{"title":"Being a master of metaphors","authors":"Hubertus Buchstein","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12661","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In his political interventions, Jürgen Habermas is a first-class rhetorician. His writing style is eloquent, polemical, rich in aperçus and metaphors, and often affective, especially angry (see Möllers, <span>2021</span>, p. 85). But there are also many metaphors in his contributions to philosophy, social theory, and political theory in which he clearly restrains himself rhetorically. Metaphors appear at crucial points in his theory formation. Formulations like the dialogical give and take of reasons “<i>in kleiner Münze</i>” (small coins), the discursive “<i>Verflüssigung</i>” (liquefaction) of traditions, the “colonization” of the lifeworld, the “center and periphery” of modern democracies, or their institutional “sluices”—a metaphor he has adopted from Bernhard Peters—create suggestive images in the minds of his readers. The author, who insists on the strict differentiation between day-to-day language, literary language, and the language of the social sciences (see Habermas, <span>1990a</span>), and whose philosophical self-understanding insists on the “unforced force of the better argument” is a master of evocative metaphors. This attribute alone makes it a pleasure to read his texts.</p><p>The German edition of his new book does not disappoint those readers in search of metaphors either. In the Marxist tradition (see Marx, <span>2011</span>), a number of metaphors are borrowed from the sphere of geology: “segments” (p. 33)<sup>1</sup> of the population, “erosion” of democracy (p. 87), normative “slopes” (p. 15), the “crumbling” of the political system (p. 109), or the “solidified lava” of anti-authoritarianism in Silicon Valley (p. 46). Some of the metaphors are nautical like normative “anchors” (p. 16), or from the theatre, like the “grimace” of libertarian political thought (p. 46). Only a few of them belong to organic life: the “root ground” of political culture (p. 32), the “<i>Gleichursprünglichkeit”</i> (co-originality) of democracy and the rule of law (p. 90), or the “nesting” of normative expectations (p. 14). Most of Habermas’ metaphors belong to the vocabulary of the technical world: the “building” of modern democracy (p. 9), “centrifugal” forms of communication (p. 43), the “architecture” of constitutional democracy (p. 32), the “net of historical memory” (p. 30), the “<i>Sollbruchstelle</i>” (predetermined breaking point) of political rights (p. 92), the “web of attitudes” (p. 30), the “social bond” (p. 31), civil society as an “early warning system” (p. 80)—and again the “flow chart” of the political system and its “filters” and “sluices” (p. 24, 100). One has to wait until the last paragraph of the book to find a military metaphor. Now is the time “<i>den Spieß umzudrehen</i>”<sup>2</sup> (p. 109) and fight the coalition of conspiracy theorists and right-wing populists.</p><p>Taking Habermas’ preference for technical metaphors into account, it comes as no surprise that he has speaks of “echo chambers” (p. 45) and “fragmentation” (p. 45) in his critical analysis of the digital public sphere. The spatial metaphor of <i>öffentlicher Raum</i> (<i>Raum</i> can literally be translated as unlimited space and as clearly limited room) is combined with the technical vocabulary of systems-theory when he mentions the “input,” “throughput,” and “output” components of the institutional infrastructure of the public sphere (pp. 38–39). In one passage of the book, Habermas even addresses the problems of metaphorical writing and states that his metaphor <i>Raum</i> “must not be overstated” (p. 60). He may have written this sentence from an unfortunate experience. More than once he has become the victim of his metaphor-rich writing style as critics have claimed that formulations like the “colonization of the lifeworld” are too vague to have real analytical power in the field of social research.</p><p>Another example is the term “ideal speech situation.” Habermas originally developed the ideal speech situation 1970 in <i>On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction</i> as an epistemological tool used to test the validity of what is essentially true or actually the case (see Habermas, <span>2001</span>). In this new book, Habermas once again pushes back vehemently against the “stubborn misunderstanding” (p. 69) about this term. First, he points out that he has not used “this misleading expression” since his 1972 essay on theories of truth. Second, the catchy formulation was never meant to be a blueprint for political institutions, but as a metaphor for the bundle of pragmatic assumptions that we actually always have to start from when we enter into a discourse about validity claims.</p><p>Nevertheless, some early advocates of the digital revolution in the first half of the 1990s like Howard Rheingold, Nicolas Negroponte, or WIRED magazine authors like John Katz used Habermas’ notions of the ideal speech situation and the unrestricted flow of communication in the public sphere as justification for their dreams of a new virtual democracy.<sup>3</sup> According to them, the World Wide Web was the technical incarnation of the ideal speech situation. In their view, the Internet matches all basic requirements of a public sphere that comes as close as possible to the normative core of deliberative democracy: The World Wide Web as the communicative infrastructure for open, unlimited, universal, anti-hierarchical, and complex political interaction. To the radical techno-optimists of those days, the Internet created a new political model, since it offered universal access, freedom of expression, unrestricted agendas, uncoerced communication, and political participation outside of traditional political institutions.</p><p>Habermas reminds the readers of his new book of the big “emancipatory promise” of the “egalitarian and unregulated” (p. 45) communicative relationships that were propagated at the beginning of the digital age. And indeed, the positive qualities attributed to political communication in the Internet by Rheingold and other optimists of electronic democracy in the 1990s strikingly resemble Habermas’ vocabulary (see Buchstein, <span>1997</span>, pp. 250–251). In his book <i>The Theory of Communicative Action</i>, Habermas defined the public sphere as “a virtually present network of communication” (Habermas, <span>1987</span>, p. 390) that is freed from any spatiotemporally restricted context. Ten years later, in his outline of the deliberative democratic ideal, he advocated a “decentred society” in which “subjectless forms of communication […] regulate the flow of deliberations” (Habermas, <span>1994</span>, p. 7). According to him, “technologies of communication […] make possible a highly differentiated network of public spheres” (Habermas, <span>1990b</span>, p. 360), The public sphere should consist of an “open and inclusive network of overlapping, subcultural politics having fluid temporal, social, and substantial boundaries” (Habermas, <span>1998</span>, p. 306). In such a “discursive structuring of public networks and arenas,” popular sovereignty “becomes anonymous” (Habermas, <span>1998</span>, p. 171).</p><p>In his new book, Habermas describes digital technology as a third evolutionary stage in the development of means for communication, following the writing of the spoken word a couple of thousand years ago and the introduction of the mechanical printing press at the beginning of early modernity. Despite the “revolutionary” (p. 41) change caused by digital technologies, he insists (again) on the social and political neutrality of new technologies. This position—already taken in the late 1960s by Herbert Marcuse—distinguishes Habermas’ argument from two rival positions within the Frankfurt School of Critical Theory. On the one hand, it departs from the optimistic positions taken by Walter Benjamin in his famous 1936 essay about the work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction or Hans-Magnus Enzensberger's <i>Baukasten zu einer Theorie der Medien</i> (1970). On the other hand, it also distances itself from Theodor W. Adorno's critique of alienated consumer culture and the thesis that the essence of the public sphere has been liquidated in the system of mass media in post-liberal societies.</p><p>Habermas stated in 1992 that the strong influence of Adorno's theory of mass culture was not difficult to discern in the first edition of <i>Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere</i> 30 years ago (see Habermas, <span>1992</span>, p. 438). There is an element of coquetry in this retrospective statement because already in the early 1960s he had made the point that the consumerist public sphere in a capitalist society should and could be transformed into a more democratic postbourgeois public sphere. The solution he offered in a less known Encyclopedia article from 1964 was a call for political intervention in order to create “a rational reorganization of social and political power” (Habermas, <span>1974</span>, p. 55). The public sphere should be brought “under the mutual control of rival organizations committed to the public sphere in their internal structure as well as in their relations with the state and each other” (Habermas, <span>1974</span>, p. 55). This sounds like an early neo-corporatist expansion of the way public TV was organized in West Germany in those days. Based on his neutralist position, Habermas already in the very beginning of his work about the public sphere more than 60 years ago subscribed to a strategy of state intervention in order to re-regulate the media system.</p><p>His considerations in <i>The Theory of Communicative Action</i> of 1981 followed the same pattern. Relying on empirical research, he argued—explicitly against Adorno—that even in shifting from writing to images and sounds, electronic media—movie, radio, and TV—have not turned mass media into an apparatus that completely dominates and permeates the language of everyday communication. Instead, he emphasized the “ambivalence” (Habermas, <span>1987</span>, p. 390) of modern mass media. But the “unleashing” of the “emancipatory potential,” which is “built into communicative structures themselves,” (Habermas, <span>1987</span>, p. 390) in the mass media has to be set into action by political measures. Habermas even mentioned Hans Magnus Enzensberger's vision of “video pluralism” and “television democracy” as attempts to overcome the centralizing media networks in this context. Since then, Habermas has stated repeatedly that modern mass media could both strengthen or undermine the rationality of political communication, depending on the way the infrastructure of the public sphere is regulated (see Habermas, <span>1992</span>, p. 437). Thirty years after Habermas first published his seminal book about the public sphere stated that there was “cause for a less pessimistic assessment” (Habermas, <span>1992</span>, p. 457) of it and of the future of democracy itself. Another 30 years later, Habermas seems to have returned to pessimism.</p><p>In his new book, Habermas repeats older statements about the importance of an accommodating, enlightened liberal political culture as the necessary condition for the existence and further development of a democratic political order. His optimism about the further development of western democracies when he published the book <i>Between Facts and Norms</i> in 1992 was still based on his hypothesis about the long-term trend toward a rationalization of the lifeworld. Thanks to the support of post-conventional socialization patterns, families and groups of citizens enter a higher stage of cognitive and moral rationality within their everyday face-to-face communication that also radiates into political communication. As is well known, he adopted the concept of civil society from Andrew Arato and Jean Cohen and turned it into the institutional source for progressive changes of reasons, values, and topics that get transmitted via mass media to the center of the political system. He described civil society as a context of discovery of morally relevant questions arising from the lifeworld. He thus assumed that the lifeworld had a rational advantage in the perception of social problems that were to be transported via social movements and the voluntary associations of civil society into the public sphere.</p><p>Habermas’ overly positive evaluation of social movements and civil society in <i>Between Facts and Norms</i> ignored the fact that a number of voluntary associations already at that time pursued conservative, reactionary, populist, and militant right-wing political goals (see Buchstein, <span>1994</span>, pp. 107–108). He restricted his considerations about civil society to the question of whether, and to what extent, a public sphere dominated by mass media could provide a realistic chance for the members of civil society to bring about political changes. In <i>Between Facts and Norms</i>, he was relatively optimistic about the possibility of further democratization. In his new book, Habermas is less optimistic. He puts more emphasis on the “vulnerability” (p. 30) of the results of socialization patterns and the precarious status of liberal democracies. He states “political regression” (p. 41) of liberal democracies around the world seems to have less confidence in the rationalization of the lifeworld.</p><p>There is a reason for this growing pessimism that has nothing to do with the current <i>Zeitgeist</i>, but follows from a subtle change in Habermas’ theory. At first glance, it seems that he is only updating his considerations about the organizational structure of the new media in order to make his argument about the new structural transformation. Both the neutralist position and the state-intervention strategy for a politics of reform and regulation can be found in his book again. Once again, he frames his reflections about the public sphere within his theory of deliberative democracy. He argues that the democratic legitimacy of modern democracies is based on the inclusiveness of the political public sphere. Mass media have an indispensable function, as they ensure the participation of citizens in a common, albeit anonymous, mass communication. Political opinions can only condense into effective public opinions and thus have a targeted influence on political decisions via the publicity of the mass media. Thus, it is imperative that the mass media have an “enlightening quality” (p. 23). The centrifugal dissolution of the limits of the simultaneously accelerated political communication to any number of participants at any distance has an “ambivalent explosive force” (p. 43). Referring to results of empirical research, Habermas notes that the deliberative quality of political communication in the internet is still an “open question” (p. 40).</p><p>According to Habermas, the “platform” (p. 44) character is what is “actually new about the new media” (p. 44). In other words, they enable all potential users to participate in the public sphere as independent authors with equal rights. Political communication no longer depends on traditional journalists or any other expert or institution for professional selection and discursive examination. But the services produced by new, privately owned social media platforms are “in no way neutral services” (p. 53). They are driven by the capitalist logic of profit-making that also puts pressure on the “old media” to adjust to the new format. According to Habermas, the emancipatory potential of the digital public sphere today is “<i>übertönt</i>” (p. 45, in the sense of dominated) by “fragmented publics” (p. 45), “bubbles” (p. 62), and “echo chambers” (p. 45). Both the basic standards for a rational debate and the inclusiveness of the public sphere are threatened to be lost. The stakes are high: the political integration of modern democracies is at risk.</p><p>It looks like a reminder of the final paragraphs of his first book on the public sphere and to his Encyclopedia article from the 1960s, when Habermas presents a strategy that includes three proposals to overcome this (newly) alarming decline of the public sphere. The first strategy counts on civic education: Citizens have to learn how to deal with this new technology in a reasonable way; and this may take some time (cf., pp. 46–47). The second strategy consists of strong state regulation of the mass media, for example, to force private owners of platforms in an effective way to correct false information or to prevent hate speech. Finally, the third reform strategy is to provide alternatives to the media power of privately owned companies. He proposes an expansion of financial support for state-funded and democratically controlled TV and radio stations (cf., p. 51 and 67), and even for (printed and digital) newspapers that fulfill certain quality standards (cf., p. 67).<sup>4</sup></p><p>This reform agenda is conservative in that it attempts to carry the media organization of the 1970s into our digital age. In his 1962 book, he glorified the bourgeois public sphere. In his new book, he is again glorifying a media system of the past. I have listed his threefold political reform agenda because it provokes a non-trivial question: How is it possible to regulate the structures of political communication in a way that strengthens enlightened discussions via legislative measures, when such regulations (at least in democracies) have to be the result of (less enlightened) political communication?</p><p>In the context of this question, it is striking that face-to-face communication gains more relevance in Habermas’ theory than before. It is a subtle change. But it has the potential to produce more than just subtle changes to Habermas’ final evaluation of the prospects for political reform of the public sphere. In his characterization of elected parliaments Habermas notes that their members “deliberate and decide <i>together</i> [emphasis in original] according to democratic procedures” (p. 24). I will not discuss the problematic theory of parliamentarism in the context of this article, but I do want to point to his formulation “deliberate <i>together</i> [emphasis in original].” In my understanding, this formulation indicates a normative preference for political communication in social face-to-face constellations, which is typical for interaction in the lifeworld. In a different section of the book, Habermas explicitly praises the deliberative quality of parliamentary decision-making because decisions are made “<i>face-to-face after democratic deliberations</i> [emphasis in original]” (p. 102). He also attests to the courts “comparatively high level of rationality” (p. 78), which seems not only to be the result of its legal institutionalization but also due to the fact that court hearings and deliberations are held face-to-face. Finally, in his characterization of social movements and a vibrant civil society he emphasizes their “face-to-face encounters” (p. 39) in everyday life and public events.</p><p>In one of the most intriguing sections of the book, Habermas speculates about a changing perception by the users of social media in which the separation between public and private communication is abolished. According to him, a significant part of digital communication today should be understood neither as public nor as private. Rather it is a sphere of communication, which has been reserved until then for private correspondences by letter, that has been bloated to a public existence. It produces a “peculiar anonymous intimacy” (p. 62) which Habermas coins a “<i>Halböffentlichkeit</i>” (p. 65—semi-public sphere) of echo chambers and filter bubbles.<sup>5</sup></p><p>However, this speculation puts Habermas in a dilemma. The lifeworld in Habermas’ theory is conceptualized as a linguistically organized and culturally transmitted stock of interpretative patterns which form the symbolic core of a society. He introduces the lifeworld as a necessary correlation to the notion of communicative action (see Baynes, <span>2016</span>, pp. 64–70). The dilemma is the following one: On the one hand, Habermas continues to base the considerations in the book on the assumption of the rational potential of the lifeworld, in particular of face-to-face communication even in different social settings. On the other hand, his speculation provides the plausible assumption that under the conditions of the current digital communication infrastructure, there will be a massive unlearning of cognitive and moral competencies among users.</p><p>In his 1962 book, Habermas argued that with the growth of mass media, the laws of the capitalist markets eventually extend and penetrate “into the substance of the works itself” (Habermas, <span>1989</span>, p. 165). This criticism was compatible with a neutralist position about new technology. In his current critique of social media, he can no longer maintain his neutralist position because he combines his observations about the semi-public sphere with the speculation that communication in such hybrid forms has the regressive effect of limited and “identity-preserving” (p. 61) moral and cognitive horizons for its users. This reduces the chances for Habermas’ reform agenda. The longer we wait for radical political reforms of the digital infrastructure, the less likely it is to win the support of democratic majorities (not to mention the problems of having to enforce them on a global scale). If we follow this line of argument, we end up with a much more pessimistic outlook than Habermas himself. But before taking Adorno's books on regressive mass culture from the shelf again, we should give empirical research a second look because there are reasons for moderate optimism. Could it be the case that Habermas is trapped in his analysis in the metaphorical language of “echo chambers” and “filter bubbles”?</p><p>Habermas’ metaphorical use of the term <i>Strukturwandel</i> (structural transformation) is also problematic. He did not invent this term for modern democratic theory. In 1932, Otto Kirchheimer spoke of the <i>Strukturwandel</i> of legitimacy in his criticism of Carl Schmitt's book on legality and legitimacy (see Kirchheimer, <span>2017</span>, p. 381). And in the early years of the Federal Republic of Germany, <i>Strukturwandel</i> of democracy was used as a concept by constitutional lawyer Gerhard Leibholz to justify state financing of political parties (see Leibholz, <span>1958</span>, pp. 79–129). Habermas’ original use of the term dates back to the late 1950s (see Yos, <span>2019</span>, pp. 429–433). In his case, it was a transmission of Franz L. Neumanns's term <i>Funktionswandel</i> of 1937. Neumann had used the phrase to describe the decline of liberal rule of law in capitalist society (see Neumann, <span>1937</span>). In his consideration of the public sphere, Habermas also dealt with a history of decline, but he substituted structure for function. Both <i>Funktionswandel</i> and <i>Strukturwandel</i> share the methodological approach to reconstruct historical changes in the development of capitalist societies as a unilinear sequence of clearly distinguishable stages.</p><p>In the way Habermas uses the term <i>Strukturwandel</i>, it is more than a rudimentary, ornamental, or weak metaphor. But even a weak metaphor fulfills the cognitive function of evoking an analogy in the realm of thought.<sup>6</sup> Habermas’ use of the term <i>Strukturwandel</i> conjures up two images. First, the image of design or assembly, which goes back to the Latin word <i>structuram</i>; structures are the basic elements that support a building or otherwise characterize the main pattern of an object. The second component of the word—<i>Wandel</i>—evokes the concept of more than slight changes; it means conversion. Thus, a structural transformation is not just any change, but a change in the essential elements of the construction giving it a novel quality. It is in this strong sense that Habermas understood his thesis of the structural transformation of the public sphere in his 1962 book. And he uses the same term 60 years later to claim a new stage in the development of the public sphere.</p><p>Hans Blumenberg has rightly argued that there is no such thing as a completely metaphor-free language (see Blumenberg, <span>1998</span>). So, let us think about changing our metaphorical vocabulary when we deal with changes in the public sphere! What about—<i>pace</i> Marx—the geological metaphor of “tectonic shifts”? This metaphor paints a different picture. It evokes the idea of the simultaneity of different fundamental movements—after all, the tectonic plates are the foundations of our living environment. Tectonic plates move simultaneously in different directions. Their movements are sometimes smooth and therefore unnoticed. Sometimes, however, their movements cause violent disturbances that destroy old structures in one fell swoop. Tectonic shifts affect everyone, but in different ways.</p><p>Some institutions of the public sphere no longer seem to change successively today, but—to stay with the metaphor—as earthquakes and volcanic eruptions. However, such massive changes may remain a locally disruptive phenomenon or may initiate a longer adjustment phase. Ultimately, question like these can only be answered by empirical research. Habermas himself was never reluctant to acknowledge the importance of empirical research for his political theory (see Buchstein, <span>2009</span>, pp. 422–423). With regard to less dramatic normal cases of tectonic shifts—readers of this article probably have suggestions for much better metaphors—they are in accordance with current empirical findings about everyday digital media use in modern democracies. The findings of several researchers do not support Habermas’ pessimistic conclusion about a new quality in the modes of political communication. “Echo chambers” and “bubbles” are exceptions rather than regular cases in today's political communication.<sup>7</sup> In addition, as Hartmut Rosa has convincingly argued, the fragmentation of online debates largely reflects the offline social fragmentation in late-modern societies (see Rosa, <span>2022</span>).<sup>8</sup></p><p>In 1992, Habermas wrote a self-critical comment about his seminal 1962 book: “My diagnosis of a unilinear development from a politically active public to one withdrawn into bad privacy [was] too simplistic” (1992, p. 438). Let us hope for the future of democracy that the diagnosis in his 2022 book is once again too unilinear and simplistic.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12661","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12661","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
In his political interventions, Jürgen Habermas is a first-class rhetorician. His writing style is eloquent, polemical, rich in aperçus and metaphors, and often affective, especially angry (see Möllers, 2021, p. 85). But there are also many metaphors in his contributions to philosophy, social theory, and political theory in which he clearly restrains himself rhetorically. Metaphors appear at crucial points in his theory formation. Formulations like the dialogical give and take of reasons “in kleiner Münze” (small coins), the discursive “Verflüssigung” (liquefaction) of traditions, the “colonization” of the lifeworld, the “center and periphery” of modern democracies, or their institutional “sluices”—a metaphor he has adopted from Bernhard Peters—create suggestive images in the minds of his readers. The author, who insists on the strict differentiation between day-to-day language, literary language, and the language of the social sciences (see Habermas, 1990a), and whose philosophical self-understanding insists on the “unforced force of the better argument” is a master of evocative metaphors. This attribute alone makes it a pleasure to read his texts.
The German edition of his new book does not disappoint those readers in search of metaphors either. In the Marxist tradition (see Marx, 2011), a number of metaphors are borrowed from the sphere of geology: “segments” (p. 33)1 of the population, “erosion” of democracy (p. 87), normative “slopes” (p. 15), the “crumbling” of the political system (p. 109), or the “solidified lava” of anti-authoritarianism in Silicon Valley (p. 46). Some of the metaphors are nautical like normative “anchors” (p. 16), or from the theatre, like the “grimace” of libertarian political thought (p. 46). Only a few of them belong to organic life: the “root ground” of political culture (p. 32), the “Gleichursprünglichkeit” (co-originality) of democracy and the rule of law (p. 90), or the “nesting” of normative expectations (p. 14). Most of Habermas’ metaphors belong to the vocabulary of the technical world: the “building” of modern democracy (p. 9), “centrifugal” forms of communication (p. 43), the “architecture” of constitutional democracy (p. 32), the “net of historical memory” (p. 30), the “Sollbruchstelle” (predetermined breaking point) of political rights (p. 92), the “web of attitudes” (p. 30), the “social bond” (p. 31), civil society as an “early warning system” (p. 80)—and again the “flow chart” of the political system and its “filters” and “sluices” (p. 24, 100). One has to wait until the last paragraph of the book to find a military metaphor. Now is the time “den Spieß umzudrehen”2 (p. 109) and fight the coalition of conspiracy theorists and right-wing populists.
Taking Habermas’ preference for technical metaphors into account, it comes as no surprise that he has speaks of “echo chambers” (p. 45) and “fragmentation” (p. 45) in his critical analysis of the digital public sphere. The spatial metaphor of öffentlicher Raum (Raum can literally be translated as unlimited space and as clearly limited room) is combined with the technical vocabulary of systems-theory when he mentions the “input,” “throughput,” and “output” components of the institutional infrastructure of the public sphere (pp. 38–39). In one passage of the book, Habermas even addresses the problems of metaphorical writing and states that his metaphor Raum “must not be overstated” (p. 60). He may have written this sentence from an unfortunate experience. More than once he has become the victim of his metaphor-rich writing style as critics have claimed that formulations like the “colonization of the lifeworld” are too vague to have real analytical power in the field of social research.
Another example is the term “ideal speech situation.” Habermas originally developed the ideal speech situation 1970 in On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction as an epistemological tool used to test the validity of what is essentially true or actually the case (see Habermas, 2001). In this new book, Habermas once again pushes back vehemently against the “stubborn misunderstanding” (p. 69) about this term. First, he points out that he has not used “this misleading expression” since his 1972 essay on theories of truth. Second, the catchy formulation was never meant to be a blueprint for political institutions, but as a metaphor for the bundle of pragmatic assumptions that we actually always have to start from when we enter into a discourse about validity claims.
Nevertheless, some early advocates of the digital revolution in the first half of the 1990s like Howard Rheingold, Nicolas Negroponte, or WIRED magazine authors like John Katz used Habermas’ notions of the ideal speech situation and the unrestricted flow of communication in the public sphere as justification for their dreams of a new virtual democracy.3 According to them, the World Wide Web was the technical incarnation of the ideal speech situation. In their view, the Internet matches all basic requirements of a public sphere that comes as close as possible to the normative core of deliberative democracy: The World Wide Web as the communicative infrastructure for open, unlimited, universal, anti-hierarchical, and complex political interaction. To the radical techno-optimists of those days, the Internet created a new political model, since it offered universal access, freedom of expression, unrestricted agendas, uncoerced communication, and political participation outside of traditional political institutions.
Habermas reminds the readers of his new book of the big “emancipatory promise” of the “egalitarian and unregulated” (p. 45) communicative relationships that were propagated at the beginning of the digital age. And indeed, the positive qualities attributed to political communication in the Internet by Rheingold and other optimists of electronic democracy in the 1990s strikingly resemble Habermas’ vocabulary (see Buchstein, 1997, pp. 250–251). In his book The Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas defined the public sphere as “a virtually present network of communication” (Habermas, 1987, p. 390) that is freed from any spatiotemporally restricted context. Ten years later, in his outline of the deliberative democratic ideal, he advocated a “decentred society” in which “subjectless forms of communication […] regulate the flow of deliberations” (Habermas, 1994, p. 7). According to him, “technologies of communication […] make possible a highly differentiated network of public spheres” (Habermas, 1990b, p. 360), The public sphere should consist of an “open and inclusive network of overlapping, subcultural politics having fluid temporal, social, and substantial boundaries” (Habermas, 1998, p. 306). In such a “discursive structuring of public networks and arenas,” popular sovereignty “becomes anonymous” (Habermas, 1998, p. 171).
In his new book, Habermas describes digital technology as a third evolutionary stage in the development of means for communication, following the writing of the spoken word a couple of thousand years ago and the introduction of the mechanical printing press at the beginning of early modernity. Despite the “revolutionary” (p. 41) change caused by digital technologies, he insists (again) on the social and political neutrality of new technologies. This position—already taken in the late 1960s by Herbert Marcuse—distinguishes Habermas’ argument from two rival positions within the Frankfurt School of Critical Theory. On the one hand, it departs from the optimistic positions taken by Walter Benjamin in his famous 1936 essay about the work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction or Hans-Magnus Enzensberger's Baukasten zu einer Theorie der Medien (1970). On the other hand, it also distances itself from Theodor W. Adorno's critique of alienated consumer culture and the thesis that the essence of the public sphere has been liquidated in the system of mass media in post-liberal societies.
Habermas stated in 1992 that the strong influence of Adorno's theory of mass culture was not difficult to discern in the first edition of Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere 30 years ago (see Habermas, 1992, p. 438). There is an element of coquetry in this retrospective statement because already in the early 1960s he had made the point that the consumerist public sphere in a capitalist society should and could be transformed into a more democratic postbourgeois public sphere. The solution he offered in a less known Encyclopedia article from 1964 was a call for political intervention in order to create “a rational reorganization of social and political power” (Habermas, 1974, p. 55). The public sphere should be brought “under the mutual control of rival organizations committed to the public sphere in their internal structure as well as in their relations with the state and each other” (Habermas, 1974, p. 55). This sounds like an early neo-corporatist expansion of the way public TV was organized in West Germany in those days. Based on his neutralist position, Habermas already in the very beginning of his work about the public sphere more than 60 years ago subscribed to a strategy of state intervention in order to re-regulate the media system.
His considerations in The Theory of Communicative Action of 1981 followed the same pattern. Relying on empirical research, he argued—explicitly against Adorno—that even in shifting from writing to images and sounds, electronic media—movie, radio, and TV—have not turned mass media into an apparatus that completely dominates and permeates the language of everyday communication. Instead, he emphasized the “ambivalence” (Habermas, 1987, p. 390) of modern mass media. But the “unleashing” of the “emancipatory potential,” which is “built into communicative structures themselves,” (Habermas, 1987, p. 390) in the mass media has to be set into action by political measures. Habermas even mentioned Hans Magnus Enzensberger's vision of “video pluralism” and “television democracy” as attempts to overcome the centralizing media networks in this context. Since then, Habermas has stated repeatedly that modern mass media could both strengthen or undermine the rationality of political communication, depending on the way the infrastructure of the public sphere is regulated (see Habermas, 1992, p. 437). Thirty years after Habermas first published his seminal book about the public sphere stated that there was “cause for a less pessimistic assessment” (Habermas, 1992, p. 457) of it and of the future of democracy itself. Another 30 years later, Habermas seems to have returned to pessimism.
In his new book, Habermas repeats older statements about the importance of an accommodating, enlightened liberal political culture as the necessary condition for the existence and further development of a democratic political order. His optimism about the further development of western democracies when he published the book Between Facts and Norms in 1992 was still based on his hypothesis about the long-term trend toward a rationalization of the lifeworld. Thanks to the support of post-conventional socialization patterns, families and groups of citizens enter a higher stage of cognitive and moral rationality within their everyday face-to-face communication that also radiates into political communication. As is well known, he adopted the concept of civil society from Andrew Arato and Jean Cohen and turned it into the institutional source for progressive changes of reasons, values, and topics that get transmitted via mass media to the center of the political system. He described civil society as a context of discovery of morally relevant questions arising from the lifeworld. He thus assumed that the lifeworld had a rational advantage in the perception of social problems that were to be transported via social movements and the voluntary associations of civil society into the public sphere.
Habermas’ overly positive evaluation of social movements and civil society in Between Facts and Norms ignored the fact that a number of voluntary associations already at that time pursued conservative, reactionary, populist, and militant right-wing political goals (see Buchstein, 1994, pp. 107–108). He restricted his considerations about civil society to the question of whether, and to what extent, a public sphere dominated by mass media could provide a realistic chance for the members of civil society to bring about political changes. In Between Facts and Norms, he was relatively optimistic about the possibility of further democratization. In his new book, Habermas is less optimistic. He puts more emphasis on the “vulnerability” (p. 30) of the results of socialization patterns and the precarious status of liberal democracies. He states “political regression” (p. 41) of liberal democracies around the world seems to have less confidence in the rationalization of the lifeworld.
There is a reason for this growing pessimism that has nothing to do with the current Zeitgeist, but follows from a subtle change in Habermas’ theory. At first glance, it seems that he is only updating his considerations about the organizational structure of the new media in order to make his argument about the new structural transformation. Both the neutralist position and the state-intervention strategy for a politics of reform and regulation can be found in his book again. Once again, he frames his reflections about the public sphere within his theory of deliberative democracy. He argues that the democratic legitimacy of modern democracies is based on the inclusiveness of the political public sphere. Mass media have an indispensable function, as they ensure the participation of citizens in a common, albeit anonymous, mass communication. Political opinions can only condense into effective public opinions and thus have a targeted influence on political decisions via the publicity of the mass media. Thus, it is imperative that the mass media have an “enlightening quality” (p. 23). The centrifugal dissolution of the limits of the simultaneously accelerated political communication to any number of participants at any distance has an “ambivalent explosive force” (p. 43). Referring to results of empirical research, Habermas notes that the deliberative quality of political communication in the internet is still an “open question” (p. 40).
According to Habermas, the “platform” (p. 44) character is what is “actually new about the new media” (p. 44). In other words, they enable all potential users to participate in the public sphere as independent authors with equal rights. Political communication no longer depends on traditional journalists or any other expert or institution for professional selection and discursive examination. But the services produced by new, privately owned social media platforms are “in no way neutral services” (p. 53). They are driven by the capitalist logic of profit-making that also puts pressure on the “old media” to adjust to the new format. According to Habermas, the emancipatory potential of the digital public sphere today is “übertönt” (p. 45, in the sense of dominated) by “fragmented publics” (p. 45), “bubbles” (p. 62), and “echo chambers” (p. 45). Both the basic standards for a rational debate and the inclusiveness of the public sphere are threatened to be lost. The stakes are high: the political integration of modern democracies is at risk.
It looks like a reminder of the final paragraphs of his first book on the public sphere and to his Encyclopedia article from the 1960s, when Habermas presents a strategy that includes three proposals to overcome this (newly) alarming decline of the public sphere. The first strategy counts on civic education: Citizens have to learn how to deal with this new technology in a reasonable way; and this may take some time (cf., pp. 46–47). The second strategy consists of strong state regulation of the mass media, for example, to force private owners of platforms in an effective way to correct false information or to prevent hate speech. Finally, the third reform strategy is to provide alternatives to the media power of privately owned companies. He proposes an expansion of financial support for state-funded and democratically controlled TV and radio stations (cf., p. 51 and 67), and even for (printed and digital) newspapers that fulfill certain quality standards (cf., p. 67).4
This reform agenda is conservative in that it attempts to carry the media organization of the 1970s into our digital age. In his 1962 book, he glorified the bourgeois public sphere. In his new book, he is again glorifying a media system of the past. I have listed his threefold political reform agenda because it provokes a non-trivial question: How is it possible to regulate the structures of political communication in a way that strengthens enlightened discussions via legislative measures, when such regulations (at least in democracies) have to be the result of (less enlightened) political communication?
In the context of this question, it is striking that face-to-face communication gains more relevance in Habermas’ theory than before. It is a subtle change. But it has the potential to produce more than just subtle changes to Habermas’ final evaluation of the prospects for political reform of the public sphere. In his characterization of elected parliaments Habermas notes that their members “deliberate and decide together [emphasis in original] according to democratic procedures” (p. 24). I will not discuss the problematic theory of parliamentarism in the context of this article, but I do want to point to his formulation “deliberate together [emphasis in original].” In my understanding, this formulation indicates a normative preference for political communication in social face-to-face constellations, which is typical for interaction in the lifeworld. In a different section of the book, Habermas explicitly praises the deliberative quality of parliamentary decision-making because decisions are made “face-to-face after democratic deliberations [emphasis in original]” (p. 102). He also attests to the courts “comparatively high level of rationality” (p. 78), which seems not only to be the result of its legal institutionalization but also due to the fact that court hearings and deliberations are held face-to-face. Finally, in his characterization of social movements and a vibrant civil society he emphasizes their “face-to-face encounters” (p. 39) in everyday life and public events.
In one of the most intriguing sections of the book, Habermas speculates about a changing perception by the users of social media in which the separation between public and private communication is abolished. According to him, a significant part of digital communication today should be understood neither as public nor as private. Rather it is a sphere of communication, which has been reserved until then for private correspondences by letter, that has been bloated to a public existence. It produces a “peculiar anonymous intimacy” (p. 62) which Habermas coins a “Halböffentlichkeit” (p. 65—semi-public sphere) of echo chambers and filter bubbles.5
However, this speculation puts Habermas in a dilemma. The lifeworld in Habermas’ theory is conceptualized as a linguistically organized and culturally transmitted stock of interpretative patterns which form the symbolic core of a society. He introduces the lifeworld as a necessary correlation to the notion of communicative action (see Baynes, 2016, pp. 64–70). The dilemma is the following one: On the one hand, Habermas continues to base the considerations in the book on the assumption of the rational potential of the lifeworld, in particular of face-to-face communication even in different social settings. On the other hand, his speculation provides the plausible assumption that under the conditions of the current digital communication infrastructure, there will be a massive unlearning of cognitive and moral competencies among users.
In his 1962 book, Habermas argued that with the growth of mass media, the laws of the capitalist markets eventually extend and penetrate “into the substance of the works itself” (Habermas, 1989, p. 165). This criticism was compatible with a neutralist position about new technology. In his current critique of social media, he can no longer maintain his neutralist position because he combines his observations about the semi-public sphere with the speculation that communication in such hybrid forms has the regressive effect of limited and “identity-preserving” (p. 61) moral and cognitive horizons for its users. This reduces the chances for Habermas’ reform agenda. The longer we wait for radical political reforms of the digital infrastructure, the less likely it is to win the support of democratic majorities (not to mention the problems of having to enforce them on a global scale). If we follow this line of argument, we end up with a much more pessimistic outlook than Habermas himself. But before taking Adorno's books on regressive mass culture from the shelf again, we should give empirical research a second look because there are reasons for moderate optimism. Could it be the case that Habermas is trapped in his analysis in the metaphorical language of “echo chambers” and “filter bubbles”?
Habermas’ metaphorical use of the term Strukturwandel (structural transformation) is also problematic. He did not invent this term for modern democratic theory. In 1932, Otto Kirchheimer spoke of the Strukturwandel of legitimacy in his criticism of Carl Schmitt's book on legality and legitimacy (see Kirchheimer, 2017, p. 381). And in the early years of the Federal Republic of Germany, Strukturwandel of democracy was used as a concept by constitutional lawyer Gerhard Leibholz to justify state financing of political parties (see Leibholz, 1958, pp. 79–129). Habermas’ original use of the term dates back to the late 1950s (see Yos, 2019, pp. 429–433). In his case, it was a transmission of Franz L. Neumanns's term Funktionswandel of 1937. Neumann had used the phrase to describe the decline of liberal rule of law in capitalist society (see Neumann, 1937). In his consideration of the public sphere, Habermas also dealt with a history of decline, but he substituted structure for function. Both Funktionswandel and Strukturwandel share the methodological approach to reconstruct historical changes in the development of capitalist societies as a unilinear sequence of clearly distinguishable stages.
In the way Habermas uses the term Strukturwandel, it is more than a rudimentary, ornamental, or weak metaphor. But even a weak metaphor fulfills the cognitive function of evoking an analogy in the realm of thought.6 Habermas’ use of the term Strukturwandel conjures up two images. First, the image of design or assembly, which goes back to the Latin word structuram; structures are the basic elements that support a building or otherwise characterize the main pattern of an object. The second component of the word—Wandel—evokes the concept of more than slight changes; it means conversion. Thus, a structural transformation is not just any change, but a change in the essential elements of the construction giving it a novel quality. It is in this strong sense that Habermas understood his thesis of the structural transformation of the public sphere in his 1962 book. And he uses the same term 60 years later to claim a new stage in the development of the public sphere.
Hans Blumenberg has rightly argued that there is no such thing as a completely metaphor-free language (see Blumenberg, 1998). So, let us think about changing our metaphorical vocabulary when we deal with changes in the public sphere! What about—pace Marx—the geological metaphor of “tectonic shifts”? This metaphor paints a different picture. It evokes the idea of the simultaneity of different fundamental movements—after all, the tectonic plates are the foundations of our living environment. Tectonic plates move simultaneously in different directions. Their movements are sometimes smooth and therefore unnoticed. Sometimes, however, their movements cause violent disturbances that destroy old structures in one fell swoop. Tectonic shifts affect everyone, but in different ways.
Some institutions of the public sphere no longer seem to change successively today, but—to stay with the metaphor—as earthquakes and volcanic eruptions. However, such massive changes may remain a locally disruptive phenomenon or may initiate a longer adjustment phase. Ultimately, question like these can only be answered by empirical research. Habermas himself was never reluctant to acknowledge the importance of empirical research for his political theory (see Buchstein, 2009, pp. 422–423). With regard to less dramatic normal cases of tectonic shifts—readers of this article probably have suggestions for much better metaphors—they are in accordance with current empirical findings about everyday digital media use in modern democracies. The findings of several researchers do not support Habermas’ pessimistic conclusion about a new quality in the modes of political communication. “Echo chambers” and “bubbles” are exceptions rather than regular cases in today's political communication.7 In addition, as Hartmut Rosa has convincingly argued, the fragmentation of online debates largely reflects the offline social fragmentation in late-modern societies (see Rosa, 2022).8
In 1992, Habermas wrote a self-critical comment about his seminal 1962 book: “My diagnosis of a unilinear development from a politically active public to one withdrawn into bad privacy [was] too simplistic” (1992, p. 438). Let us hope for the future of democracy that the diagnosis in his 2022 book is once again too unilinear and simplistic.
在他们看来,互联网符合公共领域的所有基本要求,尽可能接近协商民主的规范核心:万维网作为开放、无限、普遍、反等级和复杂的政治互动的交流基础设施。对于当时激进的技术乐观主义者来说,互联网创造了一种新的政治模式,因为它提供了普遍的访问、言论自由、不受限制的议程、不受强迫的交流以及传统政治机构之外的政治参与。哈贝马斯在他的新书中提醒读者,在数字时代之初传播的“平等主义和不受管制”(第45页)的交流关系的巨大“解放承诺”。事实上,Rheingold和其他20世纪90年代对电子民主持乐观态度的人认为,互联网上政治交流的积极品质与哈贝马斯的词汇惊人地相似(见Buchstein, 1997, pp. 250-251)。在他的著作《交际行为理论》中,哈贝马斯将公共领域定义为“一个实际上存在的交流网络”(哈贝马斯,1987,第390页),它从任何时空限制的语境中解放出来。十年后,在他对协商民主理想的概述中,他提倡一个“去中心的社会”,在这个社会中,“无主体的交流形式[…]调节审议的流动”(哈贝马斯,1994,第7页)。根据他的观点,“交流技术[…]使高度分化的公共领域网络成为可能”(哈贝马斯,1990b,第360页)。公共领域应该包括一个“开放和包容的重叠网络,亚文化政治具有流动的时间,社会,和实质性的边界”(哈贝马斯,1998,第306页)。在这种“公共网络和领域的话语结构”中,“人民主权”变得匿名”(哈贝马斯,1998,第171页)。在他的新书中,哈贝马斯将数字技术描述为通信手段发展的第三个进化阶段,继几千年前的口头文字和现代早期机械印刷机的引入之后。尽管数字技术带来了“革命性”的变化(第41页),但他(再次)坚持新技术的社会和政治中立性。这一立场——早在20世纪60年代末,赫伯特·马尔库斯就已经采取了这一立场——将哈贝马斯的论点与法兰克福批判理论学派中两个对立的立场区分开来。一方面,它背离了沃尔特·本雅明1936年关于机械复制时代艺术作品的著名文章或汉斯-马格努斯·恩森斯伯格(Hans-Magnus Enzensberger)的《媒介理论》(Baukasten zu einer Theorie der Medien, 1970)所持的乐观立场。另一方面,它也与西奥多·阿多诺(Theodor W. Adorno)对异化消费文化的批判以及公共领域的本质在后自由主义社会的大众传媒体系中被清算的论点保持距离。哈贝马斯在1992年指出,在30年前的《公共领域的结构转型》第一版中,不难看出阿多诺大众文化理论的强大影响(见哈贝马斯,1992,p. 438)。在这个回顾性的陈述中有一个调情的元素,因为早在20世纪60年代早期,他就提出了一个观点,即资本主义社会的消费主义公共领域应该也可以转变为一个更民主的后资产阶级公共领域。他在1964年的一篇不太为人所知的百科全书文章中提出的解决方案是呼吁政治干预,以创造“社会和政治权力的合理重组”(哈贝马斯,1974年,第55页)。公共领域应该“在内部结构以及与国家和彼此的关系中,置于致力于公共领域的敌对组织的相互控制之下”(哈贝马斯,1974,第55页)。这听起来像是当时西德公共电视组织方式的早期新社团主义扩张。基于他的中立立场,哈贝马斯早在60多年前关于公共领域的研究之初就赞同国家干预的策略,以重新规范媒体系统。他在1981年出版的《交际行为理论》(Theory of communication Action)中的思考也遵循了同样的模式。依靠实证研究,他认为——明确反对阿多诺——即使从文字转向图像和声音,电子媒体——电影、广播和电视——也没有把大众媒体变成一种完全支配和渗透日常交流语言的工具。相反,他强调现代大众传媒的“矛盾心理”(Habermas, 1987,第390页)。但是,“释放”大众传媒中的“解放潜力”,即“建立在传播结构本身”(哈贝马斯,1987,第390页),必须通过政治措施付诸行动。 哈贝马斯甚至提到汉斯·马格努斯·恩岑斯伯格的“视频多元主义”和“电视民主”愿景,试图在这种背景下克服媒体网络的集中化。从那以后,哈贝马斯一再强调,现代大众传媒既可以加强也可以破坏政治传播的合理性,这取决于公共领域基础设施的监管方式(见哈贝马斯,1992,第437页)。在哈贝马斯首次出版他关于公共领域的开创性著作30年后,他指出,对于公共领域和民主本身的未来,“有理由做出不那么悲观的评估”(哈贝马斯,1992年,第457页)。又过了30年,哈贝马斯似乎又回到了悲观主义。在他的新书中,哈贝马斯重复了以前关于包容的、开明的自由主义政治文化作为民主政治秩序存在和进一步发展的必要条件的重要性的陈述。1992年出版《事实与规范之间》(Between Facts and norm)一书时,他对西方民主国家进一步发展的乐观态度,仍然基于他对生活世界走向合理化的长期趋势的假设。由于后传统社会化模式的支持,家庭和公民群体在日常面对面的交流中进入了更高的认知和道德理性阶段,并辐射到政治交流中。众所周知,他借鉴了Andrew Arato和Jean Cohen的市民社会概念,并将其转化为理性、价值观和话题渐进式变化的制度源泉,通过大众传媒传播到政治体系的中心。他将公民社会描述为发现生活世界中产生的道德相关问题的环境。因此,他假设生活世界在感知社会问题方面具有理性优势,这些问题将通过社会运动和民间社会的自愿协会转移到公共领域。哈贝马斯在《事实与规范之间》中对社会运动和公民社会过于积极的评价忽略了这样一个事实,即当时已经有许多自愿协会追求保守的、反动的、民粹主义的和激进的右翼政治目标(见Buchstein, 1994,第107-108页)。他把他对公民社会的考虑限制在一个问题上,即一个由大众传播媒介主导的公共领域能否以及在多大程度上为公民社会成员提供实现政治变革的现实机会。在《事实与规范之间》中,他对进一步民主化的可能性持相对乐观的态度。在他的新书中,哈贝马斯没有那么乐观。他更加强调社会化模式的结果的“脆弱性”(第30页)和自由民主的不稳定状态。他指出,世界各地自由民主国家的“政治倒退”(第41页)似乎对生活世界的合理化缺乏信心。这种日益增长的悲观情绪是有原因的,与当前的时代精神无关,而是源于哈贝马斯理论的微妙变化。乍一看,他似乎只是在更新他对新媒体组织结构的思考,以提出他关于新结构转型的论点。在他的书中,可以再次找到中立主义立场和改革与监管政治的国家干预策略。再一次,他将他对公共领域的思考构建在他的协商民主理论中。他认为,现代民主国家的民主合法性建立在政治公共领域的包容性基础之上。大众传播媒介具有不可或缺的功能,因为它们确保公民参与共同的、尽管是匿名的大众传播。政治观点只有通过大众传媒的宣传才能凝聚成有效的民意,从而对政治决策产生有针对性的影响。因此,大众传播媒介必须具有“启发性”(第23页)。与任何距离的任何数量的参与者同时加速的政治交流的限制的离心解体具有一种“矛盾的爆发力”(第43页)。在引用实证研究的结果时,哈贝马斯指出,互联网上政治传播的审议质量仍然是一个“悬而未决的问题”(第40页)。根据哈贝马斯的说法,“平台”(第44页)的特征是“新媒体实际上是新的”(第44页)。换句话说,它们使所有潜在用户都能以独立作者的身份参与公共领域,享有平等的权利。政治传播不再依赖传统记者或任何其他专家或机构进行专业选择和话语检验。但是,新的私有社交媒体平台提供的服务“绝不是中立的服务”(第53页)。 它们是由资本主义的盈利逻辑驱动的,这也给“旧媒体”施加了压力,要求他们适应新的形式。根据哈贝马斯的说法,今天数字公共领域的解放潜力是“übertönt”(第45页,在被“碎片化的公众”(第45页)、“泡沫”(第62页)和“回音室”(第45页)所支配的意义上的。理性辩论的基本标准和公共领域的包容性都有可能丧失。风险很高:现代民主国家的政治一体化正处于危险之中。这似乎让人想起了他关于公共领域的第一本书的最后几段,以及他在20世纪60年代的百科全书文章,当时哈贝马斯提出了一种策略,其中包括三项建议,以克服这种(新出现的)令人担忧的公共领域衰退。第一个策略依赖于公民教育:公民必须学会如何以合理的方式处理这种新技术;这可能需要一些时间(参见第46-47页)。第二个策略包括对大众媒体进行强有力的国家监管,例如,迫使平台的私人所有者以有效的方式纠正虚假信息或防止仇恨言论。最后,第三个改革策略是为私营企业的媒体权力提供替代方案。他建议扩大对国家资助和民主控制的电视和广播电台的财政支持(参见第51和67页),甚至对达到某些质量标准的报纸(印刷和数字)的财政支持(参见第67页)。这一改革议程是保守的,因为它试图将20世纪70年代的媒体组织带入我们的数字时代。在他1962年出版的书中,他美化了资产阶级的公共领域。在他的新书中,他再次赞美了过去的媒体系统。我列出了他的三重政治改革议程,因为它引发了一个重要的问题:当这样的监管(至少在民主国家)必须是(不那么开明的)政治沟通的结果时,如何可能以一种通过立法措施加强开明讨论的方式来规范政治沟通的结构?在这个问题的背景下,面对面交流在哈贝马斯的理论中比以前获得了更多的相关性,这是令人惊讶的。这是一个微妙的变化。但它有可能产生比哈贝马斯对公共领域政治改革前景的最终评估的微妙变化更多的东西。哈贝马斯在他对选举议会的描述中指出,他们的成员“根据民主程序共同审议和决定”(原文强调)(第24页)。我不会在本文的背景下讨论议会制的问题理论,但我确实想指出他的表述“共同商议[原文强调]”。在我的理解中,这一表述表明了社会面对面星座对政治交流的规范性偏好,这是生活世界中典型的互动。在书的另一个部分,哈贝马斯明确赞扬了议会决策的审议质量,因为决策是“经过民主审议后面对面做出的[原文强调]”(第102页)。他还证明了法院“相对较高的理性水平”(第78页),这似乎不仅是其法律制度化的结果,也是由于法院听证会和审议是面对面进行的这一事实。最后,在他对社会运动和充满活力的公民社会的描述中,他强调了他们在日常生活和公共事件中的“面对面接触”(第39页)。在书中最有趣的部分之一,哈贝马斯推测了社交媒体用户不断变化的看法,在这种看法中,公共和私人交流之间的分离被废除了。据他说,今天数字通信的很大一部分既不应该被理解为公共的,也不应该被理解为私人的。更确切地说,这是一个交流的领域,在此之前,它一直是为私人信件保留的,现在已经膨胀到一个公共存在。它产生了一种“特殊的匿名亲密关系”(第62页),哈贝马斯创造了一个回音室和过滤气泡的“Halböffentlichkeit”(第65页-半公共领域)。然而,这种推测使哈贝马斯陷入了两难境地。在哈贝马斯的理论中,生活世界被概念化为一种语言组织和文化传播的解释模式,这些解释模式构成了社会的符号核心。他将生活世界作为交际行为概念的必要关联(见Baynes, 2016, pp. 64-70)。这个困境是这样的:一方面,哈贝马斯继续把书中的考虑建立在对生活世界的理性潜力的假设上,特别是在不同的社会环境中面对面的交流。 另一方面,他的推测提供了一个貌似合理的假设,即在当前数字通信基础设施的条件下,用户将大量忘记认知和道德能力。哈贝马斯在其1962年的著作中指出,随着大众传媒的发展,资本主义市场的规律最终延伸并渗透到“作品本身的实质”(哈贝马斯,1989年,第165页)。这种批评与对新技术持中立态度的立场是一致的。在他目前对社交媒体的批判中,他不能再保持中立的立场,因为他将他对半公共领域的观察与这种混合形式的交流对其用户的道德和认知视野的有限和“身份保留”(第61页)的推测结合起来。这减少了哈贝马斯改革议程的机会。我们等待数字基础设施的激进政治改革的时间越长,就越不可能赢得民主多数派的支持(更不用说必须在全球范围内实施这些改革的问题了)。如果我们遵循这个论点,我们最终会得到一个比哈贝马斯更悲观的观点。但在再次从书架上拿起阿多诺关于倒退的大众文化的书之前,我们应该再看看实证研究,因为我们有理由保持适度的乐观。哈贝马斯会不会被“回音室”和“过滤气泡”的隐喻语言所困?哈贝马斯对struckturwandel(结构转型)一词的隐喻性使用也存在问题。他并没有为现代民主理论发明这个术语。1932年,奥托·基希海默(Otto Kirchheimer)在批评卡尔·施密特(Carl Schmitt)关于合法性和合法性的著作时,谈到了合法性的Strukturwandel(见Kirchheimer, 2017, p. 381)。在德意志联邦共和国的早期,宪法律师格哈德·莱布霍尔兹(Gerhard Leibholz)将民主的Strukturwandel作为一个概念来为国家对政党的资助辩护(见莱布霍尔兹,1958,pp. 79-129)。哈贝马斯最初使用这一术语可以追溯到20世纪50年代末(见Yos, 2019,第429-433页)。在他的例子中,这是弗兰兹·l·诺伊曼(Franz L. neumann) 1937年的术语Funktionswandel的转译。诺伊曼用这个短语来描述资本主义社会自由法治的衰落(见诺伊曼,1937)。在他对公共领域的思考中,哈贝马斯也处理了衰落的历史,但他用结构代替了功能。Funktionswandel和Strukturwandel都将资本主义社会发展的历史变化重构为一个明显可区分的阶段的线性序列。在哈贝马斯使用Strukturwandel这个词的方式中,它不仅仅是一个基本的,装饰性的,或弱的隐喻。但是,即使是一个微弱的隐喻,也能在思想领域实现唤起类比的认知功能哈贝马斯对Strukturwandel一词的使用让人联想到两幅画面。首先是设计或装配的形象,这可以追溯到拉丁语structuram;结构是支撑建筑物或以其他方式表征物体主要模式的基本元素。“wandel”这个词的第二个组成部分唤起了不止轻微变化的概念;它意味着转换。因此,结构转型不仅仅是任何变化,而是建筑基本要素的变化,赋予其新颖的品质。正是在这种强烈的意义上,哈贝马斯理解了他在1962年出版的书中关于公共领域结构转型的论点。60年后,他用同样的术语来宣称公共领域的发展进入了一个新阶段。汉斯·布鲁门伯格正确地指出,不存在完全没有隐喻的语言(见布鲁门伯格,1998)。所以,让我们在处理公共领域的变化时,考虑改变我们的隐喻词汇吧!那么——佩斯·马克思——“构造转移”的地质隐喻呢?这个比喻描绘了一幅不同的画面。它唤起了不同基本运动同时发生的想法——毕竟,构造板块是我们生存环境的基础。构造板块同时向不同方向移动。他们的动作有时很平稳,因此不被注意。然而,有时他们的行动会引起剧烈的骚乱,一举摧毁旧建筑。构造变化影响着每个人,但方式不同。今天,公共领域的一些机构似乎不再连续地发生变化,而是像地震和火山爆发一样。然而,这种巨大的变化可能仍然是一种局部破坏性现象,或者可能开始一个较长的调整阶段。最终,像这样的问题只能通过实证研究来回答。哈贝马斯本人从不不愿意承认实证研究对他的政治理论的重要性(见Buchstein, 2009,第422-423页)。 至于不那么引人注目的结构性转变的正常案例——本文的读者可能会有更好的比喻——它们与现代民主国家日常数字媒体使用的实证研究结果一致。几位研究者的发现并不支持哈贝马斯关于政治传播模式新特性的悲观结论。在今天的政治交流中,“回音室”和“泡沫”是例外,而不是常见的情况此外,正如哈特穆特·罗莎(Hartmut Rosa)令人信服地指出的那样,在线辩论的碎片化在很大程度上反映了后现代社会中线下社会的碎片化(见罗莎,2022)。1992年,哈贝马斯对他1962年的开创性著作写了一篇自我批评的评论:“我对从政治活跃的公众到退缩到糟糕的隐私的线性发展的诊断过于简单化了”(1992年,第438页)。希望他在2022年出版的书中对民主的诊断再次过于单线化和简单化。