Andreas Heinz, Stefan Gutwinski, Eva Friedel, Nadja Samia Bahr, Rainer Spanagel, Gaetano Di Chiara
{"title":"Habitual Drug Intake Is Hard to Change: On the Discussion About Habits and Compulsions in Drug Addiction","authors":"Andreas Heinz, Stefan Gutwinski, Eva Friedel, Nadja Samia Bahr, Rainer Spanagel, Gaetano Di Chiara","doi":"10.1111/adb.70081","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In our recent opinion paper in <i>Addiction Biology</i> ‘Does compulsion explain addiction’? [<span>1</span>], we criticize that compulsive behaviour as defined primarily from the perspective of animal experimentation falls short of the clinical phenomenon. In particular, we argue that animal models of compulsion with immediate punishment do not adequately reflect long-term negative outcomes in human addiction. We also discuss that compulsive behaviour in OCD and addiction differ phenomenologically. Finally, we opine that human drug use can become a habit, but this does not imply a general loss of goal-directed decision-making. Instead, we claim that ‘individuals with drug addiction are neither automatons carrying out habitual behaviour without cognitive control nor merely individuals making bad choices’. Altogether, we conclude that habit formation can contribute to drug intake, as long as habitual behaviour is regarded as dimensionally but not categorically different from goal-directed decision-making and modifiable by human cognition. This statement is supported by studies from the ReCoDe consortium [<span>2</span>] and by a recent meta-analysis of the habit construct in animal models of alcohol use disorder [<span>3</span>], which did not indicate a strict habit-goal dichotomy. Instead, this meta-analysis suggests (i) a nuanced transition between goal directed and habitual decision making and (ii) distinguishes habitual responding from compulsivity [<span>3</span>].</p><p>Karen Ersche [<span>4</span>] criticizes our paper and suggests that OCD and addiction have more in common than we describe. She states that positive and negative reinforcement are associated with both drug intake and OCD, with which we agree. However, we disagree with Ersche's definition of compulsion as ‘ongoing actions that have become inappropriate to the immediate context’, because this definition is too broad and would, for example, include behaviours observed in bipolar and psychotic disorders unrelated to both OCD and addiction.</p><p>At one point, Ersche seems to confuse our criticism of the concept of compulsion in addiction with Lee Hogarth's criticism of the habit construct when she directly refers to one of his publications [<span>5</span>] which, however, was not cited in our opinion paper. In fact, we are not simply ‘rejecting’ the habit theory of addiction. Instead, we argue that the dual-system approach posits a categorical distinction between a habit and a goal-directed brain system, whereas nuanced transitions between these behavioural control systems occur in animals [<span>3</span>] and humans [<span>6</span>]. Thus, we argue that there is no overall loss of goal-directed behaviour, nor a general over-reliance on habits in individuals with drug addiction, but drug use itself can become a ‘habit’, that is, a bias toward drug-seeking in certain (e.g., stressful) circumstances [<span>7</span>].</p><p>Lee Hogarth [<span>8</span>] challenges our claim that habit formation contributes to drug addiction. He understands habits within the narrow confines of the habit/compulsion theory of addiction, where habits are defined as ‘representations of stimulus–response links that do not refer to goals’ [<span>9</span>]. Hogarth claims that this habit theory constructs ‘drug users as intellectually impaired’ and thus ‘recapitulate[s] the social injustice of the racial intelligence era by prematurely attributing lower task performance to drug user group membership’. His argument rests on three points: (i) that it is racist to attribute lower cognitive test performance in racialized groups to ‘race’ while ignoring social disadvantage, (ii) that habit formation is a form of intellectual impairment and (iii) that, by analogy, attributing increased habit formation as intellectual impairment to individuals with drug use disorders while ignoring social disadvantage amounts to scientific racism. With respect to (i), Hogarth cites the findings of Weiss [<span>10</span>] and claims that social disparity fully explains the difference in IQ test results between racialized groups. However, this is not true. Weiss [<span>10</span>] suggests that gaps remaining in cognitive performance after correcting for social disparities are due to ‘historical discrimination’, which includes racism. Therefore, argument (i) of Hogarth needs to be revised: It is indeed racist to attribute lower cognitive test performance in racialized groups to ‘race’ while ignoring social disadvantage AND the impact of racism itself on cognitive test performance. In fact, racism and other forms of historically embedded discrimination can induce severe stress and have profound negative effects on mental health [<span>11, 12</span>] and cognitive performance [<span>13</span>]. Such effects are then reified by the ‘race’ term, which falsely postulates categorical rather than gradual differences among populations [<span>14</span>]. Regarding argument (ii), we agree with Hogarth that some theories of addictive behaviour stigmatize patients and wrongly attribute cognitive effects of social exclusion and discrimination to genetic causes [<span>15</span>]. However, we do not view habitual behaviour as an intellectual impairment.</p><p>Habits are useful for all human beings: We could not drive a car and have a complex discussion at the same time without habit formation. In accordance with a recent meta-analysis [<span>3</span>], we observed gradual differences between habitual and goal-directed decision making and did not find a general deficit in goal-directed decision-making in persons with alcohol use disorders (AUD) [<span>16</span>]. Emphasizing that individuals with drug addiction are not ‘automatons carrying out habitual behaviour without cognitive control’ [<span>1</span>] does not rule out that specific behaviour patterns (including e.g., individually disadvantageous stress coping mechanisms) can become habitual, as evinced by the alcohol approach bias [<span>17</span>]. Individuals with AUD can change this approach bias with intensive training, indicating that individuals with habitual drug use patterns may need specific support to ‘break the habit’ Hogarth's claim that attributing habitual behaviour to individuals with substance use disorders amounts to labeling them as intellectually impaired may be motivated by theories that explain habit formation as the result of dysfunction of a higher cognitive control centre or goal-directed system. However, in our opinion article [<span>1</span>], we explicitly rejected reifying behaviour patterns such as goal-directed behaviour into ‘systems’, and we understand habit formation as an important ability. Therefore, argument (ii) of Hogarth is not in line with our point of view. With respect to argument (iii), we agree with Hogarth that social disadvantage, exclusion and discrimination play an important role in the predisposition to addiction [<span>18, 19</span>]. Moreover, we do not claim that habit formation is a pathological process that can only occur when goal-directed behaviour is impaired due to neurotoxic effects of alcohol. This being said, alcohol intake can cause neurotoxicity, which in turn can contribute to cognitive impairments that require support and therapy [<span>20-24</span>]. Ignoring the effects of drugs and drug-related mental disorders on motivation and cognition risks blaming the victims for their problems [<span>15</span>]. This unintended consequence is illustrated by Thomas Szasz [<span>25</span>], who reasoned that considering his postulated absence of valid concepts of mental illness, individuals do not have mental disorders but are instead just lazy and should therefore lose social support. In summary, we advise against trivializing the important topic of racism by inadequately equating studies measuring the neurotoxic and neurobiological effects of drugs of abuse on cognition with racist theories of group inferiority. Instead, the effects of racism on cognition and health should be taken seriously in their own right [<span>26-28</span>].</p><p>We agree with Ersche [<span>4</span>] and Hogarth [<span>8</span>] that in order to avoid stigmatization and discrimination, we need to reflect on our disease categories and their implications.</p><p>Our disease concepts must avoid stigmatizing individuals who use drugs, without denying the negative medical consequences of drug use and without excluding individuals with drug addiction from receiving the necessary support within the medical care system. We concur with Ersche's assertion that while a critical reflection of theories of addictive behaviour is good scientific practice, it necessitates the development of a more comprehensive theory to take its place. What the field of addiction critically requires is a unifying theory that integrates consistent findings across all levels of analysis—from genetic and molecular to neuronal, circuit, behavioural, and social aspects of addiction. This is an ambitious endeavour that can only be achieved through an open-minded approach by numerous experts.</p><p>The authors declare no conflicts of interest.</p>","PeriodicalId":7289,"journal":{"name":"Addiction Biology","volume":"30 10","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.6000,"publicationDate":"2025-09-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/adb.70081","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Addiction Biology","FirstCategoryId":"3","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/adb.70081","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"BIOCHEMISTRY & MOLECULAR BIOLOGY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
In our recent opinion paper in Addiction Biology ‘Does compulsion explain addiction’? [1], we criticize that compulsive behaviour as defined primarily from the perspective of animal experimentation falls short of the clinical phenomenon. In particular, we argue that animal models of compulsion with immediate punishment do not adequately reflect long-term negative outcomes in human addiction. We also discuss that compulsive behaviour in OCD and addiction differ phenomenologically. Finally, we opine that human drug use can become a habit, but this does not imply a general loss of goal-directed decision-making. Instead, we claim that ‘individuals with drug addiction are neither automatons carrying out habitual behaviour without cognitive control nor merely individuals making bad choices’. Altogether, we conclude that habit formation can contribute to drug intake, as long as habitual behaviour is regarded as dimensionally but not categorically different from goal-directed decision-making and modifiable by human cognition. This statement is supported by studies from the ReCoDe consortium [2] and by a recent meta-analysis of the habit construct in animal models of alcohol use disorder [3], which did not indicate a strict habit-goal dichotomy. Instead, this meta-analysis suggests (i) a nuanced transition between goal directed and habitual decision making and (ii) distinguishes habitual responding from compulsivity [3].
Karen Ersche [4] criticizes our paper and suggests that OCD and addiction have more in common than we describe. She states that positive and negative reinforcement are associated with both drug intake and OCD, with which we agree. However, we disagree with Ersche's definition of compulsion as ‘ongoing actions that have become inappropriate to the immediate context’, because this definition is too broad and would, for example, include behaviours observed in bipolar and psychotic disorders unrelated to both OCD and addiction.
At one point, Ersche seems to confuse our criticism of the concept of compulsion in addiction with Lee Hogarth's criticism of the habit construct when she directly refers to one of his publications [5] which, however, was not cited in our opinion paper. In fact, we are not simply ‘rejecting’ the habit theory of addiction. Instead, we argue that the dual-system approach posits a categorical distinction between a habit and a goal-directed brain system, whereas nuanced transitions between these behavioural control systems occur in animals [3] and humans [6]. Thus, we argue that there is no overall loss of goal-directed behaviour, nor a general over-reliance on habits in individuals with drug addiction, but drug use itself can become a ‘habit’, that is, a bias toward drug-seeking in certain (e.g., stressful) circumstances [7].
Lee Hogarth [8] challenges our claim that habit formation contributes to drug addiction. He understands habits within the narrow confines of the habit/compulsion theory of addiction, where habits are defined as ‘representations of stimulus–response links that do not refer to goals’ [9]. Hogarth claims that this habit theory constructs ‘drug users as intellectually impaired’ and thus ‘recapitulate[s] the social injustice of the racial intelligence era by prematurely attributing lower task performance to drug user group membership’. His argument rests on three points: (i) that it is racist to attribute lower cognitive test performance in racialized groups to ‘race’ while ignoring social disadvantage, (ii) that habit formation is a form of intellectual impairment and (iii) that, by analogy, attributing increased habit formation as intellectual impairment to individuals with drug use disorders while ignoring social disadvantage amounts to scientific racism. With respect to (i), Hogarth cites the findings of Weiss [10] and claims that social disparity fully explains the difference in IQ test results between racialized groups. However, this is not true. Weiss [10] suggests that gaps remaining in cognitive performance after correcting for social disparities are due to ‘historical discrimination’, which includes racism. Therefore, argument (i) of Hogarth needs to be revised: It is indeed racist to attribute lower cognitive test performance in racialized groups to ‘race’ while ignoring social disadvantage AND the impact of racism itself on cognitive test performance. In fact, racism and other forms of historically embedded discrimination can induce severe stress and have profound negative effects on mental health [11, 12] and cognitive performance [13]. Such effects are then reified by the ‘race’ term, which falsely postulates categorical rather than gradual differences among populations [14]. Regarding argument (ii), we agree with Hogarth that some theories of addictive behaviour stigmatize patients and wrongly attribute cognitive effects of social exclusion and discrimination to genetic causes [15]. However, we do not view habitual behaviour as an intellectual impairment.
Habits are useful for all human beings: We could not drive a car and have a complex discussion at the same time without habit formation. In accordance with a recent meta-analysis [3], we observed gradual differences between habitual and goal-directed decision making and did not find a general deficit in goal-directed decision-making in persons with alcohol use disorders (AUD) [16]. Emphasizing that individuals with drug addiction are not ‘automatons carrying out habitual behaviour without cognitive control’ [1] does not rule out that specific behaviour patterns (including e.g., individually disadvantageous stress coping mechanisms) can become habitual, as evinced by the alcohol approach bias [17]. Individuals with AUD can change this approach bias with intensive training, indicating that individuals with habitual drug use patterns may need specific support to ‘break the habit’ Hogarth's claim that attributing habitual behaviour to individuals with substance use disorders amounts to labeling them as intellectually impaired may be motivated by theories that explain habit formation as the result of dysfunction of a higher cognitive control centre or goal-directed system. However, in our opinion article [1], we explicitly rejected reifying behaviour patterns such as goal-directed behaviour into ‘systems’, and we understand habit formation as an important ability. Therefore, argument (ii) of Hogarth is not in line with our point of view. With respect to argument (iii), we agree with Hogarth that social disadvantage, exclusion and discrimination play an important role in the predisposition to addiction [18, 19]. Moreover, we do not claim that habit formation is a pathological process that can only occur when goal-directed behaviour is impaired due to neurotoxic effects of alcohol. This being said, alcohol intake can cause neurotoxicity, which in turn can contribute to cognitive impairments that require support and therapy [20-24]. Ignoring the effects of drugs and drug-related mental disorders on motivation and cognition risks blaming the victims for their problems [15]. This unintended consequence is illustrated by Thomas Szasz [25], who reasoned that considering his postulated absence of valid concepts of mental illness, individuals do not have mental disorders but are instead just lazy and should therefore lose social support. In summary, we advise against trivializing the important topic of racism by inadequately equating studies measuring the neurotoxic and neurobiological effects of drugs of abuse on cognition with racist theories of group inferiority. Instead, the effects of racism on cognition and health should be taken seriously in their own right [26-28].
We agree with Ersche [4] and Hogarth [8] that in order to avoid stigmatization and discrimination, we need to reflect on our disease categories and their implications.
Our disease concepts must avoid stigmatizing individuals who use drugs, without denying the negative medical consequences of drug use and without excluding individuals with drug addiction from receiving the necessary support within the medical care system. We concur with Ersche's assertion that while a critical reflection of theories of addictive behaviour is good scientific practice, it necessitates the development of a more comprehensive theory to take its place. What the field of addiction critically requires is a unifying theory that integrates consistent findings across all levels of analysis—from genetic and molecular to neuronal, circuit, behavioural, and social aspects of addiction. This is an ambitious endeavour that can only be achieved through an open-minded approach by numerous experts.
期刊介绍:
Addiction Biology is focused on neuroscience contributions and it aims to advance our understanding of the action of drugs of abuse and addictive processes. Papers are accepted in both animal experimentation or clinical research. The content is geared towards behavioral, molecular, genetic, biochemical, neuro-biological and pharmacology aspects of these fields.
Addiction Biology includes peer-reviewed original research reports and reviews.
Addiction Biology is published on behalf of the Society for the Study of Addiction to Alcohol and other Drugs (SSA). Members of the Society for the Study of Addiction receive the Journal as part of their annual membership subscription.