Rethinking the right to know and the case for restorative epistemic reparation

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS
Melanie Altanian
{"title":"Rethinking the right to know and the case for restorative epistemic reparation","authors":"Melanie Altanian","doi":"10.1111/josp.12492","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In the spirit of this special issue to center on wronged individuals and groups, their account of how the wrongs should be understood and repaired, and what actions promote repair, this article focuses on individuals and groups wronged by genocide and their entitlement to <i>epistemic reparation</i> in the aftermath of genocide. I argue that epistemic reparation requires not only fulfillment of the informational needs of victims, survivors, and descendants, including access to archives, documents, and provision of knowledge about violations. In addition, taking into account the idea of <i>epistemic injuries</i>, which are part and parcel of genocidal atrocities, epistemic reparation also ought to include recognition and re-establishment of victims' epistemic standing or <i>epistemic recognition</i> in short. This insight is suggested by the fact that genocide is enabled, “justified” and even prescribed through a <i>genocidal epistemology</i>, an <i>epistemology of ignorance</i> constituted by not only the propagation of falsehoods and misinformation about social reality but also abuses of epistemic authority and epistemic authoritarianism, which systematically exclude targeted groups from the community of epistemic trust. <i>Epistemic trust</i> is the kind of trust that allows us to gain or generate knowledge and other kinds of epistemic inputs from and with others. For example, we trust that others <i>tell us the truth</i>—or at least, what they hold to be true and to not intentionally deceive us—and we trust others to <i>recognize us as</i> trustworthy epistemic contributors, or to do their best to understand our words as we intend them. To be systematically and unwarrantedly <i>epistemically distrusted</i> means to be deprived of the epistemic recognition and consequently, social uptake necessary to participate, for example, in the generation of a shared understanding of social reality and to revise misunderstandings imposed by those with dominating power—in the case at hand, genocide advocates and perpetrators. Accordingly, epistemic reparation ought to include the revision of dysfunctional epistemic practices that underlie and sustain a genocidal epistemology. This would make epistemic reparation not only instrumentally valuable insofar as it may, for example through educational and informational measures, prevent the recurrence of these wrongs, but also intrinsically valuable insofar as it re-asserts and repairs survivors and descendants’ <i>epistemic standing</i>. It provides them with epistemic recognition that has been systematically withdrawn from them, making epistemic reparation a crucial element of restorative justice.</p><p>In what follows, I start by introducing the idea of a “genocidal epistemology” based on the example of the Armenian genocide of 1915–1917. This historical genocide continues to be systematically denied by the succeeding governments of Turkey, making it a useful case study for exploring the value of epistemic reparation. The methodological impetus here is to generate insights on (restorative) justice from the negative: a case in which justice has failed and continues to fail. The underlying idea is that what matters for justice or injustice is not only knowledge but also, and perhaps more crucially, (willful) <i>ignorance</i>. I discuss how these atrocities were “justified” based on a genocidal epistemology driven by ethno-nationalist ideology grounded in both racial and religious domination. Such a genocidal epistemology is generated and maintained by practices of ignorance on behalf of perpetrators, whereby the targeted groups were not only to be distrusted morally or socially but also epistemically.<sup>1</sup> These are the background conditions against which I develop my subsequent analysis of the <i>right to know</i> and its epistemically restorative potential.</p><p>Hence, second, I address the right to know, one of the United Nations Commission on Human Rights (UNCHR) core pillars for combating impunity in the aftermath of crimes under international law, and discuss its principles through the lens of <i>epistemic correctives</i>. More specifically, I argue that these principles, in acknowledging <i>epistemic rights</i>, function as correctives against the pressure of pernicious ignorance that persists in the aftermath of such crimes on behalf of perpetrators in an attempt to achieve or maintain absolution or impunity, as well as to normalize injustice, that is, consolidate domination. I then introduce an example of historical knowledge that can be regarded as a crucial epistemic corrective against pressures of Armenian genocide disinformation: knowledge of the Ottoman tribunals that attempted to prosecute perpetrators in the aftermath of the Armenian genocide and accordingly, the crucial role of the Armenian genocide in the history of international law and the concepts of “crimes against humanity” and “genocide” in particular.</p><p>Third, I highlight that the problem of genocide denialism and thus failure of epistemic reparation is not primarily the lack of relevant historical knowledge, but the epistemic practices and processes that systematically distort, occlude, or obscure such knowledge. Based on this, I propose an account of epistemic reparation that corrects a corrupted genocidal epistemology and guards against ongoing epistemic harms toward victims-survivors as well as descendants. Not only should it go along with a provision of crucial information, evidence, and knowledge about violations, but also with epistemic recognition: While the right to know is a crucial step in the formal recognition of epistemic rights, epistemic reparation must also be rooted in a commitment to restore the victims' epistemic standing and capability of epistemic contribution.<sup>2</sup></p><p>I take these cues of focusing on the “justification of injustice” from Pauer-Studer and Velleman <span>2011</span>, who are critical of the view that Nazi crimes were <i>obvious cases of immorality</i> in the context of the Third Reich. After all, “if their immorality had been as obvious to the perpetrators as it is today, the crimes might never have occurred” (p. 330). Rather, they argue that moral reasoning could misfire on such a broad scale because morality became distorted <i>at the level of its social articulation</i>. In a social and normative context infused by Nazi ideology, perpetrators were led to mischaracterize their situation “and consequently misinterpreted and misapplied the guidelines of their conventional morality” (p. 334). Hence, perpetration was enabled through distortions at the stages of moral <i>interpretation</i> and <i>application</i>, among other things, because of misconceptions of reality provided by their social context. This can entail “empirical falsehoods about ‘[the] community's particular circumstances’ (Herman, <span>1993</span>, pp. 83–84)—for example, what Arendt called ‘the lie most effective with the whole of the German people’ (Arendt, <span>1994</span>, p. 52), namely, that Germans were engaged in a <i>Schicksalskampf</i> against a race intent on annihilating them” (Pauer-Studer and Velleman <span>2011</span>, p. 352). Such empirical distortions were accompanied by normative distortions. Perpetrators considered their actions morally justified, because “moral principles were filtered through socially conditioned interpretations and perceptions that gave events a distorted normative significance” (p. 340). This was the case, for example, when the gassing of Jews was viewed by the medical staff as “humanitarian treatment for people who were going to die one way or another” (p. 345) and that it was a humane way of saving them from typhus epidemics, illustrating a distorted medical code of ethics.</p><p>It is commonly argued—and most evident in the case of the Nazi genocide of European Jewry, as mentioned above—that genocides are based on a very effective lie supported by conspiracy propaganda on behalf of the perpetrating group, namely that the targeted group presents an existential threat intent on annihilating them. The threat posed by the targeted group is exaggerated, often through their assimilation into a much more powerful enemy. In the case of Armenians, for example, the enemy of Western or Russian imperialist powers. However, the justification of genocide and its inherent denialism (of wrongdoing) consists of more than systematic disinformation, the spread of empirical falsehoods, or propagandistic lies about a community's particular circumstances. Unlike lying, <i>denying</i> precludes the acceptance of certain truths or facts. It rather points to a motivated, “active effort not to see, no matter what the evidence may be; as a result of constant distortion and redescription” (Medina, <span>2013</span>, p. 35) of the injustice.</p><p>Drawing on these insights, the “justification of genocide” is conditional upon the active or willful exclusion of targeted groups from the community of epistemic trust. Their exclusion from practices that generate shared knowledge and understanding of social reality and in particular, social grievances, enables the generation and maintenance of <i>willful ignorance</i> required for complicity and perpetration. In the following, I apply these insights to the case of the Armenian genocide. My main focus will be on the overarching, institutionalized ideology and social and normative system whereby ruling authorities could cultivate and impose a way of (un)knowing based on which perpetration could be broadly enabled, rationalized, and justified, granting not only the success of the genocide but also its long-term denialism.<sup>4</sup></p><p>The UNCHR acknowledges the <i>right to know</i>, alongside the <i>right to justice</i>, the <i>right to reparation</i> and <i>guarantees of non-recurrence</i>, as a central pillar of a “holistic” approach to transitional justice, hence a state's obligation to combat impunity and thereby protect and promote human rights in the aftermath of “serious crimes under international law.”<sup>13</sup> This means that they are not to be seen as rights and principles that can be addressed in isolation from one another. Rather, they depend on one another to achieve justice. For example, so-called “symbolic” reparations alone—such as political apologies—are not sufficient if they are not accompanied by real institutional reforms and transformations that address and repair the unjust material conditions in order to achieve full moral repair and make recurrence of social violence less likely. Further, educational measures such as the establishment of memorials and museums can be used to misinform and mislead the public if they are not properly based on respect for victims' epistemic rights; such as if they disregard crucial insights generated by those who experienced the injustice, or focus exclusively on victimhood without acknowledging the responsibility of perpetrators and conditions of perpetration. Moreover, legal prosecution and punishment of individual perpetrators will be insufficient to address and repair the systematic, social, and structural conditions that enabled vast societal complicity and support for such atrocities.</p><p>I take these to be some of the pressures (towards failure) that the GP of the right to know seek address and correct. I now introduce an example of historical knowledge particularly relevant to resist some of the pressures of pernicious ignorance in relation to the Armenian genocide. Such is the knowledge of the Ottoman tribunals that attempted to prosecute perpetrators in its aftermath and the crucial role of the Armenian genocide in the history of international law and the concepts of “crimes against humanity” and “genocide” in particular.</p><p>In what follows, I introduce a further dimension or type of recognition harm, namely <i>epistemic recognition harm</i>. This is rooted in the idea promoted by recent scholarship on epistemic injustice that we also stand in reciprocal relations of <i>epistemic recognition</i> with others and that there can be conditions or situations that render such relations seriously dysfunctional and harmful. The proposal here then, complementing Tirrell's aforementioned account, is to bring victims back into the human community through recognition of their <i>epistemic standing</i> and provision of the social uptake necessary for their <i>Capability of Epistemic Contribution</i> (Fricker, <span>2015</span>). Fricker defines this as a “social epistemic capability on the part of the individual to contribute to the pool of shared epistemic materials—materials for knowledge, understanding, and very often for practical deliberation” (p. 76). Acknowledging such a central human capability and thus, what may ground particular epistemic rights<sup>17</sup> introduces us to a further form of violence enacted or delivered through discursive behaviors, namely <i>epistemic violence</i>. This is defined by Dotson as “the failure, owing to pernicious ignorance, of hearers to meet the vulnerabilities of speakers in linguistic exchanges” (Dotson, <span>2011</span>, p. 238). Epistemic violence not only points to epistemic rights violations we may encounter in epistemically relevant linguistic exchanges such as testimony, but also its enabling background conditions, namely pernicious reliable ignorance. Indeed, a genocidal epistemology requires and is reinforced by the systematic violation and disablement of victims' capability of epistemic contribution. Let us now hone in on the relationship between ignorance, power, and the idea of restorative epistemic reparation.</p><p>While we often say “knowledge is power,” one might assume that ignorance—understood as lack of knowledge—disempowers. However, whether or not ignorance disempowers and <i>whom</i> it disempowers depends not only on the subject matter, but also on the kind of ignorance we are dealing with. We need to ask: Who is ignorant with regard to what subject matter and might such ignorance in fact be willfully and perniciously generated and maintained based on flawed cognitive norms and motives—for example, in order to defend and protect dominant privilege? Moreover, the other side of this coin is of course that those who carry threatening knowledge—such as knowledge of oppression—are intentionally disempowered. They are indeed rendered <i>powerless knowers</i>. Note that by “threatening knowledge” I mean knowledge that threatens a status quo characterized by unjust power relations. Take the case of genocide and its aftermath. Genocide consolidates domination of the perpetrating party, including the normalizing understandings related to the injustice, which serve to defend and protect dominant privilege. Such ignorance, then, is not to be understood merely in terms of an absence of knowledge (i.e., propositional ignorance), but also as substantive epistemic practice, a problem of <i>ignorant agency</i> guided by particular attitudes, cognitive norms, and evidential policies.</p><p>This shifts our analytical focus to the constitutive elements of ignorant agency; the structural social conditions that produce identities, social locations, and modes of belief formation, which become epistemically disadvantageous or defective (Alcoff, <span>2007</span>, p. 40). This is most evidently the case under structural social conditions of domination and oppression, which tend to cultivate various <i>epistemic vices</i> on behalf of dominantly situated epistemic subjects. These may include <i>epistemic laziness</i>, <i>arrogance</i>, <i>and closed-mindedness</i> with regard, especially to matters pertaining to practices of social violence (Medina, <span>2013</span>, p. 35). Such cultivated inattention and insensitivity to social violence and the stigmatizing prejudices that enable it are constitutive of the kind of active or willful ignorance produced by oppressive and particularly genocidal systems. It provides perpetrators with a particular perception and interpretations that give their actions distorted meaning; and it is essential to such ignorance that it devalues, excludes, and misrecognizes epistemic contributions provided by the victims. Hence, without addressing the genocidal epistemology and the willful ignorance that sustains it, denialism will continue to have a robust basis and remain a source of epistemic harm to victims, survivors, and descendants. It is against this background that we should formulate the need for and scope of epistemic rights and restorative epistemic reparation.</p><p>The underlying assumption here is that impunity in the aftermath of injustice, hence a failure of our ideal of transitional justice, is the norm rather than the exception and it is maintained by denialism—in the form of justification, rationalization, relativization, or trivialization of the injustice (Hovannisian, <span>1999</span>). Granted these existing pressures posed by cultures of impunity and the ignorant agency they cultivate, the right to know can plausibly be understood as an epistemic corrective. It guards against common efforts to distort, obscure, and obliterate knowledge about perpetrated injustices, which requires the ongoing exclusion or discrediting of victims' epistemic contributions. As it is formulated now, however, the right to know mainly considers entitlements to information and knowledge that are of particular moral, social and political relevance to victim-survivors and descendants. Providing access to epistemic goods such as information and knowledge about violations is not sufficient for <i>restorative</i> epistemic reparation. A further requirement is the revision of unjust epistemic practices and relations through which a genocidal epistemology was generated and maintained—essentially based on the systematic withdrawal of epistemic recognition from victims. Theories of active or willful ignorance show that there can exist epistemically substantive flaws in the very epistemic practices in need of reparation. To restore the victims' epistemic standing against this background, they need to be recognized as <i>authoritative contributors to the common pool of epistemic resources based on which knowledge and understanding of the injustice are generated</i>. This ensures that victims are indeed acknowledged as authoritative epistemic contributors and not only receivers of evidence and knowledge about violation and injustice. In short, one could say that the <i>right to know</i> (as the right to certain knowledge or other epistemic resources) should be extended in its scope to include the right <i>to be recognized as a knower</i> (as the right to epistemic contribution). I shall briefly elaborate on this idea in the remainder of this paper.</p><p>Acknowledging epistemic rights, or the “general idea that human wellbeing has an epistemic dimension” depends, according to Fricker (<span>2015</span>, p. 76), “on the idea that functioning not only as a receiver but also as a giver of epistemic materials is an aspect of human subjectivity that craves social expression through the capability to contribute beliefs and interpretations to the local epistemic economy.” If we accept this idea, epistemic reparation measures and policies ought to consider not only the right to receive epistemic materials, but to participate in their generation. Hence, it must be ensured that victims receive the social uptake required for rehabilitation of their capability of epistemic contribution, that is, their “enjoyment of epistemic relational equality” (Fricker, <span>2015</span>, p. 87). As already mentioned, a genocidal epistemology is generated and maintained based on the systematic, unwarranted exclusion or rejection of the epistemic contributions of the marginalized and victimized. In the context of the Armenian genocide and the preceding persecutions, Armenians and their intellectual contributions, social grievances and struggles, demands for reform, and resistance movement were persistently ignored, demonized, misrepresented, and violently suppressed by Ottoman authorities. Without properly addressing such misconceptions constituting genocidal epistemologies, they will continue to provide fertile ground for practices of silencing. Survivors and descendants will continue to be deprived of the social uptake needed for their capability of epistemic contribution, thereby subjecting them to ongoing testimonial and hermeneutical injustice (as I have argued elsewhere, e.g., Altanian, <span>2021a</span>, <span>2021b</span>).</p><p>Restorative epistemic reparation is thus not only instrumentally valuable insofar as it might prevent the recurrence of wrongs, but intrinsically valuable, insofar as it re-asserts and repairs survivors' and descendants' epistemic relational equality. Applying these insights to the three GP of the right to know suggests the following, extended formulations of a state's corresponding epistemic duties for combating impunity. Recall that (GP 1) pertains to the justificatory framework of a genocidal epistemology. For (GP 1) to be epistemically restorative, it ought to entail a duty to recognize victims' epistemic contributions in correcting the distorted epistemology based on which genocide perpetration was justified. (GP 2) pertains to collective memory. For it to be epistemically restorative, it ought to entail a duty to recognize the victim group's epistemic contributions, particularly to the societal practice of giving meaning to the past. (GP 3) pertains to individuals and their families right to certain kinds of knowledge, in recognition of their informational needs that carry crucial personal and moral value. Re-integrating victims-survivors in the generation of knowledge and understandings of the circumstances of perpetration and in generating meaning about what happened is crucial to help them maintain intellectual courage and epistemic self-confidence, ultimately, in order for them to indeed keep their knowledge and memory crucial for personhood. To a certain extent, (GP2) acknowledges the victim group's epistemic authority in relation to its (historical) experiences of injustice, by stating that “[a] people's knowledge of the history of its oppression is part of its heritage and, as such, must be ensured by appropriate measures in fulfillment of the State's duty to preserve archives and other evidence concerning violations of human rights and humanitarian law and to facilitate knowledge of those violations.” However, it still falls short of explicitly recognizing their status as authoritative epistemic contributors—of evidence, archives, and other epistemic resources—required for knowledge and understanding of those violations and the collective memory based on it.<sup>18</sup></p><p>In order to repair and resist the epistemically unjust legacies of a genocidal epistemology, these epistemic contributions have to be particularly recognized by representatives of the perpetrating group. Drawing on Margaret Urban Walker's notion of “making amends,” which refers to perpetrators' attempts to make things right, Almassi (<span>2018</span>, p. 10) conceives of such epistemic reparation-qua-amends not in terms of compensation, but “acts of demonstration that underwrite processes of relational repair in accordance with victims' perspectives and priorities.” Epistemic amends enable victims to trust that “they will be believed, understood, properly interpreted […] which is why prioritization of victim subjectivities is so crucial for determining the actions and outcomes needed to make amends after the perpetration, experience, and acknowledgement of epistemic injustice.” (ibid.) Thus, reparation of epistemic injustices inherent in the perpetration of genocide requires centering victims' situatedness and epistemic resources developed from such situatedness. Campbell (<span>2014</span>, p. 165) convincingly showed in her analysis of challenges faced by Truth and Reconciliation Commissions (TRC) in Settler societies like the Canadian Indian Residential Schools (IRS TRC) that in order for it to fulfill its commitment to supporting the establishment of “new relations embedded in mutual recognition and respect,” one should first identify the disrespectful challenges and contestations of memory and testimony that survivors face when remembering and sharing their experiences or histories. To provide them with due epistemic recognition requires becoming aware of and correcting for the legacy of colonialism through disrespectful challenges to memories and perspectives that they continue to face, hence the legacy of unequal moral and social-political, as well as epistemic standing. Campbell's analysis helps us see that even if epistemically restorative measures such as TRCs are implemented, the testimonies of victim-survivors do not meet a prior epistemic gap, or interpretive “terra incognita.” Instead, they bump into existing myths and narratives that “rationalize continued unequal treatment of those formerly colonized” (ibid.). One upshot of this is that their testimony will tend to be met with default skepticism and diminished credibility, in virtue of their already socially marginalized position. Hence, acknowledgment of different and in particular, oppressed “epistemic standpoints” (Harding, <span>1993</span>), situated knowledge (and ignorance) and the legacy of genocidal epistemologies that continue to shape unequal epistemic relations is necessary for restorative epistemic justice in the aftermath of colonial and imperial atrocities, including genocides.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"55 4","pages":"728-745"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2022-09-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12492","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12492","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

In the spirit of this special issue to center on wronged individuals and groups, their account of how the wrongs should be understood and repaired, and what actions promote repair, this article focuses on individuals and groups wronged by genocide and their entitlement to epistemic reparation in the aftermath of genocide. I argue that epistemic reparation requires not only fulfillment of the informational needs of victims, survivors, and descendants, including access to archives, documents, and provision of knowledge about violations. In addition, taking into account the idea of epistemic injuries, which are part and parcel of genocidal atrocities, epistemic reparation also ought to include recognition and re-establishment of victims' epistemic standing or epistemic recognition in short. This insight is suggested by the fact that genocide is enabled, “justified” and even prescribed through a genocidal epistemology, an epistemology of ignorance constituted by not only the propagation of falsehoods and misinformation about social reality but also abuses of epistemic authority and epistemic authoritarianism, which systematically exclude targeted groups from the community of epistemic trust. Epistemic trust is the kind of trust that allows us to gain or generate knowledge and other kinds of epistemic inputs from and with others. For example, we trust that others tell us the truth—or at least, what they hold to be true and to not intentionally deceive us—and we trust others to recognize us as trustworthy epistemic contributors, or to do their best to understand our words as we intend them. To be systematically and unwarrantedly epistemically distrusted means to be deprived of the epistemic recognition and consequently, social uptake necessary to participate, for example, in the generation of a shared understanding of social reality and to revise misunderstandings imposed by those with dominating power—in the case at hand, genocide advocates and perpetrators. Accordingly, epistemic reparation ought to include the revision of dysfunctional epistemic practices that underlie and sustain a genocidal epistemology. This would make epistemic reparation not only instrumentally valuable insofar as it may, for example through educational and informational measures, prevent the recurrence of these wrongs, but also intrinsically valuable insofar as it re-asserts and repairs survivors and descendants’ epistemic standing. It provides them with epistemic recognition that has been systematically withdrawn from them, making epistemic reparation a crucial element of restorative justice.

In what follows, I start by introducing the idea of a “genocidal epistemology” based on the example of the Armenian genocide of 1915–1917. This historical genocide continues to be systematically denied by the succeeding governments of Turkey, making it a useful case study for exploring the value of epistemic reparation. The methodological impetus here is to generate insights on (restorative) justice from the negative: a case in which justice has failed and continues to fail. The underlying idea is that what matters for justice or injustice is not only knowledge but also, and perhaps more crucially, (willful) ignorance. I discuss how these atrocities were “justified” based on a genocidal epistemology driven by ethno-nationalist ideology grounded in both racial and religious domination. Such a genocidal epistemology is generated and maintained by practices of ignorance on behalf of perpetrators, whereby the targeted groups were not only to be distrusted morally or socially but also epistemically.1 These are the background conditions against which I develop my subsequent analysis of the right to know and its epistemically restorative potential.

Hence, second, I address the right to know, one of the United Nations Commission on Human Rights (UNCHR) core pillars for combating impunity in the aftermath of crimes under international law, and discuss its principles through the lens of epistemic correctives. More specifically, I argue that these principles, in acknowledging epistemic rights, function as correctives against the pressure of pernicious ignorance that persists in the aftermath of such crimes on behalf of perpetrators in an attempt to achieve or maintain absolution or impunity, as well as to normalize injustice, that is, consolidate domination. I then introduce an example of historical knowledge that can be regarded as a crucial epistemic corrective against pressures of Armenian genocide disinformation: knowledge of the Ottoman tribunals that attempted to prosecute perpetrators in the aftermath of the Armenian genocide and accordingly, the crucial role of the Armenian genocide in the history of international law and the concepts of “crimes against humanity” and “genocide” in particular.

Third, I highlight that the problem of genocide denialism and thus failure of epistemic reparation is not primarily the lack of relevant historical knowledge, but the epistemic practices and processes that systematically distort, occlude, or obscure such knowledge. Based on this, I propose an account of epistemic reparation that corrects a corrupted genocidal epistemology and guards against ongoing epistemic harms toward victims-survivors as well as descendants. Not only should it go along with a provision of crucial information, evidence, and knowledge about violations, but also with epistemic recognition: While the right to know is a crucial step in the formal recognition of epistemic rights, epistemic reparation must also be rooted in a commitment to restore the victims' epistemic standing and capability of epistemic contribution.2

I take these cues of focusing on the “justification of injustice” from Pauer-Studer and Velleman 2011, who are critical of the view that Nazi crimes were obvious cases of immorality in the context of the Third Reich. After all, “if their immorality had been as obvious to the perpetrators as it is today, the crimes might never have occurred” (p. 330). Rather, they argue that moral reasoning could misfire on such a broad scale because morality became distorted at the level of its social articulation. In a social and normative context infused by Nazi ideology, perpetrators were led to mischaracterize their situation “and consequently misinterpreted and misapplied the guidelines of their conventional morality” (p. 334). Hence, perpetration was enabled through distortions at the stages of moral interpretation and application, among other things, because of misconceptions of reality provided by their social context. This can entail “empirical falsehoods about ‘[the] community's particular circumstances’ (Herman, 1993, pp. 83–84)—for example, what Arendt called ‘the lie most effective with the whole of the German people’ (Arendt, 1994, p. 52), namely, that Germans were engaged in a Schicksalskampf against a race intent on annihilating them” (Pauer-Studer and Velleman 2011, p. 352). Such empirical distortions were accompanied by normative distortions. Perpetrators considered their actions morally justified, because “moral principles were filtered through socially conditioned interpretations and perceptions that gave events a distorted normative significance” (p. 340). This was the case, for example, when the gassing of Jews was viewed by the medical staff as “humanitarian treatment for people who were going to die one way or another” (p. 345) and that it was a humane way of saving them from typhus epidemics, illustrating a distorted medical code of ethics.

It is commonly argued—and most evident in the case of the Nazi genocide of European Jewry, as mentioned above—that genocides are based on a very effective lie supported by conspiracy propaganda on behalf of the perpetrating group, namely that the targeted group presents an existential threat intent on annihilating them. The threat posed by the targeted group is exaggerated, often through their assimilation into a much more powerful enemy. In the case of Armenians, for example, the enemy of Western or Russian imperialist powers. However, the justification of genocide and its inherent denialism (of wrongdoing) consists of more than systematic disinformation, the spread of empirical falsehoods, or propagandistic lies about a community's particular circumstances. Unlike lying, denying precludes the acceptance of certain truths or facts. It rather points to a motivated, “active effort not to see, no matter what the evidence may be; as a result of constant distortion and redescription” (Medina, 2013, p. 35) of the injustice.

Drawing on these insights, the “justification of genocide” is conditional upon the active or willful exclusion of targeted groups from the community of epistemic trust. Their exclusion from practices that generate shared knowledge and understanding of social reality and in particular, social grievances, enables the generation and maintenance of willful ignorance required for complicity and perpetration. In the following, I apply these insights to the case of the Armenian genocide. My main focus will be on the overarching, institutionalized ideology and social and normative system whereby ruling authorities could cultivate and impose a way of (un)knowing based on which perpetration could be broadly enabled, rationalized, and justified, granting not only the success of the genocide but also its long-term denialism.4

The UNCHR acknowledges the right to know, alongside the right to justice, the right to reparation and guarantees of non-recurrence, as a central pillar of a “holistic” approach to transitional justice, hence a state's obligation to combat impunity and thereby protect and promote human rights in the aftermath of “serious crimes under international law.”13 This means that they are not to be seen as rights and principles that can be addressed in isolation from one another. Rather, they depend on one another to achieve justice. For example, so-called “symbolic” reparations alone—such as political apologies—are not sufficient if they are not accompanied by real institutional reforms and transformations that address and repair the unjust material conditions in order to achieve full moral repair and make recurrence of social violence less likely. Further, educational measures such as the establishment of memorials and museums can be used to misinform and mislead the public if they are not properly based on respect for victims' epistemic rights; such as if they disregard crucial insights generated by those who experienced the injustice, or focus exclusively on victimhood without acknowledging the responsibility of perpetrators and conditions of perpetration. Moreover, legal prosecution and punishment of individual perpetrators will be insufficient to address and repair the systematic, social, and structural conditions that enabled vast societal complicity and support for such atrocities.

I take these to be some of the pressures (towards failure) that the GP of the right to know seek address and correct. I now introduce an example of historical knowledge particularly relevant to resist some of the pressures of pernicious ignorance in relation to the Armenian genocide. Such is the knowledge of the Ottoman tribunals that attempted to prosecute perpetrators in its aftermath and the crucial role of the Armenian genocide in the history of international law and the concepts of “crimes against humanity” and “genocide” in particular.

In what follows, I introduce a further dimension or type of recognition harm, namely epistemic recognition harm. This is rooted in the idea promoted by recent scholarship on epistemic injustice that we also stand in reciprocal relations of epistemic recognition with others and that there can be conditions or situations that render such relations seriously dysfunctional and harmful. The proposal here then, complementing Tirrell's aforementioned account, is to bring victims back into the human community through recognition of their epistemic standing and provision of the social uptake necessary for their Capability of Epistemic Contribution (Fricker, 2015). Fricker defines this as a “social epistemic capability on the part of the individual to contribute to the pool of shared epistemic materials—materials for knowledge, understanding, and very often for practical deliberation” (p. 76). Acknowledging such a central human capability and thus, what may ground particular epistemic rights17 introduces us to a further form of violence enacted or delivered through discursive behaviors, namely epistemic violence. This is defined by Dotson as “the failure, owing to pernicious ignorance, of hearers to meet the vulnerabilities of speakers in linguistic exchanges” (Dotson, 2011, p. 238). Epistemic violence not only points to epistemic rights violations we may encounter in epistemically relevant linguistic exchanges such as testimony, but also its enabling background conditions, namely pernicious reliable ignorance. Indeed, a genocidal epistemology requires and is reinforced by the systematic violation and disablement of victims' capability of epistemic contribution. Let us now hone in on the relationship between ignorance, power, and the idea of restorative epistemic reparation.

While we often say “knowledge is power,” one might assume that ignorance—understood as lack of knowledge—disempowers. However, whether or not ignorance disempowers and whom it disempowers depends not only on the subject matter, but also on the kind of ignorance we are dealing with. We need to ask: Who is ignorant with regard to what subject matter and might such ignorance in fact be willfully and perniciously generated and maintained based on flawed cognitive norms and motives—for example, in order to defend and protect dominant privilege? Moreover, the other side of this coin is of course that those who carry threatening knowledge—such as knowledge of oppression—are intentionally disempowered. They are indeed rendered powerless knowers. Note that by “threatening knowledge” I mean knowledge that threatens a status quo characterized by unjust power relations. Take the case of genocide and its aftermath. Genocide consolidates domination of the perpetrating party, including the normalizing understandings related to the injustice, which serve to defend and protect dominant privilege. Such ignorance, then, is not to be understood merely in terms of an absence of knowledge (i.e., propositional ignorance), but also as substantive epistemic practice, a problem of ignorant agency guided by particular attitudes, cognitive norms, and evidential policies.

This shifts our analytical focus to the constitutive elements of ignorant agency; the structural social conditions that produce identities, social locations, and modes of belief formation, which become epistemically disadvantageous or defective (Alcoff, 2007, p. 40). This is most evidently the case under structural social conditions of domination and oppression, which tend to cultivate various epistemic vices on behalf of dominantly situated epistemic subjects. These may include epistemic laziness, arrogance, and closed-mindedness with regard, especially to matters pertaining to practices of social violence (Medina, 2013, p. 35). Such cultivated inattention and insensitivity to social violence and the stigmatizing prejudices that enable it are constitutive of the kind of active or willful ignorance produced by oppressive and particularly genocidal systems. It provides perpetrators with a particular perception and interpretations that give their actions distorted meaning; and it is essential to such ignorance that it devalues, excludes, and misrecognizes epistemic contributions provided by the victims. Hence, without addressing the genocidal epistemology and the willful ignorance that sustains it, denialism will continue to have a robust basis and remain a source of epistemic harm to victims, survivors, and descendants. It is against this background that we should formulate the need for and scope of epistemic rights and restorative epistemic reparation.

The underlying assumption here is that impunity in the aftermath of injustice, hence a failure of our ideal of transitional justice, is the norm rather than the exception and it is maintained by denialism—in the form of justification, rationalization, relativization, or trivialization of the injustice (Hovannisian, 1999). Granted these existing pressures posed by cultures of impunity and the ignorant agency they cultivate, the right to know can plausibly be understood as an epistemic corrective. It guards against common efforts to distort, obscure, and obliterate knowledge about perpetrated injustices, which requires the ongoing exclusion or discrediting of victims' epistemic contributions. As it is formulated now, however, the right to know mainly considers entitlements to information and knowledge that are of particular moral, social and political relevance to victim-survivors and descendants. Providing access to epistemic goods such as information and knowledge about violations is not sufficient for restorative epistemic reparation. A further requirement is the revision of unjust epistemic practices and relations through which a genocidal epistemology was generated and maintained—essentially based on the systematic withdrawal of epistemic recognition from victims. Theories of active or willful ignorance show that there can exist epistemically substantive flaws in the very epistemic practices in need of reparation. To restore the victims' epistemic standing against this background, they need to be recognized as authoritative contributors to the common pool of epistemic resources based on which knowledge and understanding of the injustice are generated. This ensures that victims are indeed acknowledged as authoritative epistemic contributors and not only receivers of evidence and knowledge about violation and injustice. In short, one could say that the right to know (as the right to certain knowledge or other epistemic resources) should be extended in its scope to include the right to be recognized as a knower (as the right to epistemic contribution). I shall briefly elaborate on this idea in the remainder of this paper.

Acknowledging epistemic rights, or the “general idea that human wellbeing has an epistemic dimension” depends, according to Fricker (2015, p. 76), “on the idea that functioning not only as a receiver but also as a giver of epistemic materials is an aspect of human subjectivity that craves social expression through the capability to contribute beliefs and interpretations to the local epistemic economy.” If we accept this idea, epistemic reparation measures and policies ought to consider not only the right to receive epistemic materials, but to participate in their generation. Hence, it must be ensured that victims receive the social uptake required for rehabilitation of their capability of epistemic contribution, that is, their “enjoyment of epistemic relational equality” (Fricker, 2015, p. 87). As already mentioned, a genocidal epistemology is generated and maintained based on the systematic, unwarranted exclusion or rejection of the epistemic contributions of the marginalized and victimized. In the context of the Armenian genocide and the preceding persecutions, Armenians and their intellectual contributions, social grievances and struggles, demands for reform, and resistance movement were persistently ignored, demonized, misrepresented, and violently suppressed by Ottoman authorities. Without properly addressing such misconceptions constituting genocidal epistemologies, they will continue to provide fertile ground for practices of silencing. Survivors and descendants will continue to be deprived of the social uptake needed for their capability of epistemic contribution, thereby subjecting them to ongoing testimonial and hermeneutical injustice (as I have argued elsewhere, e.g., Altanian, 2021a, 2021b).

Restorative epistemic reparation is thus not only instrumentally valuable insofar as it might prevent the recurrence of wrongs, but intrinsically valuable, insofar as it re-asserts and repairs survivors' and descendants' epistemic relational equality. Applying these insights to the three GP of the right to know suggests the following, extended formulations of a state's corresponding epistemic duties for combating impunity. Recall that (GP 1) pertains to the justificatory framework of a genocidal epistemology. For (GP 1) to be epistemically restorative, it ought to entail a duty to recognize victims' epistemic contributions in correcting the distorted epistemology based on which genocide perpetration was justified. (GP 2) pertains to collective memory. For it to be epistemically restorative, it ought to entail a duty to recognize the victim group's epistemic contributions, particularly to the societal practice of giving meaning to the past. (GP 3) pertains to individuals and their families right to certain kinds of knowledge, in recognition of their informational needs that carry crucial personal and moral value. Re-integrating victims-survivors in the generation of knowledge and understandings of the circumstances of perpetration and in generating meaning about what happened is crucial to help them maintain intellectual courage and epistemic self-confidence, ultimately, in order for them to indeed keep their knowledge and memory crucial for personhood. To a certain extent, (GP2) acknowledges the victim group's epistemic authority in relation to its (historical) experiences of injustice, by stating that “[a] people's knowledge of the history of its oppression is part of its heritage and, as such, must be ensured by appropriate measures in fulfillment of the State's duty to preserve archives and other evidence concerning violations of human rights and humanitarian law and to facilitate knowledge of those violations.” However, it still falls short of explicitly recognizing their status as authoritative epistemic contributors—of evidence, archives, and other epistemic resources—required for knowledge and understanding of those violations and the collective memory based on it.18

In order to repair and resist the epistemically unjust legacies of a genocidal epistemology, these epistemic contributions have to be particularly recognized by representatives of the perpetrating group. Drawing on Margaret Urban Walker's notion of “making amends,” which refers to perpetrators' attempts to make things right, Almassi (2018, p. 10) conceives of such epistemic reparation-qua-amends not in terms of compensation, but “acts of demonstration that underwrite processes of relational repair in accordance with victims' perspectives and priorities.” Epistemic amends enable victims to trust that “they will be believed, understood, properly interpreted […] which is why prioritization of victim subjectivities is so crucial for determining the actions and outcomes needed to make amends after the perpetration, experience, and acknowledgement of epistemic injustice.” (ibid.) Thus, reparation of epistemic injustices inherent in the perpetration of genocide requires centering victims' situatedness and epistemic resources developed from such situatedness. Campbell (2014, p. 165) convincingly showed in her analysis of challenges faced by Truth and Reconciliation Commissions (TRC) in Settler societies like the Canadian Indian Residential Schools (IRS TRC) that in order for it to fulfill its commitment to supporting the establishment of “new relations embedded in mutual recognition and respect,” one should first identify the disrespectful challenges and contestations of memory and testimony that survivors face when remembering and sharing their experiences or histories. To provide them with due epistemic recognition requires becoming aware of and correcting for the legacy of colonialism through disrespectful challenges to memories and perspectives that they continue to face, hence the legacy of unequal moral and social-political, as well as epistemic standing. Campbell's analysis helps us see that even if epistemically restorative measures such as TRCs are implemented, the testimonies of victim-survivors do not meet a prior epistemic gap, or interpretive “terra incognita.” Instead, they bump into existing myths and narratives that “rationalize continued unequal treatment of those formerly colonized” (ibid.). One upshot of this is that their testimony will tend to be met with default skepticism and diminished credibility, in virtue of their already socially marginalized position. Hence, acknowledgment of different and in particular, oppressed “epistemic standpoints” (Harding, 1993), situated knowledge (and ignorance) and the legacy of genocidal epistemologies that continue to shape unequal epistemic relations is necessary for restorative epistemic justice in the aftermath of colonial and imperial atrocities, including genocides.

重新思考知情权和恢复性认知赔偿的案例
本着这期特刊关注受伤害的个人和群体的精神,他们对如何理解和纠正错误的解释,以及采取什么行动促进纠正,本文重点关注受种族灭绝伤害的个人和群体,以及他们在种族灭绝之后获得认知赔偿的权利。我认为,知识赔偿不仅需要满足受害者、幸存者和后代的信息需求,包括获取档案、文件和提供有关侵犯的知识。此外,考虑到作为种族灭绝暴行重要组成部分的认知伤害的概念,认知赔偿还应包括承认和重新建立受害者的认知地位或简而言之认知承认。种族灭绝是通过种族灭绝认识论得以实现、“合理化”甚至规定的,这种无知的认识论不仅由对社会现实的虚假和错误信息的传播构成,而且由对认识论权威和认识论威权主义的滥用构成,这种认识论权威和认识论威权主义系统地将目标群体排除在认识论信任的社区之外。认知信任是一种信任,它允许我们从他人那里或与他人一起获得或产生知识和其他类型的认知输入。例如,我们相信别人告诉我们真相——或者至少,他们认为是真实的,而不是故意欺骗我们——我们相信别人把我们看作是值得信赖的认知贡献者,或者尽他们最大的努力理解我们的话语。系统地、毫无根据地在认识上不信任意味着被剥夺了认识上的认可,因此,被剥夺了参与所必需的社会吸收,例如,在对社会现实的共同理解的产生中,以及修正那些拥有主导权力的人强加的误解——在目前的情况下,种族灭绝倡导者和肇事者。因此,认知修复应该包括对功能失调的认知实践的修正,这些实践是构成和维持种族灭绝认识论的基础。这将使知识赔偿不仅在工具上有价值,因为它可以,例如通过教育和信息措施,防止这些错误的再次发生,而且在本质上也有价值,因为它重新确立和修复了幸存者和后代的知识地位。它为他们提供了被系统地从他们身上撤回的认知认识,使认知补偿成为恢复性司法的关键要素。接下来,我将以1915-1917年亚美尼亚种族灭绝为例,首先介绍“种族灭绝认识论”的概念。这一历史上的种族灭绝继续被土耳其的继任政府系统地否认,使其成为探索知识赔偿价值的有用案例研究。这里的方法论动力是从消极的角度产生对(恢复性)司法的见解:司法已经失败并继续失败的案例。其基本思想是,影响正义或不正义的不仅是知识,而且可能更重要的是(故意的)无知。我讨论了这些暴行是如何基于种族和宗教统治下的民族主义意识形态驱动的种族灭绝认识论而“合理化”的。这种种族灭绝认识论是由代表犯罪者的无知做法产生和维持的,因此目标群体不仅在道德上或社会上是不可信的,而且在认识论上也是不可信的在这些背景条件下,我展开了对知情权及其在认识论上的恢复潜力的后续分析。因此,第二,我要谈谈知情权问题,这是联合国人权委员会打击国际法规定的犯罪后有罪不罚现象的核心支柱之一,并从纠正认识的角度讨论其原则。更具体地说,我认为这些原则在承认认识权利的过程中,起到了纠正的作用,以对抗有害的无知的压力,这种无知在犯罪后持续存在,代表犯罪者试图实现或维持赦免或有罪不罚,以及使不公正正常化,即巩固统治。然后,我介绍了一个历史知识的例子,可以被视为对亚美尼亚种族灭绝虚假信息压力的重要认知纠正:了解奥斯曼法庭在亚美尼亚种族灭绝之后试图起诉肇事者,因此,亚美尼亚种族灭绝在国际法历史上的关键作用,特别是“危害人类罪”和“种族灭绝”的概念。 第三,我要强调的是,种族灭绝否认主义的问题以及因此而导致的认知修复的失败,主要不是缺乏相关的历史知识,而是系统性地扭曲、遮蔽或模糊这些知识的认知实践和过程。在此基础上,我提出了一种认识论补偿的解释,它纠正了腐败的种族灭绝认识论,并防止对受害者-幸存者及其后代的持续认知伤害。不仅要提供有关侵权行为的关键信息、证据和知识,而且要有认识上的承认:虽然知情权是正式承认认识权利的关键一步,但认识上的赔偿也必须植根于恢复受害者的认识地位和知识贡献能力的承诺。我从Pauer-Studer和Velleman(2011)那里得到了关注“不公正辩护”的线索,他们对纳粹罪行是第三帝国背景下明显的不道德案例的观点持批评态度。毕竟,“如果他们的不道德行为对肇事者来说像今天这样明显,那么这些罪行可能永远不会发生”(第330页)。相反,他们认为道德推理可能在如此大的范围内失败,因为道德在其社会表达水平上被扭曲了。在纳粹意识形态灌输的社会和规范背景下,犯罪者被引导对其处境进行错误的描述,“因而误解和误用其传统道德准则”(第334页)。因此,犯罪行为是通过在道德解释和应用阶段的扭曲,除其他外,由于他们的社会环境所提供的对现实的误解而得以实现的。这可能导致“关于‘社区的特殊情况’的经验谎言”(赫尔曼,1993年,第83-84页)——例如,阿伦特所说的“对整个德国人民最有效的谎言”(阿伦特,1994年,第52页),即德国人参与了一场反对意图消灭他们的种族的Schicksalskampf”(鲍尔-斯图德和维勒曼2011年,第352页)。这种经验上的扭曲伴随着规范上的扭曲。肇事者认为他们的行为在道德上是正当的,因为“道德原则通过社会条件的解释和观念过滤,使事件具有扭曲的规范意义”(第340页)。例如,对犹太人使用毒气被医务人员视为“对以这种或那种方式死去的人的人道主义治疗”(第345页),这是拯救他们免遭斑疹伤寒流行的人道主义方式,说明了一种扭曲的医疗道德准则。人们普遍认为,正如上面提到的,纳粹对欧洲犹太人的种族灭绝是最明显的,种族灭绝是基于一个非常有效的谎言,由代表犯罪集团的阴谋宣传所支持,即目标群体呈现出一种生存威胁,意图消灭他们。目标群体构成的威胁被夸大了,通常是由于他们被同化为一个更强大的敌人。以亚美尼亚人为例,他们是西方或俄罗斯帝国主义列强的敌人。然而,种族灭绝的正当性及其固有的(对不法行为的)否认不仅仅是系统性的虚假信息、经验谬误的传播或对一个社区特定情况的宣传谎言。与说谎不同,否认排除了对某些真理或事实的接受。相反,它指的是一种有动机的、“积极的努力,不管证据是什么,都不去看;由于不断的扭曲和重新描述”(麦地那,2013年,第35页)的不公正。根据这些见解,“为种族灭绝辩护”的条件是主动或故意将目标群体排除在认知信任社区之外。他们被排除在产生对社会现实,特别是对社会不满的共同知识和理解的实践之外,使他们能够产生和维持共谋和犯罪所必需的故意无知。在下文中,我将这些见解应用到亚美尼亚种族灭绝的案例中。我的主要重点将放在总体的、制度化的意识形态以及社会和规范体系上,在这个体系中,统治当局可以培养和强加一种(不)知道的方式,在这种方式的基础上,犯罪行为可以得到广泛的支持、合理化和正当化,不仅使种族灭绝取得成功,而且使其长期被否认。联合国人权事务高级专员办事处承认,知情权、获得赔偿的权利和保证不再发生的权利是过渡时期司法“整体”方法的核心支柱,因此,一个国家有义务打击有罪不罚现象,从而在“国际法规定的严重罪行”发生后保护和促进人权。 " 13这意味着,它们不应被视为可以彼此孤立地处理的权利和原则。相反,他们依靠彼此来实现正义。例如,所谓的“象征性”赔偿——如政治道歉——如果不伴随着真正的制度改革和变革,以解决和修复不公正的物质条件,以实现全面的道德修复,并减少社会暴力再次发生的可能性,则是不够的。此外,建立纪念馆和博物馆等教育措施如果不适当地以尊重受害者的知识权利为基础,可能被用来误导和误导公众;例如,如果他们无视那些经历不公正的人所产生的重要见解,或者只关注受害者,而不承认肇事者的责任和犯罪条件。此外,对个别肇事者的法律起诉和惩罚将不足以解决和修复导致大规模社会共谋和支持此类暴行的系统、社会和结构条件。我认为这些是一些压力(走向失败)的权利的GP寻求解决和纠正。我现在要介绍一个历史知识的例子,这与抵制与亚美尼亚种族灭绝有关的有害无知的一些压力特别相关。这就是对奥斯曼法庭在其后果中试图起诉肇事者的了解,以及亚美尼亚种族灭绝在国际法史上的关键作用,特别是“危害人类罪”和“种族灭绝”的概念。接下来,我将介绍认知伤害的另一个维度或类型,即认知认知伤害。这根植于最近关于认知不公正的学术研究中提出的观点,即我们也与他人处于认知认知的相互关系中,并且可能存在使这种关系严重失调和有害的条件或情况。因此,我的建议是,通过承认受害者的认知地位,并为他们的认知贡献能力提供必要的社会吸收,将受害者带回人类社会,这是对蒂雷尔上述说法的补充(Fricker, 2015)。弗里克将其定义为“个人的一种社会认知能力,为共享的认知材料——知识、理解和经常用于实践思考的材料——做出贡献”(第76页)。认识到这样一种核心的人类能力,从而认识到可能成为特定认知权利基础的东西,17向我们介绍了通过话语行为制定或传递的另一种形式的暴力,即认知暴力。Dotson将其定义为“在语言交流中,听者由于有害的无知而未能满足说话者的弱点”(Dotson, 2011, p. 238)。认知暴力不仅指向我们在与认知相关的语言交流(如证词)中可能遇到的认知权利侵犯,而且还指向其支持的背景条件,即有害的可靠无知。事实上,种族灭绝认识论要求并通过系统地侵犯和剥夺受害者的知识贡献能力而得到加强。现在让我们仔细研究一下无知、权力和恢复性认知补偿之间的关系。虽然我们经常说“知识就是力量”,但有人可能会认为无知——被理解为缺乏知识——会剥夺权力。然而,无知是否会剥夺人的权力,以及被无知剥夺的是谁,这不仅取决于主题,还取决于我们正在处理的无知的种类。我们需要问:谁对什么主题是无知的?这种无知实际上可能是基于有缺陷的认知规范和动机——例如,为了捍卫和保护支配特权——故意和有害地产生和维持的吗?此外,这枚硬币的另一面当然是那些拥有威胁性知识的人——比如关于压迫的知识——被故意剥夺了权力。他们确实成了无能为力的知者。请注意,我所说的“威胁性知识”是指威胁到以不公正的权力关系为特征的现状的知识。以种族灭绝及其后果为例。种族灭绝巩固了行为人的统治,包括使与不公正有关的理解正常化,这些理解有助于捍卫和保护占统治地位的特权。因此,这种无知不应该仅仅被理解为知识的缺失(即命题性无知),还应该被理解为实质性的认知实践,这是一个由特定态度、认知规范和证据政策指导的无知代理的问题。 这就把我们的分析焦点转移到了无知代理的构成要素上;产生身份、社会位置和信仰形成模式的结构性社会条件,在认识论上变得不利或有缺陷(Alcoff, 2007, p. 40)。在统治和压迫的结构性社会条件下,这是最明显的情况,这倾向于为处于统治地位的认知主体培养各种认知上的恶习。这些可能包括认识上的懒惰、傲慢和思想上的封闭,特别是在与社会暴力实践有关的问题上(麦地那,2013年,第35页)。这种对社会暴力的刻意忽视和不敏感,以及使之成为可能的污名化偏见,构成了压迫性和特别是种族灭绝制度所产生的那种主动或故意的无知。它为犯罪者提供了一种特殊的感知和解释,赋予他们的行为扭曲的意义;这种无知的本质是贬低、排斥和错误认识受害者提供的认知贡献。因此,如果不解决种族灭绝认识论和维持它的故意无知,否认主义将继续拥有强大的基础,并仍然是对受害者,幸存者和后代的认知伤害的来源。正是在这样的背景下,我们应该明确认识权利和恢复性认识赔偿的必要性和范围。这里的基本假设是,不公正的后果是有罪不罚,因此我们的过渡正义理想的失败,是规范而不是例外,它是由否认主义维持的-以不公正的辩护,合理化,相对化或轻视的形式(Hovannisian, 1999)。考虑到有罪不罚的文化和他们培养的无知机构所造成的这些现有压力,知情权可以被合理地理解为一种认知纠正。它可以防止歪曲、模糊和抹杀有关已犯下的不公正行为的知识的共同努力,这需要持续排除或诋毁受害者的认识贡献。然而,按照现在的表述,知情权主要考虑到对受害者-幸存者及其后代具有特别道德、社会和政治意义的信息和知识的权利。提供获取知识产品的途径,例如关于违规行为的信息和知识,不足以实现恢复性的知识赔偿。进一步的要求是修正不公正的认识论实践和关系,通过这些实践和关系,种族灭绝认识论得以产生和维持——本质上是基于系统地从受害者那里撤回认识论认识。主动无知或故意无知的理论表明,在需要弥补的认知实践中可能存在认知上的实质性缺陷。在这种背景下,为了恢复受害者的认知地位,他们需要被认为是共同认知资源的权威贡献者,而对不公正的认识和理解正是基于这些资源产生的。这确保受害者确实被承认为权威的知识贡献者,而不仅仅是关于侵犯和不公正的证据和知识的接受者。简而言之,人们可以说,知情权(作为获得某些知识或其他知识资源的权利)的范围应该扩大,以包括被承认为知识者的权利(作为知识贡献的权利)。我将在本文的其余部分简要阐述这一观点。根据Fricker(2015,第76页)的说法,承认认知权利,或“人类福祉具有认知维度的一般观点”取决于“不仅作为认知材料的接受者,而且作为给予者的功能是人类主体性的一个方面,它渴望通过为当地认知经济贡献信仰和解释的能力来实现社会表达。”如果我们接受这一观点,知识补偿措施和政策不仅要考虑知识材料的接受权,而且要考虑知识材料的生成权。因此,必须确保受害者获得恢复其知识贡献能力所需的社会吸收,即他们“享有知识关系平等”(Fricker, 2015, p. 87)。如前所述,种族灭绝认识论的产生和维持是基于系统地、毫无根据地排斥或拒绝边缘化和受害者的认识论贡献。在亚美尼亚种族灭绝和先前的迫害的背景下,亚美尼亚人及其智力贡献、社会不满和斗争、改革要求和抵抗运动一直被奥斯曼当局忽视、妖魔化、歪曲和暴力镇压。 如果不适当处理构成灭绝种族认识论的这些误解,它们将继续为沉默的做法提供肥沃的土壤。幸存者和后代将继续被剥夺他们的认知贡献能力所需要的社会吸收,从而使他们遭受持续的证词和解释学上的不公正(正如我在其他地方所争论的,例如,Altanian, 2021a, 2021b)。因此,恢复性的认知修复不仅在工具上有价值,因为它可以防止错误的再次发生,而且在本质上有价值,因为它重新断言和修复了幸存者和后代的认知关系平等。将这些见解应用到知情权的三个GP中,可以得出以下结论,即一个国家在打击有罪不罚方面相应的认识义务的扩展公式。回想一下,(GP 1)属于种族灭绝认识论的辩护框架。对于(GP 1)在认识论上的恢复,它应该包含一种责任,即承认受害者在纠正歪曲的认识论方面的贡献,这种认识论是为种族灭绝罪行辩护的基础。(GP 2)属于集体记忆。为了在认知上恢复,它应该包含一种责任,即承认受害者群体的认知贡献,特别是对赋予过去意义的社会实践。(GP 3)涉及个人及其家庭获得某些知识的权利,认识到他们的信息需求具有至关重要的个人和道德价值。让受害者和幸存者重新融入对犯罪环境的认识和理解以及对所发生的事情的理解,这对帮助他们保持智力上的勇气和认知上的自信至关重要,最终,为了让他们真正保持对人格至关重要的知识和记忆。在某种程度上,(GP2)承认受害者群体对其(历史)不公正经历的认识权威,指出“人民对其受压迫历史的了解是其遗产的一部分,因此必须采取适当措施确保,以履行国家保存有关侵犯人权和人道主义法的档案和其他证据的义务,并促进对这些侵犯行为的了解。”然而,它仍然没有明确承认他们作为权威知识贡献者的地位——证据、档案和其他知识资源——需要了解和理解这些违法行为和基于它的集体记忆。18为了修复和抵制种族灭绝认识论在认识论上的不公正遗产,这些认识论的贡献必须得到犯罪群体代表的特别认可。根据玛格丽特·厄本·沃克(Margaret Urban Walker)的“弥补”概念(指犯罪者试图纠正错误),Almassi(2018,第10页)认为,这种认识论上的补偿——准弥补,不是从赔偿的角度出发,而是“根据受害者的观点和优先事项,保证关系修复过程的展示行为”。认知修正使受害者相信“他们会被相信、理解、正确地解释[…],这就是为什么优先考虑受害者的主体性对于确定在犯罪、经历和承认认知不公正之后做出修正所需的行动和结果是如此重要。(同上)因此,对犯下种族灭绝罪行所固有的认识上的不公正的补救需要以受害者的处境和从这种处境中发展出来的认识资源为中心。Campbell (2014, p. 165)在她对加拿大印第安人寄宿学校(IRS TRC)等移民社会中真相与和解委员会(TRC)所面临的挑战的分析中令人信服地表明,为了使其履行支持建立“相互承认和尊重的新关系”的承诺,人们应该首先确定幸存者在回忆和分享他们的经历或历史时所面临的不尊重的挑战和记忆和证词的争论。为他们提供应有的认知认知,需要通过对他们继续面临的记忆和观点的不尊重挑战来意识和纠正殖民主义的遗产,因此是不平等的道德和社会政治遗产,以及认知地位。坎贝尔的分析帮助我们看到,即使实施了诸如TRCs之类的认知恢复措施,受害者-幸存者的证词也不能满足先前的认知差距,或解释“未知领域”。相反,他们碰到了现存的神话和叙事,这些神话和叙事“合理化了对那些前殖民地的不平等待遇”(同上)。 这样做的一个结果是,由于他们已经处于社会边缘地位,他们的证词往往会遭到默认的怀疑和可信度下降。因此,承认不同的,特别是受压迫的“认识论立场”(Harding, 1993)、所处的知识(和无知)以及种族灭绝认识论的遗产继续塑造不平等的认识论关系,对于在殖民和帝国暴行(包括种族灭绝)之后恢复认识正义是必要的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信