不仅仅是通过其他方式的战争:跨国界的接触作为政治斗争

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Lucia M. Rafanelli
{"title":"不仅仅是通过其他方式的战争:跨国界的接触作为政治斗争","authors":"Lucia M. Rafanelli","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12719","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Counterinsurgency: The US sends troops to Libya to fight an insurgent group. The insurgents claim the US launched an attack that failed to properly safeguard against civilian deaths. They make this claim publicly, hoping global public opinion will turn against the US and lead it to curtail its attacks, preventing further civilian (and non-civilian) deaths. Activists and media outlets pick up the story and report it around the world. I call cases like this—cross-border political engagements including both kinetic and non-kinetic elements—hybrid cases.1 It is not obvious how to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases. Should we understand them as warfare—conflicts between “enemies” locked in a “radically adversarial relationship” whose main task is to harm each other and whose main normative quandary is how much and what kind of harm they are permitted to inflict (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? Or should we understand them as some (other) kind of political struggle? The question of which analytic frame to adopt is important, as, I will argue, there are serious democratic costs associated with understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare. In Counterinsurgency, understanding civilian casualty reports made by journalists, activists, and insurgents as acts of war would mean seeing them as acts meant to cause harm (by debilitating “enemy” forces) and as strategic communications whose purpose and value were, at best, unconnected to their truth. It would mean seeing their authors as potentially liable to attack—as Gross does when he describes journalists as “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (2015, p. 300) and argues they are therefore liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (2015, p. 269). And it would mean seeing their audiences as pawns to be manipulated by propagandists. Understanding civilian casualty reports instead as part of a political struggle would mean seeing them as statements that could inform, inspire critical reflection, and form the basis of democratic deliberation and contestation—which might not be contained within the borders of a single state. It would mean seeing their authors as sources of potentially weighty claims deserving real consideration and seeing their audiences as interlocutors capable of judging and responding in good faith to those claims. Existing scholarship does not often explicitly recognize the question of whether to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare or political struggle—let alone explicitly evaluate the costs and benefits of making one choice or another.2 Nonetheless, some (e.g., Blank, 2017; Gross, 2015; Gross & Meisels, 2017a; Kittrie, 2016; Walzer, 2017) tend to treat them more like warfare, and others (e.g., Jurkevics, 2019; Miller, 2010, pp. 247–57; Miller, 2018; Valdez, 2019a, 2019b) tend to treat them more like political struggle. Here, I make explicit the implicit assumptions behind these two approaches, argue that adopting the war paradigm (understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as “warfare”) has significant democratic costs, and argue that adopting an alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate these costs. More specifically, overreliance on the war paradigm undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become—and be recognized as—a site of genuinely democratic politics. It does so in three ways. First, it presents global political actors as enemies enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii), dedicated to harming and vanquishing each other. This obscures the possibility that they might develop relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders—precisely the kinds of relationships that best enable democratic politics. Second, adopting the war paradigm encourages the assumption that participants in cross-border politics act only in the service of their war strategy—rather than to advance potentially democratic deliberation or political struggle. The prevalence of this assumption can, in turn, transform the institutions through which people participate in cross-border politics (e.g., the media)—changing them from potential catalysts for democratic politics into vehicles through which belligerents carry out their war efforts. Third, if people believe participants in cross-border politics act only to further a war strategy, they may prematurely discount participants’ legitimate moral arguments, assuming these arguments are advanced purely instrumentally. Whereas adopting the war paradigm risks incurring these democratic costs, I argue we could mitigate them by adopting the political struggle paradigm. This alternate paradigm casts participants in cross-border politics as participants in a shared political struggle who do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents, who may be open to revising their ends in response to pushback from opponents in ways combatants are not, and whose behavior should be governed primarily by principles of political responsibility (rather than, e.g., just war principles or principles of military strategy). Moreover, according to the political struggle paradigm, the border need not cleanly divide opponents from allies.3 Below, I more thoroughly define the war paradigm. I then argue that overreliance on it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become (and be recognized as) a site of genuinely democratic politics in the three ways suggested above. Finally, I outline the alternative political struggle paradigm and argue that adopting it can mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm. I do not claim that we should never use the war paradigm. Perhaps sometimes we should bear its democratic costs. Someone who sees little value in democratizing cross-border politics may judge the democratic costs of the war paradigm as morally insignificant. I will not attempt to defend democracy against its critics here. But understanding the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm is a prerequisite for making any credible judgment about whether those costs are worth bearing—even a credible judgment that they are worth bearing. I enable this understanding here by illustrating the democratic costs of the war paradigm and how adopting an alternate paradigm could mitigate them. In revealing a new obstacle to the democratization of cross-border politics (overreliance on the war paradigm), my arguments may have added significance for proponents of transnational democracy (e.g., Benhabib, 2005, 2009; Bohman, 2007), but they remain important for anyone interested in honestly assessing the democratic costs and benefits of employing one or another analytic frame to understand cross-border politics. The war paradigm is a particular way of conceptualizing and analyzing political activity. It is only plausible to use the war paradigm when such activity involves actors with opposing ends, so I will assume this is true in all the cases I discuss. Employing the war paradigm to analyze political activity means treating participants as if they are enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Writing about conflicts that do not take the form of conventional kinetic warfare (“soft war”), Walzer illustrates how identifying these conflicts as “war” involves assuming this adversarial relationship as a central feature: “‘we’ are trying to harm enemies who are trying to harm ‘us.’ And in this kind of warfare, as in any other, the combatants need to know what harms are permissible and what harms aren't, who can be targeted and who must not be targeted” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Walzer writes this in a forward to Gross and Meisels’ (2017a, p. 1) edited volume Soft War, which presents many modes of political engagement, including “all non-kinetic measures, whether persuasive or coercive, including cyber warfare and economic sanctions; media warfare and propaganda, nonviolent resistance and civil disobedience, boycotts and ‘lawfare’” as forms of “war”—albeit of the “soft” variety. In fairness to Walzer, he does not argue that we should always understand these modes of engagement as “war,” but rather articulates (some of) the implications of doing so. He highlights some of the assumptions we make when we categorize an activity as “war.” That is, he articulates some of the implicit assumptions underlying the war paradigm, which I aim to make explicit here. Specifically, Walzer notes that in “war,” the main task of each actor is to harm those on opposing sides until they are defeated. The main normative question facing each actor is: How much and what kind of harm am I justified in causing my enemies (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? This does not mean that radically adversarial relationships of this kind must be the only ones present in a political encounter for the war paradigm to be appropriate. Even enemies in war may share friendships, familial relationships, romantic relationships, and acts of mercy. But the choice to analyze their political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat their identities as enemies as their central identities, their task of harming their enemies to advance their own ends as their central task, and the normative question of how much and what kind of harm they should cause their enemies as their central normative quandary. The choice to analyze political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat political actors’ identities, tasks, and normative quandaries as defined by other (less radically adversarial) relationships as marginal. In other words, analyzing political activity using the war paradigm means analyzing it through an adversarial lens. Employing the war paradigm also involves making certain assumptions about the principles that should govern political actors’ behavior, though the specific assumptions it entails vary depending on the role one occupies. For example, for political theorists, employing the war paradigm involves appealing to “just war” principles such as just cause (wars should only be waged for specified reasons), last resort (wars should only be waged after other options have been exhausted), discrimination (warring parties should attack only legitimate targets), necessity (every war campaign should be necessary to achieve a legitimate end), and proportionality (neither the war as a whole nor any individual act of war should cause too much damage compared to the benefits it promises).4 For legal analysts, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the law of armed conflict (LOAC), which “governs the conduct of states, individuals, and non-state actors during armed conflict” and is largely based on just war principles (Blank, 2017, pp. 90–91). For military leaders, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the principles of military strategy, which may also include or be constrained by just war principles. Having clarified what the “war paradigm” is, I can now assess the costs of employing it to analyze the non-kinetic elements in hybrid cases of cross-border politics. In questioning whether we should use the war paradigm to analyze activities that are not literal warfare, I sympathize with advocates of jus ad vim, who argue we should not use just war theory to analyze the use of force-short-of-war (see Brunstetter, 2021; Brunstetter & Braun, 2013; for a review of the jus ad vim literature, see Galliott, 2019). However, jus ad vim theorists are still concerned with the use of force. Indeed, Brunstetter (2021, p. 8) explicitly limits his discussion to acts “that involve kinetic, lethal force.” Conversely, I focus on the non-kinetic elements of cross-border conflict. Thus, my analysis provides a necessary supplement to the jus ad vim literature—exposing another domain (non-kinetic engagement in the context of hybrid conflicts) in which overreliance on the war paradigm has significant disadvantages and, eventually, illustrating how adopting the alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate them. First, employing the war paradigm to analyze the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases involves adopting—or encouraging others to adopt—an adversarial point of view that casts participants on opposite sides of the border as “enemies” enmeshed in a radically adversarial relationship. This, in turn, undermines democracy by discouraging the formation and recognition of respectful relationships conducive to mutual learning and shutting down the possibility of solidaristic collaboration across borders. This part of my argument resembles Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–104) view that pluralist democracy is stymied when political opponents see each other as “enem[ies] to be destroyed” (2000, p. 102) and enabled when they see each other instead as legitimate adversaries entitled to promote their views in the political arena. However, my view differs from Mouffe's in key respects—foremost, in its focus on the international context. Moreover, when Mouffe (2009) considers the implications of her democratic theory for international relations, she concludes we should strive for a “multipolar” world divided into distinct regions, each governed according to its own culture and values, and each enacting its own form of democracy, all of which are recognized as legitimate. But this tells us nothing about what would be necessary for political activity transcending the boundaries of Mouffe's regions to be democratic. That is the question I address here. Mouffe (2009, p. 553) accepts the division of the world into distinct “blocs” and envisions democracy as best served when none of these blocs tries to impose its values on the others. Conversely, I explore how the interstitial space between societies (which in many cases will be a space between regions or “blocs”) can itself be a site of democratic politics—and what could undermine its democratic potential. It is also noteworthy that my arguments (unlike Mouffe's) should be acceptable to a wide variety of democratic theorists, not only agonists. My arguments do not rely on any one conception of democracy—only on the existence of a few preconditions for democracy, endorsed by a wide range of democratic theorists who advocate divergent conceptions of democracy. In addition to making my view more ecumenical, this means I avoid the pitfall Mouffe (2009) identifies with some liberal theories of democracy—that they admit only one model of democracy as legitimate. Though theorists disagree about the precise requirements of democratic politics, there are a few features widely considered to be necessary for democracy. First, for political contestation to be democratic, all participants must be recognized as equally capable of making valid claims potentially worthy of being taken up by other participants. A wide range of democratic theorists with varying substantive and methodological commitments, including Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276), Blajer de la Garza (n.d., p. 13), Knight and Johnson (1997, pp. 279–282), Mouffe (2000, pp. 101–104), Schwartzberg (2016), and Young (2000, pp. 9–11, 23), have treated such equality as a central feature of democracy. Recognizing participants in political contestation as equals, in turn, requires genuine, good-faith consideration of their (often competing) claims. Part of genuinely considering a claim in good faith is admitting the possibility that it may have merit, even if this would necessitate revising one's own claims. Thus, democratic politics requires respectful recognition of others’ perspectives and openness to the possibility of learning from or collaborating with others who may be on the opposite side of a salient political divide. A similarly wide range of democratic theorists identify this as a central feature of democracy. For example, Young (2000, p. 3) maintains that democratic decision-making “requires a give and take that often leads to compromise” and that in a genuine democracy, “people aim to persuade one another of…their claims, and are open to having their own opinions…change in the process” (2000, p. 6). Blajer de la Garza (n.d., p. 13) holds that democratic deliberation requires open-mindedness and willingness to change one's opinion in response to others’ arguments. Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276) describes democratic decision-making as “a process of discussion…wherein others take one's views seriously and respond to one's views” and in which “each person's judgment…must be taken seriously.” And a distinguishing trait of agonistic democracy in Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–103) view is that political opponents recognize each other's claims as legitimate and worth considering as interpretations of what commitments to liberty and equality require. Mouffe (2000, p. 102) also notes that participants in democratic politics can compromise and be “converted” to each other's perspectives. We can conclude, then, that a wide range of democratic theorists (despite their other disagreements) identify respectful recognition of others’ perspectives and openness to the possibility of learning from or collaborating with others (even political opponents) as central features of democracy. Granted, democratic politics may also require more than this. Respectful relationships conducive to mutual learning and collaboration may not be sufficient for democracy. But I maintain they are necessary, and this should be an uncontroversial assumption given the range of democratic theorists who endorse some version of it. Therefore, if (as I argue) adopting the war paradigm undermines our ability to recognize such democracy-supporting relationships when they transcend national borders, it undermines our ability to recognize cross-border political activity as democratic, even when it is in fact democratic. And if (as I argue) adopting the war paradigm undermines the ability of participants in cross-border politics to maintain democracy-supporting relationships, it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become democratic—even if full democracy would require more in addition to these democracy-supporting relationships. If theorists present parties to cross-border political engagements as neatly divided enemies, with people on one side of the border dedicated to harming and destroying people on the other side, they will not likely interpret those parties as respectfully engaging with the perspectives of or being open to learning from or collaborating with people across the border. Thus, theorists who adopt the war paradigm will not likely interpret participants in cross-border politics as engaging in democratic politics. They will therefore risk overlooking or misrecognizing democratic cross-border politics if it does occur. Similarly, adopting the war paradigm will constrain how theorists see the options participants in cross-border politics face, obscuring some available options and overemphasizing others. Theorists beholden to the war paradigm will likely interpret participants as choosing among different ways of waging war—of harming their enemies—perhaps suitably constrained by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy. They will be correspondingly less likely to interpret participants as choosing among different ways of engaging in democratic politics—or even as choosing between waging war and engaging in democratic politics. The outcome of this choice (to wage war) is presupposed by the adoption of the war paradigm. In short, theorists who adopt the war paradigm interpret cross-border politics as adversarial rather than collaborative, likely overlook possibilities for collaboration and consultation among parties across borders, and can in turn fail to recognize these phenomena when they do occur. Moreover, if participants in cross-border politics adopt the war paradigm themselves, they will see those across the border as enemies they must harm and destroy—and arguably will not respectfully engage with the latter's perspectives, or be open to learning from or collaborating with them. That is, people on opposite sides of the border will not be able to engage together in democratic politics when they think of each other as enemies in this way. But this is precisely how they must think of each other when they understand their conflict in terms of the war paradigm. Gross's work illustrates these risks well. He uses the war paradigm to analyze several non-kinetic actions, grouping “armed violence, non-kinetic force, and soft power” together under the rubric of “guerrilla warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 22). He treats “civil disobedience and nonviolent resistance” (Gross, 2015, p. 31) and what he calls “media warfare” as tactics of guerilla warfare (Gross, 2015, p. 30). “Media warfare,” as he understands it, is “characterized by an aggressive campaign of public diplomacy”—or, in another formulation, aggressive efforts to “disseminate opinion-shaping information” (Gross, 2015, p. 30). To clarify, Gross does not claim every attempt to “disseminate opinion-shaping information” (or every act of civil disobedience or nonviolent resistance) is an act of guerilla war. But for the purposes of developing an ethics of insurgency, his analysis focuses on devising ethical principles to govern these activities when they are understood as guerilla warfare. Even assuming Gross only means his analysis to apply in a subset of cases (because not all public diplomacy campaigns should be understood as guerilla warfare), his work still illustrates what happens when theorists do characterize them as warfare—how this characterization can affect theorists’ normative recommendations and understandings of the options open to participants in cross-border politics. Gross's choice to characterize the kinds of non-kinetic public diplomacy he analyzes as “media warfare” (even though he leaves open the possibility that other kinds may not qualify as warfare) directly affects his assessment of how participants should behave and what reasons should guide both their behavior and theorists’ evaluation of it. To illustrate, let's apply Gross's treatment of “media warfare” to the Counterinsurgency case. Understanding the activists and journalists reporting insurgents’ claims about civilian deaths as members of civil society rather than participants in the insurgents’ war would lead one to conclude they were not legitimate targets liable to attack as soldiers would be. Gross (2015, p. 300) might agree that completely neutral “third-party journalists” deserve special protection. However, he would arguably treat non-neutral parties, like activists and “media workers affiliated with a party to the conflict,” as engaging in warfare even if they only undertook the non-kinetic activity of disseminating information about civilian deaths (Gross, 2015, p. 300). It is with reference to such partisan media workers that Gross says journalists are “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 300). (It is ambiguous how partisan one must be to forfeit “their claims to neutrality and the protection it infers” (Gross, 2015, p. 300).) Elsewhere, Gross argues journalists—it is not clear whether he means all journalists whose work benefits one party to a war or only those officially associated with a warring party—are liable to harm much like other combatants because they are “among the primary agents of media warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 269). Though the fact that they usually do not pose lethal threats to others means they usually are not liable to be killed, the fact that they pose threats as participants in a war means they are liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (Gross, 2015, p. 269). Since Gross suggests we consider even non-kinetic media operations as possible acts of war, he would seem to present journalists—at least partisan journalists, and at most any journalists consistently disseminating information that could help insurgents—as participants in insurgents’ war. Characterizing the journalists in Counterinsurgency in this way would present them as enemies of all who oppose the insurgents, thereby obscuring the possibility that they may have any number of collaborative or solidaristic relationships with their audiences around the world. More generally, because Gross understands media activity using the war paradigm's adversarial lens, he would be ill-suited to recognize such cross-border collaboration and solidarity if they occurred. If participants in cross-border politics also adopt this lens—perhaps, as Gross suggests, incarcerating journalists that spread information favorable to their “enemies”—this could prevent cross-border collaboration from occurring in the first place. Moreover, if we understand insurgents, journalists reporting their claims, and audiences receiving them as co-participants in potentially democratic politics, we might characterize the insurgents’ options and their attendant advantages and disadvantages roughly as follows: They could truthfully depict events on the ground, providing transparency to an otherwise opaque military operation and giving global publics access to the information necessary to assess and, if appropriate, democratically contest it. Alternatively, they could present information in a deceptive way without outright lying. This would still give global publics access to true information they would otherwise lack. But the insurgents’ deception would detract from transparency and from the integrity of any democratic contestation based on their claims. Finally, the insurgents could spread unambiguously false information. Although this might serve their own strategic objectives, it would do nothing to enhance transparency and would deeply undermine the integrity of any political contestation based on their claims. Gross (2015, p. 271) recognizes these alternatives, distinguishing among “white, gray, or black” propaganda based on “truths, half-truths, and lies,” respectively. But, strikingly, his assessment of what option “guerrillas” should choose has virtually nothing to do with the independent merits of disseminating true information to or enabling good-faith deliberation among global publics (as opposed to manipulating them). These things are largely absent from Gross's analysis because “the truth is a legitimate casualty of just war” (2015, p. 269). Thus, he suggests, the ethical principles that usually govern communication do not apply in the same way to guerillas, and their decisions to deceive should instead be governed largely by the rules of war, such as necessity, proportionality, and other in bello rules (Gross, 2015, pp. 30, 269). If we thought of people separated by national borders (e.g., journalists, their sources in Libya (who may also be insurgents), and their audiences around the world) as potential collaborators or partners—perhaps engaged in a joint endeavor to uncover and appropriately respond to the truth about a military operation's threat to civilians—we would see deceitful interactions among them as unequivocally bad and as undermining their ability to engage in genuine democratic deliberation with each other. Gross (2015, pp. 288–9, 292) himself recognizes how deception can undermine the informed, conscientious decision-making democratic politics requires. But, in his view, this democratic politics is only appropriate within a state: “the importance of truth telling and disclosure is strongest among compatriots. Lying to the enemy is a different issue” (Gross, 2015, p. 289). Even when acknowledging that some non-enemy international actors “have a prima facie right to know the truth,” Gross (2015, p. 290) asserts, “their right seems considerably weaker than compatriots’ rights” and their claim to be told the truth can be overridden by considerations of military necessity. According to Gross (2015, pp. 290, 298), citizens of a democratic state are vested with civic responsibilities by virtue of the social contract their state embodies, which they can only exercise if they have access to accurate information about their government's operations. This provides a powerful reason for honesty and transparency among co-citizens. But this reason does not apply across borders: While co-citizens may be entitled to honesty, transparency, and the balanced presentation of opposing views, “Enemies…deserve no such temperance” (Gross, 2015, p. 298). This ambivalence about honesty toward non-compatriots underwrites Gross's startling suggestion that it is morally irrelevant whether the information disseminated as part of “media warfare” is true. For example, discussing the footage of a young boy's death that was used to spur on Palestinians and sour public opinion toward Israel in the Second Intifada, Gross (2015, p. 285) says, “it does not matter whether the video was fabricated or authentic.” He makes the same claim about records of the “Santa Cruz massacre” that aided the East Timorese in their fight for independence, arguing it would be of little moral consequence if we discovered the incident “was a staged media event” (Gross, 2015, p. 286). Because he does not see democratic politics as something that does or should occur as part of cross-border engagement, Gross is unconcerned about the ways such deception and manipulation would undercut the collaboration and solidarity needed for democratic politics. And those who behaved as Gross suggests, readily deceiving non-compatriots whenever this was a necessary and proportional way to serve their war aims (even assuming those aims were just), would be ill-placed to develop collaborative and solidaristic relationships with the targets of their deception. Thus, Gross's characterization of journalists as warriors and information dissemination as w","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Not just war by other means: Cross‐border engagement as political struggle\",\"authors\":\"Lucia M. Rafanelli\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12719\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Counterinsurgency: The US sends troops to Libya to fight an insurgent group. The insurgents claim the US launched an attack that failed to properly safeguard against civilian deaths. They make this claim publicly, hoping global public opinion will turn against the US and lead it to curtail its attacks, preventing further civilian (and non-civilian) deaths. Activists and media outlets pick up the story and report it around the world. I call cases like this—cross-border political engagements including both kinetic and non-kinetic elements—hybrid cases.1 It is not obvious how to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases. Should we understand them as warfare—conflicts between “enemies” locked in a “radically adversarial relationship” whose main task is to harm each other and whose main normative quandary is how much and what kind of harm they are permitted to inflict (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? Or should we understand them as some (other) kind of political struggle? The question of which analytic frame to adopt is important, as, I will argue, there are serious democratic costs associated with understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare. In Counterinsurgency, understanding civilian casualty reports made by journalists, activists, and insurgents as acts of war would mean seeing them as acts meant to cause harm (by debilitating “enemy” forces) and as strategic communications whose purpose and value were, at best, unconnected to their truth. It would mean seeing their authors as potentially liable to attack—as Gross does when he describes journalists as “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (2015, p. 300) and argues they are therefore liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (2015, p. 269). And it would mean seeing their audiences as pawns to be manipulated by propagandists. Understanding civilian casualty reports instead as part of a political struggle would mean seeing them as statements that could inform, inspire critical reflection, and form the basis of democratic deliberation and contestation—which might not be contained within the borders of a single state. It would mean seeing their authors as sources of potentially weighty claims deserving real consideration and seeing their audiences as interlocutors capable of judging and responding in good faith to those claims. Existing scholarship does not often explicitly recognize the question of whether to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare or political struggle—let alone explicitly evaluate the costs and benefits of making one choice or another.2 Nonetheless, some (e.g., Blank, 2017; Gross, 2015; Gross & Meisels, 2017a; Kittrie, 2016; Walzer, 2017) tend to treat them more like warfare, and others (e.g., Jurkevics, 2019; Miller, 2010, pp. 247–57; Miller, 2018; Valdez, 2019a, 2019b) tend to treat them more like political struggle. Here, I make explicit the implicit assumptions behind these two approaches, argue that adopting the war paradigm (understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as “warfare”) has significant democratic costs, and argue that adopting an alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate these costs. More specifically, overreliance on the war paradigm undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become—and be recognized as—a site of genuinely democratic politics. It does so in three ways. First, it presents global political actors as enemies enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii), dedicated to harming and vanquishing each other. This obscures the possibility that they might develop relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders—precisely the kinds of relationships that best enable democratic politics. Second, adopting the war paradigm encourages the assumption that participants in cross-border politics act only in the service of their war strategy—rather than to advance potentially democratic deliberation or political struggle. The prevalence of this assumption can, in turn, transform the institutions through which people participate in cross-border politics (e.g., the media)—changing them from potential catalysts for democratic politics into vehicles through which belligerents carry out their war efforts. Third, if people believe participants in cross-border politics act only to further a war strategy, they may prematurely discount participants’ legitimate moral arguments, assuming these arguments are advanced purely instrumentally. Whereas adopting the war paradigm risks incurring these democratic costs, I argue we could mitigate them by adopting the political struggle paradigm. This alternate paradigm casts participants in cross-border politics as participants in a shared political struggle who do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents, who may be open to revising their ends in response to pushback from opponents in ways combatants are not, and whose behavior should be governed primarily by principles of political responsibility (rather than, e.g., just war principles or principles of military strategy). Moreover, according to the political struggle paradigm, the border need not cleanly divide opponents from allies.3 Below, I more thoroughly define the war paradigm. I then argue that overreliance on it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become (and be recognized as) a site of genuinely democratic politics in the three ways suggested above. Finally, I outline the alternative political struggle paradigm and argue that adopting it can mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm. I do not claim that we should never use the war paradigm. Perhaps sometimes we should bear its democratic costs. Someone who sees little value in democratizing cross-border politics may judge the democratic costs of the war paradigm as morally insignificant. I will not attempt to defend democracy against its critics here. But understanding the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm is a prerequisite for making any credible judgment about whether those costs are worth bearing—even a credible judgment that they are worth bearing. I enable this understanding here by illustrating the democratic costs of the war paradigm and how adopting an alternate paradigm could mitigate them. In revealing a new obstacle to the democratization of cross-border politics (overreliance on the war paradigm), my arguments may have added significance for proponents of transnational democracy (e.g., Benhabib, 2005, 2009; Bohman, 2007), but they remain important for anyone interested in honestly assessing the democratic costs and benefits of employing one or another analytic frame to understand cross-border politics. The war paradigm is a particular way of conceptualizing and analyzing political activity. It is only plausible to use the war paradigm when such activity involves actors with opposing ends, so I will assume this is true in all the cases I discuss. Employing the war paradigm to analyze political activity means treating participants as if they are enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Writing about conflicts that do not take the form of conventional kinetic warfare (“soft war”), Walzer illustrates how identifying these conflicts as “war” involves assuming this adversarial relationship as a central feature: “‘we’ are trying to harm enemies who are trying to harm ‘us.’ And in this kind of warfare, as in any other, the combatants need to know what harms are permissible and what harms aren't, who can be targeted and who must not be targeted” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Walzer writes this in a forward to Gross and Meisels’ (2017a, p. 1) edited volume Soft War, which presents many modes of political engagement, including “all non-kinetic measures, whether persuasive or coercive, including cyber warfare and economic sanctions; media warfare and propaganda, nonviolent resistance and civil disobedience, boycotts and ‘lawfare’” as forms of “war”—albeit of the “soft” variety. In fairness to Walzer, he does not argue that we should always understand these modes of engagement as “war,” but rather articulates (some of) the implications of doing so. He highlights some of the assumptions we make when we categorize an activity as “war.” That is, he articulates some of the implicit assumptions underlying the war paradigm, which I aim to make explicit here. Specifically, Walzer notes that in “war,” the main task of each actor is to harm those on opposing sides until they are defeated. The main normative question facing each actor is: How much and what kind of harm am I justified in causing my enemies (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? This does not mean that radically adversarial relationships of this kind must be the only ones present in a political encounter for the war paradigm to be appropriate. Even enemies in war may share friendships, familial relationships, romantic relationships, and acts of mercy. But the choice to analyze their political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat their identities as enemies as their central identities, their task of harming their enemies to advance their own ends as their central task, and the normative question of how much and what kind of harm they should cause their enemies as their central normative quandary. The choice to analyze political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat political actors’ identities, tasks, and normative quandaries as defined by other (less radically adversarial) relationships as marginal. In other words, analyzing political activity using the war paradigm means analyzing it through an adversarial lens. Employing the war paradigm also involves making certain assumptions about the principles that should govern political actors’ behavior, though the specific assumptions it entails vary depending on the role one occupies. For example, for political theorists, employing the war paradigm involves appealing to “just war” principles such as just cause (wars should only be waged for specified reasons), last resort (wars should only be waged after other options have been exhausted), discrimination (warring parties should attack only legitimate targets), necessity (every war campaign should be necessary to achieve a legitimate end), and proportionality (neither the war as a whole nor any individual act of war should cause too much damage compared to the benefits it promises).4 For legal analysts, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the law of armed conflict (LOAC), which “governs the conduct of states, individuals, and non-state actors during armed conflict” and is largely based on just war principles (Blank, 2017, pp. 90–91). For military leaders, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the principles of military strategy, which may also include or be constrained by just war principles. Having clarified what the “war paradigm” is, I can now assess the costs of employing it to analyze the non-kinetic elements in hybrid cases of cross-border politics. In questioning whether we should use the war paradigm to analyze activities that are not literal warfare, I sympathize with advocates of jus ad vim, who argue we should not use just war theory to analyze the use of force-short-of-war (see Brunstetter, 2021; Brunstetter & Braun, 2013; for a review of the jus ad vim literature, see Galliott, 2019). However, jus ad vim theorists are still concerned with the use of force. Indeed, Brunstetter (2021, p. 8) explicitly limits his discussion to acts “that involve kinetic, lethal force.” Conversely, I focus on the non-kinetic elements of cross-border conflict. Thus, my analysis provides a necessary supplement to the jus ad vim literature—exposing another domain (non-kinetic engagement in the context of hybrid conflicts) in which overreliance on the war paradigm has significant disadvantages and, eventually, illustrating how adopting the alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate them. First, employing the war paradigm to analyze the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases involves adopting—or encouraging others to adopt—an adversarial point of view that casts participants on opposite sides of the border as “enemies” enmeshed in a radically adversarial relationship. This, in turn, undermines democracy by discouraging the formation and recognition of respectful relationships conducive to mutual learning and shutting down the possibility of solidaristic collaboration across borders. This part of my argument resembles Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–104) view that pluralist democracy is stymied when political opponents see each other as “enem[ies] to be destroyed” (2000, p. 102) and enabled when they see each other instead as legitimate adversaries entitled to promote their views in the political arena. However, my view differs from Mouffe's in key respects—foremost, in its focus on the international context. Moreover, when Mouffe (2009) considers the implications of her democratic theory for international relations, she concludes we should strive for a “multipolar” world divided into distinct regions, each governed according to its own culture and values, and each enacting its own form of democracy, all of which are recognized as legitimate. But this tells us nothing about what would be necessary for political activity transcending the boundaries of Mouffe's regions to be democratic. That is the question I address here. Mouffe (2009, p. 553) accepts the division of the world into distinct “blocs” and envisions democracy as best served when none of these blocs tries to impose its values on the others. Conversely, I explore how the interstitial space between societies (which in many cases will be a space between regions or “blocs”) can itself be a site of democratic politics—and what could undermine its democratic potential. It is also noteworthy that my arguments (unlike Mouffe's) should be acceptable to a wide variety of democratic theorists, not only agonists. My arguments do not rely on any one conception of democracy—only on the existence of a few preconditions for democracy, endorsed by a wide range of democratic theorists who advocate divergent conceptions of democracy. In addition to making my view more ecumenical, this means I avoid the pitfall Mouffe (2009) identifies with some liberal theories of democracy—that they admit only one model of democracy as legitimate. Though theorists disagree about the precise requirements of democratic politics, there are a few features widely considered to be necessary for democracy. First, for political contestation to be democratic, all participants must be recognized as equally capable of making valid claims potentially worthy of being taken up by other participants. A wide range of democratic theorists with varying substantive and methodological commitments, including Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276), Blajer de la Garza (n.d., p. 13), Knight and Johnson (1997, pp. 279–282), Mouffe (2000, pp. 101–104), Schwartzberg (2016), and Young (2000, pp. 9–11, 23), have treated such equality as a central feature of democracy. Recognizing participants in political contestation as equals, in turn, requires genuine, good-faith consideration of their (often competing) claims. Part of genuinely considering a claim in good faith is admitting the possibility that it may have merit, even if this would necessitate revising one's own claims. Thus, democratic politics requires respectful recognition of others’ perspectives and openness to the possibility of learning from or collaborating with others who may be on the opposite side of a salient political divide. A similarly wide range of democratic theorists identify this as a central feature of democracy. For example, Young (2000, p. 3) maintains that democratic decision-making “requires a give and take that often leads to compromise” and that in a genuine democracy, “people aim to persuade one another of…their claims, and are open to having their own opinions…change in the process” (2000, p. 6). Blajer de la Garza (n.d., p. 13) holds that democratic deliberation requires open-mindedness and willingness to change one's opinion in response to others’ arguments. Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276) describes democratic decision-making as “a process of discussion…wherein others take one's views seriously and respond to one's views” and in which “each person's judgment…must be taken seriously.” And a distinguishing trait of agonistic democracy in Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–103) view is that political opponents recognize each other's claims as legitimate and worth considering as interpretations of what commitments to liberty and equality require. Mouffe (2000, p. 102) also notes that participants in democratic politics can compromise and be “converted” to each other's perspectives. We can conclude, then, that a wide range of democratic theorists (despite their other disagreements) identify respectful recognition of others’ perspectives and openness to the possibility of learning from or collaborating with others (even political opponents) as central features of democracy. Granted, democratic politics may also require more than this. Respectful relationships conducive to mutual learning and collaboration may not be sufficient for democracy. But I maintain they are necessary, and this should be an uncontroversial assumption given the range of democratic theorists who endorse some version of it. Therefore, if (as I argue) adopting the war paradigm undermines our ability to recognize such democracy-supporting relationships when they transcend national borders, it undermines our ability to recognize cross-border political activity as democratic, even when it is in fact democratic. And if (as I argue) adopting the war paradigm undermines the ability of participants in cross-border politics to maintain democracy-supporting relationships, it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become democratic—even if full democracy would require more in addition to these democracy-supporting relationships. If theorists present parties to cross-border political engagements as neatly divided enemies, with people on one side of the border dedicated to harming and destroying people on the other side, they will not likely interpret those parties as respectfully engaging with the perspectives of or being open to learning from or collaborating with people across the border. Thus, theorists who adopt the war paradigm will not likely interpret participants in cross-border politics as engaging in democratic politics. They will therefore risk overlooking or misrecognizing democratic cross-border politics if it does occur. Similarly, adopting the war paradigm will constrain how theorists see the options participants in cross-border politics face, obscuring some available options and overemphasizing others. Theorists beholden to the war paradigm will likely interpret participants as choosing among different ways of waging war—of harming their enemies—perhaps suitably constrained by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy. They will be correspondingly less likely to interpret participants as choosing among different ways of engaging in democratic politics—or even as choosing between waging war and engaging in democratic politics. The outcome of this choice (to wage war) is presupposed by the adoption of the war paradigm. In short, theorists who adopt the war paradigm interpret cross-border politics as adversarial rather than collaborative, likely overlook possibilities for collaboration and consultation among parties across borders, and can in turn fail to recognize these phenomena when they do occur. Moreover, if participants in cross-border politics adopt the war paradigm themselves, they will see those across the border as enemies they must harm and destroy—and arguably will not respectfully engage with the latter's perspectives, or be open to learning from or collaborating with them. That is, people on opposite sides of the border will not be able to engage together in democratic politics when they think of each other as enemies in this way. But this is precisely how they must think of each other when they understand their conflict in terms of the war paradigm. Gross's work illustrates these risks well. He uses the war paradigm to analyze several non-kinetic actions, grouping “armed violence, non-kinetic force, and soft power” together under the rubric of “guerrilla warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 22). He treats “civil disobedience and nonviolent resistance” (Gross, 2015, p. 31) and what he calls “media warfare” as tactics of guerilla warfare (Gross, 2015, p. 30). “Media warfare,” as he understands it, is “characterized by an aggressive campaign of public diplomacy”—or, in another formulation, aggressive efforts to “disseminate opinion-shaping information” (Gross, 2015, p. 30). To clarify, Gross does not claim every attempt to “disseminate opinion-shaping information” (or every act of civil disobedience or nonviolent resistance) is an act of guerilla war. But for the purposes of developing an ethics of insurgency, his analysis focuses on devising ethical principles to govern these activities when they are understood as guerilla warfare. Even assuming Gross only means his analysis to apply in a subset of cases (because not all public diplomacy campaigns should be understood as guerilla warfare), his work still illustrates what happens when theorists do characterize them as warfare—how this characterization can affect theorists’ normative recommendations and understandings of the options open to participants in cross-border politics. Gross's choice to characterize the kinds of non-kinetic public diplomacy he analyzes as “media warfare” (even though he leaves open the possibility that other kinds may not qualify as warfare) directly affects his assessment of how participants should behave and what reasons should guide both their behavior and theorists’ evaluation of it. To illustrate, let's apply Gross's treatment of “media warfare” to the Counterinsurgency case. Understanding the activists and journalists reporting insurgents’ claims about civilian deaths as members of civil society rather than participants in the insurgents’ war would lead one to conclude they were not legitimate targets liable to attack as soldiers would be. Gross (2015, p. 300) might agree that completely neutral “third-party journalists” deserve special protection. However, he would arguably treat non-neutral parties, like activists and “media workers affiliated with a party to the conflict,” as engaging in warfare even if they only undertook the non-kinetic activity of disseminating information about civilian deaths (Gross, 2015, p. 300). It is with reference to such partisan media workers that Gross says journalists are “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 300). (It is ambiguous how partisan one must be to forfeit “their claims to neutrality and the protection it infers” (Gross, 2015, p. 300).) Elsewhere, Gross argues journalists—it is not clear whether he means all journalists whose work benefits one party to a war or only those officially associated with a warring party—are liable to harm much like other combatants because they are “among the primary agents of media warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 269). Though the fact that they usually do not pose lethal threats to others means they usually are not liable to be killed, the fact that they pose threats as participants in a war means they are liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (Gross, 2015, p. 269). Since Gross suggests we consider even non-kinetic media operations as possible acts of war, he would seem to present journalists—at least partisan journalists, and at most any journalists consistently disseminating information that could help insurgents—as participants in insurgents’ war. Characterizing the journalists in Counterinsurgency in this way would present them as enemies of all who oppose the insurgents, thereby obscuring the possibility that they may have any number of collaborative or solidaristic relationships with their audiences around the world. More generally, because Gross understands media activity using the war paradigm's adversarial lens, he would be ill-suited to recognize such cross-border collaboration and solidarity if they occurred. If participants in cross-border politics also adopt this lens—perhaps, as Gross suggests, incarcerating journalists that spread information favorable to their “enemies”—this could prevent cross-border collaboration from occurring in the first place. Moreover, if we understand insurgents, journalists reporting their claims, and audiences receiving them as co-participants in potentially democratic politics, we might characterize the insurgents’ options and their attendant advantages and disadvantages roughly as follows: They could truthfully depict events on the ground, providing transparency to an otherwise opaque military operation and giving global publics access to the information necessary to assess and, if appropriate, democratically contest it. Alternatively, they could present information in a deceptive way without outright lying. This would still give global publics access to true information they would otherwise lack. But the insurgents’ deception would detract from transparency and from the integrity of any democratic contestation based on their claims. Finally, the insurgents could spread unambiguously false information. Although this might serve their own strategic objectives, it would do nothing to enhance transparency and would deeply undermine the integrity of any political contestation based on their claims. Gross (2015, p. 271) recognizes these alternatives, distinguishing among “white, gray, or black” propaganda based on “truths, half-truths, and lies,” respectively. But, strikingly, his assessment of what option “guerrillas” should choose has virtually nothing to do with the independent merits of disseminating true information to or enabling good-faith deliberation among global publics (as opposed to manipulating them). These things are largely absent from Gross's analysis because “the truth is a legitimate casualty of just war” (2015, p. 269). Thus, he suggests, the ethical principles that usually govern communication do not apply in the same way to guerillas, and their decisions to deceive should instead be governed largely by the rules of war, such as necessity, proportionality, and other in bello rules (Gross, 2015, pp. 30, 269). If we thought of people separated by national borders (e.g., journalists, their sources in Libya (who may also be insurgents), and their audiences around the world) as potential collaborators or partners—perhaps engaged in a joint endeavor to uncover and appropriately respond to the truth about a military operation's threat to civilians—we would see deceitful interactions among them as unequivocally bad and as undermining their ability to engage in genuine democratic deliberation with each other. Gross (2015, pp. 288–9, 292) himself recognizes how deception can undermine the informed, conscientious decision-making democratic politics requires. But, in his view, this democratic politics is only appropriate within a state: “the importance of truth telling and disclosure is strongest among compatriots. Lying to the enemy is a different issue” (Gross, 2015, p. 289). Even when acknowledging that some non-enemy international actors “have a prima facie right to know the truth,” Gross (2015, p. 290) asserts, “their right seems considerably weaker than compatriots’ rights” and their claim to be told the truth can be overridden by considerations of military necessity. According to Gross (2015, pp. 290, 298), citizens of a democratic state are vested with civic responsibilities by virtue of the social contract their state embodies, which they can only exercise if they have access to accurate information about their government's operations. This provides a powerful reason for honesty and transparency among co-citizens. But this reason does not apply across borders: While co-citizens may be entitled to honesty, transparency, and the balanced presentation of opposing views, “Enemies…deserve no such temperance” (Gross, 2015, p. 298). This ambivalence about honesty toward non-compatriots underwrites Gross's startling suggestion that it is morally irrelevant whether the information disseminated as part of “media warfare” is true. For example, discussing the footage of a young boy's death that was used to spur on Palestinians and sour public opinion toward Israel in the Second Intifada, Gross (2015, p. 285) says, “it does not matter whether the video was fabricated or authentic.” He makes the same claim about records of the “Santa Cruz massacre” that aided the East Timorese in their fight for independence, arguing it would be of little moral consequence if we discovered the incident “was a staged media event” (Gross, 2015, p. 286). Because he does not see democratic politics as something that does or should occur as part of cross-border engagement, Gross is unconcerned about the ways such deception and manipulation would undercut the collaboration and solidarity needed for democratic politics. And those who behaved as Gross suggests, readily deceiving non-compatriots whenever this was a necessary and proportional way to serve their war aims (even assuming those aims were just), would be ill-placed to develop collaborative and solidaristic relationships with the targets of their deception. Thus, Gross's characterization of journalists as warriors and information dissemination as w\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-25\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12719\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.12719","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

这种替代性范式将跨境政治的参与者视为共同政治斗争的参与者,他们不一定会寻求伤害或摧毁对手,他们可能会以战斗人员不会的方式修改他们的目标,他们的行为应该主要受政治责任原则(而不是正义战争原则或军事战略原则)的支配。此外,根据政治斗争范式,边界不需要将对手与盟友明确区分开来下面,我将更彻底地定义战争范式。然后,我认为,过度依赖它会破坏跨境政治以上述三种方式成为(并被认可为)真正民主政治场所的潜力。最后,我概述了另一种政治斗争范式,并认为采用它可以减轻与战争范式相关的民主成本。我并不是说我们永远不应该使用战争模式。也许有时我们应该承担它的民主代价。一些认为跨境政治民主化没有价值的人可能会认为战争模式的民主成本在道德上是微不足道的。我不会试图在这里为民主辩护,反对它的批评者。但是,理解采用战争模式的民主代价,是对这些代价是否值得承担做出任何可信判断的先决条件——甚至是一个值得承担的可信判断。我在这里通过说明战争范式的民主成本以及如何采用替代范式来减轻这些成本来实现这种理解。在揭示跨境政治民主化的新障碍(过度依赖战争范式)时,我的论点可能对跨国民主的支持者具有重要意义(例如,Benhabib, 2005年,2009年;Bohman, 2007),但对于任何有兴趣诚实地评估民主成本和使用一个或另一个分析框架来理解跨境政治的利益的人来说,它们仍然很重要。战争范式是对政治活动进行概念化和分析的一种特殊方式。只有当这样的活动涉及具有对立目的的行动者时,才有可能使用战争范式,所以我将假设在我讨论的所有情况下都是如此。采用战争范式来分析政治活动意味着将参与者视为陷入“一种彻底的对抗关系”(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)。Walzer在撰写不采用传统动能战(“软战争”)形式的冲突时,说明了如何将这些冲突识别为“战争”,包括将这种对抗关系作为核心特征:“‘我们’试图伤害那些试图伤害‘我们’的敌人。“在这种战争中,就像在任何其他战争中一样,战斗人员需要知道什么伤害是允许的,什么伤害是不允许的,谁可以成为目标,谁不能成为目标”(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)。Walzer在格罗斯和梅塞尔斯(2017a, p. 1)编辑的《软战争》一书中写道,该书提出了许多政治参与模式,包括“所有非动态措施,无论是有说服力的还是强制性的,包括网络战和经济制裁;媒体战和宣传,非暴力抵抗和公民不服从,抵制和“法律战”作为“战争”的形式——尽管是“软”的形式。公平地说,沃尔泽并没有主张我们应该总是把这些交战模式理解为“战争”,而是阐明了这样做的(一些)含义。他强调了当我们将一项活动归类为“战争”时所做的一些假设。也就是说,他阐明了一些隐含在战争范式下的假设,我想在这里明确说明。具体来说,沃尔泽指出,在“战争”中,每一个行动者的主要任务是伤害对方,直到他们被击败。每个行为者面临的主要规范性问题是:我给敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害是合理的(见Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)?这并不意味着这种完全对立的关系必须是政治遭遇中唯一合适的战争模式。即使是战争中的敌人也可能分享友谊、家庭关系、浪漫关系和仁慈的行为。但是选择用战争的范式来分析他们的政治活动就是选择把他们作为敌人的身份作为他们的中心身份,他们的任务是伤害他们的敌人来实现他们自己的目的,这是他们的中心任务,他们应该给敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害这是他们的中心规范困境。选择使用战争范式来分析政治活动,就是选择将政治参与者的身份、任务和规范困境(由其他(不太激进的敌对)关系定义)视为边缘。 换句话说,用战争范式来分析政治活动意味着从对抗的角度来分析。运用战争范式还涉及对应该支配政治行为者行为的原则做出某些假设,尽管它所需要的具体假设因其所扮演的角色而异。例如,对于政治理论家来说,使用战争范式涉及诉诸“正义战争”原则,如正当理由(战争应仅出于特定原因发动),最后手段(战争应仅在其他选择已用尽后发动),歧视(交战各方应仅攻击合法目标),必要性(每一场战争都应是实现合法目的所必需的),3、相称性(无论战争作为一个整体还是任何单独的战争行为,都不应造成与其所承诺的利益相比过大的损害)对于法律分析师来说,采用战争范式意味着假设行为应主要受武装冲突法(LOAC)的支配,该法“支配武装冲突期间国家、个人和非国家行为体的行为”,并且主要基于正义战争原则(Blank, 2017, pp. 90-91)。对于军事领导人来说,采用战争范式意味着假设行为应该主要受军事战略原则的支配,这也可能包括或受到正义战争原则的约束。澄清了什么是“战争范式”之后,我现在可以评估使用它来分析跨境政治混合情况下的非动力因素的成本。在质疑我们是否应该使用战争范式来分析不是字面上的战争的活动时,我同情正义的倡导者,他们认为我们不应该使用正义战争理论来分析短期战争武力的使用(见Brunstetter, 2021;Brunstetter & Braun, 2013;有关唯命是文献的回顾,请参阅Galliott, 2019)。然而,依法治罪的理论家仍然关注武力的使用。事实上,Brunstetter(2021,第8页)明确地将他的讨论局限于“涉及动能、致命力量”的行为。相反,我关注的是跨境冲突的非动力因素。因此,我的分析提供了对唯法文献的必要补充——揭示了另一个领域(混合冲突背景下的非动态交战),在这个领域中,过度依赖战争范式具有显著的缺点,并最终说明了采用替代的政治斗争范式如何减轻这些缺点。首先,运用战争范式来分析混合案例的非动态因素,包括采用——或鼓励他人采用——一种对抗性的观点,这种观点将边界两侧的参与者视为陷入彻底对抗关系的“敌人”。这反过来又破坏了民主,因为它阻碍了有利于相互学习的尊重关系的形成和承认,并关闭了跨国界团结合作的可能性。我的论点的这一部分类似于Mouffe(2000,第101-104页)的观点,即当政治对手将彼此视为“要被摧毁的敌人”(2000,第102页)时,多元民主就会受到阻碍,而当他们将彼此视为有权在政治舞台上推广自己观点的合法对手时,多元民主就会得以实现。然而,我的观点在关键方面与墨菲的不同——最重要的是,它对国际背景的关注。此外,当Mouffe(2009)考虑到她的民主理论对国际关系的影响时,她得出结论,我们应该努力建立一个“多极”世界,将其划分为不同的地区,每个地区根据自己的文化和价值观进行治理,每个地区制定自己的民主形式,所有这些都被认为是合法的。但这并没有告诉我们,超越墨菲的地区边界的政治活动是民主的,需要什么条件。这就是我在这里提出的问题。墨菲(2009,第553页)接受将世界划分为不同的“集团”,并设想当这些集团中没有一个试图将其价值观强加给其他集团时,民主是最好的。相反,我探索社会之间的间隙空间(在许多情况下是地区或“集团”之间的空间)本身如何成为民主政治的场所,以及什么可能破坏其民主潜力。同样值得注意的是,我的论点(不像墨菲的)应该被广泛的民主理论家所接受,而不仅仅是激动论者。我的论点并不依赖于任何一种民主概念——只依赖于民主存在的几个先决条件,这些条件得到了广泛的民主理论家的认可,他们主张不同的民主概念。除了使我的观点更加普世化之外,这意味着我避免了Mouffe(2009)与一些自由主义民主理论认同的陷阱——他们只承认一种民主模式是合法的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Not just war by other means: Cross‐border engagement as political struggle
Counterinsurgency: The US sends troops to Libya to fight an insurgent group. The insurgents claim the US launched an attack that failed to properly safeguard against civilian deaths. They make this claim publicly, hoping global public opinion will turn against the US and lead it to curtail its attacks, preventing further civilian (and non-civilian) deaths. Activists and media outlets pick up the story and report it around the world. I call cases like this—cross-border political engagements including both kinetic and non-kinetic elements—hybrid cases.1 It is not obvious how to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases. Should we understand them as warfare—conflicts between “enemies” locked in a “radically adversarial relationship” whose main task is to harm each other and whose main normative quandary is how much and what kind of harm they are permitted to inflict (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? Or should we understand them as some (other) kind of political struggle? The question of which analytic frame to adopt is important, as, I will argue, there are serious democratic costs associated with understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare. In Counterinsurgency, understanding civilian casualty reports made by journalists, activists, and insurgents as acts of war would mean seeing them as acts meant to cause harm (by debilitating “enemy” forces) and as strategic communications whose purpose and value were, at best, unconnected to their truth. It would mean seeing their authors as potentially liable to attack—as Gross does when he describes journalists as “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (2015, p. 300) and argues they are therefore liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (2015, p. 269). And it would mean seeing their audiences as pawns to be manipulated by propagandists. Understanding civilian casualty reports instead as part of a political struggle would mean seeing them as statements that could inform, inspire critical reflection, and form the basis of democratic deliberation and contestation—which might not be contained within the borders of a single state. It would mean seeing their authors as sources of potentially weighty claims deserving real consideration and seeing their audiences as interlocutors capable of judging and responding in good faith to those claims. Existing scholarship does not often explicitly recognize the question of whether to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare or political struggle—let alone explicitly evaluate the costs and benefits of making one choice or another.2 Nonetheless, some (e.g., Blank, 2017; Gross, 2015; Gross & Meisels, 2017a; Kittrie, 2016; Walzer, 2017) tend to treat them more like warfare, and others (e.g., Jurkevics, 2019; Miller, 2010, pp. 247–57; Miller, 2018; Valdez, 2019a, 2019b) tend to treat them more like political struggle. Here, I make explicit the implicit assumptions behind these two approaches, argue that adopting the war paradigm (understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as “warfare”) has significant democratic costs, and argue that adopting an alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate these costs. More specifically, overreliance on the war paradigm undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become—and be recognized as—a site of genuinely democratic politics. It does so in three ways. First, it presents global political actors as enemies enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii), dedicated to harming and vanquishing each other. This obscures the possibility that they might develop relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders—precisely the kinds of relationships that best enable democratic politics. Second, adopting the war paradigm encourages the assumption that participants in cross-border politics act only in the service of their war strategy—rather than to advance potentially democratic deliberation or political struggle. The prevalence of this assumption can, in turn, transform the institutions through which people participate in cross-border politics (e.g., the media)—changing them from potential catalysts for democratic politics into vehicles through which belligerents carry out their war efforts. Third, if people believe participants in cross-border politics act only to further a war strategy, they may prematurely discount participants’ legitimate moral arguments, assuming these arguments are advanced purely instrumentally. Whereas adopting the war paradigm risks incurring these democratic costs, I argue we could mitigate them by adopting the political struggle paradigm. This alternate paradigm casts participants in cross-border politics as participants in a shared political struggle who do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents, who may be open to revising their ends in response to pushback from opponents in ways combatants are not, and whose behavior should be governed primarily by principles of political responsibility (rather than, e.g., just war principles or principles of military strategy). Moreover, according to the political struggle paradigm, the border need not cleanly divide opponents from allies.3 Below, I more thoroughly define the war paradigm. I then argue that overreliance on it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become (and be recognized as) a site of genuinely democratic politics in the three ways suggested above. Finally, I outline the alternative political struggle paradigm and argue that adopting it can mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm. I do not claim that we should never use the war paradigm. Perhaps sometimes we should bear its democratic costs. Someone who sees little value in democratizing cross-border politics may judge the democratic costs of the war paradigm as morally insignificant. I will not attempt to defend democracy against its critics here. But understanding the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm is a prerequisite for making any credible judgment about whether those costs are worth bearing—even a credible judgment that they are worth bearing. I enable this understanding here by illustrating the democratic costs of the war paradigm and how adopting an alternate paradigm could mitigate them. In revealing a new obstacle to the democratization of cross-border politics (overreliance on the war paradigm), my arguments may have added significance for proponents of transnational democracy (e.g., Benhabib, 2005, 2009; Bohman, 2007), but they remain important for anyone interested in honestly assessing the democratic costs and benefits of employing one or another analytic frame to understand cross-border politics. The war paradigm is a particular way of conceptualizing and analyzing political activity. It is only plausible to use the war paradigm when such activity involves actors with opposing ends, so I will assume this is true in all the cases I discuss. Employing the war paradigm to analyze political activity means treating participants as if they are enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Writing about conflicts that do not take the form of conventional kinetic warfare (“soft war”), Walzer illustrates how identifying these conflicts as “war” involves assuming this adversarial relationship as a central feature: “‘we’ are trying to harm enemies who are trying to harm ‘us.’ And in this kind of warfare, as in any other, the combatants need to know what harms are permissible and what harms aren't, who can be targeted and who must not be targeted” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Walzer writes this in a forward to Gross and Meisels’ (2017a, p. 1) edited volume Soft War, which presents many modes of political engagement, including “all non-kinetic measures, whether persuasive or coercive, including cyber warfare and economic sanctions; media warfare and propaganda, nonviolent resistance and civil disobedience, boycotts and ‘lawfare’” as forms of “war”—albeit of the “soft” variety. In fairness to Walzer, he does not argue that we should always understand these modes of engagement as “war,” but rather articulates (some of) the implications of doing so. He highlights some of the assumptions we make when we categorize an activity as “war.” That is, he articulates some of the implicit assumptions underlying the war paradigm, which I aim to make explicit here. Specifically, Walzer notes that in “war,” the main task of each actor is to harm those on opposing sides until they are defeated. The main normative question facing each actor is: How much and what kind of harm am I justified in causing my enemies (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? This does not mean that radically adversarial relationships of this kind must be the only ones present in a political encounter for the war paradigm to be appropriate. Even enemies in war may share friendships, familial relationships, romantic relationships, and acts of mercy. But the choice to analyze their political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat their identities as enemies as their central identities, their task of harming their enemies to advance their own ends as their central task, and the normative question of how much and what kind of harm they should cause their enemies as their central normative quandary. The choice to analyze political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat political actors’ identities, tasks, and normative quandaries as defined by other (less radically adversarial) relationships as marginal. In other words, analyzing political activity using the war paradigm means analyzing it through an adversarial lens. Employing the war paradigm also involves making certain assumptions about the principles that should govern political actors’ behavior, though the specific assumptions it entails vary depending on the role one occupies. For example, for political theorists, employing the war paradigm involves appealing to “just war” principles such as just cause (wars should only be waged for specified reasons), last resort (wars should only be waged after other options have been exhausted), discrimination (warring parties should attack only legitimate targets), necessity (every war campaign should be necessary to achieve a legitimate end), and proportionality (neither the war as a whole nor any individual act of war should cause too much damage compared to the benefits it promises).4 For legal analysts, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the law of armed conflict (LOAC), which “governs the conduct of states, individuals, and non-state actors during armed conflict” and is largely based on just war principles (Blank, 2017, pp. 90–91). For military leaders, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the principles of military strategy, which may also include or be constrained by just war principles. Having clarified what the “war paradigm” is, I can now assess the costs of employing it to analyze the non-kinetic elements in hybrid cases of cross-border politics. In questioning whether we should use the war paradigm to analyze activities that are not literal warfare, I sympathize with advocates of jus ad vim, who argue we should not use just war theory to analyze the use of force-short-of-war (see Brunstetter, 2021; Brunstetter & Braun, 2013; for a review of the jus ad vim literature, see Galliott, 2019). However, jus ad vim theorists are still concerned with the use of force. Indeed, Brunstetter (2021, p. 8) explicitly limits his discussion to acts “that involve kinetic, lethal force.” Conversely, I focus on the non-kinetic elements of cross-border conflict. Thus, my analysis provides a necessary supplement to the jus ad vim literature—exposing another domain (non-kinetic engagement in the context of hybrid conflicts) in which overreliance on the war paradigm has significant disadvantages and, eventually, illustrating how adopting the alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate them. First, employing the war paradigm to analyze the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases involves adopting—or encouraging others to adopt—an adversarial point of view that casts participants on opposite sides of the border as “enemies” enmeshed in a radically adversarial relationship. This, in turn, undermines democracy by discouraging the formation and recognition of respectful relationships conducive to mutual learning and shutting down the possibility of solidaristic collaboration across borders. This part of my argument resembles Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–104) view that pluralist democracy is stymied when political opponents see each other as “enem[ies] to be destroyed” (2000, p. 102) and enabled when they see each other instead as legitimate adversaries entitled to promote their views in the political arena. However, my view differs from Mouffe's in key respects—foremost, in its focus on the international context. Moreover, when Mouffe (2009) considers the implications of her democratic theory for international relations, she concludes we should strive for a “multipolar” world divided into distinct regions, each governed according to its own culture and values, and each enacting its own form of democracy, all of which are recognized as legitimate. But this tells us nothing about what would be necessary for political activity transcending the boundaries of Mouffe's regions to be democratic. That is the question I address here. Mouffe (2009, p. 553) accepts the division of the world into distinct “blocs” and envisions democracy as best served when none of these blocs tries to impose its values on the others. Conversely, I explore how the interstitial space between societies (which in many cases will be a space between regions or “blocs”) can itself be a site of democratic politics—and what could undermine its democratic potential. It is also noteworthy that my arguments (unlike Mouffe's) should be acceptable to a wide variety of democratic theorists, not only agonists. My arguments do not rely on any one conception of democracy—only on the existence of a few preconditions for democracy, endorsed by a wide range of democratic theorists who advocate divergent conceptions of democracy. In addition to making my view more ecumenical, this means I avoid the pitfall Mouffe (2009) identifies with some liberal theories of democracy—that they admit only one model of democracy as legitimate. Though theorists disagree about the precise requirements of democratic politics, there are a few features widely considered to be necessary for democracy. First, for political contestation to be democratic, all participants must be recognized as equally capable of making valid claims potentially worthy of being taken up by other participants. A wide range of democratic theorists with varying substantive and methodological commitments, including Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276), Blajer de la Garza (n.d., p. 13), Knight and Johnson (1997, pp. 279–282), Mouffe (2000, pp. 101–104), Schwartzberg (2016), and Young (2000, pp. 9–11, 23), have treated such equality as a central feature of democracy. Recognizing participants in political contestation as equals, in turn, requires genuine, good-faith consideration of their (often competing) claims. Part of genuinely considering a claim in good faith is admitting the possibility that it may have merit, even if this would necessitate revising one's own claims. Thus, democratic politics requires respectful recognition of others’ perspectives and openness to the possibility of learning from or collaborating with others who may be on the opposite side of a salient political divide. A similarly wide range of democratic theorists identify this as a central feature of democracy. For example, Young (2000, p. 3) maintains that democratic decision-making “requires a give and take that often leads to compromise” and that in a genuine democracy, “people aim to persuade one another of…their claims, and are open to having their own opinions…change in the process” (2000, p. 6). Blajer de la Garza (n.d., p. 13) holds that democratic deliberation requires open-mindedness and willingness to change one's opinion in response to others’ arguments. Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276) describes democratic decision-making as “a process of discussion…wherein others take one's views seriously and respond to one's views” and in which “each person's judgment…must be taken seriously.” And a distinguishing trait of agonistic democracy in Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–103) view is that political opponents recognize each other's claims as legitimate and worth considering as interpretations of what commitments to liberty and equality require. Mouffe (2000, p. 102) also notes that participants in democratic politics can compromise and be “converted” to each other's perspectives. We can conclude, then, that a wide range of democratic theorists (despite their other disagreements) identify respectful recognition of others’ perspectives and openness to the possibility of learning from or collaborating with others (even political opponents) as central features of democracy. Granted, democratic politics may also require more than this. Respectful relationships conducive to mutual learning and collaboration may not be sufficient for democracy. But I maintain they are necessary, and this should be an uncontroversial assumption given the range of democratic theorists who endorse some version of it. Therefore, if (as I argue) adopting the war paradigm undermines our ability to recognize such democracy-supporting relationships when they transcend national borders, it undermines our ability to recognize cross-border political activity as democratic, even when it is in fact democratic. And if (as I argue) adopting the war paradigm undermines the ability of participants in cross-border politics to maintain democracy-supporting relationships, it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become democratic—even if full democracy would require more in addition to these democracy-supporting relationships. If theorists present parties to cross-border political engagements as neatly divided enemies, with people on one side of the border dedicated to harming and destroying people on the other side, they will not likely interpret those parties as respectfully engaging with the perspectives of or being open to learning from or collaborating with people across the border. Thus, theorists who adopt the war paradigm will not likely interpret participants in cross-border politics as engaging in democratic politics. They will therefore risk overlooking or misrecognizing democratic cross-border politics if it does occur. Similarly, adopting the war paradigm will constrain how theorists see the options participants in cross-border politics face, obscuring some available options and overemphasizing others. Theorists beholden to the war paradigm will likely interpret participants as choosing among different ways of waging war—of harming their enemies—perhaps suitably constrained by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy. They will be correspondingly less likely to interpret participants as choosing among different ways of engaging in democratic politics—or even as choosing between waging war and engaging in democratic politics. The outcome of this choice (to wage war) is presupposed by the adoption of the war paradigm. In short, theorists who adopt the war paradigm interpret cross-border politics as adversarial rather than collaborative, likely overlook possibilities for collaboration and consultation among parties across borders, and can in turn fail to recognize these phenomena when they do occur. Moreover, if participants in cross-border politics adopt the war paradigm themselves, they will see those across the border as enemies they must harm and destroy—and arguably will not respectfully engage with the latter's perspectives, or be open to learning from or collaborating with them. That is, people on opposite sides of the border will not be able to engage together in democratic politics when they think of each other as enemies in this way. But this is precisely how they must think of each other when they understand their conflict in terms of the war paradigm. Gross's work illustrates these risks well. He uses the war paradigm to analyze several non-kinetic actions, grouping “armed violence, non-kinetic force, and soft power” together under the rubric of “guerrilla warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 22). He treats “civil disobedience and nonviolent resistance” (Gross, 2015, p. 31) and what he calls “media warfare” as tactics of guerilla warfare (Gross, 2015, p. 30). “Media warfare,” as he understands it, is “characterized by an aggressive campaign of public diplomacy”—or, in another formulation, aggressive efforts to “disseminate opinion-shaping information” (Gross, 2015, p. 30). To clarify, Gross does not claim every attempt to “disseminate opinion-shaping information” (or every act of civil disobedience or nonviolent resistance) is an act of guerilla war. But for the purposes of developing an ethics of insurgency, his analysis focuses on devising ethical principles to govern these activities when they are understood as guerilla warfare. Even assuming Gross only means his analysis to apply in a subset of cases (because not all public diplomacy campaigns should be understood as guerilla warfare), his work still illustrates what happens when theorists do characterize them as warfare—how this characterization can affect theorists’ normative recommendations and understandings of the options open to participants in cross-border politics. Gross's choice to characterize the kinds of non-kinetic public diplomacy he analyzes as “media warfare” (even though he leaves open the possibility that other kinds may not qualify as warfare) directly affects his assessment of how participants should behave and what reasons should guide both their behavior and theorists’ evaluation of it. To illustrate, let's apply Gross's treatment of “media warfare” to the Counterinsurgency case. Understanding the activists and journalists reporting insurgents’ claims about civilian deaths as members of civil society rather than participants in the insurgents’ war would lead one to conclude they were not legitimate targets liable to attack as soldiers would be. Gross (2015, p. 300) might agree that completely neutral “third-party journalists” deserve special protection. However, he would arguably treat non-neutral parties, like activists and “media workers affiliated with a party to the conflict,” as engaging in warfare even if they only undertook the non-kinetic activity of disseminating information about civilian deaths (Gross, 2015, p. 300). It is with reference to such partisan media workers that Gross says journalists are “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 300). (It is ambiguous how partisan one must be to forfeit “their claims to neutrality and the protection it infers” (Gross, 2015, p. 300).) Elsewhere, Gross argues journalists—it is not clear whether he means all journalists whose work benefits one party to a war or only those officially associated with a warring party—are liable to harm much like other combatants because they are “among the primary agents of media warfare” (Gross, 2015, p. 269). Though the fact that they usually do not pose lethal threats to others means they usually are not liable to be killed, the fact that they pose threats as participants in a war means they are liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (Gross, 2015, p. 269). Since Gross suggests we consider even non-kinetic media operations as possible acts of war, he would seem to present journalists—at least partisan journalists, and at most any journalists consistently disseminating information that could help insurgents—as participants in insurgents’ war. Characterizing the journalists in Counterinsurgency in this way would present them as enemies of all who oppose the insurgents, thereby obscuring the possibility that they may have any number of collaborative or solidaristic relationships with their audiences around the world. More generally, because Gross understands media activity using the war paradigm's adversarial lens, he would be ill-suited to recognize such cross-border collaboration and solidarity if they occurred. If participants in cross-border politics also adopt this lens—perhaps, as Gross suggests, incarcerating journalists that spread information favorable to their “enemies”—this could prevent cross-border collaboration from occurring in the first place. Moreover, if we understand insurgents, journalists reporting their claims, and audiences receiving them as co-participants in potentially democratic politics, we might characterize the insurgents’ options and their attendant advantages and disadvantages roughly as follows: They could truthfully depict events on the ground, providing transparency to an otherwise opaque military operation and giving global publics access to the information necessary to assess and, if appropriate, democratically contest it. Alternatively, they could present information in a deceptive way without outright lying. This would still give global publics access to true information they would otherwise lack. But the insurgents’ deception would detract from transparency and from the integrity of any democratic contestation based on their claims. Finally, the insurgents could spread unambiguously false information. Although this might serve their own strategic objectives, it would do nothing to enhance transparency and would deeply undermine the integrity of any political contestation based on their claims. Gross (2015, p. 271) recognizes these alternatives, distinguishing among “white, gray, or black” propaganda based on “truths, half-truths, and lies,” respectively. But, strikingly, his assessment of what option “guerrillas” should choose has virtually nothing to do with the independent merits of disseminating true information to or enabling good-faith deliberation among global publics (as opposed to manipulating them). These things are largely absent from Gross's analysis because “the truth is a legitimate casualty of just war” (2015, p. 269). Thus, he suggests, the ethical principles that usually govern communication do not apply in the same way to guerillas, and their decisions to deceive should instead be governed largely by the rules of war, such as necessity, proportionality, and other in bello rules (Gross, 2015, pp. 30, 269). If we thought of people separated by national borders (e.g., journalists, their sources in Libya (who may also be insurgents), and their audiences around the world) as potential collaborators or partners—perhaps engaged in a joint endeavor to uncover and appropriately respond to the truth about a military operation's threat to civilians—we would see deceitful interactions among them as unequivocally bad and as undermining their ability to engage in genuine democratic deliberation with each other. Gross (2015, pp. 288–9, 292) himself recognizes how deception can undermine the informed, conscientious decision-making democratic politics requires. But, in his view, this democratic politics is only appropriate within a state: “the importance of truth telling and disclosure is strongest among compatriots. Lying to the enemy is a different issue” (Gross, 2015, p. 289). Even when acknowledging that some non-enemy international actors “have a prima facie right to know the truth,” Gross (2015, p. 290) asserts, “their right seems considerably weaker than compatriots’ rights” and their claim to be told the truth can be overridden by considerations of military necessity. According to Gross (2015, pp. 290, 298), citizens of a democratic state are vested with civic responsibilities by virtue of the social contract their state embodies, which they can only exercise if they have access to accurate information about their government's operations. This provides a powerful reason for honesty and transparency among co-citizens. But this reason does not apply across borders: While co-citizens may be entitled to honesty, transparency, and the balanced presentation of opposing views, “Enemies…deserve no such temperance” (Gross, 2015, p. 298). This ambivalence about honesty toward non-compatriots underwrites Gross's startling suggestion that it is morally irrelevant whether the information disseminated as part of “media warfare” is true. For example, discussing the footage of a young boy's death that was used to spur on Palestinians and sour public opinion toward Israel in the Second Intifada, Gross (2015, p. 285) says, “it does not matter whether the video was fabricated or authentic.” He makes the same claim about records of the “Santa Cruz massacre” that aided the East Timorese in their fight for independence, arguing it would be of little moral consequence if we discovered the incident “was a staged media event” (Gross, 2015, p. 286). Because he does not see democratic politics as something that does or should occur as part of cross-border engagement, Gross is unconcerned about the ways such deception and manipulation would undercut the collaboration and solidarity needed for democratic politics. And those who behaved as Gross suggests, readily deceiving non-compatriots whenever this was a necessary and proportional way to serve their war aims (even assuming those aims were just), would be ill-placed to develop collaborative and solidaristic relationships with the targets of their deception. Thus, Gross's characterization of journalists as warriors and information dissemination as w
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信