分解、重组和定位昼夜机制:发展机制解释的三个任务

W. Bechtel, A. Abrahamsen
{"title":"分解、重组和定位昼夜机制:发展机制解释的三个任务","authors":"W. Bechtel, A. Abrahamsen","doi":"10.1515/9783110328851.177","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Success in reductionistic research in cognitive science or biology is often portrayed as eliminating any need for independent explanations at higher levels. On the standard philosophical account, successful reduction of a higher level science means that its laws can be derived from those of a lower level science and hence perform no explanatory work of their own. But this misrepresents what successful reductionistic inquiry promises or can deliver. At least in the life sciences (including cognitive science), the usual focus of reductionistic inquiry is not the discovery of laws at a lower level than some law of initial interest. Instead, investigators begin with a phenomenon and general idea of the mechanism responsible for it and seek to discover its component parts and operations and how they work together. The focus of actual reductionistic inquiry is the decomposition of mechanisms, not the derivation of laws, and the desire to understand scientific inquiry in this way has led some of us to propose and develop a new mechanistic philosophy of science. Building this new approach has required a variety of case studies of scientific inquiry. Our own most recent case is research on the circadian rhythms exhibited in numerous behaviors and physiological functions. Researchers have had considerable success with the most basic reductionistic task in this field: identifying the parts within organisms that are important to the generation of the rhythms. In mammals, it has been found that many individual neurons in the suprachiasmatic nucleus function as clocks, and that key components include genes such as Period ( Per ) and Cryptochrome ( Cry ) and the proteins PER and CRY into which they are translated. Moreover, some key operations performed by these parts are known: PER and CRY form a compound (dimer) which is transported into the nucleus and inhibits Per and Cry , hence reducing the rate of production of further molecules of PER and CRY. Reductionistic research in the last 15 years has succeeded in identifying these and many other parts of the clockworks. Such inquiry, no matter how successful it is in finding the parts and characterizing the operations they perform, does not suffice to explain circadian phenomena. The operations performed by the parts in individual cells are organized and orchestrated such that the cell functions as a unit – one that displays complex temporal dynamics. Moreover, there are operations between SCN cells that synchronize their oscillations and between SCN cells and the receptors responsive to environmental cues that entrain the clock to the local time and between SCN cells and the many bodily organs that exhibit circadian behavior. Finally, there are operations connecting the organism to the environment, especially to sources of light and temperature. None of these operations at higher levels are discovered by focusing on the operations involving genes and proteins inside SCN cells—they require tools and techniques appropriate to the level at which the operations are occurring. An especially challenging part of inquiry in the life sciences involves relating parts and operations at different levels. Within the mechanistic framework, these are best handled not by invoking notions such as top-down or bottom-up causation, but by understanding the constitutive relation between a mechanism and its component parts and operations. When the mechanism is affected by operations impinging on it, so are some of its components. Conversely, when some of its components are changed by being operated on by other components, the mechanism as a whole and the operations in which it engages are changed. The ontological picture, as exemplified in modern biology, is one in which the capacity of mechanisms to operate in their environments is explained at lower levels but the mechanisms (as wholes) interact causally with other mechanisms at higher levels. This picture iterates as one goes to even lower levels by decomposing a part of the original mechanism into its parts or to higher levels as one treats the original mechanism as a part in a yet higherlevel mechanism. There are operations at multiple levels of organization and no level is eliminated by discovering the operations within it that enable a given mechanism to interact with others at its level.","PeriodicalId":317292,"journal":{"name":"From ontos verlag: Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society - New Series","volume":"12 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2013-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"28","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"DECOMPOSING, RECOMPOSING, AND SITUATING CIRCADIAN MECHANISMS: THREE TASKS IN DEVELOPING MECHANISTIC EXPLANATIONS\",\"authors\":\"W. Bechtel, A. Abrahamsen\",\"doi\":\"10.1515/9783110328851.177\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Success in reductionistic research in cognitive science or biology is often portrayed as eliminating any need for independent explanations at higher levels. On the standard philosophical account, successful reduction of a higher level science means that its laws can be derived from those of a lower level science and hence perform no explanatory work of their own. But this misrepresents what successful reductionistic inquiry promises or can deliver. At least in the life sciences (including cognitive science), the usual focus of reductionistic inquiry is not the discovery of laws at a lower level than some law of initial interest. Instead, investigators begin with a phenomenon and general idea of the mechanism responsible for it and seek to discover its component parts and operations and how they work together. The focus of actual reductionistic inquiry is the decomposition of mechanisms, not the derivation of laws, and the desire to understand scientific inquiry in this way has led some of us to propose and develop a new mechanistic philosophy of science. Building this new approach has required a variety of case studies of scientific inquiry. Our own most recent case is research on the circadian rhythms exhibited in numerous behaviors and physiological functions. Researchers have had considerable success with the most basic reductionistic task in this field: identifying the parts within organisms that are important to the generation of the rhythms. In mammals, it has been found that many individual neurons in the suprachiasmatic nucleus function as clocks, and that key components include genes such as Period ( Per ) and Cryptochrome ( Cry ) and the proteins PER and CRY into which they are translated. Moreover, some key operations performed by these parts are known: PER and CRY form a compound (dimer) which is transported into the nucleus and inhibits Per and Cry , hence reducing the rate of production of further molecules of PER and CRY. Reductionistic research in the last 15 years has succeeded in identifying these and many other parts of the clockworks. Such inquiry, no matter how successful it is in finding the parts and characterizing the operations they perform, does not suffice to explain circadian phenomena. The operations performed by the parts in individual cells are organized and orchestrated such that the cell functions as a unit – one that displays complex temporal dynamics. Moreover, there are operations between SCN cells that synchronize their oscillations and between SCN cells and the receptors responsive to environmental cues that entrain the clock to the local time and between SCN cells and the many bodily organs that exhibit circadian behavior. Finally, there are operations connecting the organism to the environment, especially to sources of light and temperature. None of these operations at higher levels are discovered by focusing on the operations involving genes and proteins inside SCN cells—they require tools and techniques appropriate to the level at which the operations are occurring. An especially challenging part of inquiry in the life sciences involves relating parts and operations at different levels. Within the mechanistic framework, these are best handled not by invoking notions such as top-down or bottom-up causation, but by understanding the constitutive relation between a mechanism and its component parts and operations. When the mechanism is affected by operations impinging on it, so are some of its components. Conversely, when some of its components are changed by being operated on by other components, the mechanism as a whole and the operations in which it engages are changed. The ontological picture, as exemplified in modern biology, is one in which the capacity of mechanisms to operate in their environments is explained at lower levels but the mechanisms (as wholes) interact causally with other mechanisms at higher levels. This picture iterates as one goes to even lower levels by decomposing a part of the original mechanism into its parts or to higher levels as one treats the original mechanism as a part in a yet higherlevel mechanism. There are operations at multiple levels of organization and no level is eliminated by discovering the operations within it that enable a given mechanism to interact with others at its level.\",\"PeriodicalId\":317292,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"From ontos verlag: Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society - New Series\",\"volume\":\"12 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2013-11-07\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"28\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"From ontos verlag: Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society - New Series\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110328851.177\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"From ontos verlag: Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society - New Series","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110328851.177","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 28

摘要

认知科学或生物学中还原论研究的成功常常被描述为消除了在更高层次上对独立解释的任何需要。按照标准的哲学解释,对一门高级科学的成功还原意味着,它的规律可以从一门低级科学的规律中推导出来,因此它们自己没有任何解释性的工作。但这曲解了成功的还原论研究承诺或能够提供的东西。至少在生命科学(包括认知科学)中,还原论探究的通常焦点不是发现比最初感兴趣的一些规律更低层次的规律。相反,调查人员从现象和机制的一般概念开始,试图发现其组成部分和操作以及它们如何协同工作。实际还原论探究的重点是机制的分解,而不是规律的推导,以这种方式理解科学探究的愿望导致我们中的一些人提出并发展了一种新的机械科学哲学。建立这种新方法需要对科学探究进行各种各样的案例研究。我们最近的一个案例是对许多行为和生理功能中所表现出的昼夜节律的研究。研究人员在这一领域最基本的还原论任务上取得了相当大的成功:确定生物体内对节律产生重要的部分。在哺乳动物中,已经发现视交叉上核中的许多单个神经元具有时钟的功能,其关键成分包括周期(Per)和隐花色素(Cry)等基因,以及它们被翻译成的Per和Cry蛋白质。此外,这些部分执行的一些关键操作是已知的:PER和CRY形成一种化合物(二聚体),这种化合物被转运到细胞核中并抑制PER和CRY,从而降低PER和CRY进一步分子的产生速度。在过去的15年里,还原论的研究已经成功地确定了这些和许多其他部分的时钟装置。这样的调查,无论在寻找这些部件和描述它们所执行的操作方面多么成功,都不足以解释昼夜节律现象。各部分在单个细胞中执行的操作被组织和协调,使细胞作为一个单元发挥作用——一个显示复杂的时间动态的单元。此外,在SCN细胞之间存在同步振荡的操作,在SCN细胞和响应环境信号的受体之间存在操作,这些环境信号将时钟引导到当地时间,在SCN细胞和许多表现出昼夜节律行为的身体器官之间存在操作。最后,还有将有机体与环境联系起来的操作,特别是和光和温度的来源。通过关注SCN细胞内涉及基因和蛋白质的操作,没有发现这些更高水平的操作——它们需要与操作发生的水平相适应的工具和技术。在生命科学研究中,一个特别具有挑战性的部分涉及到不同层次的相关部分和操作。在机制框架中,最好不是通过调用诸如自顶向下或自底向上的因果关系之类的概念来处理这些问题,而是通过理解机制及其组成部分和操作之间的本构关系来处理。当机制受到冲击操作的影响时,它的一些组件也会受到影响。相反,当它的一些组件通过被其他组件操作而改变时,整个机制及其所从事的操作就会发生变化。就像现代生物学的例子一样,本体论是一种机制在其环境中运作的能力在较低的层次上得到解释,但机制(作为整体)与其他机制在较高的层次上产生因果关系。当人们将原始机制的一部分分解成它的各个部分时,这幅图就会迭代到更低的层次,或者当人们将原始机制作为更高层次机制的一部分时,这幅图就会迭代到更高的层次。在组织的多个层次上存在操作,并且没有任何一个层次可以通过发现允许给定机制与其层次上的其他机制进行交互的操作而被消除。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
DECOMPOSING, RECOMPOSING, AND SITUATING CIRCADIAN MECHANISMS: THREE TASKS IN DEVELOPING MECHANISTIC EXPLANATIONS
Success in reductionistic research in cognitive science or biology is often portrayed as eliminating any need for independent explanations at higher levels. On the standard philosophical account, successful reduction of a higher level science means that its laws can be derived from those of a lower level science and hence perform no explanatory work of their own. But this misrepresents what successful reductionistic inquiry promises or can deliver. At least in the life sciences (including cognitive science), the usual focus of reductionistic inquiry is not the discovery of laws at a lower level than some law of initial interest. Instead, investigators begin with a phenomenon and general idea of the mechanism responsible for it and seek to discover its component parts and operations and how they work together. The focus of actual reductionistic inquiry is the decomposition of mechanisms, not the derivation of laws, and the desire to understand scientific inquiry in this way has led some of us to propose and develop a new mechanistic philosophy of science. Building this new approach has required a variety of case studies of scientific inquiry. Our own most recent case is research on the circadian rhythms exhibited in numerous behaviors and physiological functions. Researchers have had considerable success with the most basic reductionistic task in this field: identifying the parts within organisms that are important to the generation of the rhythms. In mammals, it has been found that many individual neurons in the suprachiasmatic nucleus function as clocks, and that key components include genes such as Period ( Per ) and Cryptochrome ( Cry ) and the proteins PER and CRY into which they are translated. Moreover, some key operations performed by these parts are known: PER and CRY form a compound (dimer) which is transported into the nucleus and inhibits Per and Cry , hence reducing the rate of production of further molecules of PER and CRY. Reductionistic research in the last 15 years has succeeded in identifying these and many other parts of the clockworks. Such inquiry, no matter how successful it is in finding the parts and characterizing the operations they perform, does not suffice to explain circadian phenomena. The operations performed by the parts in individual cells are organized and orchestrated such that the cell functions as a unit – one that displays complex temporal dynamics. Moreover, there are operations between SCN cells that synchronize their oscillations and between SCN cells and the receptors responsive to environmental cues that entrain the clock to the local time and between SCN cells and the many bodily organs that exhibit circadian behavior. Finally, there are operations connecting the organism to the environment, especially to sources of light and temperature. None of these operations at higher levels are discovered by focusing on the operations involving genes and proteins inside SCN cells—they require tools and techniques appropriate to the level at which the operations are occurring. An especially challenging part of inquiry in the life sciences involves relating parts and operations at different levels. Within the mechanistic framework, these are best handled not by invoking notions such as top-down or bottom-up causation, but by understanding the constitutive relation between a mechanism and its component parts and operations. When the mechanism is affected by operations impinging on it, so are some of its components. Conversely, when some of its components are changed by being operated on by other components, the mechanism as a whole and the operations in which it engages are changed. The ontological picture, as exemplified in modern biology, is one in which the capacity of mechanisms to operate in their environments is explained at lower levels but the mechanisms (as wholes) interact causally with other mechanisms at higher levels. This picture iterates as one goes to even lower levels by decomposing a part of the original mechanism into its parts or to higher levels as one treats the original mechanism as a part in a yet higherlevel mechanism. There are operations at multiple levels of organization and no level is eliminated by discovering the operations within it that enable a given mechanism to interact with others at its level.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信