Fumbling for the New and Unknown. On the Emergence of Epistemic Things in G. Ch. Lichtenberg's Sudelbücher**

IF 0.6 2区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
Elisabetta Mengaldo
{"title":"Fumbling for the New and Unknown. On the Emergence of Epistemic Things in G. Ch. Lichtenberg's Sudelbücher**","authors":"Elisabetta Mengaldo","doi":"10.1002/bewi.202200033","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In the writings of the polymath and experimental scientist Georg Christoph Lichtenberg (1742–1799) one sometimes comes across startlingly modern observations on the phenomenology of scientific activity, for example on the relationship between experiment and hypothesis, on the role of contingence in scientific discoveries, or on the dialectic between the invention of the new and the arrangement of accumulated knowledge. In a record of his private notebooks, known as <i>Sudelbücher</i> (“Waste Books”), he casually notes what constitutes a pure demonstration experiment:</p><p>Now that we know nature, even a child understands that an experiment is nothing more than a compliment paid to it. It is a mere ceremony. We know its answers beforehand. We ask nature for its consensus as the great lords ask the estates.<sup>1</sup></p><p>Demonstration experiments were common around the eighteenth century, not only for didactic purposes, but also in the many forms of spectacularization of science, which concerned in particular a then new and mysterious field of knowledge: electricity. The aforementioned definition, however, also brings with it an implicit distinction between a demonstration experiment and a proper experiment: in the former, phenomena we already know are just confirmed and displayed; in the second, something new, which we haven't discovered yet, comes forth. It was precisely this dialectic of expectability and surprise, typical of scientific activity, that engrossed Ludwik Fleck in the twentieth century. According to Fleck, valuable experiments are always “unclear, unfinished, unique”;<sup>2</sup> as soon as they become clear and arbitrarily reproducible, they are at best suited for demonstration purposes, but no longer useful for research purposes, for “the richer the unknown, the newer the field of research, the less clear the experiments are.”<sup>3</sup> Hans-Jörg Rheinberger later took this tension further and reformulated it as a relationship between “epistemic things” and “technical objects.”</p><p>In his epochal book <i>Toward a History of Epistemic Things</i> (1997), Rheinberger defines experimental systems as “the smallest integral working units of research,” which “give unknown answers to questions that the experimenters themselves are not yet able clearly to ask.”<sup>4</sup> Quoting François Jacob, he also calls them “machines for making the future.”<sup>5</sup> Experimental systems consist of two components: epistemic things and technical objects. The research object is defined as an epistemic thing, which means “material entities or processes—physical structures, chemical reactions, biological functions—that constitute the objects of inquiry.” These objects “present themselves in a characteristic, irreducible vagueness,” which is indispensable, because “paradoxically, epistemic things embody what one does not yet know.”<sup>6</sup> Rheinberger explicitly follows Bruno Latour's idea of the indefinability of the new research object. Technical objects, on the other hand, are to be understood as the material, technical arrangement, that makes the production of epistemic things possible in the first place: “instruments, inscription devices, model organisms, and the floating theorems or boundary concepts attached to them.”<sup>7</sup> Thus, epistemic things build a bridge into the future, while technical objects remain anchored in the present: “A technical product […] is an answering machine,” whereas “an epistemic object is first and foremost a question-generating machine”.<sup>8</sup> Epistemic things, however, can in turn transform into technical objects, which then again (in a productive dialectic between stable-known devices and new-unknown objects of inquiry), help to bring forth new epistemic things.</p><p>In the research systems, epistemic things have three important properties. One should first of all distinguish epistemic things from epistemic objects: in Bruno Latour's concept of non-human actors the latter are pure and objective facts (“matter of facts”), whereas epistemic things also fulfil an inner, emotional concern, thus “matters of concern.”<sup>9</sup> The second aspect is the constitutive theoretical, medial, and technical hybridity of epistemic things, and thus also the constitutive provisionality of their definitions. Eventually, the emergence of epistemic things is not a matter of pure theory and speculation, but is always linked to epistemic practices such as experimental arrangements, measurements, representation procedures, and so on.</p><p> </p><p>In this paper, I will attempt to describe Lichtenberg's <i>Sudelbücher</i> as the site of the serendipitous encounter of two practices, both central to the natural scientist <i>and</i> to the writer: writing down collected data (observations, experimental protocols, calculations, etc.) and experimenting in order to be able to produce the new and coveted but as yet undefined object of research (the epistemic thing) from a given and more or less fixed setting (the technical thing). Thus, these texts set in motion a peculiar feedback between repetition and renewal. On the one hand, they operate with traditional procedures of classification and representation of already known information assets (in terms of the history of knowledge: with taxonomies; in rhetorical terms: with <i>inventio</i> and <i>ars topica</i>). On the other hand, they attempt to generate new ideas and peculiar thought experiments from the archived written material and from the witty associations that spring from it. Rhetorical <i>inventio</i> becomes scientific invention.<sup>10</sup></p><p>As a scientist, Lichtenberg was primarily concerned with the epistemic thing of the eighteenth century par excellence—electricity. In the history of science, his name is linked to the discovery of the electric figures named after him, which consist of branching electric discharges that sometimes appears on the surface or in the interior of insulating materials. His Essay <i>Von einer neuen Art, die Natur und Bewegung der elektrischen Materie zu erforschen</i> (1778), with which he informed the scientific community about his discovery, is also interesting for historical epistemology as well as for the rhetoric of science for several reasons. First, because Lichtenberg is fully aware of the role of chance in the discovery process and reflects on it several times in this text. Second, because the invisible epistemic thing called electricity produces effects (the figures, precisely, that look like snowflakes or flowers) that also have aesthetic appeal. Their particular beauty, which Lichtenberg describes with delight, even seems to be the necessary equivalent of their definitional vagueness. Thirdly, because this text employs several narrative procedures that reveal it to be a perfect example of the auctorial science narration still typical in the eighteenth century.<sup>11</sup></p><p>But what do Lichtenberg's <i>Sudelbücher</i> have to do with epistemic things? First of all, it is important to say that they are not diaries, because they are mostly not dated. Lichtenberg entrusted all sorts of thoughts to the <i>Sudelbücher</i>, in which he made notes very regularly: experimental protocols, cursory observations, calculations, funny ideas and linguistic jokes, quotations from other books with his own commentary, drafts of short essays to be published in journals, and more. The thematic spectrum is very heterogeneous and by no means limited to questions of experimental science or laboratory technology; it extends to anthropological-psychological, literary-critical, and political topics. Although Lichtenberg, from the <i>Sudelbuch</i> H onwards, noted down his scientific and humanistic notes separately,<sup>12</sup> the interaction of the “two cultures”<sup>13</sup> is constitutive for these notebooks, which served him also as research notebooks in the broadest sense of the word.</p><p>The term <i>Zettelwirtschaft</i> (“economy of the scribble”) coined by Rheinberger in <i>An Epistemology of the Concrete</i> can be applied well to these notebooks, because it turns out to be the expression par excellence of a science in the making. The terms encapsulates the “rough notes, scrips and scribblings, and revised write-ups that offer insight into concrete processes of knowledge formation” and are therefore “still of the order of the experimental engagement and entanglement.”<sup>14</sup> Among the numerous tools of knowledge that accompany modern research practices (laboratory tools, experimental arrangements, libraries, archives, etc.) there is thus the desk as well, which has the status of a research laboratory in the broadest sense. As an expression of a science in the making, however, and precisely because of their provisionality, small and unfinished text formats such as notes, scribbles, slips of paper, etc., turn out to be the media par excellence for the production of new epistemic things, one of whose central characteristics is provisional vagueness.</p><p>The <i>Sudelbücher</i> are a vast repository in which the act of writing things down first serves to stabilize knowledge; but at the same time, they prove to be a sort of research site for questioning numerous objects of knowledge and for provisionally answering the questions that Lichtenberg keeps asking himself the whole time. Thus, the scene of writing becomes here “the arena of knowledge and of its emergence.”<sup>15</sup> The three over-mentioned factors that play a role in the emergence of epistemic things can be observed in them. Firstly, the private character of these notebooks automatically makes the topics they deal with matters of concern: not or not only supposedly objective facts are dealt with here, but things that concern the author, that is, things to which an affective and emotional investment is attached. Secondly, they are necessarily bound to an epistemic practice—in this case, to the act of writing down—in which the relevance of the things, and thus their emergence at all, first appears. Thirdly, Lichtenberg's epistemic things are hybrid objects of knowledge that are investigated through his scribble economy, and the <i>Sudelbuch</i> is the technical medium in which the questioning of these things unfolds.<sup>16</sup> The hybridity of this small, provisional prose, as well as its text-genetic status as a work in progress, makes it an excellent epistemic and poetological engine, capable of maintaining the difficult balance between a firmly consolidated, stored knowledge and the open thought experiments that generate new knowledge.</p><p> </p><p>In the following, I will take a closer look at one notebook—notebook J. This notebook (or rather: its scientific half) occupies a special place in the <i>Sudelbücher</i>, because its entries can also be read firstly as notes on a planned compendium of physics, and secondly as private comments on what was probably the most important handbook of physics at the time, the <i>Anfangsgründe der Naturlehre</i> (1772) by Johann Polycarp Erxleben, Lichtenberg's predecessor in the chair of experimental physics in Göttingen. Lichtenberg used this compendium as the basis for his lectures, and after Erxleben's death (1777) he published four further editions of it. His handwritten marginalia in the handbook were not only used for the lecture, but many of them were included in the next editions in the form of additions and improvements. The records from notebook J were written between the beginning of 1789 and April 1793, the period in which almost all the marginalia in Lichtenberg's hand copy of the 4th edition of the <i>Anfangsgründe der Naturlehre</i> were written as well.<sup>17</sup> It is worth comparing some passages, also with regard to the emergence of epistemic things.</p><p>First of all, it is remarkable that the half of notebook J that deals with scientific topics is titled “1789. Miscellaneous notes (actually just a finger pointing) about physics and mathematics.”<sup>18</sup> The gesture of finger-pointing refers to future knowledge that can only be hinted at, and the notes are rather directional approximations whose intuitive moment, however, makes them all the more valuable despite or precisely because of their fleetingness.<sup>19</sup> This heading is followed by methodical instructions on how to produce the new, however improbable and absurd it may seem in the present: “Since everyone immediately thinks of the ordinary, go at once deliberately to the unusual and uncommon. Sexus plantarum, Sexus astrorum, acidorum et alcalinorum pp.” (J 1254) Scattered throughout the notebook are thoughts that highlight the difficulty and, at the same time, the inevitability of re-thinking, which can be fostered by the attitude of doubting and questioning in the first place, such as in the following entries:</p><p>Questioning things that are now believed without further investigation—that is the main thing everywhere. (J 1276)</p><p>On the reason why it is so difficult to invent something new and useful. (J 1279)</p><p>Why do I believe this? Is it really made up like this [.] (J 1326)<sup>20</sup></p><p>The fact that they are provisional and rather heuristic thoughts is also proved by their elliptical structure, for they are often unfinished sentences (e. g., infinitive clauses). According to my thesis, the whole notebook J therefore reads as a self-discipline guide, in order to learn thinking differently and producing bizarre connections of thought, which can promote the emergence of new epistemic things.</p><p>Sometimes a shift from technical objects to epistemic things becomes visible in the notebooks. From the 3rd edition of the <i>Anfangsgründe</i> (1784) onwards, Lichtenberg precedes the beginning of Erxleben's paragraphs with a “Description of Smeaton's Air Pump” (which had been fabricated by the British engineer John Smeaton in 1771). At the end he describes his personal variant of the air pump (provided with an illustration, see Figure 1): here, a tube is attached that is connected at the other end to a bell through which the air is sucked up.\n</p><p>Then Lichtenberg adds:</p><p>In passing I note that the connection of the tube to the bell is most conveniently made by means of a small resin vial, for in this way the bell can still be turned and adjusted without damaging the tube, which is fixed tightly to the pump.<sup>21</sup></p><p>The “small resin vial” is here only a small technical device that facilitates the functioning of the air pump. A few years later (1790), however, a peculiar development takes place in notebook J. Along a few notes, Lichtenberg ponders various phenomena during extreme temperature changes. J 1261 is a sort of methodical instruction that follows the short report (J 1260) on a real experiment of his own with heat and cold: “Something quite paradoxical about this, which no man can yet have easily thought of” (J 1261).<sup>22</sup> Paradoxical ideas are thus not only possible, but they prove to be very useful because they can trigger further, inventive thoughts. What now follows is a truly bizarre thought experiment about the freezing of cities:</p><p>It is not at all difficult to produce heat in the greatest cold, but it requires much skill to produce cold in great heat. It is possible to burn down a house and towns in the greatest cold, but as yet we know of no means of making the people in one village freeze to death while the others nearby have the most pleasant summer. In itself, the one is as little impossible as the other. (J 1262)<sup>23</sup></p><p>A few pages further down, Lichtenberg notes a thought experiment by Erasmus Darwin, which he had formulated in an essay on freezing experiments published in 1788 in the <i>Philosophical Transactions</i>:</p><p>Mr. Darwin believes in his beautiful frigorific Experiments on the mechanical Expansion of air (Philos. Trans[actions] Vol. 1788) that one will perhaps seriously learn once more to make the wind, as I do of the freezing of cities. Monstrous thoughts also have their uses. (J 1380)<sup>24</sup></p><p>Here, the idea of “monstrous thoughts” refers back to Lichtenberg's own idea of the “freezing of the cities.” This then triggers the next note, which also belongs to his own methodological guideline: “Can a monstrous thought be attached here, as those in the preceding §. are” (J 1381).<sup>25</sup> Two entries further down, we finally encounter the very resin vial that figured as a small technical device in the description of Smeaton's air pump: “To fill a resin vial with powder like a cannon cracker and to ignite it” (J 1383).<sup>26</sup> This strange, witty link of thought obviously plays on the idea of a quite concrete monstrosity—the danger of destruction by this novel weapon. There follows another entry with its own little thought experiment (which, as is often the case, is formulated as a conditional clause<sup>27</sup>) about the substitution of cupping glasses with resin vials:</p><p>In the bath I found that the resin vials suck in excellently, if one could give them even more elasticity, or if one could have them even stiffer than my flaky one, then they could be used quite well instead of the cupping glasses. (J 1384)<sup>28</sup></p><p>In the last examples given above, it is obvious that the small resin vial in the <i>Sudelbücher</i> is not merely a technical device within a larger apparatus (as Lichtenberg's description of the air pump in the compendium), but it is repurposed to reveal another epistemic thing, even if only as a little thought-experimental fantasy or in a monstrous idea like the record about the cannon cracket. And indeed, further down in notebook J, Lichtenberg wonders whether his own instruments can be converted and repurposed:</p><p>Must once go through my entire cabinet with the question: what else can this instrument be used for apart from its actual purpose. I believe that I will be able to save a lot by doing this. For example, the lamps of the pyrometer could be used quite well for Kempelen's machine. Pockholz's balls in electrical experiments. […] (J 2138)<sup>29</sup></p><p>Thus, the familiar technical object serves to generate new epistemic things when placed in a different context—in a different experimental system.<sup>30</sup> Because it often produces bizarre ideas and “monstrous thoughts,” the investigation of new epistemic things tends to be commended to the private <i>Sudelbücher</i> and not to the glosses on Erxleben's compendium; to the conversation with himself and not to the (often agonally colored) dialogue with his predecessor. No coincidence, then, that they are sometimes born at night time. The aforementioned entry J 2138 ends with this very personal note: “This can become a good occupation during sleepless nights.”<sup>31</sup> In his considerations on the economy of the scribble, Rheinberger takes on François Jacob's concept of “night science” (in contrast to the well-ordered “day science”), of which the research notes form a “residuum”:</p><p>By contrast, night science wanders blind. It hesitates, stumbles, recoils, sweats, wakes with a start. Doubting everything, it is forever trying to find itself, question itself, pull itself back together. Night science is a sort of workshop of the possible where what will become the building material of science is worked out. Where hypotheses remain in the form of vague presentiments and woolly impressions. Where phenomena are still no more than solitary events with no link between them. Where the design of experiments has barely taken shape. Where thought makes its way along meandering paths and twisting lanes, most often leading nowhere.<sup>32</sup></p><p>The <i>Sudelbücher</i> prove to be not only a scientific but also an epistemological question-generating machine. They are the ideal place for thought experiments, for witty associations, thus for the extension to other fields of knowledge—to other experimental systems. The new epistemic things emerging here appear as “vague presentiments”; the fact that they are entrusted to these private notebooks automatically makes them not cold objects of research, but highly personal and warm matters of concern.</p>","PeriodicalId":55388,"journal":{"name":"Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6000,"publicationDate":"2022-09-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://ftp.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pub/pmc/oa_pdf/06/f9/BEWI-45-452.PMC9544490.pdf","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/bewi.202200033","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

In the writings of the polymath and experimental scientist Georg Christoph Lichtenberg (1742–1799) one sometimes comes across startlingly modern observations on the phenomenology of scientific activity, for example on the relationship between experiment and hypothesis, on the role of contingence in scientific discoveries, or on the dialectic between the invention of the new and the arrangement of accumulated knowledge. In a record of his private notebooks, known as Sudelbücher (“Waste Books”), he casually notes what constitutes a pure demonstration experiment:

Now that we know nature, even a child understands that an experiment is nothing more than a compliment paid to it. It is a mere ceremony. We know its answers beforehand. We ask nature for its consensus as the great lords ask the estates.1

Demonstration experiments were common around the eighteenth century, not only for didactic purposes, but also in the many forms of spectacularization of science, which concerned in particular a then new and mysterious field of knowledge: electricity. The aforementioned definition, however, also brings with it an implicit distinction between a demonstration experiment and a proper experiment: in the former, phenomena we already know are just confirmed and displayed; in the second, something new, which we haven't discovered yet, comes forth. It was precisely this dialectic of expectability and surprise, typical of scientific activity, that engrossed Ludwik Fleck in the twentieth century. According to Fleck, valuable experiments are always “unclear, unfinished, unique”;2 as soon as they become clear and arbitrarily reproducible, they are at best suited for demonstration purposes, but no longer useful for research purposes, for “the richer the unknown, the newer the field of research, the less clear the experiments are.”3 Hans-Jörg Rheinberger later took this tension further and reformulated it as a relationship between “epistemic things” and “technical objects.”

In his epochal book Toward a History of Epistemic Things (1997), Rheinberger defines experimental systems as “the smallest integral working units of research,” which “give unknown answers to questions that the experimenters themselves are not yet able clearly to ask.”4 Quoting François Jacob, he also calls them “machines for making the future.”5 Experimental systems consist of two components: epistemic things and technical objects. The research object is defined as an epistemic thing, which means “material entities or processes—physical structures, chemical reactions, biological functions—that constitute the objects of inquiry.” These objects “present themselves in a characteristic, irreducible vagueness,” which is indispensable, because “paradoxically, epistemic things embody what one does not yet know.”6 Rheinberger explicitly follows Bruno Latour's idea of the indefinability of the new research object. Technical objects, on the other hand, are to be understood as the material, technical arrangement, that makes the production of epistemic things possible in the first place: “instruments, inscription devices, model organisms, and the floating theorems or boundary concepts attached to them.”7 Thus, epistemic things build a bridge into the future, while technical objects remain anchored in the present: “A technical product […] is an answering machine,” whereas “an epistemic object is first and foremost a question-generating machine”.8 Epistemic things, however, can in turn transform into technical objects, which then again (in a productive dialectic between stable-known devices and new-unknown objects of inquiry), help to bring forth new epistemic things.

In the research systems, epistemic things have three important properties. One should first of all distinguish epistemic things from epistemic objects: in Bruno Latour's concept of non-human actors the latter are pure and objective facts (“matter of facts”), whereas epistemic things also fulfil an inner, emotional concern, thus “matters of concern.”9 The second aspect is the constitutive theoretical, medial, and technical hybridity of epistemic things, and thus also the constitutive provisionality of their definitions. Eventually, the emergence of epistemic things is not a matter of pure theory and speculation, but is always linked to epistemic practices such as experimental arrangements, measurements, representation procedures, and so on.

 

In this paper, I will attempt to describe Lichtenberg's Sudelbücher as the site of the serendipitous encounter of two practices, both central to the natural scientist and to the writer: writing down collected data (observations, experimental protocols, calculations, etc.) and experimenting in order to be able to produce the new and coveted but as yet undefined object of research (the epistemic thing) from a given and more or less fixed setting (the technical thing). Thus, these texts set in motion a peculiar feedback between repetition and renewal. On the one hand, they operate with traditional procedures of classification and representation of already known information assets (in terms of the history of knowledge: with taxonomies; in rhetorical terms: with inventio and ars topica). On the other hand, they attempt to generate new ideas and peculiar thought experiments from the archived written material and from the witty associations that spring from it. Rhetorical inventio becomes scientific invention.10

As a scientist, Lichtenberg was primarily concerned with the epistemic thing of the eighteenth century par excellence—electricity. In the history of science, his name is linked to the discovery of the electric figures named after him, which consist of branching electric discharges that sometimes appears on the surface or in the interior of insulating materials. His Essay Von einer neuen Art, die Natur und Bewegung der elektrischen Materie zu erforschen (1778), with which he informed the scientific community about his discovery, is also interesting for historical epistemology as well as for the rhetoric of science for several reasons. First, because Lichtenberg is fully aware of the role of chance in the discovery process and reflects on it several times in this text. Second, because the invisible epistemic thing called electricity produces effects (the figures, precisely, that look like snowflakes or flowers) that also have aesthetic appeal. Their particular beauty, which Lichtenberg describes with delight, even seems to be the necessary equivalent of their definitional vagueness. Thirdly, because this text employs several narrative procedures that reveal it to be a perfect example of the auctorial science narration still typical in the eighteenth century.11

But what do Lichtenberg's Sudelbücher have to do with epistemic things? First of all, it is important to say that they are not diaries, because they are mostly not dated. Lichtenberg entrusted all sorts of thoughts to the Sudelbücher, in which he made notes very regularly: experimental protocols, cursory observations, calculations, funny ideas and linguistic jokes, quotations from other books with his own commentary, drafts of short essays to be published in journals, and more. The thematic spectrum is very heterogeneous and by no means limited to questions of experimental science or laboratory technology; it extends to anthropological-psychological, literary-critical, and political topics. Although Lichtenberg, from the Sudelbuch H onwards, noted down his scientific and humanistic notes separately,12 the interaction of the “two cultures”13 is constitutive for these notebooks, which served him also as research notebooks in the broadest sense of the word.

The term Zettelwirtschaft (“economy of the scribble”) coined by Rheinberger in An Epistemology of the Concrete can be applied well to these notebooks, because it turns out to be the expression par excellence of a science in the making. The terms encapsulates the “rough notes, scrips and scribblings, and revised write-ups that offer insight into concrete processes of knowledge formation” and are therefore “still of the order of the experimental engagement and entanglement.”14 Among the numerous tools of knowledge that accompany modern research practices (laboratory tools, experimental arrangements, libraries, archives, etc.) there is thus the desk as well, which has the status of a research laboratory in the broadest sense. As an expression of a science in the making, however, and precisely because of their provisionality, small and unfinished text formats such as notes, scribbles, slips of paper, etc., turn out to be the media par excellence for the production of new epistemic things, one of whose central characteristics is provisional vagueness.

The Sudelbücher are a vast repository in which the act of writing things down first serves to stabilize knowledge; but at the same time, they prove to be a sort of research site for questioning numerous objects of knowledge and for provisionally answering the questions that Lichtenberg keeps asking himself the whole time. Thus, the scene of writing becomes here “the arena of knowledge and of its emergence.”15 The three over-mentioned factors that play a role in the emergence of epistemic things can be observed in them. Firstly, the private character of these notebooks automatically makes the topics they deal with matters of concern: not or not only supposedly objective facts are dealt with here, but things that concern the author, that is, things to which an affective and emotional investment is attached. Secondly, they are necessarily bound to an epistemic practice—in this case, to the act of writing down—in which the relevance of the things, and thus their emergence at all, first appears. Thirdly, Lichtenberg's epistemic things are hybrid objects of knowledge that are investigated through his scribble economy, and the Sudelbuch is the technical medium in which the questioning of these things unfolds.16 The hybridity of this small, provisional prose, as well as its text-genetic status as a work in progress, makes it an excellent epistemic and poetological engine, capable of maintaining the difficult balance between a firmly consolidated, stored knowledge and the open thought experiments that generate new knowledge.

 

In the following, I will take a closer look at one notebook—notebook J. This notebook (or rather: its scientific half) occupies a special place in the Sudelbücher, because its entries can also be read firstly as notes on a planned compendium of physics, and secondly as private comments on what was probably the most important handbook of physics at the time, the Anfangsgründe der Naturlehre (1772) by Johann Polycarp Erxleben, Lichtenberg's predecessor in the chair of experimental physics in Göttingen. Lichtenberg used this compendium as the basis for his lectures, and after Erxleben's death (1777) he published four further editions of it. His handwritten marginalia in the handbook were not only used for the lecture, but many of them were included in the next editions in the form of additions and improvements. The records from notebook J were written between the beginning of 1789 and April 1793, the period in which almost all the marginalia in Lichtenberg's hand copy of the 4th edition of the Anfangsgründe der Naturlehre were written as well.17 It is worth comparing some passages, also with regard to the emergence of epistemic things.

First of all, it is remarkable that the half of notebook J that deals with scientific topics is titled “1789. Miscellaneous notes (actually just a finger pointing) about physics and mathematics.”18 The gesture of finger-pointing refers to future knowledge that can only be hinted at, and the notes are rather directional approximations whose intuitive moment, however, makes them all the more valuable despite or precisely because of their fleetingness.19 This heading is followed by methodical instructions on how to produce the new, however improbable and absurd it may seem in the present: “Since everyone immediately thinks of the ordinary, go at once deliberately to the unusual and uncommon. Sexus plantarum, Sexus astrorum, acidorum et alcalinorum pp.” (J 1254) Scattered throughout the notebook are thoughts that highlight the difficulty and, at the same time, the inevitability of re-thinking, which can be fostered by the attitude of doubting and questioning in the first place, such as in the following entries:

Questioning things that are now believed without further investigation—that is the main thing everywhere. (J 1276)

On the reason why it is so difficult to invent something new and useful. (J 1279)

Why do I believe this? Is it really made up like this [.] (J 1326)20

The fact that they are provisional and rather heuristic thoughts is also proved by their elliptical structure, for they are often unfinished sentences (e. g., infinitive clauses). According to my thesis, the whole notebook J therefore reads as a self-discipline guide, in order to learn thinking differently and producing bizarre connections of thought, which can promote the emergence of new epistemic things.

Sometimes a shift from technical objects to epistemic things becomes visible in the notebooks. From the 3rd edition of the Anfangsgründe (1784) onwards, Lichtenberg precedes the beginning of Erxleben's paragraphs with a “Description of Smeaton's Air Pump” (which had been fabricated by the British engineer John Smeaton in 1771). At the end he describes his personal variant of the air pump (provided with an illustration, see Figure 1): here, a tube is attached that is connected at the other end to a bell through which the air is sucked up.

Then Lichtenberg adds:

In passing I note that the connection of the tube to the bell is most conveniently made by means of a small resin vial, for in this way the bell can still be turned and adjusted without damaging the tube, which is fixed tightly to the pump.21

The “small resin vial” is here only a small technical device that facilitates the functioning of the air pump. A few years later (1790), however, a peculiar development takes place in notebook J. Along a few notes, Lichtenberg ponders various phenomena during extreme temperature changes. J 1261 is a sort of methodical instruction that follows the short report (J 1260) on a real experiment of his own with heat and cold: “Something quite paradoxical about this, which no man can yet have easily thought of” (J 1261).22 Paradoxical ideas are thus not only possible, but they prove to be very useful because they can trigger further, inventive thoughts. What now follows is a truly bizarre thought experiment about the freezing of cities:

It is not at all difficult to produce heat in the greatest cold, but it requires much skill to produce cold in great heat. It is possible to burn down a house and towns in the greatest cold, but as yet we know of no means of making the people in one village freeze to death while the others nearby have the most pleasant summer. In itself, the one is as little impossible as the other. (J 1262)23

A few pages further down, Lichtenberg notes a thought experiment by Erasmus Darwin, which he had formulated in an essay on freezing experiments published in 1788 in the Philosophical Transactions:

Mr. Darwin believes in his beautiful frigorific Experiments on the mechanical Expansion of air (Philos. Trans[actions] Vol. 1788) that one will perhaps seriously learn once more to make the wind, as I do of the freezing of cities. Monstrous thoughts also have their uses. (J 1380)24

Here, the idea of “monstrous thoughts” refers back to Lichtenberg's own idea of the “freezing of the cities.” This then triggers the next note, which also belongs to his own methodological guideline: “Can a monstrous thought be attached here, as those in the preceding §. are” (J 1381).25 Two entries further down, we finally encounter the very resin vial that figured as a small technical device in the description of Smeaton's air pump: “To fill a resin vial with powder like a cannon cracker and to ignite it” (J 1383).26 This strange, witty link of thought obviously plays on the idea of a quite concrete monstrosity—the danger of destruction by this novel weapon. There follows another entry with its own little thought experiment (which, as is often the case, is formulated as a conditional clause27) about the substitution of cupping glasses with resin vials:

In the bath I found that the resin vials suck in excellently, if one could give them even more elasticity, or if one could have them even stiffer than my flaky one, then they could be used quite well instead of the cupping glasses. (J 1384)28

In the last examples given above, it is obvious that the small resin vial in the Sudelbücher is not merely a technical device within a larger apparatus (as Lichtenberg's description of the air pump in the compendium), but it is repurposed to reveal another epistemic thing, even if only as a little thought-experimental fantasy or in a monstrous idea like the record about the cannon cracket. And indeed, further down in notebook J, Lichtenberg wonders whether his own instruments can be converted and repurposed:

Must once go through my entire cabinet with the question: what else can this instrument be used for apart from its actual purpose. I believe that I will be able to save a lot by doing this. For example, the lamps of the pyrometer could be used quite well for Kempelen's machine. Pockholz's balls in electrical experiments. […] (J 2138)29

Thus, the familiar technical object serves to generate new epistemic things when placed in a different context—in a different experimental system.30 Because it often produces bizarre ideas and “monstrous thoughts,” the investigation of new epistemic things tends to be commended to the private Sudelbücher and not to the glosses on Erxleben's compendium; to the conversation with himself and not to the (often agonally colored) dialogue with his predecessor. No coincidence, then, that they are sometimes born at night time. The aforementioned entry J 2138 ends with this very personal note: “This can become a good occupation during sleepless nights.”31 In his considerations on the economy of the scribble, Rheinberger takes on François Jacob's concept of “night science” (in contrast to the well-ordered “day science”), of which the research notes form a “residuum”:

By contrast, night science wanders blind. It hesitates, stumbles, recoils, sweats, wakes with a start. Doubting everything, it is forever trying to find itself, question itself, pull itself back together. Night science is a sort of workshop of the possible where what will become the building material of science is worked out. Where hypotheses remain in the form of vague presentiments and woolly impressions. Where phenomena are still no more than solitary events with no link between them. Where the design of experiments has barely taken shape. Where thought makes its way along meandering paths and twisting lanes, most often leading nowhere.32

The Sudelbücher prove to be not only a scientific but also an epistemological question-generating machine. They are the ideal place for thought experiments, for witty associations, thus for the extension to other fields of knowledge—to other experimental systems. The new epistemic things emerging here appear as “vague presentiments”; the fact that they are entrusted to these private notebooks automatically makes them not cold objects of research, but highly personal and warm matters of concern.

Abstract Image

摸索新的和未知的。论G. Ch. Lichtenberg的《sudelb》中认识论事物的出现
在博学多才和实验科学家Georg Christoph Lichtenberg(1742-1799)的著作中,人们有时会遇到对科学活动现象学的惊人现代观察,例如实验与假设之间的关系,科学发现中偶然性的作用,或新发明与积累知识之间的辩证关系。在他被称为“sudelb<e:1> cher”(“废书”)的私人笔记本记录中,他不经意地记录了一个纯粹的示范实验的构成:既然我们了解了自然,即使是一个孩子也明白,一个实验只不过是对它的一种赞美。这只是一个仪式。我们事先知道它的答案。我们向大自然寻求共识,就像领主向庄园寻求共识一样。论证实验在18世纪前后很常见,不仅用于教学目的,而且用于多种形式的科学奇观化,特别是涉及当时新的和神秘的知识领域:电学。不过,在前面的定义里,也暗含着论证实验和真正的实验的区别:在论证实验里,我们已经知道的现象只是得到证实和展示而已;在第二个阶段,一些新的,我们还没有发现的东西出现了。正是这种可预期性和意外性的辩证关系,这种典型的科学活动,使路德维克·弗列克在20世纪全神贯注。根据弗莱克的观点,有价值的实验总是“不明确的、未完成的、独特的”;2一旦它们变得清晰和任意可复制,它们最多只适合用于演示目的,但对研究目的不再有用,因为“未知的东西越丰富,研究领域越新,实验就越不清晰。”3 Hans-Jörg莱茵伯格后来进一步将这种紧张关系重新表述为“认知事物”和“技术对象”之间的关系。莱茵伯格在其划时代的著作《认知事物的历史》(1997)中将实验系统定义为“最小的完整的研究工作单元”,它“为实验者自己还不能清楚地提出的问题提供未知的答案”。引用弗朗索瓦·雅各布的话,他还称它们为“创造未来的机器”。实验系统由两部分组成:认知事物和技术对象。研究对象被定义为一种认识论的东西,即“构成研究对象的物质实体或过程——物理结构、化学反应、生物功能”。这些对象“以一种特有的、不可简化的模糊性呈现自己”,这是必不可少的,因为“矛盾的是,认知的事物体现了人们还不知道的东西。”6莱茵伯格明确地遵循了布鲁诺·拉图尔关于新研究对象的不可定义性的观点。另一方面,技术对象应该被理解为物质的、技术的安排,它首先使认知事物的生产成为可能:“工具、铭文装置、模式生物,以及附着在它们上面的浮动定理或边界概念。”因此,认识论的事物建立了一座通往未来的桥梁,而技术对象仍然锚定在现在:“技术产品[…]是一台答录机”,而“认识论的对象首先是一台产生问题的机器”然而,认识论的事物反过来可以转化为技术对象,然后再一次(在稳定已知的手段和新的未知的研究对象之间的生产辩证法中),帮助产生新的认识论的事物。在研究体系中,认识性事物具有三个重要性质。首先,我们应该区分认识的事物和认识的对象:在布鲁诺·拉图尔的非人类行动者的概念中,后者是纯粹和客观的事实(“事实之物”),而认识的事物也实现了一种内在的、情感的关注,因此是“关注的事物”。第二个方面是认识论事物的构成性理论、媒介和技术混杂性,因此也是它们定义的构成暂时性。最终,认知事物的出现不是一个纯粹的理论和推测的问题,而总是与认知实践,如实验安排、测量、表征程序等联系在一起。在这篇论文中,我将试图把李希滕贝格的sudelb<e:1>描述为两种实践偶然相遇的场所,这两种实践对自然科学家和作家都很重要:写下收集到的数据(观察、实验协议、计算等),并进行实验,以便能够从给定的、或多或少固定的环境(技术方面)中产生新的、令人垂涎的、但尚未定义的研究对象(认知方面的东西)。因此,这些文本在重复和更新之间启动了一种特殊的反馈。 这种小而临时的散文的混杂性,以及它作为一项正在进行的工作的文本遗传地位,使它成为一个优秀的认识论和诗学引擎,能够在牢固巩固、储存的知识和产生新知识的开放思想实验之间保持困难的平衡。下面,我将仔细研究一款笔记本电脑J.这款笔记本电脑(或者更确切地说:它的科学部分)在sudelb<e:1>中占据了一个特殊的位置,因为它的条目也可以作为计划中的物理学纲要的注释来阅读,其次是作为对当时可能是最重要的物理学手册的私人评论,由约翰·波利卡普·埃克斯莱本(Lichtenberg的前任,Göttingen实验物理学主席)撰写的《anfangsgrnde der Naturlehre》(1772年)。利希滕贝格用这个纲要作为他讲课的基础,在Erxleben死后(1777年),他又出版了四个版本。他在手册中手写的旁注不仅用于演讲,而且其中许多以补充和改进的形式包含在下一版中。笔记本J的记录是在1789年初到1793年4月之间写的,这段时间里,利希滕贝格手抄的《anfangsgrnde der Naturlehre》第四版的几乎所有旁注都是在这个时期写的有一些段落值得比较,同样是关于认识论事物的出现。首先,值得注意的是,笔记本J中关于科学话题的那一半被命名为“1789”。关于物理和数学的杂项笔记(实际上只是指指点点)。指指点点的手势指的是未来的知识,这些知识只能被暗示,而这些音符是相当有方向性的近似,然而,它们的直觉时刻使它们更有价值,尽管或恰恰因为它们转瞬即逝在这个标题之后,是关于如何创造新事物的有条理的说明,不管它在现在看来是多么的不可思议和荒谬:“既然每个人一想到的都是普通的东西,那就立刻刻意去创造不寻常的和不寻常的东西。”《植物性》、《星际性》、《酸与碱》(J 1254)。在整个笔记中,散落着强调困难的思想,同时,重新思考的必然性,这可以通过首先怀疑和质疑的态度来培养,例如下面的条目:质疑现在没有进一步调查就相信的事情——这是无处不在的主要事情。(J 1276)关于为什么发明新的有用的东西如此困难的原因。(J 1279)我为什么相信这个?真的是这样编的吗?[J 1326]它们是暂时的、相当启发式的思想,这一事实也可以从它们的椭圆结构中得到证明,因为它们往往是未完成的句子(例如:,不定式从句)。因此,根据我的论文,整本笔记本J作为一种自律指南来阅读,以学习不同的思维方式,产生奇怪的思维联系,从而促进新的认知事物的出现。有时,在笔记本中可以看到从技术对象到认知事物的转变。从anfangsgrnde的第三版(1784年)开始,Lichtenberg在Erxleben的段落开始之前加上了“对Smeaton气泵的描述”(这是由英国工程师John Smeaton在1771年制造的)。最后,他描述了他个人的气泵变体(提供了一个插图,见图1):在这里,一根管子连接在另一端的钟,通过它吸入空气。然后利希滕贝格补充说:顺便说一句,我注意到,用一个小树脂瓶来连接管子和钟是最方便的,因为用这种方法,钟仍然可以转动和调整,而不会损坏紧紧固定在泵上的管子。21“小树脂瓶”在这里只是一个便于气泵工作的小技术装置。然而,几年后(1790年),在j号笔记本上发生了一个奇特的发展。利希滕贝格沿着几条笔记思考了极端温度变化期间的各种现象。J 1261是一种有条理的指导,它遵循了他自己对冷热的真实实验的简短报告(J 1260):“关于这一点相当矛盾,没有人能轻易地想到”(J 1261)因此,矛盾的想法不仅是可能的,而且它们被证明是非常有用的,因为它们可以引发进一步的、创造性的想法。接下来的是一个关于城市结冰的真正奇怪的思想实验:在最冷的地方产生热量一点也不难,但在最热的地方产生冷却需要很高的技巧。 在最寒冷的天气里烧毁一座房子和一座城镇是可能的,但是到目前为止,我们还不知道有什么办法能让一个村庄的人冻死,而附近的其他村庄却在享受最愉快的夏天。就其本身而言,前者和后者一样几乎不可能。再往下几页,利希滕贝格提到了伊拉斯谟·达尔文的一个思想实验,他在1788年发表在《哲学汇刊》上的一篇关于冷冻实验的文章中阐述了这个实验。达尔文相信他关于空气机械膨胀的美丽的寒冷的实验(Philos)。(译[动]卷1788)一个人也许会再次认真地学习制造风,就像我对城市的冰冻所做的那样。可怕的思想也有它的用处。在这里,“可怕的思想”指的是李希滕贝格自己的“冻结城市”的想法。这就触发了下一个音符,这也属于他自己的方法论指南:“在这里能附著一个可怕的思想吗?(J 1381).25再往下看,我们终于遇到了一个树脂瓶,在对斯米顿气泵的描述中,它被认为是一个小的技术装置:“像大炮一样把树脂瓶装满粉末,然后点燃它”(J 1383)这种奇特而机智的思想联系显然是利用了一个相当具体的怪物的概念——这种新型武器的毁灭危险。接下来是另一个条目,它有自己的小思想实验(通常情况下,这是一个条件条款),是关于用树脂小瓶代替拔罐杯的:在洗澡时,我发现树脂小瓶的吸力很好,如果能给它们更大的弹性,或者如果能让它们比我的薄片小瓶更硬,那么它们就可以很好地代替拔罐杯。(J 1384)在上面给出的最后一个例子中,很明显,sudelb<s:1> cher中的小树脂瓶不仅仅是一个更大设备中的技术设备(如利希滕贝格在概要中对气泵的描述),而且它被重新用于揭示另一个认知的东西,即使只是作为一个小小的思想实验幻想或在一个可怕的想法中,如关于大炮噼啪声的记录。事实上,在笔记本J的后面,利希滕贝格想知道他自己的仪器是否可以转换和重新使用:我必须在我的整个橱柜里找一个问题:除了它的实际用途之外,这个仪器还能做什么?我相信这样做可以节省很多钱。例如,高温计的灯可以很好地用于肯佩伦的机器。电学实验中的波克霍尔兹球。[…](J 2138)因此,当把熟悉的技术对象放在不同的环境中——在不同的实验系统中,就会产生新的认知事物因为它经常产生奇怪的想法和“怪异的想法”,所以对新的认知事物的研究往往被推荐给私人的sudelb<s:1> cher,而不是Erxleben纲要上的注释;和他自己的对话,而不是和他的前任的(通常是痛苦的)对话。因此,它们有时出生在夜间并非巧合。前面提到的条目j2138以这句非常私人的注释结尾:“这可以成为一个在不眠之夜的好职业。31在他对涂鸦经济的思考中,莱茵伯格采用了弗朗索瓦·雅各布(franois Jacob)的“夜间科学”概念(与井然有序的“日间科学”形成对比),其中的研究笔记形成了“残留物”:相比之下,夜间科学是盲目的。它犹豫,跌跌撞撞,退缩,流汗,猛然惊醒。怀疑一切,它永远在试图找到自己,质疑自己,让自己重新振作起来。夜间科学是一种可能性的车间,在那里,将成为科学建筑材料的东西被设计出来。假设以模糊的预感和模糊的印象的形式存在。在那里,现象仍然只是孤立的事件,它们之间没有联系。那里的实验设计几乎还没有成型。在那里,思想沿着蜿蜒的小径和曲折的小巷前进,大多数情况下都没有结果。32 . sudelb<e:1>被证明不仅是一个科学的,而且是一个认识论的问题生成机器。它们是思想实验、诙谐联想的理想场所,因此可以扩展到其他知识领域——其他实验体系。在这里出现的新的认识事物表现为“模糊的预感”;它们被委托给这些私人笔记本的事实自动使它们不再是冰冷的研究对象,而是高度个人化和温暖的关注事项。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte
Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 社会科学-科学史与科学哲学
CiteScore
0.80
自引率
16.70%
发文量
43
审稿时长
>12 weeks
期刊介绍: Die Geschichte der Wissenschaften ist in erster Linie eine Geschichte der Ideen und Entdeckungen, oft genug aber auch der Moden, Irrtümer und Missverständnisse. Sie hängt eng mit der Entwicklung kultureller und zivilisatorischer Leistungen zusammen und bleibt von der politischen Geschichte keineswegs unberührt.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信