真理、不连贯和科学的演变

Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen
{"title":"真理、不连贯和科学的演变","authors":"Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen","doi":"10.1017/9781108653206.012","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"property. Now the key question is: What is the linguistic role of “truth” that could be used to substitute the abstract concept of truth? Sellars’s view is that for a proposition to be true, it means that it is assertible: “True is the same as semantically assertible” (Sellars 1967, 101). Brandom’s interpretation of Sellars’s position is that talk about truth is “misleading talk about what one is doing in saying something in the sense of making a statement: the use of ‘truth’ is to be understood in terms of the platitude that asserting is taking true” (Brandom 2015, 258). The Sellarsian view of truth is a form of deflationarism in something like the following way. The proper use of “true” enables one to make the following inference: from “Bob is five feet tall is true” to “Bob is five feet tall.” In order for this to work, it is necessary to understand the kinds of inferences that are warranted. Sellars’s idea is that the use of language always takes place in a frame and in the space of reasons stipulated by a specific language game and its world view. The idea of frame-dependent inferences well serves Kuhn’s request that “truth” must be able to discriminate between epistemic candidates. “Truth” thus plays a special social-discursive role and its correct application in sentences means that the inferences taken are appropriate. The focus in judging whether an inference is warranted must be determined on the basis of the inferential specifics of a framework. It may be difficult to outline a general theory of correct inferences because we are dealing with material inferences whose validity depends on non-logical vocabularies. I finish this section on truth and coherence with an illustration of legitimate or warranted and illegitimate or unwarranted semantically assertible inferences in a frame of pre-Copernican and Copernican astronomy (cf. SSR-4, 115). A pre-Copernican could say that “the yellow object in the sky is a planet is true” (pointing to the Moon), dropping “true”, and inferring therefore that “the yellow object in the sky is a planet”. In the preCopernican framework this inference is legitimate and semantically assertible. In a Copernican framework, this exemplifies faulty reasoning. A Copernican would say something like “the yellow object in the sky is a satellite is true” inferring that “the yellow object in the sky is a satellite”. Although the notion of “truth” hardly adds anything substantial, this is one way in which it can be kept as a (more or less redundant) linguistic device, quite as Kuhn required: it indicates an approval of the stated, and by extension, correct inferences maintaining truth-values constant. In conclusion, this pragmatist notion of truth allows one to discriminate between acceptable and unacceptable inferences. It also sheds light on the frameworks and on how their legitimate rules of reasoning vary in the 220 jouni-matti kuukkanen C:/ITOOLS/WMS/CUP-NEW/26474462/WORKINGFOLDER/WRAY-OPM/9781108498296C11.3D 221 [202–221] 29.12.2020 12:16AM history of science. Like Kuhn said it, there is no Archimedean platform. Finally, when this idea of truth is applied synchronically to different coexisting frameworks or lexicons of science, it becomes understandable how there can simultaneously be different and distinct truths, that is, semantically assertible statements, in disciplines despite the incoherence of the overall system of the sciences.","PeriodicalId":148089,"journal":{"name":"Interpreting Kuhn","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2021-06-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Truth, Incoherence, and the Evolution of Science\",\"authors\":\"Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen\",\"doi\":\"10.1017/9781108653206.012\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"property. Now the key question is: What is the linguistic role of “truth” that could be used to substitute the abstract concept of truth? Sellars’s view is that for a proposition to be true, it means that it is assertible: “True is the same as semantically assertible” (Sellars 1967, 101). Brandom’s interpretation of Sellars’s position is that talk about truth is “misleading talk about what one is doing in saying something in the sense of making a statement: the use of ‘truth’ is to be understood in terms of the platitude that asserting is taking true” (Brandom 2015, 258). The Sellarsian view of truth is a form of deflationarism in something like the following way. The proper use of “true” enables one to make the following inference: from “Bob is five feet tall is true” to “Bob is five feet tall.” In order for this to work, it is necessary to understand the kinds of inferences that are warranted. Sellars’s idea is that the use of language always takes place in a frame and in the space of reasons stipulated by a specific language game and its world view. The idea of frame-dependent inferences well serves Kuhn’s request that “truth” must be able to discriminate between epistemic candidates. “Truth” thus plays a special social-discursive role and its correct application in sentences means that the inferences taken are appropriate. The focus in judging whether an inference is warranted must be determined on the basis of the inferential specifics of a framework. It may be difficult to outline a general theory of correct inferences because we are dealing with material inferences whose validity depends on non-logical vocabularies. I finish this section on truth and coherence with an illustration of legitimate or warranted and illegitimate or unwarranted semantically assertible inferences in a frame of pre-Copernican and Copernican astronomy (cf. SSR-4, 115). A pre-Copernican could say that “the yellow object in the sky is a planet is true” (pointing to the Moon), dropping “true”, and inferring therefore that “the yellow object in the sky is a planet”. In the preCopernican framework this inference is legitimate and semantically assertible. In a Copernican framework, this exemplifies faulty reasoning. A Copernican would say something like “the yellow object in the sky is a satellite is true” inferring that “the yellow object in the sky is a satellite”. Although the notion of “truth” hardly adds anything substantial, this is one way in which it can be kept as a (more or less redundant) linguistic device, quite as Kuhn required: it indicates an approval of the stated, and by extension, correct inferences maintaining truth-values constant. In conclusion, this pragmatist notion of truth allows one to discriminate between acceptable and unacceptable inferences. It also sheds light on the frameworks and on how their legitimate rules of reasoning vary in the 220 jouni-matti kuukkanen C:/ITOOLS/WMS/CUP-NEW/26474462/WORKINGFOLDER/WRAY-OPM/9781108498296C11.3D 221 [202–221] 29.12.2020 12:16AM history of science. Like Kuhn said it, there is no Archimedean platform. Finally, when this idea of truth is applied synchronically to different coexisting frameworks or lexicons of science, it becomes understandable how there can simultaneously be different and distinct truths, that is, semantically assertible statements, in disciplines despite the incoherence of the overall system of the sciences.\",\"PeriodicalId\":148089,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Interpreting Kuhn\",\"volume\":\"10 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2021-06-30\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"2\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Interpreting Kuhn\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108653206.012\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Interpreting Kuhn","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108653206.012","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

摘要

财产。现在的关键问题是:“真理”的语言角色是什么,可以用来代替抽象的真理概念?Sellars的观点是,一个命题为真,就意味着它是可断言的:“真与语义上可断言的是一样的”(Sellars 1967, 101)。布兰顿对塞拉斯立场的解释是,谈论真理是“在陈述的意义上误导性地谈论一个人在做什么:“真理”的使用是根据陈词滥调来理解的,即断言是真实的”(布兰顿2015,258)。塞拉的真理观是通货紧缩主义的一种形式,大致如下。正确使用" true "可以使人做出以下推论:从" Bob是五英尺高是真的"到" Bob是五英尺高"。为了做到这一点,有必要了解有根据的各种推论。Sellars的观点是,语言的使用总是发生在特定语言游戏及其世界观所规定的框架和理性空间中。框架依赖推理的概念很好地满足了库恩的要求,即“真理”必须能够区分认知候选者。因此,“真理”起着特殊的社会话语作用,在句子中正确运用真理意味着所作的推论是恰当的。判断推理是否合理的重点必须根据框架的推理细节来确定。可能很难概括出正确推论的一般理论,因为我们处理的是材料推论,其有效性依赖于非逻辑词汇。在前哥白尼和哥白尼天文学的框架下,我用一个合理的或有根据的和不合理的或无根据的语义上可断言的推论来结束关于真理和一致性的部分(参见ssr - 4,115)。一个前哥白尼主义者可以说“天空中黄色的物体是一颗行星是真的”(指着月亮),扔下“真的”,从而推断出“天空中黄色的物体是一颗行星”。在前白尼框架中,这个推论是合法的,并且在语义上是可断言的。在哥白尼的框架中,这是错误推理的例证。哥白尼主义者会说"天空中的黄色物体是卫星"这样的话是对的,由此推断"天空中的黄色物体是卫星"。尽管“真理”的概念几乎没有增加任何实质性的东西,但这是它可以作为一种(或多或少是多余的)语言手段的一种方式,正如库恩所要求的那样:它表明了对陈述的认可,并引申为保持真值不变的正确推论。总之,这种实用主义的真理概念允许人们区分可接受和不可接受的推论。它还揭示了框架及其合理推理规则在220 jouni-matti kuukkanen C:/ITOOLS/WMS/CUP-NEW/26474462/WORKINGFOLDER/ wry - opm /9781108498296C11.3D 221 [202-221] 29.12.2020 12:16AM科学史中的变化。就像库恩说的,没有阿基米德平台。最后,当真理的概念同步应用于不同的共存框架或科学词汇时,尽管科学的整体系统不连贯,但在学科中如何同时存在不同的和不同的真理,即语义上可断言的陈述,就变得可以理解了。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Truth, Incoherence, and the Evolution of Science
property. Now the key question is: What is the linguistic role of “truth” that could be used to substitute the abstract concept of truth? Sellars’s view is that for a proposition to be true, it means that it is assertible: “True is the same as semantically assertible” (Sellars 1967, 101). Brandom’s interpretation of Sellars’s position is that talk about truth is “misleading talk about what one is doing in saying something in the sense of making a statement: the use of ‘truth’ is to be understood in terms of the platitude that asserting is taking true” (Brandom 2015, 258). The Sellarsian view of truth is a form of deflationarism in something like the following way. The proper use of “true” enables one to make the following inference: from “Bob is five feet tall is true” to “Bob is five feet tall.” In order for this to work, it is necessary to understand the kinds of inferences that are warranted. Sellars’s idea is that the use of language always takes place in a frame and in the space of reasons stipulated by a specific language game and its world view. The idea of frame-dependent inferences well serves Kuhn’s request that “truth” must be able to discriminate between epistemic candidates. “Truth” thus plays a special social-discursive role and its correct application in sentences means that the inferences taken are appropriate. The focus in judging whether an inference is warranted must be determined on the basis of the inferential specifics of a framework. It may be difficult to outline a general theory of correct inferences because we are dealing with material inferences whose validity depends on non-logical vocabularies. I finish this section on truth and coherence with an illustration of legitimate or warranted and illegitimate or unwarranted semantically assertible inferences in a frame of pre-Copernican and Copernican astronomy (cf. SSR-4, 115). A pre-Copernican could say that “the yellow object in the sky is a planet is true” (pointing to the Moon), dropping “true”, and inferring therefore that “the yellow object in the sky is a planet”. In the preCopernican framework this inference is legitimate and semantically assertible. In a Copernican framework, this exemplifies faulty reasoning. A Copernican would say something like “the yellow object in the sky is a satellite is true” inferring that “the yellow object in the sky is a satellite”. Although the notion of “truth” hardly adds anything substantial, this is one way in which it can be kept as a (more or less redundant) linguistic device, quite as Kuhn required: it indicates an approval of the stated, and by extension, correct inferences maintaining truth-values constant. In conclusion, this pragmatist notion of truth allows one to discriminate between acceptable and unacceptable inferences. It also sheds light on the frameworks and on how their legitimate rules of reasoning vary in the 220 jouni-matti kuukkanen C:/ITOOLS/WMS/CUP-NEW/26474462/WORKINGFOLDER/WRAY-OPM/9781108498296C11.3D 221 [202–221] 29.12.2020 12:16AM history of science. Like Kuhn said it, there is no Archimedean platform. Finally, when this idea of truth is applied synchronically to different coexisting frameworks or lexicons of science, it becomes understandable how there can simultaneously be different and distinct truths, that is, semantically assertible statements, in disciplines despite the incoherence of the overall system of the sciences.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信