The Invention of Duty: Stoicism as Deontology by Jack Visnjic (review)

IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
W. Stephens
{"title":"The Invention of Duty: Stoicism as Deontology by Jack Visnjic (review)","authors":"W. Stephens","doi":"10.1353/hph.2022.0060","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"philosophers’ broader philosophical views. Chapter 8 reintroduces a prominent example of this phenomenon from chapter 3—the difficulties that constitutive relativity creates for the theory of the Forms—and persuasively reconstructs one of Aristotle’s arguments against the Forms in On Ideas as a valid reductio, based only on assumptions about the nature of relativity that are shared by Aristotle and his Platonist targets. Chapters 9 and 10 take up the Stoic treatment of relatives. Chapter 9 provides a constitutive reading of two kinds of relatives that the Stoics distinguished. “Relatively disposed things,” like “father,” are directly constituted by a relation, whereas “differentiated relatives,” like knowledge and perception, are directly constituted by a power that is, in turn, constituted by a relation to its correlative. Chapter 10 then surveys the philosophical uses the Stoics may have made of these notions. For instance, Duncombe finds a role for differentiated relatives in the Stoic account of mixture and makes illuminating use of his account of relatively disposed things in reconstructing a debate between Aristo and Chrysippus about the unity of virtue. The study concludes with Sextus Empiricus, who, according to Duncombe, operates with a “conceptual” view of relativity in his arguments against his dogmatic opponents. The conceptual view modifies the standard constitutive view by introducing the qualification that a relative “is constituted by being conceived relative to something” (244). Duncombe suggests that Sextus moves to the conceptual level because the standard constitutive views involve claims about the natures of relatives—claims that Sextus, as a Pyrrhonian Skeptic, cannot endorse (245). This is an intriguing example of Duncombe’s third major thesis in the book, that philosophers’ larger philosophical outlooks affected their views of relativity (249), but I found myself wondering whether this explanation for Sextus’s innovation is consistent with the idea that skeptics speak without endorsing the claims they make (PH I,13; 192–93), which Duncombe invokes in claiming that Sextus’s commitment to conceptual relativity is purely dialectical (233, 237). If Sextus’s remarks about relativity are purely dialectical, considerations about what Sextus, as a skeptic, can and cannot endorse should be irrelevant. This book is a rare kind of achievement in ancient scholarship, dealing as it does with a subject that is understudied and yet, as Duncombe convincingly shows, indispensable for properly understanding ancient philosophical thought on many key topics. Given the range of problems on which the book makes new progress, it will be a rewarding read for just about anyone working on Greek philosophy. I a n J . C a m p b e l l Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"60 1","pages":"690 - 692"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2022-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2022.0060","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

philosophers’ broader philosophical views. Chapter 8 reintroduces a prominent example of this phenomenon from chapter 3—the difficulties that constitutive relativity creates for the theory of the Forms—and persuasively reconstructs one of Aristotle’s arguments against the Forms in On Ideas as a valid reductio, based only on assumptions about the nature of relativity that are shared by Aristotle and his Platonist targets. Chapters 9 and 10 take up the Stoic treatment of relatives. Chapter 9 provides a constitutive reading of two kinds of relatives that the Stoics distinguished. “Relatively disposed things,” like “father,” are directly constituted by a relation, whereas “differentiated relatives,” like knowledge and perception, are directly constituted by a power that is, in turn, constituted by a relation to its correlative. Chapter 10 then surveys the philosophical uses the Stoics may have made of these notions. For instance, Duncombe finds a role for differentiated relatives in the Stoic account of mixture and makes illuminating use of his account of relatively disposed things in reconstructing a debate between Aristo and Chrysippus about the unity of virtue. The study concludes with Sextus Empiricus, who, according to Duncombe, operates with a “conceptual” view of relativity in his arguments against his dogmatic opponents. The conceptual view modifies the standard constitutive view by introducing the qualification that a relative “is constituted by being conceived relative to something” (244). Duncombe suggests that Sextus moves to the conceptual level because the standard constitutive views involve claims about the natures of relatives—claims that Sextus, as a Pyrrhonian Skeptic, cannot endorse (245). This is an intriguing example of Duncombe’s third major thesis in the book, that philosophers’ larger philosophical outlooks affected their views of relativity (249), but I found myself wondering whether this explanation for Sextus’s innovation is consistent with the idea that skeptics speak without endorsing the claims they make (PH I,13; 192–93), which Duncombe invokes in claiming that Sextus’s commitment to conceptual relativity is purely dialectical (233, 237). If Sextus’s remarks about relativity are purely dialectical, considerations about what Sextus, as a skeptic, can and cannot endorse should be irrelevant. This book is a rare kind of achievement in ancient scholarship, dealing as it does with a subject that is understudied and yet, as Duncombe convincingly shows, indispensable for properly understanding ancient philosophical thought on many key topics. Given the range of problems on which the book makes new progress, it will be a rewarding read for just about anyone working on Greek philosophy. I a n J . C a m p b e l l Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin
Jack Visnjic的《责任的发明:作为道义论的斯多葛主义》(综述)
哲学家更广泛的哲学观点。第8章重新介绍了第3章中这一现象的一个突出例子——本构相对论给形式理论带来的困难——并令人信服地重建了亚里士多德在《论思想》中反对形式的一个论点,将其作为一种有效的还原论,仅基于亚里士多德和他的柏拉图主义目标对相对论性质的共同假设。第9章和第10章介绍了斯多葛学派对待亲属的方法。第9章提供了斯多葛学派区分的两种亲属的构成解读。“相对处置的事物”,如“父亲”,直接由一种关系构成,而“分化的亲属”,如知识和感知,直接由权力构成,而权力又由与其相关的关系构成。第10章考察了斯多葛学派对这些概念的哲学运用。例如,Duncombe在斯多葛学派对混合的描述中发现了有区别的亲属的作用,并在重建Aristo和Chrysippus之间关于美德统一的辩论中,启发性地利用了他对相对处置的事物的描述。这项研究的结论是Sextus Empiricus,根据Duncombe的说法,他在反对教条主义对手的论点中使用了相对论的“概念”观点。概念观点修改了标准的构成观点,引入了亲属“通过相对于某物的构思而构成”的资格(244)。Duncombe认为,Sextus之所以进入概念层面,是因为标准的构成观点涉及对亲属性质的主张——Sextus作为一个皮尔逊怀疑论者,不能支持这种主张(245)。这是Duncombe在书中的第三个主要论点的一个有趣的例子,即哲学家更大的哲学观影响了他们的相对论观点(249),但我发现自己在想,对Sextus创新的这种解释是否与怀疑论者在说话时不认可他们的主张的观点一致(PHI,13;192-93),Duncombe在声称Sextus对概念相对性的承诺是纯粹辩证的时援引了这一点(233237)。如果塞克斯图斯关于相对论的言论纯粹是辩证的,那么作为一个怀疑论者,考虑塞克斯图斯可以支持什么和不能支持什么应该是无关紧要的。这本书是古代学术界罕见的成就,它处理了一个研究不足的主题,但正如邓科姆令人信服地表明的那样,这对于正确理解古代哲学思想的许多关键主题是不可或缺的。考虑到这本书在一系列问题上取得了新的进展,对于任何研究希腊哲学的人来说,这本书都将是一本值得一读的书。我是J。柏林洪堡大学
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
72
期刊介绍: Since January 2002, the Journal of the History of Philosophy has been published by The Johns Hopkins University Press. For subscriptions, change of address, and back issues, please contact Subscription Services. In addition to photocopying allowed by the "fair use" doctrine, JHP authorizes personal or educational multiple-copying by instructors for use within a course. This policy does not cover photocopying for commercial use either by individuals or publishers. All such uses must be authorized by JHP.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信