权利与善:征税权、价值创造与国际税收修辞

David R. Elkins
{"title":"权利与善:征税权、价值创造与国际税收修辞","authors":"David R. Elkins","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3615648","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"A prominent theme in the discourse of international taxation is that taxing rights should follow wealth production. Examples of current attempts to implement such a proposition include the OECD’s BEPS project and the frequently heard calls to adopt some form of international formulary apportionment.<br><br>In considering the validity of this proposition, the paper with rely on the familiar dichotomy in moral philosophy between the right and the good. In the context of international taxation, the right involves a host country's deontological claim to receive a portion of the income produced within its borders. The good involves the claim that host countries need revenue from multinational enterprises (MNEs) to fund public goods. Although the literature often conflates these two claims, they are distinct and require separate analysis. <br><br>Within the realm of the right, we must make a further distinction between two different types of right-based claims. On the one hand, a host country may assert that MNEs who choose to operate in its territory take upon themselves an implicit contractual obligation to pay tax as delineated in the host country's laws. When the host country imposes an income tax, MNEs are in effect contractually obligated to pay the host country a percentage of the income generated by their economic activity in the host country. Alternatively, the host country may assert a neo-Lockean claim to a commensurate share of the wealth that its social capital – in the broadest possible sense of the term – helped to create.<br><br>Regarding the contractual claim, I argue that the terms of the contract are in almost all cases delineated by the host country's tax legislation. In effect the host country offers a standard-from contract to foreign entities, which then signify their assent by investing or otherwise operating in the host country's territory. Consequently, if the terms of the agreement are difficult to enforce, the most obvious response would be to adopt terms that are more easily enforceable. I posit that the reason host countries do not do so is because a stricter tax regime would make it difficult to compete for international investments against countries whose tax systems are easier to manipulate. In other words, the so-called \"loopholes\" are actually part and parcel of the implicit contractual arrangement between the host country and the MNE.<br><br>The neo-Lockean argument is that creation of wealth within a country's borders is effectively a joint project involving the exploitation of the MNE's resources along with the social capital – in the broadest sense of the term – of the host country. Under neo-Lockean theory, the host country is entitled to a share of the income commensurate with its contribution to the production of that wealth, and income tax is the means by which it asserts that right. Profit shifting by MNEs understates the wealth actually created within the host country's territory and prevents the host country from claiming its fair share of that income. I contend that this argument too does not succeed. First, from the mere fact that an MNE derives wealth from its operations in the territory of a certain country, it does not necessarily follow that the host country's social capital contributes in any meaningful way to the production of that wealth. Second, even when there is reliance upon the social capital of the host country, the MNE will in most cases pay for its exploitation of the host country's social capital via factor prices (particularly salaries and rent). Third, to the extent that the positive contribution of its social capital is not reflected in factor prices, the host country should be able effectively to impose tax on foreign entities. Its desire for more MNE tax revenue than it is capable of collecting in a competitive atmosphere constitutes at least prima facia evidence that it wants more than its actual contribution to the creation of wealth.<br><br>Moving from the right to the good, it is often asserted that budgetary exigencies of host countries require that they collect taxes from MNEs and that without such revenue their ability to supply essential public good would be seriously curtailed. However, this utilitarian claim does nothing to support the proposition that taxing rights should follow the production of wealth. In allocating taxing rights under the umbrella of the good, it is needs and the capacity to meet those needs that should dictate taxing power. To which of any number countries the international tax regime should grant the power to tax a particular MNE's income in the name of the good would be a function of the extent to which granting the taxing power to any particular country would promote total human happiness. The location of wealth production is irrelevant from this perspective.<br><br>The article concludes by considering why the principle that taxing rights should follow value creation has gained such prominence in the discourse on international taxation. I speculate that what actually motivates countries is a parochial concept of the good in which the welfare of their constituents takes precedence over the welfare of others. However, as it is difficult to seek international cooperation to implement such a principle, they instead attempt to justify their position in terms of an objective principle, even if that principle ultimately lacks a normative justification.","PeriodicalId":119398,"journal":{"name":"Political Economy - Development: Fiscal & Monetary Policy eJournal","volume":"47 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2020-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Right and the Good: Taxing Rights, Value Creation, and the Rhetoric of International Taxation\",\"authors\":\"David R. Elkins\",\"doi\":\"10.2139/ssrn.3615648\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"A prominent theme in the discourse of international taxation is that taxing rights should follow wealth production. Examples of current attempts to implement such a proposition include the OECD’s BEPS project and the frequently heard calls to adopt some form of international formulary apportionment.<br><br>In considering the validity of this proposition, the paper with rely on the familiar dichotomy in moral philosophy between the right and the good. In the context of international taxation, the right involves a host country's deontological claim to receive a portion of the income produced within its borders. The good involves the claim that host countries need revenue from multinational enterprises (MNEs) to fund public goods. Although the literature often conflates these two claims, they are distinct and require separate analysis. <br><br>Within the realm of the right, we must make a further distinction between two different types of right-based claims. On the one hand, a host country may assert that MNEs who choose to operate in its territory take upon themselves an implicit contractual obligation to pay tax as delineated in the host country's laws. When the host country imposes an income tax, MNEs are in effect contractually obligated to pay the host country a percentage of the income generated by their economic activity in the host country. Alternatively, the host country may assert a neo-Lockean claim to a commensurate share of the wealth that its social capital – in the broadest possible sense of the term – helped to create.<br><br>Regarding the contractual claim, I argue that the terms of the contract are in almost all cases delineated by the host country's tax legislation. In effect the host country offers a standard-from contract to foreign entities, which then signify their assent by investing or otherwise operating in the host country's territory. Consequently, if the terms of the agreement are difficult to enforce, the most obvious response would be to adopt terms that are more easily enforceable. I posit that the reason host countries do not do so is because a stricter tax regime would make it difficult to compete for international investments against countries whose tax systems are easier to manipulate. In other words, the so-called \\\"loopholes\\\" are actually part and parcel of the implicit contractual arrangement between the host country and the MNE.<br><br>The neo-Lockean argument is that creation of wealth within a country's borders is effectively a joint project involving the exploitation of the MNE's resources along with the social capital – in the broadest sense of the term – of the host country. Under neo-Lockean theory, the host country is entitled to a share of the income commensurate with its contribution to the production of that wealth, and income tax is the means by which it asserts that right. Profit shifting by MNEs understates the wealth actually created within the host country's territory and prevents the host country from claiming its fair share of that income. I contend that this argument too does not succeed. First, from the mere fact that an MNE derives wealth from its operations in the territory of a certain country, it does not necessarily follow that the host country's social capital contributes in any meaningful way to the production of that wealth. Second, even when there is reliance upon the social capital of the host country, the MNE will in most cases pay for its exploitation of the host country's social capital via factor prices (particularly salaries and rent). Third, to the extent that the positive contribution of its social capital is not reflected in factor prices, the host country should be able effectively to impose tax on foreign entities. Its desire for more MNE tax revenue than it is capable of collecting in a competitive atmosphere constitutes at least prima facia evidence that it wants more than its actual contribution to the creation of wealth.<br><br>Moving from the right to the good, it is often asserted that budgetary exigencies of host countries require that they collect taxes from MNEs and that without such revenue their ability to supply essential public good would be seriously curtailed. However, this utilitarian claim does nothing to support the proposition that taxing rights should follow the production of wealth. In allocating taxing rights under the umbrella of the good, it is needs and the capacity to meet those needs that should dictate taxing power. To which of any number countries the international tax regime should grant the power to tax a particular MNE's income in the name of the good would be a function of the extent to which granting the taxing power to any particular country would promote total human happiness. The location of wealth production is irrelevant from this perspective.<br><br>The article concludes by considering why the principle that taxing rights should follow value creation has gained such prominence in the discourse on international taxation. I speculate that what actually motivates countries is a parochial concept of the good in which the welfare of their constituents takes precedence over the welfare of others. However, as it is difficult to seek international cooperation to implement such a principle, they instead attempt to justify their position in terms of an objective principle, even if that principle ultimately lacks a normative justification.\",\"PeriodicalId\":119398,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Political Economy - Development: Fiscal & Monetary Policy eJournal\",\"volume\":\"47 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2020-01-15\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Political Economy - Development: Fiscal & Monetary Policy eJournal\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3615648\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Political Economy - Development: Fiscal & Monetary Policy eJournal","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3615648","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在国际税收论述中,一个突出的主题是征税权应该遵循财富生产。目前尝试执行这一提议的例子包括经合发组织的BEPS项目和经常听到的要求采用某种形式的国际公式分摊办法的呼吁。在考虑这一命题的有效性时,本文将依赖于道德哲学中熟悉的权利与善的二分法。在国际税收的背景下,这种权利涉及东道国在道义上要求接收其境内产生的收入的一部分。公益涉及到东道国需要跨国企业(MNEs)的收入来资助公益的主张。虽然文献经常将这两种说法混为一谈,但它们是截然不同的,需要单独分析。在权利范围内,我们必须进一步区分两种不同类型的基于权利的主张。一方面,东道国可能会主张,选择在其领土上经营的跨国公司承担了东道国法律所规定的隐性合同义务纳税。当东道国征收所得税时,跨国公司实际上有合同义务向东道国支付其在东道国进行经济活动所产生收入的一定百分比。另一种选择是,东道国可能会主张一种新洛克式的主张,即对其社会资本(在最广泛的意义上)帮助创造的财富享有相称的份额。关于合同索赔,我认为在几乎所有情况下,合同条款都是由东道国的税收立法规定的。实际上,东道国提供了一个标准——从合同到外国实体,然后外国实体通过在东道国领土上投资或以其他方式经营来表示他们的同意。因此,如果协议的条款难以执行,最明显的反应将是采用更容易执行的条款。我认为,东道国不这样做的原因是,更严格的税收制度将使其难以与税收制度更容易操纵的国家竞争国际投资。换句话说,所谓的“漏洞”实际上是东道国与跨国公司之间隐性合同安排的重要组成部分。新洛克主义的观点是,在一国境内创造财富实际上是一个联合项目,涉及跨国公司的资源以及东道国的社会资本(在最广泛的意义上)的开发。根据新洛克理论,东道国有权获得与其对财富生产的贡献相称的收入份额,而所得税是它维护这一权利的手段。跨国公司的利润转移低估了在东道国领土内实际创造的财富,并阻止东道国要求其公平份额的收入。我认为这个论点也不成立。首先,仅仅从跨国公司从其在某一国家领土上的经营中获得财富这一事实来看,并不一定意味着东道国的社会资本以任何有意义的方式为该财富的生产做出了贡献。其次,即使依赖东道国的社会资本,跨国公司在大多数情况下也会通过要素价格(特别是工资和租金)为其对东道国社会资本的开发付出代价。第三,如果其社会资本的积极贡献没有反映在要素价格中,东道国应该能够有效地对外国实体征税。它希望跨国公司的税收超过它在竞争环境中所能征收的税收,这至少是初步证据,表明它想要的超过它对创造财富的实际贡献。从权利转到利益,经常有人断言,东道国的预算紧急情况要求它们向跨国公司征税,如果没有这种收入,它们提供基本公共利益的能力将受到严重削弱。然而,这种功利主义的主张并不能支持征税权应该随着财富的产生而产生的命题。在商品的保护伞下分配征税权时,需要和满足这些需要的能力应该决定征税权。国际税收制度应授予哪些国家以商品的名义对某一特定跨国公司的收入征税的权力,这取决于授予某一特定国家征税权力能在多大程度上促进人类的总体幸福。从这个角度来看,财富生产的地点是无关紧要的。最后,本文分析了税收权应遵循价值创造原则在国际税收论述中如此突出的原因。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
The Right and the Good: Taxing Rights, Value Creation, and the Rhetoric of International Taxation
A prominent theme in the discourse of international taxation is that taxing rights should follow wealth production. Examples of current attempts to implement such a proposition include the OECD’s BEPS project and the frequently heard calls to adopt some form of international formulary apportionment.

In considering the validity of this proposition, the paper with rely on the familiar dichotomy in moral philosophy between the right and the good. In the context of international taxation, the right involves a host country's deontological claim to receive a portion of the income produced within its borders. The good involves the claim that host countries need revenue from multinational enterprises (MNEs) to fund public goods. Although the literature often conflates these two claims, they are distinct and require separate analysis.

Within the realm of the right, we must make a further distinction between two different types of right-based claims. On the one hand, a host country may assert that MNEs who choose to operate in its territory take upon themselves an implicit contractual obligation to pay tax as delineated in the host country's laws. When the host country imposes an income tax, MNEs are in effect contractually obligated to pay the host country a percentage of the income generated by their economic activity in the host country. Alternatively, the host country may assert a neo-Lockean claim to a commensurate share of the wealth that its social capital – in the broadest possible sense of the term – helped to create.

Regarding the contractual claim, I argue that the terms of the contract are in almost all cases delineated by the host country's tax legislation. In effect the host country offers a standard-from contract to foreign entities, which then signify their assent by investing or otherwise operating in the host country's territory. Consequently, if the terms of the agreement are difficult to enforce, the most obvious response would be to adopt terms that are more easily enforceable. I posit that the reason host countries do not do so is because a stricter tax regime would make it difficult to compete for international investments against countries whose tax systems are easier to manipulate. In other words, the so-called "loopholes" are actually part and parcel of the implicit contractual arrangement between the host country and the MNE.

The neo-Lockean argument is that creation of wealth within a country's borders is effectively a joint project involving the exploitation of the MNE's resources along with the social capital – in the broadest sense of the term – of the host country. Under neo-Lockean theory, the host country is entitled to a share of the income commensurate with its contribution to the production of that wealth, and income tax is the means by which it asserts that right. Profit shifting by MNEs understates the wealth actually created within the host country's territory and prevents the host country from claiming its fair share of that income. I contend that this argument too does not succeed. First, from the mere fact that an MNE derives wealth from its operations in the territory of a certain country, it does not necessarily follow that the host country's social capital contributes in any meaningful way to the production of that wealth. Second, even when there is reliance upon the social capital of the host country, the MNE will in most cases pay for its exploitation of the host country's social capital via factor prices (particularly salaries and rent). Third, to the extent that the positive contribution of its social capital is not reflected in factor prices, the host country should be able effectively to impose tax on foreign entities. Its desire for more MNE tax revenue than it is capable of collecting in a competitive atmosphere constitutes at least prima facia evidence that it wants more than its actual contribution to the creation of wealth.

Moving from the right to the good, it is often asserted that budgetary exigencies of host countries require that they collect taxes from MNEs and that without such revenue their ability to supply essential public good would be seriously curtailed. However, this utilitarian claim does nothing to support the proposition that taxing rights should follow the production of wealth. In allocating taxing rights under the umbrella of the good, it is needs and the capacity to meet those needs that should dictate taxing power. To which of any number countries the international tax regime should grant the power to tax a particular MNE's income in the name of the good would be a function of the extent to which granting the taxing power to any particular country would promote total human happiness. The location of wealth production is irrelevant from this perspective.

The article concludes by considering why the principle that taxing rights should follow value creation has gained such prominence in the discourse on international taxation. I speculate that what actually motivates countries is a parochial concept of the good in which the welfare of their constituents takes precedence over the welfare of others. However, as it is difficult to seek international cooperation to implement such a principle, they instead attempt to justify their position in terms of an objective principle, even if that principle ultimately lacks a normative justification.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信