of them.

In addressing this question, Horkheimer's call for a dynamic relationship between fact and value, mind and reality, is highly relevant. The importance of the reality side is obvious. It is immediately evident that the scale of ecological devastation, together with the rapidity at which it has happened and continues to happen, means that any attempt philosophically to interpret its implications must go together with multiple strands of empirical investigation. It must incorporate “work on the object,” preferably cooperative work, conducted in the areas mentioned by Horkheimer: sociology, economics, history, and psychology. We can add to this list just about all other disciplines in the human sciences, for example, ethnography, science and technology studies, archaeology and geography, and the entire palette of research areas in the natural sciences. Furthermore, the urgent imperative to halt ecological devastation, and where possible, to remedy its worst effects, calls for praxis: theoretically guided social transformation aimed at bringing about change for the better.

But the mind side of the relationship is just as relevant. One reason for this is the contemporary “post-truth” culture, which undermines truth claims made by the empirical sciences, with knock-on effects for the validity claims of any philosophical or social theory. Widespread feelings of disorientation are a consequence of this. Disorientation leads easily to apathy when it comes to possibilities for socially transformative action. Critical theory's tasks of orientation and guidance acquire special importance in such circumstances. Although Horkheimer does not include these tasks explicitly in his account of social philosophy, they are implicit in the interpretative aim he attributes to it: its concern to interpret the (materially based, socially produced) “fate of humans” from the point of view of the “true value and content of human existence.” A danger here, however, is that social philosophy's concern to orient and guide may be authoritarian. Clearly, this is a problem for critical theory in the Marxist tradition, which connects human emancipation with the free development of individuals in association with others (Marx & Engels, 1848). Accordingly, critical theory's orientation and guidance should foster such development, which means, at a minimum, that it must always be open to critical questioning by those it addresses and, in this sense, non-authoritarian (Cooke, 2005). In his political writings of the late 1960s, Theodor W. Adorno, Horkheimer's collaborator and colleague at the Institute, draws a link between (what I call) an authoritarian conception of theory and a kind of political activism he calls “actionism” (Adorno, 2005). In my reading of Adorno, he acknowledges that actionists may initially be theoretically motivated. However, due to a fixation on action, they subsequently leave to one side the question of the theory's validity, deeming it irrelevant to the fundamental social transformation the objective facts of the situation demand. This leaves no room for critical interrogation of the theory's analyses of what is wrong with existing social and political reality and of its (usually tacit) projections of a better alternative. Adorno offers a trenchant critique of this action-fixation (see Cooke, 2020b, pp. 585–591). As he describes it, actionism serves to distract from the only kind of genuinely transformative praxis possible in the social conditions of the time, which is resistance to the power of the totality in the form of unrelenting, unsparing self-reflection, coupled with reflection based on a theoretically guided interpretation of the causes of the current catastrophe. Actionism works against the required transformation, since it generates the false belief that resistance of this kind is not necessary; it thereby not only serves the power of the oppressive totality but also strengthens it. This is why, in my terms, critical theory today must offer authoritative, yet non-authoritarian diagnoses of social reality and utopian projections of better alternatives.4 By this I mean that its guidance and orientation must be authoritative in the sense of having the power to move the hearts and minds of its addressees, giving them reason to feel that it is “advice that they may not safely ignore” (Mommsen, 1888, cited in Arendt, 1977)5; yet, at the same time, it must be non-authoritarian by acknowledging its own inherent contestability and opening its prescriptions and recommendations to critical challenge by everyone affected by them (Cooke, 2020c).

Human-induced ecological devastation on a global scale poses many other difficulties for contemporary critical theory. A particular challenge is how to reconcile the need for ecological sustainability with critical theory's projections of an emancipated social condition, since it is hard to imagine how an emancipatory aim such as the free development of each individual could be achieved without a significant material impact on the earth's ecosystems. However, here too Horkheimer's programmatic writings from the 1930s, with their emphasis on the dynamic interplay between mind and reality, between the material and spiritual dimensions of human life, seem to me a fruitful starting point. They remind us that the concrete material impact of humans on earth is not a given but something that demands ongoing critical attention through reference to scientific findings, while keeping in view the importance of achieving a good life on this planet for each human individual within a corresponding good society.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信