Technology, capitalism, and the social contract

IF 3.6 2区 哲学 Q2 BUSINESS
Philip Stiles, Eleanor Toye Scott, Pradeep Debata
{"title":"Technology, capitalism, and the social contract","authors":"Philip Stiles,&nbsp;Eleanor Toye Scott,&nbsp;Pradeep Debata","doi":"10.1111/beer.12567","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Capitalism is intimately bound up with technology. Societies change through advances in technology, and technology sets the boundaries for what is possible within work organisations and social institutions. Debates about the direction of capitalism emerge periodically following the introduction and uptake of new technologies (Harcourt, <span>2014</span>). The most recent candidate for generating discussion about the future of capitalism is digital technology, which includes artificial intelligence, machine learning, algorithms, and the internet of things (Brynjolfsson &amp; McAfee, <span>2014</span>). Digital technology has been placed at the heart of ‘the fourth industrial revolution’ (Schwab, <span>2017</span>). The capacity for these technologies to alter how organisations and employees work together and with it, capitalism itself, has generated a burgeoning and disparate literature. Two broad competing narratives have emerged. First, some scholars have predicted an intensification and entrenchment of capitalism. Scholars in the labour process tradition (e.g., Kellogg et al., <span>2020</span>; Thompson &amp; Briken, <span>2017</span>) have highlighted how key elements of digital technology have shifted far greater control towards the employer in the employment relationship, leading to increasing exploitation of certain groups of workers and less influence and ownership by individuals. For example, digital technology can provide, through the use of monitors or tags or sensors, the ability to track employees and bring heightened predictability and control of employees, bringing about what has been terms variously as “datafication of employment” (O'Neil, <span>2016</span>), or the “digitalisation of the worker” (Warhurst &amp; Hunt, <span>2019</span>). The complexity of new technology can also entail that employees become passive users of it, rather than being active in its development and roll out, leading to their deskilling (Bader &amp; Kaiser, <span>2019</span>; Russell, <span>2012</span>). A second theme is that digital technology has led to a “tipping point” in capitalism (Thompson, <span>2019</span>). There are two distinct aspects to this. The first concerns the possibility for new technology to reshape traditional ways of working. For example, research on “cognitive capitalism” (Hardt &amp; Negri, <span>2001</span>) has argued that technological innovation will dramatically drive down the costs of production, and knowledge will spread widely, to such an extent that capitalism will no longer be an effective economic approach, and a new social order of collaborative networks will develop, which will be characterised by greater democracy and emancipation.</p><p>The second tipping point is “post-work”. New technology raises the possibilities of greater automation and with it the likelihood of increasing unemployment. As unemployment increases, this will have a strong negative effect on consumption by individuals. Given the foundational nature of consumption for capitalism, this turn would mark a “crisis” for capitalism (Hughes &amp; Southern, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>Common to both themes is a recognition that the traditional social contract is changing. The social contract is an implicit agreement among the members of a society to cooperate for social benefits, Traditional social contracts have been characterised as a set of relations between the state, capital, and labour (Fisher, <span>2010</span>). Until now, for most jurisdictions, the social contract has been negotiated to provide a large workforce of full-time employees, relatively secure jobs, wage growth in line with productivity, and shared risk taking between employer and employee, (Manyika et al., <span>2020</span>). However, the rise of digital technology has gone hand-in-hand with the increasing globalisation of major organisations making for a greater mobility of capital and a lessening of state and labour influence (Weil, <span>2017</span>).</p><p>Recent movements such as “conscious capitalism” (Mackay &amp; Sisodia, <span>2014</span>), and the “purposeful organisation” (Mayer, <span>2018</span>) have been influential, and the concept of “inclusive capitalism” has been advocated by the Bank of England (<span>2018</span>). Within these initiatives is an implicit imperative to treat workers as more than economic assets but as social beings. There is a turn towards looking at the future of capitalism not merely from an economic point of view but also an ethical one. The central principle of such approaches in the notion of “reciprocal obligation”, rather than pure economic growth, as the basis for a cooperative world, sustainable society.</p><p>In this article, we draw on these ideas and draw out implications for the social contract from the increasing use of digital technology. We look first at the particular consequences of digital technology for the employment relationship. We then turn to the consequences for capitalism and identify three particular narratives: in entrenching of capitalism, amendments to capitalism, and post-capitalism. Our aim is to focus on current uses of digital technology and changes that are already present in the workplace and rely on empirical evidence rather than develop speculative ideas about large-scale economic and social change. We conclude with some reflection on ethics and trust.</p><p>Within capitalist society, technology is a mechanism intended to increase the generation of capital primarily through increasing automation and more rapid execution and delivery of products and services (Smith, <span>2019</span>; Thompson &amp; O'Doherty, <span>2013</span>).</p><p>For Marx, technology and society are the two forces of social production, with technology providing the force of production and society providing social relations (Marx, <span>1847/1955</span>; 1978). This perspective highlights the embedded nature of technology within the capitalist process, rather than technology being a neutral, rational mechanism that is somehow apolitical. (Fisher, <span>2010</span>). Schumpeter (<span>1942</span>) identified technology as a principal means of creative destruction. Creative destruction, which Schumpeter (<span>1942</span>) considered ‘the essential fact about capitalism’, refers to the waves of innovation on both products and processes that disrupt and replace existing practices.</p><p>Both Marx and Schumpeter believed that capitalism could not be sustained. For Marx, capitalism will reach a crisis brought about by overaccumulation, a crisis characterised by intensified exploitation of workers, a large increase in routine work, and the dramatic fall in the costs of production. A new social order, based on collaborative social principles, would be the inevitable result. For Schumpeter, there is a limit ultimately to total output and creative destruction will be unable to break through this. This will lead to a stagnation of the market and the end of capitalism (Yun, <span>2015</span>).</p><p>Both Marx and Schumpeter argue for the emancipatory significance of the dissolution of capitalism and the promise of a new social order (Adler, <span>1990</span>, <span>2001</span>).</p><p>More recently, other economists have highlighted the transformational capacities of new technology. For example, Rifkin (<span>2011</span>) and Piketty (<span>2014</span>) both predicted the decline of the labour force, rising inequalities between elite skilled workers and the vast majority who will be unemployed, and a completely changed working week. Their solution is a newsocial contract, with the development of a networked society based on mutual cooperation and not run-on capitalist lines.</p><p>Calls for the social contract to be recalibrated have emerged in response to the increasing pervasiveness of digital technology. The notion of the social contract has a long history, rooted in classic liberal philosophical tradition, including notably Hobbes (<span>2012/1651</span>), Kant (<span>1999/1797</span>), Locke (<span>1987/1689</span>), and Rousseau (<span>1973/1762</span>), and more recently in the work of contractarians such as Nozick (<span>1974</span>), Rawls (<span>1971</span>), and Scanlon (<span>1998</span>). Thought there is significant variation between forms of social contract in the literature, a common thread is that the social contract is viewed as a necessary mechanism to establish fairness of outcomes and social cohesion within a population. In economic versions of social contracts, the nation state is at the heart of any social contract (McCandless et al., <span>2018</span>). Social contracts establish the set of reciprocal obligations between the state and other key constituencies (Muggah et al., <span>2012</span>), primary among them are capital and labour.</p><p>It is important to recognise that, for many scholars, the delineation of sharp boundaries between industrial or innovation eras is crude and unreflective of widespread variations between countries, industries and fails to account for strong continuities across eras (Thompson, <span>2019</span>). Nevertheless, there does seem to be truth in the perspective that there was cohesiveness between key economic actors within national or regional boundaries in the post WW2 era (Thompson, <span>2003</span>).</p><p>The effect of digital technology on the social contract has been a major shift in risk taking away from capital towards labour. For example, the McKinsey Global Institute states that: “individuals have had to assume greater responsibility for their economic outcomes. While many have benefited from this evolution, for a significant number of individuals the changes are spurring uncertainty, pessimism, and a general loss of trust in institutions” (Manyika et al., <span>2020</span>: 1).</p><p>A number of suggestions has been put forward to restructure the social contract. Most focus on the need to induce greater reciprocity and social collaborations, and not simply economic growth and prosperity. They also include methods to reduce growing inequalities of economic and social power. In the next section, we outline some of the core consequences of digital technology for the employment relationship.</p><p>In this section, we examine certain emergent aspects of digital technology which make them highly consequential for the social contract. More specifically, we distinguish four aspects: flexibility and precarity, work intensification, autonomy, and human values.</p><p>We examine certain consequences of digital technology for the employment relationship and how this may influence the nature of capitalism. More specifically, we distinguish three consequential aspects: the entrenchment of capitalism, the amendment of capitalism, and alternatives to capitalism.</p><p>Technology tends to be conceptualised as either good vs bad, leading to the development of either a utopian or a dystopian future. The problematic assumptions underlying both these perspectives—technological determinism on the one hand, and technology as a mechanism in class struggle on the other—have produced a polarised picture of technology's role in capitalism. Such perspectives do not take into account the tensions inherent with technology and some of the contradictions that introducing technology can have both within organisations and society as a whole.</p><p>Technological innovation is made possible by the numerous decisions by a wide variety of actors, from developers and engineers to investors and managers, and through the buying choices of customers. These in turn affect, and are affected by prevailing economic and social considerations. There are human choices being made in this process about how organisations will respond to technology-related opportunities and risks.</p><p>It is clear that digital technology, together with globalisation, is changing the social contract to enable capital to move beyond the nation state, and a decline in cohesiveness with the key economic actors of society has resulted. On some views this is leading to an intensification of the pressures facing the current social contract, and a strengthening of capital with regard to labour and to the state. A different set of views call for amendments to the social contract, to counter the effects of increasing informality and non-standard forms of employment, A third perspective highlights the need for a radical social contract based on post-work scenarios, which predict ever-greater reliance on communal and cooperative activity, a much more interventionist state, and a renegotiation of social life after capitalism.</p><p>Much of the discussion about the entrenching of the capitalist model has focused on developing an increasing range of flexible (and precarious) work arrangements, rising work intensity and reducing autonomy and the ramping up of monitoring and control of workers. These practices are often situated in cost-reducing approaches and are characteristic of “finance-drive business models” (Thompson 2020). But of course, much of firms' concerns is to develop a highly talented innovative group of workers and to allow them to flourish. Again, controls can be put in place here, particularly through behavioural and affective control and the management of emotions. But as digital technology increases its reach within society, and knowledge becomes ever more significant (Adler, <span>2001</span>), the need to open up trust-based approaches rather than control-based, to the social contract, becomes more important (Glikson &amp; Wooley, <span>2020</span>). As Adler states (Adler, <span>2001</span>: 220).</p><p>“Building on many decades of research on the critical role of informal organization in innovation, community—particularly in the form of “communities of practice”—is increasingly recognized as the organizational principle most effective in generating and sharing new knowledge.”</p><p>Though this concept has a long tradition, the emphasis on “progressive” capitalism seen recently has emphasised the need to extend trust. The focus on ensuring long-term investment in human capital and increasing stakeholder power through the greater involvement of employees and customers in the running of companies would be steps forward in ensuring grater sharing of risk and reward in organisations. To reduce inequalities, government, whether national or local, would be required to intervene more to secure fair outcomes and to invest in both training and also social protections.</p><p>The emphasis on trust chimes strongly with ideas of “reciprocal obligation” (Collier, <span>2018</span>). Digital technology may be eroding the sense of mutual obligation, on which fruitful social arrangements depend. The ethical remedy is to emphasise mutual obligation and norms of reciprocity. This call also has a long history, and indeed Adam Smith's The Moral Corporation. More recently instances (Collier, the Moral Philosophers etc) have called for a move away from utilitarianism and Rawlsian conceptions of the social contract, which “individualise and reduce social obligation” towards more communitarian and socially based forms of social contract.</p><p>The so-called crisis of capitalism highlights that fact that individuals are not only workers but are also consumers, and citizens. Reflecting the new dynamic that digital technology has infused into these roles, a new social contract is necessary. There is unlikely to be a quick fix and the possibility of a radical break with the current social contract is unlikely to be sharp or decisive. Elements of the three possibilities we have discussed will likely evolve piecemeal. There will continue to be elements of competition and collaboration that are facilitated by digital technology (Fuchs, <span>2008</span>, <span>2014</span>). While technology is still often regarded in a deterministic way, and while capitalist realism seems hegemonic (Fisher, <span>2010</span>), nonetheless, other emerging possibilities are gaining ground. Determining the kind of society, we would find desirable is not solely a technological nor an economic question, but a political and an ethical one.</p><p>We confirm that there were no conflicts of interest in the writing of this article.</p>","PeriodicalId":29886,"journal":{"name":"Business Ethics the Environment & Responsibility","volume":"34 1","pages":"32-42"},"PeriodicalIF":3.6000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/beer.12567","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Business Ethics the Environment & Responsibility","FirstCategoryId":"96","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/beer.12567","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"BUSINESS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Capitalism is intimately bound up with technology. Societies change through advances in technology, and technology sets the boundaries for what is possible within work organisations and social institutions. Debates about the direction of capitalism emerge periodically following the introduction and uptake of new technologies (Harcourt, 2014). The most recent candidate for generating discussion about the future of capitalism is digital technology, which includes artificial intelligence, machine learning, algorithms, and the internet of things (Brynjolfsson & McAfee, 2014). Digital technology has been placed at the heart of ‘the fourth industrial revolution’ (Schwab, 2017). The capacity for these technologies to alter how organisations and employees work together and with it, capitalism itself, has generated a burgeoning and disparate literature. Two broad competing narratives have emerged. First, some scholars have predicted an intensification and entrenchment of capitalism. Scholars in the labour process tradition (e.g., Kellogg et al., 2020; Thompson & Briken, 2017) have highlighted how key elements of digital technology have shifted far greater control towards the employer in the employment relationship, leading to increasing exploitation of certain groups of workers and less influence and ownership by individuals. For example, digital technology can provide, through the use of monitors or tags or sensors, the ability to track employees and bring heightened predictability and control of employees, bringing about what has been terms variously as “datafication of employment” (O'Neil, 2016), or the “digitalisation of the worker” (Warhurst & Hunt, 2019). The complexity of new technology can also entail that employees become passive users of it, rather than being active in its development and roll out, leading to their deskilling (Bader & Kaiser, 2019; Russell, 2012). A second theme is that digital technology has led to a “tipping point” in capitalism (Thompson, 2019). There are two distinct aspects to this. The first concerns the possibility for new technology to reshape traditional ways of working. For example, research on “cognitive capitalism” (Hardt & Negri, 2001) has argued that technological innovation will dramatically drive down the costs of production, and knowledge will spread widely, to such an extent that capitalism will no longer be an effective economic approach, and a new social order of collaborative networks will develop, which will be characterised by greater democracy and emancipation.

The second tipping point is “post-work”. New technology raises the possibilities of greater automation and with it the likelihood of increasing unemployment. As unemployment increases, this will have a strong negative effect on consumption by individuals. Given the foundational nature of consumption for capitalism, this turn would mark a “crisis” for capitalism (Hughes & Southern, 2019).

Common to both themes is a recognition that the traditional social contract is changing. The social contract is an implicit agreement among the members of a society to cooperate for social benefits, Traditional social contracts have been characterised as a set of relations between the state, capital, and labour (Fisher, 2010). Until now, for most jurisdictions, the social contract has been negotiated to provide a large workforce of full-time employees, relatively secure jobs, wage growth in line with productivity, and shared risk taking between employer and employee, (Manyika et al., 2020). However, the rise of digital technology has gone hand-in-hand with the increasing globalisation of major organisations making for a greater mobility of capital and a lessening of state and labour influence (Weil, 2017).

Recent movements such as “conscious capitalism” (Mackay & Sisodia, 2014), and the “purposeful organisation” (Mayer, 2018) have been influential, and the concept of “inclusive capitalism” has been advocated by the Bank of England (2018). Within these initiatives is an implicit imperative to treat workers as more than economic assets but as social beings. There is a turn towards looking at the future of capitalism not merely from an economic point of view but also an ethical one. The central principle of such approaches in the notion of “reciprocal obligation”, rather than pure economic growth, as the basis for a cooperative world, sustainable society.

In this article, we draw on these ideas and draw out implications for the social contract from the increasing use of digital technology. We look first at the particular consequences of digital technology for the employment relationship. We then turn to the consequences for capitalism and identify three particular narratives: in entrenching of capitalism, amendments to capitalism, and post-capitalism. Our aim is to focus on current uses of digital technology and changes that are already present in the workplace and rely on empirical evidence rather than develop speculative ideas about large-scale economic and social change. We conclude with some reflection on ethics and trust.

Within capitalist society, technology is a mechanism intended to increase the generation of capital primarily through increasing automation and more rapid execution and delivery of products and services (Smith, 2019; Thompson & O'Doherty, 2013).

For Marx, technology and society are the two forces of social production, with technology providing the force of production and society providing social relations (Marx, 1847/1955; 1978). This perspective highlights the embedded nature of technology within the capitalist process, rather than technology being a neutral, rational mechanism that is somehow apolitical. (Fisher, 2010). Schumpeter (1942) identified technology as a principal means of creative destruction. Creative destruction, which Schumpeter (1942) considered ‘the essential fact about capitalism’, refers to the waves of innovation on both products and processes that disrupt and replace existing practices.

Both Marx and Schumpeter believed that capitalism could not be sustained. For Marx, capitalism will reach a crisis brought about by overaccumulation, a crisis characterised by intensified exploitation of workers, a large increase in routine work, and the dramatic fall in the costs of production. A new social order, based on collaborative social principles, would be the inevitable result. For Schumpeter, there is a limit ultimately to total output and creative destruction will be unable to break through this. This will lead to a stagnation of the market and the end of capitalism (Yun, 2015).

Both Marx and Schumpeter argue for the emancipatory significance of the dissolution of capitalism and the promise of a new social order (Adler, 19902001).

More recently, other economists have highlighted the transformational capacities of new technology. For example, Rifkin (2011) and Piketty (2014) both predicted the decline of the labour force, rising inequalities between elite skilled workers and the vast majority who will be unemployed, and a completely changed working week. Their solution is a newsocial contract, with the development of a networked society based on mutual cooperation and not run-on capitalist lines.

Calls for the social contract to be recalibrated have emerged in response to the increasing pervasiveness of digital technology. The notion of the social contract has a long history, rooted in classic liberal philosophical tradition, including notably Hobbes (2012/1651), Kant (1999/1797), Locke (1987/1689), and Rousseau (1973/1762), and more recently in the work of contractarians such as Nozick (1974), Rawls (1971), and Scanlon (1998). Thought there is significant variation between forms of social contract in the literature, a common thread is that the social contract is viewed as a necessary mechanism to establish fairness of outcomes and social cohesion within a population. In economic versions of social contracts, the nation state is at the heart of any social contract (McCandless et al., 2018). Social contracts establish the set of reciprocal obligations between the state and other key constituencies (Muggah et al., 2012), primary among them are capital and labour.

It is important to recognise that, for many scholars, the delineation of sharp boundaries between industrial or innovation eras is crude and unreflective of widespread variations between countries, industries and fails to account for strong continuities across eras (Thompson, 2019). Nevertheless, there does seem to be truth in the perspective that there was cohesiveness between key economic actors within national or regional boundaries in the post WW2 era (Thompson, 2003).

The effect of digital technology on the social contract has been a major shift in risk taking away from capital towards labour. For example, the McKinsey Global Institute states that: “individuals have had to assume greater responsibility for their economic outcomes. While many have benefited from this evolution, for a significant number of individuals the changes are spurring uncertainty, pessimism, and a general loss of trust in institutions” (Manyika et al., 2020: 1).

A number of suggestions has been put forward to restructure the social contract. Most focus on the need to induce greater reciprocity and social collaborations, and not simply economic growth and prosperity. They also include methods to reduce growing inequalities of economic and social power. In the next section, we outline some of the core consequences of digital technology for the employment relationship.

In this section, we examine certain emergent aspects of digital technology which make them highly consequential for the social contract. More specifically, we distinguish four aspects: flexibility and precarity, work intensification, autonomy, and human values.

We examine certain consequences of digital technology for the employment relationship and how this may influence the nature of capitalism. More specifically, we distinguish three consequential aspects: the entrenchment of capitalism, the amendment of capitalism, and alternatives to capitalism.

Technology tends to be conceptualised as either good vs bad, leading to the development of either a utopian or a dystopian future. The problematic assumptions underlying both these perspectives—technological determinism on the one hand, and technology as a mechanism in class struggle on the other—have produced a polarised picture of technology's role in capitalism. Such perspectives do not take into account the tensions inherent with technology and some of the contradictions that introducing technology can have both within organisations and society as a whole.

Technological innovation is made possible by the numerous decisions by a wide variety of actors, from developers and engineers to investors and managers, and through the buying choices of customers. These in turn affect, and are affected by prevailing economic and social considerations. There are human choices being made in this process about how organisations will respond to technology-related opportunities and risks.

It is clear that digital technology, together with globalisation, is changing the social contract to enable capital to move beyond the nation state, and a decline in cohesiveness with the key economic actors of society has resulted. On some views this is leading to an intensification of the pressures facing the current social contract, and a strengthening of capital with regard to labour and to the state. A different set of views call for amendments to the social contract, to counter the effects of increasing informality and non-standard forms of employment, A third perspective highlights the need for a radical social contract based on post-work scenarios, which predict ever-greater reliance on communal and cooperative activity, a much more interventionist state, and a renegotiation of social life after capitalism.

Much of the discussion about the entrenching of the capitalist model has focused on developing an increasing range of flexible (and precarious) work arrangements, rising work intensity and reducing autonomy and the ramping up of monitoring and control of workers. These practices are often situated in cost-reducing approaches and are characteristic of “finance-drive business models” (Thompson 2020). But of course, much of firms' concerns is to develop a highly talented innovative group of workers and to allow them to flourish. Again, controls can be put in place here, particularly through behavioural and affective control and the management of emotions. But as digital technology increases its reach within society, and knowledge becomes ever more significant (Adler, 2001), the need to open up trust-based approaches rather than control-based, to the social contract, becomes more important (Glikson & Wooley, 2020). As Adler states (Adler, 2001: 220).

“Building on many decades of research on the critical role of informal organization in innovation, community—particularly in the form of “communities of practice”—is increasingly recognized as the organizational principle most effective in generating and sharing new knowledge.”

Though this concept has a long tradition, the emphasis on “progressive” capitalism seen recently has emphasised the need to extend trust. The focus on ensuring long-term investment in human capital and increasing stakeholder power through the greater involvement of employees and customers in the running of companies would be steps forward in ensuring grater sharing of risk and reward in organisations. To reduce inequalities, government, whether national or local, would be required to intervene more to secure fair outcomes and to invest in both training and also social protections.

The emphasis on trust chimes strongly with ideas of “reciprocal obligation” (Collier, 2018). Digital technology may be eroding the sense of mutual obligation, on which fruitful social arrangements depend. The ethical remedy is to emphasise mutual obligation and norms of reciprocity. This call also has a long history, and indeed Adam Smith's The Moral Corporation. More recently instances (Collier, the Moral Philosophers etc) have called for a move away from utilitarianism and Rawlsian conceptions of the social contract, which “individualise and reduce social obligation” towards more communitarian and socially based forms of social contract.

The so-called crisis of capitalism highlights that fact that individuals are not only workers but are also consumers, and citizens. Reflecting the new dynamic that digital technology has infused into these roles, a new social contract is necessary. There is unlikely to be a quick fix and the possibility of a radical break with the current social contract is unlikely to be sharp or decisive. Elements of the three possibilities we have discussed will likely evolve piecemeal. There will continue to be elements of competition and collaboration that are facilitated by digital technology (Fuchs, 2008, 2014). While technology is still often regarded in a deterministic way, and while capitalist realism seems hegemonic (Fisher, 2010), nonetheless, other emerging possibilities are gaining ground. Determining the kind of society, we would find desirable is not solely a technological nor an economic question, but a political and an ethical one.

We confirm that there were no conflicts of interest in the writing of this article.

技术、资本主义和社会契约
资本主义与技术紧密相连。社会随着技术的进步而变化,技术为工作组织和社会机构的可能性设定了界限。随着新技术的引入和吸收,关于资本主义方向的争论会周期性地出现(Harcourt, 2014)。引发关于资本主义未来讨论的最新候选是数字技术,其中包括人工智能、机器学习、算法和物联网(Brynjolfsson &amp;McAfee, 2014)。数字技术已被置于“第四次工业革命”的核心(Schwab, 2017)。这些技术改变了组织和员工的合作方式,以及与之合作的资本主义本身的能力,催生了一种新兴的、截然不同的文学。两种相互竞争的说法已经出现。首先,一些学者预测资本主义将会加强和巩固。劳动过程传统的学者(如Kellogg等人,2020;汤普森,Briken, 2017)强调了数字技术的关键要素如何在雇佣关系中向雇主转移了更大的控制权,导致对某些工人群体的剥削增加,个人的影响力和所有权减少。例如,通过使用监视器或标签或传感器,数字技术可以提供跟踪员工的能力,并提高对员工的可预测性和控制力,从而实现各种术语的“就业数据化”(O'Neil, 2016)或“工人数字化”(Warhurst &amp;亨特,2019)。新技术的复杂性也可能导致员工成为被动的用户,而不是积极参与技术的开发和推广,从而导致他们的技能下降(Bader &amp;皇帝,2019;罗素,2012)。第二个主题是数字技术导致了资本主义的“临界点”(Thompson, 2019)。这有两个不同的方面。第一个担忧是新技术重塑传统工作方式的可能性。例如对“认知资本主义”的研究(Hardt &amp;内格里(Negri, 2001)认为,技术创新将极大地降低生产成本,知识将广泛传播,达到这样的程度,资本主义将不再是一种有效的经济方式,合作网络的新社会秩序将发展,其特点是更大的民主和解放。第二个转折点是“工作后”。新技术提高了自动化程度的可能性,随之而来的是失业率上升的可能性。随着失业率的上升,这将对个人消费产生强烈的负面影响。考虑到资本主义消费的基本性质,这种转变将标志着资本主义的“危机”(休斯& &;南部,2019)。这两个主题的共同点是认识到传统的社会契约正在发生变化。社会契约是社会成员之间为社会利益而合作的隐含协议。传统的社会契约被描述为国家、资本和劳动力之间的一组关系(Fisher, 2010)。到目前为止,对于大多数司法管辖区,社会契约已经通过谈判提供了大量的全职员工,相对安全的工作,与生产率一致的工资增长,以及雇主和雇员之间共同承担风险,(Manyika等人,2020)。然而,数字技术的兴起与主要组织的日益全球化密切相关,从而提高了资本的流动性,减少了国家和劳动力的影响(Weil, 2017)。最近的一些运动,如“有意识的资本主义”(麦凯;Sisodia, 2014)和“有目的的组织”(Mayer, 2018)已经产生了影响,“包容性资本主义”的概念已经被英格兰银行(2018)所倡导。在这些举措中,有一种隐含的必要性,即不仅要将工人视为经济资产,还要将其视为社会存在。人们开始转向不仅从经济角度,而且从伦理角度来看待资本主义的未来。这种方法的核心原则是“互惠义务”的概念,而不是纯粹的经济增长,作为合作世界、可持续社会的基础。在本文中,我们借鉴了这些观点,并从数字技术的日益使用中得出了对社会契约的影响。我们首先看看数字技术对雇佣关系的特殊影响。然后我们转向资本主义的后果,并确定三种特定的叙述:资本主义的巩固,资本主义的修正和后资本主义。 我们的目标是关注当前数字技术的使用和工作场所中已经存在的变化,并依赖于经验证据,而不是对大规模的经济和社会变革发展推测性的想法。最后,我们对道德和信任进行了一些反思。在资本主义社会中,技术是一种旨在通过提高自动化程度和更快地执行和交付产品和服务来增加资本产生的机制(Smith, 2019;汤普森,奥多尔蒂,2013)。对马克思来说,技术和社会是社会生产的两种力量,技术提供生产力,社会提供社会关系(马克思,1847/1955;1978)。这种观点强调了技术在资本主义过程中的内在本质,而不是技术是一种中立的、理性的、在某种程度上与政治无关的机制。(费舍尔,2010)。熊彼特(1942)认为技术是创造性破坏的主要手段。熊彼特(1942)认为,创造性破坏是“资本主义的基本事实”,指的是产品和流程上的创新浪潮,它们破坏和取代了现有的做法。马克思和熊彼特都认为资本主义是不可持续的。在马克思看来,资本主义将陷入一场由过度积累带来的危机,这场危机的特征是对工人的剥削加剧,日常工作的大量增加,生产成本的急剧下降。建立在协作社会原则基础上的新社会秩序将是不可避免的结果。在熊彼特看来,总产出最终是有极限的,创造性破坏将无法突破这一极限。这将导致市场停滞和资本主义的终结(Yun, 2015)。马克思和熊彼特都认为资本主义解体的解放意义和新社会秩序的承诺(阿德勒,1990,2001)。最近,其他经济学家强调了新技术的变革能力。例如,Rifkin(2011)和Piketty(2014)都预测了劳动力的减少,精英技术工人和绝大多数失业者之间的不平等加剧,以及工作周的完全改变。他们的解决方案是一种新的社会契约,发展一个基于相互合作的网络社会,而不是一成不变的资本主义路线。为了应对数字技术的日益普及,出现了重新调整社会契约的呼声。社会契约的概念有着悠久的历史,根植于经典的自由主义哲学传统,包括著名的霍布斯(2012/1651)、康德(1999/1797)、洛克(1987/1689)和卢梭(1973/1762),以及最近的契约主义者,如诺齐克(1974)、罗尔斯(1971)和斯坎伦(1998)。虽然文献中社会契约的形式存在显著差异,但一个共同的线索是,社会契约被视为在人群中建立公平结果和社会凝聚力的必要机制。在社会契约的经济版本中,民族国家是任何社会契约的核心(McCandless et al., 2018)。社会契约在国家和其他关键利益相关者之间建立了一套互惠义务(Muggah et al., 2012),其中主要是资本和劳动力。重要的是要认识到,对于许多学者来说,工业或创新时代之间的尖锐界限的划定是粗糙的,不能反映国家、行业之间的广泛差异,也不能解释不同时代之间的强烈连续性(Thompson, 2019)。然而,二战后国家或地区边界内的关键经济参与者之间存在凝聚力的观点似乎是正确的(Thompson, 2003)。数字技术对社会契约的影响是风险从资本向劳动力转移的重大转变。例如,麦肯锡全球研究所(McKinsey Global Institute)指出:“个人不得不为自己的经济成果承担更大的责任。虽然许多人从这种演变中受益,但对于相当多的个人来说,这些变化正在刺激不确定性、悲观主义和对制度的普遍丧失信任”(Manyika et al., 2020: 1)。大多数的重点是需要促进更大的互惠和社会合作,而不仅仅是经济增长和繁荣。它们还包括减少日益增长的经济和社会权力不平等的方法。在下一节中,我们将概述数字技术对雇佣关系的一些核心影响。在本节中,我们将研究数字技术的某些新兴方面,这些方面使它们对社会契约产生重大影响。 更具体地说,我们区分了四个方面:灵活性和不稳定性、工作强化、自主性和人类价值观。我们研究了数字技术对雇佣关系的某些影响,以及这可能如何影响资本主义的本质。更具体地说,我们区分了三个相应的方面:资本主义的壕沟,资本主义的修正,以及资本主义的替代品。技术往往被概念化为好与坏,导致乌托邦或反乌托邦未来的发展。这两种观点背后的有问题的假设——一方面是技术决定论,另一方面是技术作为阶级斗争的机制——产生了技术在资本主义中角色的两极分化图景。这种观点没有考虑到技术固有的紧张关系,以及引入技术在组织和整个社会内部可能产生的一些矛盾。从开发人员、工程师到投资者和管理人员,以及通过客户的购买选择,各种各样的参与者做出的众多决策使技术创新成为可能。这些因素反过来又影响到普遍存在的经济和社会因素,并受到它们的影响。在这个过程中,组织将如何应对与技术相关的机会和风险,这是人类做出的选择。很明显,数字技术与全球化一起,正在改变社会契约,使资本能够超越民族国家,从而导致与社会主要经济参与者的凝聚力下降。一些人认为,这加剧了当前社会契约所面临的压力,并加强了资本对劳动力和国家的影响。另一组不同的观点要求修改社会契约,以应对日益增加的非正式和非标准就业形式的影响。第三种观点强调需要基于后工作情景的激进社会契约,这预测了对社区和合作活动的越来越大的依赖,一个更多的干预主义国家,以及对资本主义后社会生活的重新谈判。关于资本主义模式根深蒂固的讨论,大多集中在发展越来越多的灵活(和不稳定)的工作安排,提高工作强度,减少自主权,加强对工人的监督和控制。这些做法通常处于降低成本的方法中,是“金融驱动的商业模式”的特征(Thompson 2020)。当然,很多公司关心的是培养一支极具创新才能的员工队伍,并让他们蓬勃发展。同样,可以在这里进行控制,特别是通过行为和情感控制以及情绪管理。但随着数字技术在社会中的影响力越来越大,知识变得越来越重要(Adler, 2001),对社会契约开放基于信任的方法而不是基于控制的方法变得更加重要(Glikson &amp;伍力,2020)。正如阿德勒所说(阿德勒,2001:220)。“基于对非正式组织在创新中的关键作用的数十年研究,社区——特别是以‘实践社区’的形式——越来越被认为是在产生和分享新知识方面最有效的组织原则。”尽管这一概念有着悠久的传统,但最近对“进步的”资本主义的强调强调了扩大信任的必要性。专注于确保对人力资本的长期投资,并通过员工和客户更多地参与公司运营来增强利益相关者的权力,将是确保组织内更大程度地分担风险和回报的进步。为了减少不平等,国家或地方政府都需要加大干预力度,以确保公平的结果,并在培训和社会保护方面进行投资。对信任的强调与“互惠义务”的理念非常吻合(Collier, 2018)。数字技术可能正在侵蚀富有成效的社会安排所依赖的相互义务感。道德上的补救是强调相互义务和互惠准则。这种呼吁也有很长的历史,亚当·斯密的《道德公司》也是如此。最近的例子(科利尔,道德哲学家等)呼吁远离功利主义和罗尔斯的社会契约概念,这些概念“个性化和减少社会义务”,转向更多的社区主义和基于社会的社会契约形式。所谓的资本主义危机强调了这样一个事实,即个人不仅是工人,也是消费者和公民。为了反映数字技术为这些角色注入的新活力,一种新的社会契约是必要的。 不太可能有一个快速解决方案,与当前社会契约彻底决裂的可能性也不太可能是尖锐或决定性的。我们所讨论的三种可能性的要素可能会逐渐演变。数字技术将继续促进竞争和合作的要素(Fuchs, 2008, 2014)。虽然技术仍然经常被认为是一种决定论的方式,而资本主义现实主义似乎是霸权的(Fisher, 2010),尽管如此,其他新兴的可能性正在取得进展。决定我们想要什么样的社会,不仅是一个技术或经济问题,而且是一个政治和伦理问题。我们确认在撰写本文时不存在任何利益冲突。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
5.20
自引率
19.00%
发文量
86
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信