Theoretical problems with oversimplifying autistic diversity into a single category

IF 1.4 3区 心理学 Q4 PSYCHOLOGY, SOCIAL
Brett Heasman, Lisa Parfitt
{"title":"Theoretical problems with oversimplifying autistic diversity into a single category","authors":"Brett Heasman,&nbsp;Lisa Parfitt","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12388","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Mao (<span>2023</span>) presents a unified theory of language acquisition and processing which aims to bridge the gap between nativist and constructionist views on pragmatic competence. Mao argues that autism comprises a specific population which reveals how an Integrative Model of Pragmatic Competence works given apparent autistic difficulties in pragmatic competence but intact grammatical and lexical systems. Mao concludes that features perceived to be indicative of all autistic people (egocentrism and a lack of theory of mind) do not prevent linguistic competence. It is possible for internal modular components of language to function without recourse to intersubjective sociocultural engagement. It is argued this ultimately supports a nativist view over a constructionist view in relation to language acquisition, thus Mao proposes subsequent research should focus on neurobiological aspects of language acquisition and processing.</p><p>Our commentary will not focus on the broader linguistic debate about reconciling the positions between nativism and constructionism. Rather, we wish instead to focus specifically on the assumption Mao puts forward that autistic people constitute a homogenous category for studying the basic properties of human language. This assumption underscores theoretical problems within the linguistic ideas proposed which will be discussed below. It also has important moral and ethical implications in light of the way autistic people have been historically misrepresented as being entirely egocentric and unable to partake in authentic sociocultural life (Heasman &amp; Gillespie, <span>2018</span>; Ochs et al., <span>2004</span>). Indeed, a more precise application of the double empathy theory (i.e., that there is a gap in understanding between autistic and non-autistic people due to two-way dispositional differences), highlights how double empathy is a relational construct and functions to critically examine how autism knowledge is produced. Thus, the double empathy theory can help to guard against the risks of unintentionally perpetuating overgeneralised deficit-framed stereotypes of autism. We therefore raise five issues with Moa's theory and suggest that a pathway forward to strengthen the theory would be to shift focus away from the complex label of autism and instead define populations for study based on specific linguistic measures relevant to the research question at hand.</p><p>First, Mao acknowledges that the label of autism describes a wide range of linguistic abilities from lacking functional language to competent verbal abilities. Such extremes in linguistic competence presents problems for the ambitious aim of developing a model of human language and its use that could resolve the divergent beliefs between constructionism and nativism. The problem is that while autistic people may demonstrate a range of linguistic abilities, the reasons why are multifaceted, as autism is not a linguistic diagnosis, it is a complex amalgamation of social, cognitive, sensory and interactional criteria. Across the autism spectrum there are vastly different competencies, developmental trajectories, associated learning abilities and co-occurring diagnoses that would greatly complicate attempts to create a unifying linguistic theory using this label alone. Moreover, there are notable differences in linguistic ability within this population, such as between autistic males and females, where females are observed to have a higher propensity for communicative and pragmatic skills (Sturrock et al., <span>2021</span>). Therefore, any linguistic model that aims to develop hypotheses from studying autistic people needs to consider this complexity.</p><p>A second issue in theorisation results from how Mao presents ever-shifting definitions of autism to support a specific linguistic profile comprising two core features, an enduring insufficiency in intersubjective communication and lasting difficulties in mind-reading. This creates further problems as this “linguistic profile” is now no longer specific to autistic people. It is possible for someone to demonstrate difficulties in intersubjective communication but not be autistic, for example people who have been diagnosed with social pragmatic disorder but do not have any other criteria associated with an autism spectrum diagnosis. Indeed, there is also a wealth of literature on the difficulty non-autistic interlocutors experience with intersubjective aspects of language (e.g., the study of conversational repairs; Schegloff, <span>1992</span>). What would have strengthened Mao's theory here is a more specific operationalisation of what is meant by intersubjectivity and how the criteria apply specifically to autistic people, as intersubjectivity has been used to describe a variety of different interactional situations (Gillespie &amp; Cornish, <span>2010</span>). Indeed, Mao appears to propose that immediate consensus is the only form of “successful” intersubjective communication, a view which contrasts with the more distal patterns of intersubjectivity observed between autistic interlocutors (Heasman &amp; Gillespie, <span>2019b</span>).</p><p>A third issue, related to the above point, is the claim that difficulties in mind-reading are a core component of autistic non-intersubjective language use. Mao makes a broad claim when describing autistic individuals as conducting self-sufficient thinking activities without mind-reading. To claim that autistic people completely lack the ability to understand others' intentions and thoughts is an oversimplification and inconsistent with contemporary evidence which highlights a much more nuanced picture of how autistic people interact with each other (Crompton et al., <span>2020</span>), with familiar others (Heasman &amp; Gillespie, <span>2018</span>), and indeed, how non-autistic people struggle to imagine autistic minds (Sasson &amp; Morrison, <span>2019</span>). Mind-reading and theory of mind have received numerous critiques (Boucher, <span>2012</span>; Dant, <span>2015</span>; Yergeau &amp; Huebner, <span>2017</span>) which should be acknowledged within the rationale of the linguistic theory presented. However, Mao further conflates mind-reading with another construct of egocentrism, where autistic people are described as egocentric but capable of steady mental computations. This is a vague claim which is not indicative of the diversity of autistic subjectivity or consistent with autobiographical accounts of autism (Milton &amp; Sims, <span>2016</span>; Ridout, <span>2017</span>). Egocentrism is a highly contentious construct as it very much depends on one's position within a social field as to whether speech can be classified as egocentric. Therefore, the use of this broad term when referring to autistic people has been debunked for many reasons, not least because it is not only autistic people that could be said to engage in egocentric speech (Begeer et al., <span>2016</span>).</p><p>A fourth issue derives from evidence used to support arguments about autism. Dated references are used to support broad assumptions, such as the use of Baron-Cohen et al. (<span>1985</span>) to suggest that autistic people with high verbal ability have a very slim chance of understanding the intentions of others. This is an issue given the extent to which autism research has been enriched in recent years through both the neurodiversity paradigm and through the inclusion of autistic voice in research which had been previously “frozen out” of the literature (Milton, <span>2014</span>). At other times, Mao argues by analogy with reference to savants, such as Stephen Wiltshire and William Christopher. Yet not all savants are autistic and savants themselves are an incredibly rare population. Savants are therefore not a suitable analogy for the wider autistic spectrum, nor as a basis for developing a universal theory of language.</p><p>These four issues concerned with accurately defining autism result in a fifth issue, the misapplication of the double empathy theory. Mao uses the double empathy problem as evidence to support the claim that linguistic pragmatic processing is fundamentally different between these parties. A closer reading of the theory, proposed by autistic sociologist Milton (<span>2014</span>), highlights that (1) the double empathy gap is a relational difference, not a deficit attributable to one party as Mao implies; (2) that the difference is caused by a range of factors far beyond linguistic processing style; and (3) the gap is amplified by harmful stereotypes about autism which circulate within science and popular culture.</p><p>The idea that (1) the double empathy gap is a dyadic relational construct rather than an individual one impacts strategies for reducing said gap. Specifically, it follows that reducing dispositional difference (or increased similarity) would lead to a reduction in the gap, and empirical research has shown this to be the case within a communicative context where autistic peer-to-peer communication is successful, but autistic to non-autistic communication less so (Crompton et al., <span>2021</span>). Indeed, differences between autistic and non-autistic people can even be ameliorated by supporting shared interactional experiences (Chapple et al., <span>2021</span>). However, Mao situates pragmatic difficulty as internalised to the autistic individual alone. Under this proposal, autistic parties sharing the same pragmatic difficulties would not be able to overcome a double empathy gap. Thus, the fit between double empathy and the linguistic theory Mao presents appears to not be aligned.</p><p>The idea (2) that double empathy is attributable to factors beyond linguistic features alone has already been addressed above. However, (3) the potential to reinforce negative stereotypes of autism through scientific endeavour does require attention, as has been highlighted through the study of looping effects and epistemic injustice (Chapman &amp; Carel, <span>2022</span>; Hacking, <span>1999</span>). The representations of autism created through scientific inquiry can impact the way autistic people see themselves, often in negative ways given their focus on deficits (Milton, <span>2014</span>). Autistic people navigate stigma at various levels while also historically having their voice and personal lived experience overlooked (Botha et al., <span>2022</span>; Heasman &amp; Gillespie, <span>2019a</span>). For this reason, it is important for studies to take a careful and sensitive approach towards the topic of autism which recognises the potential for autistic people to read, research and engage with the work presented.</p><p>For Mao's linguistic theory to be taken forward, we would strongly recommend avoiding the heterogenous label of autism to illustrate a universal property of language acquisition. Rather, a more precise measure of verbal and pragmatic competence, specific to the research question at hand, would help to yield a more robust exploration of the ideas presented.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.4000,"publicationDate":"2023-05-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12388","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","FirstCategoryId":"102","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jtsb.12388","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"PSYCHOLOGY, SOCIAL","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Mao (2023) presents a unified theory of language acquisition and processing which aims to bridge the gap between nativist and constructionist views on pragmatic competence. Mao argues that autism comprises a specific population which reveals how an Integrative Model of Pragmatic Competence works given apparent autistic difficulties in pragmatic competence but intact grammatical and lexical systems. Mao concludes that features perceived to be indicative of all autistic people (egocentrism and a lack of theory of mind) do not prevent linguistic competence. It is possible for internal modular components of language to function without recourse to intersubjective sociocultural engagement. It is argued this ultimately supports a nativist view over a constructionist view in relation to language acquisition, thus Mao proposes subsequent research should focus on neurobiological aspects of language acquisition and processing.

Our commentary will not focus on the broader linguistic debate about reconciling the positions between nativism and constructionism. Rather, we wish instead to focus specifically on the assumption Mao puts forward that autistic people constitute a homogenous category for studying the basic properties of human language. This assumption underscores theoretical problems within the linguistic ideas proposed which will be discussed below. It also has important moral and ethical implications in light of the way autistic people have been historically misrepresented as being entirely egocentric and unable to partake in authentic sociocultural life (Heasman & Gillespie, 2018; Ochs et al., 2004). Indeed, a more precise application of the double empathy theory (i.e., that there is a gap in understanding between autistic and non-autistic people due to two-way dispositional differences), highlights how double empathy is a relational construct and functions to critically examine how autism knowledge is produced. Thus, the double empathy theory can help to guard against the risks of unintentionally perpetuating overgeneralised deficit-framed stereotypes of autism. We therefore raise five issues with Moa's theory and suggest that a pathway forward to strengthen the theory would be to shift focus away from the complex label of autism and instead define populations for study based on specific linguistic measures relevant to the research question at hand.

First, Mao acknowledges that the label of autism describes a wide range of linguistic abilities from lacking functional language to competent verbal abilities. Such extremes in linguistic competence presents problems for the ambitious aim of developing a model of human language and its use that could resolve the divergent beliefs between constructionism and nativism. The problem is that while autistic people may demonstrate a range of linguistic abilities, the reasons why are multifaceted, as autism is not a linguistic diagnosis, it is a complex amalgamation of social, cognitive, sensory and interactional criteria. Across the autism spectrum there are vastly different competencies, developmental trajectories, associated learning abilities and co-occurring diagnoses that would greatly complicate attempts to create a unifying linguistic theory using this label alone. Moreover, there are notable differences in linguistic ability within this population, such as between autistic males and females, where females are observed to have a higher propensity for communicative and pragmatic skills (Sturrock et al., 2021). Therefore, any linguistic model that aims to develop hypotheses from studying autistic people needs to consider this complexity.

A second issue in theorisation results from how Mao presents ever-shifting definitions of autism to support a specific linguistic profile comprising two core features, an enduring insufficiency in intersubjective communication and lasting difficulties in mind-reading. This creates further problems as this “linguistic profile” is now no longer specific to autistic people. It is possible for someone to demonstrate difficulties in intersubjective communication but not be autistic, for example people who have been diagnosed with social pragmatic disorder but do not have any other criteria associated with an autism spectrum diagnosis. Indeed, there is also a wealth of literature on the difficulty non-autistic interlocutors experience with intersubjective aspects of language (e.g., the study of conversational repairs; Schegloff, 1992). What would have strengthened Mao's theory here is a more specific operationalisation of what is meant by intersubjectivity and how the criteria apply specifically to autistic people, as intersubjectivity has been used to describe a variety of different interactional situations (Gillespie & Cornish, 2010). Indeed, Mao appears to propose that immediate consensus is the only form of “successful” intersubjective communication, a view which contrasts with the more distal patterns of intersubjectivity observed between autistic interlocutors (Heasman & Gillespie, 2019b).

A third issue, related to the above point, is the claim that difficulties in mind-reading are a core component of autistic non-intersubjective language use. Mao makes a broad claim when describing autistic individuals as conducting self-sufficient thinking activities without mind-reading. To claim that autistic people completely lack the ability to understand others' intentions and thoughts is an oversimplification and inconsistent with contemporary evidence which highlights a much more nuanced picture of how autistic people interact with each other (Crompton et al., 2020), with familiar others (Heasman & Gillespie, 2018), and indeed, how non-autistic people struggle to imagine autistic minds (Sasson & Morrison, 2019). Mind-reading and theory of mind have received numerous critiques (Boucher, 2012; Dant, 2015; Yergeau & Huebner, 2017) which should be acknowledged within the rationale of the linguistic theory presented. However, Mao further conflates mind-reading with another construct of egocentrism, where autistic people are described as egocentric but capable of steady mental computations. This is a vague claim which is not indicative of the diversity of autistic subjectivity or consistent with autobiographical accounts of autism (Milton & Sims, 2016; Ridout, 2017). Egocentrism is a highly contentious construct as it very much depends on one's position within a social field as to whether speech can be classified as egocentric. Therefore, the use of this broad term when referring to autistic people has been debunked for many reasons, not least because it is not only autistic people that could be said to engage in egocentric speech (Begeer et al., 2016).

A fourth issue derives from evidence used to support arguments about autism. Dated references are used to support broad assumptions, such as the use of Baron-Cohen et al. (1985) to suggest that autistic people with high verbal ability have a very slim chance of understanding the intentions of others. This is an issue given the extent to which autism research has been enriched in recent years through both the neurodiversity paradigm and through the inclusion of autistic voice in research which had been previously “frozen out” of the literature (Milton, 2014). At other times, Mao argues by analogy with reference to savants, such as Stephen Wiltshire and William Christopher. Yet not all savants are autistic and savants themselves are an incredibly rare population. Savants are therefore not a suitable analogy for the wider autistic spectrum, nor as a basis for developing a universal theory of language.

These four issues concerned with accurately defining autism result in a fifth issue, the misapplication of the double empathy theory. Mao uses the double empathy problem as evidence to support the claim that linguistic pragmatic processing is fundamentally different between these parties. A closer reading of the theory, proposed by autistic sociologist Milton (2014), highlights that (1) the double empathy gap is a relational difference, not a deficit attributable to one party as Mao implies; (2) that the difference is caused by a range of factors far beyond linguistic processing style; and (3) the gap is amplified by harmful stereotypes about autism which circulate within science and popular culture.

The idea that (1) the double empathy gap is a dyadic relational construct rather than an individual one impacts strategies for reducing said gap. Specifically, it follows that reducing dispositional difference (or increased similarity) would lead to a reduction in the gap, and empirical research has shown this to be the case within a communicative context where autistic peer-to-peer communication is successful, but autistic to non-autistic communication less so (Crompton et al., 2021). Indeed, differences between autistic and non-autistic people can even be ameliorated by supporting shared interactional experiences (Chapple et al., 2021). However, Mao situates pragmatic difficulty as internalised to the autistic individual alone. Under this proposal, autistic parties sharing the same pragmatic difficulties would not be able to overcome a double empathy gap. Thus, the fit between double empathy and the linguistic theory Mao presents appears to not be aligned.

The idea (2) that double empathy is attributable to factors beyond linguistic features alone has already been addressed above. However, (3) the potential to reinforce negative stereotypes of autism through scientific endeavour does require attention, as has been highlighted through the study of looping effects and epistemic injustice (Chapman & Carel, 2022; Hacking, 1999). The representations of autism created through scientific inquiry can impact the way autistic people see themselves, often in negative ways given their focus on deficits (Milton, 2014). Autistic people navigate stigma at various levels while also historically having their voice and personal lived experience overlooked (Botha et al., 2022; Heasman & Gillespie, 2019a). For this reason, it is important for studies to take a careful and sensitive approach towards the topic of autism which recognises the potential for autistic people to read, research and engage with the work presented.

For Mao's linguistic theory to be taken forward, we would strongly recommend avoiding the heterogenous label of autism to illustrate a universal property of language acquisition. Rather, a more precise measure of verbal and pragmatic competence, specific to the research question at hand, would help to yield a more robust exploration of the ideas presented.

将自闭症多样性过度简化为单一类别的理论问题
毛认为,自闭症包括一个特定的人群,这揭示了在自闭症患者在语用能力方面存在明显困难但语法和词汇系统完好的情况下,语用能力综合模型是如何工作的。毛总结说,被认为是所有自闭症患者的特征(自我中心主义和缺乏心理理论)并不妨碍语言能力。语言的内部模块组件有可能在不依赖于主体间社会文化参与的情况下发挥作用。作者认为,这最终支持了语言习得的本土主义观点,而不是建构主义观点,因此,毛建议后续研究应侧重于语言习得和加工的神经生物学方面。我们的评论不会集中在更广泛的关于调和本土主义和建构主义之间立场的语言学辩论上。相反,我们希望把重点放在毛提出的假设上,即自闭症患者构成了研究人类语言基本特性的同质类别。这一假设强调了所提出的语言学思想中的理论问题,这些问题将在下面讨论。鉴于自闭症患者在历史上被错误地描述为完全以自我为中心,无法参与真正的社会文化生活,它也具有重要的道德和伦理意义(Heasman &;Gillespie, 2018;Ochs et al., 2004)。事实上,双重共情理论(即,由于双向性格差异,自闭症患者和非自闭症患者之间的理解存在差距)的更精确应用,强调了双重共情是一种关系结构,并具有批判性地审视自闭症知识如何产生的功能。因此,双重共情理论可以帮助我们避免无意识地延续过度概括的自闭症缺陷刻板印象的风险。因此,我们对Moa的理论提出了五个问题,并建议加强这一理论的途径是将注意力从自闭症的复杂标签上转移开来,而是根据与手头研究问题相关的特定语言测量来定义研究人群。首先,毛承认自闭症的标签描述了广泛的语言能力,从缺乏功能性语言到有能力的语言能力。这种极端的语言能力给建立一种人类语言及其使用模式的宏伟目标带来了问题,这种模式可以解决建构主义和本土主义之间的分歧。问题是,虽然自闭症患者可能表现出一系列的语言能力,但原因是多方面的,因为自闭症不是一种语言诊断,它是社会、认知、感官和互动标准的复杂融合。在自闭症谱系中,有非常不同的能力、发展轨迹、相关的学习能力和共同发生的诊断,这将使仅仅使用这个标签来创建统一的语言理论的尝试变得非常复杂。此外,在这一人群中,语言能力也存在显著差异,例如在自闭症男性和女性之间,女性被观察到具有更高的交际和语用技能倾向(Sturrock et al., 2021)。因此,任何旨在通过研究自闭症患者提出假设的语言模型都需要考虑到这种复杂性。理论化的第二个问题是,毛提出了不断变化的自闭症定义,以支持特定的语言特征,包括两个核心特征:主体间沟通的持续不足和读心术的持续困难。这造成了进一步的问题,因为这种“语言概况”现在不再是针对自闭症患者的。有些人可能表现出主体间沟通的困难,但不是自闭症,例如,被诊断为社会实用主义障碍的人,但没有任何与自闭症谱系诊断相关的其他标准。事实上,也有大量的文献研究非自闭症对话者在语言的主体间性方面遇到的困难(例如,会话修复的研究;Schegloff, 1992)。对于主体间性是什么意思,以及这些标准如何具体适用于自闭症患者,这将进一步加强毛的理论,因为主体间性已经被用来描述各种不同的互动情况(Gillespie &康沃尔,2010)。 事实上,毛似乎提出,即时共识是“成功的”主体间沟通的唯一形式,这一观点与在自闭症对话者之间观察到的更远的主体间模式形成对比(Heasman &Gillespie, 2019 b)。与上述观点相关的第三个问题是,读心术的困难是自闭症非主体间语言使用的核心组成部分。毛在描述自闭症患者无需读心术就能进行自给自足的思维活动时,提出了一个宽泛的主张。声称自闭症患者完全缺乏理解他人意图和想法的能力是一种过度简化,与当代证据不一致,这些证据强调了自闭症患者如何与他人(Crompton et al., 2020),与熟悉的人(Heasman &Gillespie, 2018),事实上,非自闭症患者如何努力想象自闭症患者的思想(Sasson &莫里森,2019)。读心术和心智理论受到了许多批评(Boucher, 2012;次煤,2015;Yergeau,Huebner, 2017),这应该在提出的语言学理论的基本原理中得到承认。然而,毛进一步将读心术与另一种自我中心主义的概念混为一谈,在这种概念中,自闭症患者被描述为以自我为中心,但能够进行稳定的心理计算。这是一个模糊的说法,既没有表明自闭症主体性的多样性,也与自闭症的自传描述不一致(弥尔顿和安普;西姆斯,2016;Ridout 2017)。自我中心主义是一个非常有争议的概念,因为它在很大程度上取决于一个人在社会领域中的地位,即言论是否可以被归类为自我中心。因此,在提到自闭症患者时使用这个广义术语已经被揭穿了,原因有很多,尤其是因为不仅仅是自闭症患者可以说是在进行以自我为中心的演讲(Begeer等人,2016)。第四个问题来自于支持自闭症论点的证据。过时的参考文献被用来支持广泛的假设,例如Baron-Cohen等人(1985)认为具有高语言能力的自闭症患者理解他人意图的机会非常渺茫。这是一个问题,因为近年来,通过神经多样性范式和将自闭症的声音纳入研究,自闭症研究在一定程度上得到了丰富,而这些研究以前被“冻结”在文献中(Milton, 2014)。在其他时候,毛通过引用学者的类比来论证,比如斯蒂芬·威尔特希尔和威廉·克里斯托弗。然而,并不是所有的学者都是自闭的,学者本身就是一个非常罕见的群体。因此,学者不适用于更广泛的自闭症谱系,也不能作为发展普遍语言理论的基础。这四个与准确定义自闭症有关的问题导致了第五个问题,即双重共情理论的误用。毛用双重共情问题作为证据来支持语言语用处理在这些当事人之间存在根本差异的说法。仔细阅读自闭症社会学家弥尔顿(Milton, 2014)提出的理论,可以发现:(1)双重共情差距是一种关系差异,而不是毛所暗示的一方的缺陷;(2)这种差异是由一系列因素造成的,远远超出了语言加工风格的范围;(3)科学和大众文化中流传的关于自闭症的有害刻板印象扩大了这一差距。(1)双重共情差距是一种二元关系结构,而不是个体关系结构,这一观点影响了减少双重共情差距的策略。具体来说,减少性格差异(或增加相似性)会导致差距缩小,实证研究表明,在自闭症对等交流成功的交际环境中,情况就是如此,但自闭症与非自闭症的交流就不那么成功了(Crompton等人,2021)。事实上,自闭症患者和非自闭症患者之间的差异甚至可以通过支持共享的互动体验来改善(Chapple et al., 2021)。然而,毛认为实用困难是自闭症个体的内化。在这一提议下,患有同样务实困难的自闭症患者将无法克服双重同理心鸿沟。因此,双重共情与毛提出的语言学理论之间的契合似乎并不一致。关于双重共情可归因于语言特征之外的因素的观点(2)已经在上面讨论过了。然而,(3)通过科学努力强化对自闭症的负面刻板印象的可能性确实需要注意,正如通过对循环效应和认知不公的研究所强调的那样(Chapman &卡尔,2022;黑客,1999)。 通过科学探究创造的自闭症表征会影响自闭症患者看待自己的方式,通常是消极的方式,因为他们关注的是缺陷(Milton, 2014)。自闭症患者在不同程度上被污名化,同时他们的声音和个人生活经历也被忽视(Botha等人,2022;Heasman,Gillespie, 2019)。出于这个原因,对自闭症的研究采取谨慎和敏感的方法是很重要的,这种方法认识到自闭症患者阅读、研究和参与所呈现的工作的潜力。为了进一步推广毛的语言学理论,我们强烈建议避免给自闭症贴上异质标签,以说明语言习得的普遍特性。相反,针对手头的研究问题,对语言和语用能力进行更精确的测量,将有助于对所提出的观点进行更有力的探索。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.30
自引率
14.30%
发文量
36
期刊介绍: The Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour publishes original theoretical and methodological articles that examine the links between social structures and human agency embedded in behavioural practices. The Journal is truly unique in focusing first and foremost on social behaviour, over and above any disciplinary or local framing of such behaviour. In so doing, it embraces a range of theoretical orientations and, by requiring authors to write for a wide audience, the Journal is distinctively interdisciplinary and accessible to readers world-wide in the fields of psychology, sociology and philosophy.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信