Space, time and parsimony

IF 1.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
NOUS Pub Date : 2022-06-17 DOI:10.1111/nous.12420
Daniel Nolan
{"title":"Space, time and parsimony","authors":"Daniel Nolan","doi":"10.1111/nous.12420","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This paper argues that all of the standard theories about the divisions of space and time can benefit from, and may need to rely on, parsimony considerations. More specifically, whether spacetime is discrete, gunky or pointy, there are wildly unparsimonious rivals to standard accounts that need to be resisted by proponents of those accounts, and only parsimony considerations offer a natural way of doing that resisting. Furthermore, quantitative parsimony considerations appear to be needed in many of these cases. When scientists evaluate scientific theories, they often have to rely on many criteria besides whether the relevant theories are consistent with the evidence so far. For one thing, it is harder than it looks to have evidence flatly contradict hypotheses, especially when we remember how easy it is to chalk recalcitrant results up to noise, or experimental error, or bias, or as-yet-undiscovered factors, and the fact that our theories often only have probabilistic connections to data. For another, it is relatively easy to come up with different theories that agree on any given body of data, though many will look like mere philosophers' tricks rather than serious scientific rivals. Finally, we need theories to help tell us about tricky cases that we have not observed so far: and when we are setting up experiments or observations we are not already sure about, we want to put extra effort into testing plausible theories of the new phenomena, rather than doing undirected data collection. But this suggests that we want criteria of plausibility that help choose between theories that have not already been ruled out by the evidence we already have. Scientists do seem to use criteria such as simplicity, coherence with theories in other areas, inductive considerations, valuing explanatory hypotheses, and so on. Call criteria of theory choice like these \"theoretical virtues\". 1","PeriodicalId":48158,"journal":{"name":"NOUS","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.8000,"publicationDate":"2022-06-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"NOUS","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12420","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

This paper argues that all of the standard theories about the divisions of space and time can benefit from, and may need to rely on, parsimony considerations. More specifically, whether spacetime is discrete, gunky or pointy, there are wildly unparsimonious rivals to standard accounts that need to be resisted by proponents of those accounts, and only parsimony considerations offer a natural way of doing that resisting. Furthermore, quantitative parsimony considerations appear to be needed in many of these cases. When scientists evaluate scientific theories, they often have to rely on many criteria besides whether the relevant theories are consistent with the evidence so far. For one thing, it is harder than it looks to have evidence flatly contradict hypotheses, especially when we remember how easy it is to chalk recalcitrant results up to noise, or experimental error, or bias, or as-yet-undiscovered factors, and the fact that our theories often only have probabilistic connections to data. For another, it is relatively easy to come up with different theories that agree on any given body of data, though many will look like mere philosophers' tricks rather than serious scientific rivals. Finally, we need theories to help tell us about tricky cases that we have not observed so far: and when we are setting up experiments or observations we are not already sure about, we want to put extra effort into testing plausible theories of the new phenomena, rather than doing undirected data collection. But this suggests that we want criteria of plausibility that help choose between theories that have not already been ruled out by the evidence we already have. Scientists do seem to use criteria such as simplicity, coherence with theories in other areas, inductive considerations, valuing explanatory hypotheses, and so on. Call criteria of theory choice like these "theoretical virtues". 1
空间,时间和节俭
本文认为,所有关于空间和时间划分的标准理论都可以从简约考虑中受益,并且可能需要依赖于简约考虑。更具体地说,无论时空是离散的、粘性的还是尖的,都有一些非常不节俭的标准解释的对手,需要这些解释的支持者加以抵制,而只有节俭的考虑提供了一种自然的抵制方式。此外,在许多这种情况下,似乎需要考虑数量上的节俭。当科学家评估科学理论时,除了相关理论是否与目前的证据一致外,他们还常常要依赖许多标准。首先,要找到完全与假设相矛盾的证据,比看起来要困难得多,尤其是当我们记得,把难以驾驭的结果归结为噪音、实验错误、偏见或尚未发现的因素是多么容易的时候,以及我们的理论往往与数据只有概率联系的事实。另一方面,相对容易提出对任何给定数据一致的不同理论,尽管许多看起来只是哲学家的把戏,而不是严肃的科学竞争对手。最后,我们需要理论来帮助我们了解迄今为止尚未观察到的棘手情况:当我们正在建立我们尚未确定的实验或观察结果时,我们希望投入额外的精力来测试新现象的合理理论,而不是进行无方向的数据收集。但这表明,我们需要一个合理的标准,帮助我们在尚未被现有证据排除的理论之间做出选择。科学家们似乎确实使用诸如简单性、与其他领域理论的一致性、归纳考虑、重视解释性假设等标准。把理论选择的标准称为这些“理论美德”。1
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
NOUS
NOUS PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
5.10
自引率
4.80%
发文量
34
期刊介绍: Noûs, a premier philosophy journal, publishes articles that address the whole range of topics at the center of philosophical debate, as well as long critical studies of important books. Subscribers to Noûs also receive two prestigious annual publications at no additional cost: Philosophical Issues and Philosophical Perspectives.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信