Oligarchy, Democracy, and Plebeianism: For a Political Conceptualization

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
José Maurício Domingues
{"title":"Oligarchy, Democracy, and Plebeianism: For a Political Conceptualization","authors":"José Maurício Domingues","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.70004","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Oligarchy is back. That is, it has recently essayed to make a conceptual comeback because it has never disappeared from the way societies are ruled and, particularly and specifically in modernity, political life. What is it, though? Mostly it has remained untheorized or undertheorized in modernity, despite some critical approaches having mentioned it in connection to liberalism, such as Castoriadis’ (<span>1999</span>, 153ff), whereas others, within democratic liberalism, pointed to it as a stage in the development of liberalism that would have been already superseded, such as Santos (<span>2013</span>). This article precisely aims to engage with it in modernity and critically assess its relation to democracy, including its relation to plebeianism.</p><p>Since apparently the Persians, but more consistently with the Greeks and above all Aristotle, oligarchy entered the vocabulary of power and rule (or “government”), having a sort of half-life in Medieval times, when monarchical power and the papacy held center stage in the discussions about power. Oligarchy re-emerged in the Renaissance, for instance, in Machiavelli, and early modern thinking, including Montesquieu, but was eventually sidelined by a different sort of vocabulary in which the ancient tradition of “forms of rule” (or “government”) played no role. Yet the theories of “elites,” especially Mosca and Pareto, as well as liberal approaches, provided new names for this old phenomenon, which could not be entirely overlooked, actually hypostatizing it as a universal and inexorable phenomenon (Urbinati <span>2010</span>). Only here and there, with limited consequences, were such ideas resumed by modern thinkers. The state, representation, and other concepts took the place of the forms of rule within a new caesura regarding the discourse about power and the emergence of a specific dimension in modernity, the political one.</p><p>Despite the analysis of the oligarchization of the inner life of political parties as a distinctive phenomenon, particularly in Michels’ (<span>1911/2009</span>) classic work about the German Social Democratic Party (which refrains from discussing oligarchy as a form of government or rule), that is, as strictly political, oligarchy has primarily been understood according to Aristotle's (<span>1996</span>) definition, that is, as the self-oriented rule of the few. These are, in fact and at the same time, the rich—thus configuring a “plutocracy.” This is also McCormick's (<span>2011</span>) and Winters’ (<span>2011</span>) perspective, the main references for contemporary discussions, as well as that of other recent authors such as Arlen (<span>2019, 2023</span>), Vergara (<span>2020</span>), and Bagg (<span>2022</span>), as well as Kalyvas (<span>2019</span>), with an opposition between the oligarchy and the “poor.”1</p><p>Winters stresses that oligarchs are concerned with and dedicate themselves to the “defence of property,” which is based, differently from Rome, on “strong property rights.” On the other hand, oligarchs do not usually hold office (when they do, “vanity” is often the reason why). In any case, they have developed—by means that he does not actually clarify—an “Income Defense Industry,” hiding wealth, evading taxes, and using “complex tax shelters.” Oligarchs, Winters (<span>2011</span>, xi–xvi, 7–8) argues, are to be seen as <i>individuals</i> (not, for instance, corporations). As he elaborates his arguments, Winters states that—in variance with Aristotle, he suggests, though he also stresses, in a different passage, that the latter links power and wealth—he does not think that oligarchy is simply the rule of the few: He is keen to emphasize its “material foundations,” with wealth inequality producing extreme political inequality (Winters <span>2011</span>, 3, 27). Winters does recognize that there are other sources of power, based on political rights, official positions, coercive and mobilizational power, along with material power. Official positions are separated out in the modern state; that is to say, they do not directly derive from wealth, he points out. On the other hand, oligarchs are able to exert huge influence on such officials. Although he is mainly interested in what he calls “civil oligarchy” (which depends on a system of laws), Winters (<span>2011</span>, 34ff, 209, chaps. 2–5) proposed a typology of oligarchies (warring, ruling, sultanistic, tamed, and wild, along with the “civil” variant, which is the outstandingly modern one). Finally, Winters stresses the difference between the concepts of oligarchy and “elite,” which obscured, in the case of Mosca and Pareto, the role of wealth since it was too encompassing. The issue would have also been misunderstood by Michels when he defined the German Social Democratic Party as oligarchic. In contradistinction, from the Soviet Union to Cuba, we actually found elite rule, but such societies should not be characterized as oligarchic since wealth played no role in them (Winters <span>2011</span>, 8, 275–77).</p><p>In turn, McCormick is much more ambiguous in his characterization of oligarchy. He mixes without greater worry oligarchy and elites (“socioeconomic and political”) (McCormick <span>2011</span>, 1, 13–17, 167), without really defining each of them very clearly, though wealth always appears as a major issue for the characterization of their power (with, sometimes, “class” and “class consciousness” being mentioned without any specification). Actually, during most of the book, McCormick barely speaks of oligarchies except with reference to Rome and the Italian Renaissance republics, and mostly as he discusses Machiavelli's work. It is really only in the chapter about “Post-electoral democracies” that McCormick more systematically works with the idea of oligarchy—yet mainly to contrast it with reformed, hence properly democratic, republics (McCormick <span>2011</span>, chaps. 6–7).</p><p>The same mix between “elites” and “oligarchy” appears in Vergara's work. We have experienced—seemingly in the last decades—a systematic decay—“systemic corruption”—of the liberal representative government. It manifests itself in the “oligarchization” of power in society (configuring a “trend”). A small minority has accumulated and monopolized wealth, with dire political consequences. The power of the <i>few</i> has increasingly become exclusive; they have become the sole rulers, against the interests of the <i>many</i>, with the elites left to comfortably “police themselves.” She strongly asserts that liberal representative democracies are <i>not</i> mixed regimes—they are rather “monocratic,” with, simply, a “separation of functions.” Although she had previously mentioned the oligarchization of power in society, she eventually states her main concern: “Political power is today de facto oligarchic” (Vergara <span>2020</span>, 1–4). Although the latter assertion is largely correct, I believe the former is not. A reason for this different assessment will be given later in this article.</p><p>Both McCormick and Vergara are above all intent on defending a plebeian perspective. Their depiction of oligarchy is thus less systematic than Winter's. I will return to plebeianism toward the end of the article. For now, let us critically discuss these authors’ views of oligarchies and elites.</p><p>I do not entirely want to deny their descriptions and conceptualizations, yet I think they are often reductive or confusing. It would be ludicrous to overlook how wealth sways political life and how the rich have numerous channels through which they reach out to politicians and influence or even harness their actions according to their objectives. They are surely concerned with the defense of their property, wealth, and income (which are, incidentally, different phenomena). We need, however, to develop a more precise view of oligarchy in modernity, with its specificity, hence also going beyond the loose idea of “elites” (which, moreover, cannot but be infused with underlying positive resonances, recalling aristocracies to mind). Despite the prominence of concentrated economic power, I want to argue that we have to see oligarchy in terms of political power as such. In Aristotle's time, there was a close articulation among material, military, and, for lack of a better word, say, “governmental” power. Rule tightly weaved all these elements together. In modernity, there came about nevertheless a differentiation of the political dimension from other social dimensions, whereas socioeconomic classes are now more central in the material, socioeconomic dimension. The political dimension—likewise the economic one—has acquired its own logic and sources of power. That much is recognized by Winters, as we saw above, though we will need to introduce further distinctions to properly grasp this dimension. In particular, we need to draw the proper conclusions from this differentiation, which Winters only partly does. Finally, McCormick's reference to social classes must be properly articulated, especially regarding modernity.</p><p>When I speak of oligarchy in this article, it is therefore basically to <i>political oligarchy</i> that I refer. We could speak of economic oligarchies in order to single out the wealthiest people in one country and, at this stage, even in the whole world, even though dominant economic classes are larger than this cohort of superrich people. More approximatively, we could perhaps point to oligarchies in other areas of human activities, from the arts to sports and beyond. But, of utmost importance to political dynamics, I want to discuss specifically how political power—state-based but with connections in political processes in society at large—is shaped in modernity and how this is established through the rule of the political few. Although political power has also been characterized by the growing importance of wealth, we cannot directly derive this trend, which Vergara correctly identifies, from the influence of wealth, though this is also a cause and effect of political oligarchization. The socioeconomic and political powerful agents who McCormick often joins together in one breath need to be distinguished—not to belittle the role of property and wealth, which are more than just a crucial aspect of class relations in modern societies based on capitalism, but to support a proper understanding of how they relate to political power in its specificity.</p><p>This outlook will allow us to see how political power is organized in this specific dimension and is exercised by <i>political collectivities</i>. That is to say, we will observe how it assumes a peculiar form in modernity but also in the attempts to move beyond it, which we can call authoritarian collectivism, where the few also ruled (in a more integral alternative social formation) and rule (after an economic transition to capitalism). We will be able thereby to discuss how pro-capitalist, pro-business political collectivities operate and how left-wing forces are usually traversed by oligarchic tendencies, too, constituting oligarchic structures, which have been transferred from parties to state structures and vice versa. How this combines with elements of the rule of the one—autocratic—and of the many—democratic—can then be discussed. We will, in addition, see how those who do not share in the exercise of power should be defined as “plebeians”—politically, that is—and the contemporary political dynamic, in which the verticality of the exercise of (oligarchic) political power is time and again rejected (Breaugh <span>2007</span>; McCormick 2011; Green <span>2016</span>; Vergara <span>2020</span>; Ramírez <span>2022</span>), which others prefer to treat foremost through the category of the “poor” (Kalyvas <span>2019</span>; Arlen 2019).</p><p>In the next sections, (1) I further elaborate on the differentiation of the political dimension and discuss the relations among oligarchy, elites, and social classes; (2) I then systematically define the concepts of political system and political regimes, as well as carry out a discussion of the forms of rule in modernity (mainly under liberalism) and postmodernity (authoritarian collectivism), with dynamic elements; (3) finally, I take up the problem of political plebeianism, as well as of the “poor” and related concepts, which leads me to discuss the remedies recently proposed to address these issues; (4) a conclusion follows. I should note, before moving further, that, although strongly engaged with political theory, this is a work of political sociology, which I actually deem of great relevance to furthering the contemporary debate on oligarchy and plebeianism.</p><p>There was no politics as such before modernity. Power was undoubtedly an issue that existentially cut across all civilizations and specific social formations (specific “societies”). Neither social life nor social relations, vertical or horizontal, exist without it. Domination and ruling, with their hierarchical verticality, became indeed connected to the state. However, how diverse “sources” of power combined differed significantly from the sort of arrangement modernity brought about. We do not need to accept the idea that an evolution led from simple, undifferentiated societies to complex ones, where differentiation dominated and implied new mechanisms of coordination. There have been many paths in social evolution and development, different combinations of material, ruling, and spiritual power, which do not allow for a flat picture of a unilinear process. Nevertheless, in what henceforth became the “West,” modernity slowly emerged, and the political dimension differentiated out.3 It contained a way of organizing power that initially should be domesticated and perhaps disguised, with any new political features as such disappearing in any case. This was so because the political representative system—both legislative and, even more so, executive—was supposed to merely maintain pristine civil—less so political—rights for all the citizens who had decided to build this new state apparatus, fundamentally based on abstract law. For the observance of law and to keep those pristine rights, legal and repressive forces (eventually a differentiated-out police) linked to the executive and the judiciary had a crucial role to play, which was tin a sense passive, aiming at the maintenance of pristine relations between abstract citizens. As it unfolded, political modernity became increasingly politicized, with the concrete issues of social life invading that abstract dimension in what regards both citizens and state, with at the same time an expansion and democratization of political modernity. This configured an expansive trend regarding the combination of republicanism and liberalism that was hegemonic in modernity (since the 1970s, reversed in the direction of renewed oligarchization, which formally kept democratic institutions).</p><p>It is true that we partly use the same vocabulary as the Greeks and the Romans, particularly “politics,” “citizenship,” and the “public,” along with those forms of rule. However, several of these terms meant absolutely different things now and then. Just take “politics,” a central concept in Greece and in modernity. In Aristotle (<span>1996</span>, especially 72ff), in such a “political” framework it is not only, and perhaps not even mainly, the exercise of power that is at stake. As Hegel <span>(1820/1986)</span> perceived, he was referring to an “ethical totality” (<i>Sittlichkeit</i>)—which included the <i>oikos</i> and the family, to start with—as well as values and the belonging to a city—the <i>polis</i>—the only place and circumstance where life was meaningful and genuinely human. Those forms of rule or government—monarchy and tyranny, aristocracy and oligarchy, and isonomy and democracy—directly pointed to the exercise of power, as such not “political,” a word reserved for a more encompassing reality (that of the “polis” in general). The first term of the pair was meant to be positive, virtuous, as rulers would be concerned with the common good; the second, in contrast, was negative, as they would rule according to their self-interest. Aristotle was much more aware than most writers until the beginning of modernity of the role of material interests and power concerning those forms of government or rule, yet the polis was much more than that.</p><p>With Machiavelli, we started to speak of naked power, the state, and a particular dimension of the former's exercise. This was consolidated with Hobbes and subsequent authors. Note as well that such forms of rule or government have been seen, from Aristotle through Montesquieu to the “framers” of the United States Constitution and beyond, often as composite, that is, as mixed forms, in which the rule of the one, of the few, and of the many may combine in varied ways. Actually, many authors—such as Aristotle, Machiavelli, and those US “framers”—favored such mixed forms, which they deemed more stable and as embodying the advantages of different principles. The framers were happy to see, hovering above their limited democracy, a “natural aristocracy” of the spirit, as they fancied themselves (Jefferson <span>1813/1959</span>; moreover, before him and with a direct influence upon his views, see Harrington <span>1656/1992</span>, 23; see also McCormick <span>2011</span>, for the Italian Renaissance, especially Guicciardini).</p><p>This move also required a reflection on how power—specifically political, now—would be organized, who would rule, and how these persons would rule or govern. The answer developed piecemeal, in theory and practice. The North American War of Independence (replicated but with much less global impact in the south of the continent) and the French Revolution still made use, in a good measure, of the old, classical teachings. New concepts were crafted too, some already found to some extent in the Medieval vocabulary, though in other registers, such as “representation,” to deal with the complexity of the new civilization; or, with its modern meaning crafted slightly earlier, the “state,” to refer to the machine of rule. Nevertheless, what had been, until the beginning of modernity, the standard vocabulary and typology to deal with forms of rule or government—the rule or government of the one, the few, and the many—gave way to democracy, “representative” but for some currents, as a demand, “direct” too, “dictatorship” (meaning something else than it did for the Romans), and eventually more euphemistic, supposedly technical terms such as Dahl's (<span>1960/1963</span>) “closed hegemonies,” “competitive oligarchies,” “inclusive hegemonies,” and “polyarchy”—with henceforth a legion of directly empirically based typologies.</p><p>Yet classical ideas somehow lived on, sparsely and incompletely, in some approaches. This was the case, for instance, of Michels’ aforementioned work. They were present in Schmitt's (<span>1928/1993</span>, 292–303) analyses, in particular when he discussed how elections embodied an aristocratic principle, in contrast to the Greek lot and the plebiscitary acclamation he envisaged for his model of (supposedly) “democracy” (see also Manin <span>1997</span>). “Extra-parliamentary” fierce criticisms of the political system and its insulation from the citizenry also resumed the classical vocabulary (see Agnoli <span>1967/1990</span>), which was, time and again, applied, curiously, by some analysis of “real socialism” (Tucker <span>1963</span>; Cohen <span>1985</span>; Author, 2024). But a major conceptual shift had actually taken place.</p><p>The concepts of aristocracy and oligarchy ended up giving way to the rule or government of the “elites” (Mosca <span>1895/1923</span>; Pareto <span>1916/1923</span>) when analysts were wont to speak of power differentials, with liberals usually uncomfortable with the looming need to recognize that in their representative democracy there were rulers and the ruled. At the same time, liberal theories concerned with political modernity increasingly tended to see politics as a representation of societal interests (which were either more “universal” as to representatives, as Burke stressed, or particularized ones, as Marx and later liberals such as Dahl pointed out).</p><p>To be sure, utilitarian liberalism was aware of what Bentham <span>(1822/1988</span>, 115–122) called “sinister interests” (of lawyers and judges as well as politicians), a sort of interest deviously aiming at one's happiness (“utility”). It was nevertheless seen as connected to the rule of the one or the few. Once the many ruled (through the few, though!), Bentham thought interests—with the universal public good in command—would be aligned appropriately, such as in the United States. He was wrong, though. More control may be achieved, but sectional interests will remain in what amounts to a sort of mixed government insofar as the political system distinguishes between those who govern and the governed, rulers and the ruled, as I further argue below. Partly surely influenced by Rousseau, Robespierre, though accepting the representative principle, he himself a parliamentarian, was aware of the problem and denounced its creeping relevance. In contradistinction to Burke, for instance, Robespierre suggested, as solutions to the autonomization of the interests of the representatives vis-à-vis the citizens who elected them, a number of measures: virtue, more frequent elections, the at least potentially frequent turnover of parliamentarians, hence the immersion of representatives in the people at least for a length of time, along with open public deliberation and the interdiction of participation in the executive of members of parliament (Mathiez <span>1920/2018</span>, 33–38). Whether the “incorruptible” followed his own advice during his time in office begs the question.4</p><p>A further, though brief, discussion of Marxist perspectives as well as a Weberian one that resumes some of its perspectives is in order, as especially the former current has given particular attention to the relation between wealth, property, and income, on the one hand, and political power, on the other; and, of course, to social classes, a concept that cannot be properly replaced by oligarchy (which ends up as a mere synonym for the superrich, also a vague though sensitizing descriptive notion). Political theorists of oligarchy, blending indistinguishably political and economic power, often totally overlook this crucial literature. But they do that at their own peril, as these have been the authors who have really tried to grasp—though drawing upon the concept of social class rather than economic oligarchy or elites—the connection between wealth and property, on the one hand, and political power, on the other—mostly the state in general in their theories, which is also a shortcoming.</p><p>Marx and Engels <span>(1848/1978)</span> originally—in a manifesto that referred to a period in which the electoral franchise was extremely restricted—affirmed that the state was a “committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie” (though their conceptions became increasingly more complex and nuanced as modernity advanced and their thought matured). Almost a century later, although Gramsci <span>(1929-35/2001)</span> stressed the class character of the (enlarged) state and “hegemony,” he did recognize, on the other hand, that usually the ruling classes did not govern directly, maintaining a more distant relation with politics. In the even later Marxist debate, Miliband (<span>1969</span>) argued that the ruling classes did govern directly but was sharply criticized by Poulantzas (<span>1978</span>), who developed a more mediated theory that regarded the state as a “field of struggles” between the classes, jettisoning the simpler idea that it was the executive “committee” of the bourgeois, to start with due to its complexity. Offe's (<span>1972/1973, 1986</span>) perspective was even more mediated: the main concern of the state and politicians was the reproduction of their own power, for which the smooth accumulation of capital was necessary, implying therefore an inevitable adjustment to the interests and demands of capitalists rather than their direct representation. Resuming Poulantzas’ views, Jessop (2008) almost dissociated the state from capitalist classes or classes, though without denying their concrete intertwinement. This had been a step more radically taken by Block (<span>1977</span>) several years before, according to whom (at variance with a class-instrumentalist perspective and going beyond Offe's older works) the responsivity of “state managers” to fragmented capitalists’ interests rests on their own eagerness to remain in power.</p><p>We thus see that the tendency within Marxism is to look at politics and the state as conditioned by social classes and (“in the last instance”) the economy, but also that a rather nuanced standpoint was eventually articulated (although there is in these authors hardly an adequate distinction between the state and the political system, which is very important and on which I shall elaborate below). The so-called instrumentalist perspective was ditched. I think this was a very positive development. That is to say, Marxism went far beyond Marx and Engels’ original views, partly historically justified only, which at this point in history are false. This is not to deny that the rich—or the bourgeoisie, however we define it in the era of corporate capitalism—have enormous influence in politics—especially and visibly in the United States; but this influence is indirect, while capitalists—or businesspeople more generally—must grapple with the interests of professional politicians, as well as of bureaucrats (in which, for instance, the European Union excels).</p><p>The Weberian tradition, especially with Mann (1993), also came to recognize the links between social classes and the state, hence between wealth and politics, but did not subordinate the latter to the former either, though their solutions (cf. Mann's social “crystallizations” within the state) are elusive. This should be borne in mind in the further development of this article. Such sociological understanding is not inimical to the idea that wealth is a determinant of politics and that the very rich are intent on defending their properties and assets, which they are. It points, however, to a view in which the complexities of modern and especially contemporary society are taken into account. This is, on the other hand, very different from what elitist theories suggest, in which the specific mechanisms of the generation and reproduction of power often tend to disappear and an inevitability of, positively conceived, power differentials is supposed and explained away. Moreover, to be sure, the direct weight of the rich (bourgeoisies or economic oligarchies) upon the political system varies in space-time—from country to country and in different periods—something not to be lost from sight when more empirically oriented analyses are undertaken, which shall not be the case here.</p><p>More recently, the professionalization of politics and of political systems has been put under scrutiny. It has allowed for the transition of the kind of politician who, in Weber's (<span>1919/1988</span>) classical terms, lives “for politics” to those who live “off politics.” Traditional oligarchies are hence also overcome, but, as such, this does not alter the oligarchic character of political systems, with politicians very much aware of their specificity and own interests, including enriching themselves since many or even most of them were not really rich before entering politics (Borchert and Zeiss <span>2003</span>). This transition developed along with the democratization of political systems through mass parties, but it is by no means incompatible with processes that entail de-democratization.</p><p>At this stage, the question should thus be unambiguously stated: It is the exercise of power in rather autonomous ways and the customary defense of political power privileges that is at stake for political oligarchies, even though they are frequently closely aligned with the dominant classes (conceptually defined), the rich (phenomenologically perceived and described), and the like, or are actually part of them. If dominant classes and the rich are concerned with property as well as income and wealth, and authoritarian collectivist oligarchies are concerned with maintaining their power, from which the control of the corporate property they enjoyed derived, in liberal systems of rule, control of political power also has an independent logic, separate from the economic dimension, that is, wealth and property (with state capitalism combining both logics). This arrangement is directly related to the modern differentiation of the political dimension and does not depend directly on the wishes of political officials—professional politicians—who may even be uncomfortable with it. It also implies an internal logic related to acquiring and maintaining power, regarding self-interest, and beliefs in the limited imaginary of liberal democracy or oligarchy. This rests on a lot of ideology—this concept understood as the structuration of a universe of meaning that, usually including some varied level of plausibility or truth, hides part of reality and furnishes specious justifications for its problematic or especially ugly aspects. This is even more true of the mix between party-state rule and capitalism today.</p><p>Michels was in particular very concerned with how oligarchization developed within organizations—mass organizations, envisaged as a means to achieve the opposite objective, namely, democratization. If liberals have consistently, at least until recently, looked the other way regarding the oligarchic elements of liberal democracy, that closure of power was one of the problems and impasses that workers’ parties and the tradition of workers’ councils tried to tackle. The fact that oligarchized organizations pushed for overall democratization—and largely succeeded—and organized popular participation does not make them non-oligarchic. What is more, this oligarchic character harbored innumerable problems that either did surface with a vengeance in the postrevolutionary period or eventually marred the very possibility of further democratization and true reformism. This is a crucial paradox—Michel's paradox, we can call it—that accompanied political modernity in the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries. At least in this form, it is no longer with us, although organizations and especially large national parties, let alone the international sphere, imply such reiterated complication, with, simultaneously, a demand for democratization and the rule of the few, which has become paramount today.5 There has been—today we can clearly see, though many refuse to face it—a rather naive belief in Marxism, according to which once the state and political power disappeared, as a consequence of the end of private property, the problem would also wither away. The working classes would, moreover, control the process and prevent its developing distortions (an issue that made Bolsheviks nervous, though excessive self-confidence led them to wish the problem away—see, for instance, clearly, Bukharin <span>1925</span>). They all chose to overlook a problem Bakunin <span>(1873/1990)</span> had early on pointed out, with direct reference to Marx.</p><p>Oligarchic rule may not be universal and inevitable. It is, however, very hard to overcome in any sort of overall social arrangement.</p><p>In order to further elaborate on the differentiation of the political dimension in modernity and grasp some further aspect of oligarchic rule, I must now systematically tackle the concept of <i>political system</i>, which I have thus far employed without properly defining it, as well as the concept of <i>political regime</i>.6 The state has been seen, in too many approaches and analyses, as the site of the exercise of political power. But this is problematic. Both concepts, of the state and of political systems, referring to different issues, must be retained. Although any part of the state may be politicized at any moment, the core of politics is actually the political system, basically the legislative and executive powers, where law is produced and decisions are taken. Politicians, today mostly elected though not always, operate in the political system, whereas bureaucrats occupy non-elective positions. To be sure, this distinction is relative, but most of the state is most of the time politically rather neutral, such as the courts and the at present extremely differentiated administrative apparatus, including the army, though it is permeated by ideologies and political preferences, and in moments of crisis or due to politicians’ decisions its formal neutrality can quickly change. Oligarchic power is exercised fundamentally in and through those two specific elements of the political system. Under liberal representative democracy, elected officials control these spaces, with a more vertical arrangement obtaining in party-state systems. If this is the state aspect of the political system, we must, however, also point to a societal political system, which organizes interests, values, and a societal agenda, in any case often in direct contact with the state political system, although at times it is strongly repressed. Unions, associations, non-profit, and non-governmental organizations are its pillars. The political system, with its two sides, is cast here with an analytical rather than a descriptive perspective.</p><p>Political systems are, moreover, concretely organized through different types of political regimes. Political regimes imply different relations between the state and the societal political system, different degrees of articulation between the executive and the legislative, the contours of both, the intensity of surveillance and repression, as well as whether the one, the few, or the many are those who rule (or whether a mixed arrangement obtains). As stated above, typologies of political regimes are legion and may include traditional oligarchy, traditional autocracy, democracy, fascism, bureaucratic military dictatorship, and many other variants for capitalist societies, whereas autocracy and oligarchy were the staples of those who studied “communist” societies. We may say that, from the second half of the twentieth century onward, liberal representative democracy prevailed, but also that since the 1970s a process of re-oligarchization, leading to what we may call <i>advanced liberal oligarchy</i>, has gained momentum (<i>advanced autocracy</i> developing as well—for instance, in Russia, despite its even thinner democratic façade, with aurocratic elements appearing in many places, for instance in the US). <i>Liberal representative democracy has always been a mixed regime</i>, combining polyarchic elements (freedom of speech, manifestation and organization, open contestation, and the free participation of the many) and oligarchic ones (the control of the state political system and, from there, of much of the machine of the state as well as the media and even of other parts of the societal political system, such as non-profit and non-governmental organizations).</p><p>It has been the development of its oligarchy core to the detriment of its democratic elements—including the strengthening and closing of the state political system to the detriment of its societal counterpart—that largely explains the concerns of the authors who in the last decades returned to the study of oligarchy. In contrast, whereas the party-state remains in place in many countries, the teachings of the authors who had studied them have seemingly been forgotten. Although there was formerly a democratizing expansion, today we face a strong de-democratizing trend. Wealth plays a role in this developing situation, with politicians and dominant classes intertwined in these new developments, which, moreover, lessen the relevance of the societal political system, in whose opinions and demands political oligarchies are not interested—and may as well try to suppress. Along with de-democratization, neoliberal policies, or at best what can be defined as social liberal policies, have been opposed to universalizing social policies, at best catering for the poor.</p><p>If liberal representative democracy is indeed a mixed regime—contra Vergara's understanding of it as “monocratic”—we should not belittle its democratic aspects—which she apparently does. We should stick to this evaluation despite the stronghold exercised by oligarchic agents and institutions as well as the influence of the rich—the capitalist class, to be precise, today often its fractions linked to finance capital, and more recently big tech, as Marxist authors have in different ways emphasized. Those democratic aspects are a crucial acquisition of modernity, in tandem with the development of social rights and the like, through fierce political struggles between the many and the few. They must be resumed, and those political and social aspects further strengthened, including the subsumption of private property to the interests and needs of the citizenry at large.</p><p>Some political agents, including professional politicians, would indeed like to overcome this oligarchic character, something very hard to happen as this arrangement is obdurate and very difficult to change, especially at this point in time, when there is little stable citizen mobilization. Superseding it would require, besides, proper alternatives if new forms of the exercise of power were to prevail. The only real alterative ever tried—the power of revolutionary councils—has thus far failed. Besides, the party-state rule has even less room for democracy, if at all: it is purely oligarchic or even autocratic. It is not a mixed regime.</p><p>Although oligarchic rule has been reinforced, socio-political dynamics have included another trend. The autonomization, individual and collective, of individuals in the recent decades has gone hand in hand and apace with disaffection with their national political systems, including formerly mass political parties. Although there are powerful underlying social processes contributing in this direction, in particular “disembedding processes” that “free” individuals from political links and force them to autonomously take decisions, it is the self-determination of individuals as political agents and a deep political malaise that stand at the core of such developments. Since the 2000s, we have observed this trend worldwide, with different authors trying to grasp who these agents are and how to mobilize them for social emancipation (Bringel and Domingues <span>2015</span>; Domingues <span>2024</span>, chap. 8; Urbinati <span>2020</span>).</p><p>This has had an impact, more or less direct, on political theory andpolitical sociology. A strand parallel to the discussion of oligarchy has thus emerged, even if it is rather the identification of oligarchic rule that was an initial motivation for its further development, whereby both issues appear entangled. This strand has featured the assertion of plebeianism in different forms. Some insist on more subjective perspectives, others on institutional reforms that would provide democracy with a plebeian correction.</p><p>In the first case, we find Breaugh and Green. Breaugh (<span>2007</span>, xv–xxiii) speaks of the “experience” of the “plebs” as that of “…achieving dignity through political agency” and reconstructs historical moments of collective mobilization born out of the “desire for freedom.” Plebeianism is for him not an identity but rather the “political event” of the constitution of a “political subject.” It cannot, however, be sustained for any length of time. In turn, Green speaks of the “shadow of unfairness,” which leads ordinary citizens—who are actually second-class citizens—to feel at a “remove” from politics since the many—in contradistinction to the powerful few—do not, and cannot, have any expectation of real political influence. While representation is “opaque” and beyond accountability, the distance from politics for most citizens is compounded, in ways Green does not really explain, by the intrusion of socioeconomic inequalities—plutocracy—in the civic space. Against an exclusively “sunny” view of liberal representative democracy, he stresses its shadows (Green <span>2016</span>, 3–7). Against this predicament, Green suggests that in “plebeian democracy” (for which he looks especially at Rome for precedents), second-class citizens should learn to engage in various forms of “principled vulgarity” regarding discursivity and gladly embrace some level of “reasonable envy,” “arbitrariness,” and “rancor.” Although he stresses the need for “special regulatory treatment” of the powerful, particularly regarding the wealthy as well as redistributive measures and “protective” strategies for plebeians, Green does not think the situation is really amenable to far-reaching change. This is why he demands a sort of positive political realism. Although he supports liberal democracy, a proven political system in which “free and equal citizenship” has a real, albeit limited, place and in which we can further emancipation to some extent, he claims that politics is unlikely to be a source of happiness for plebeians. They are therefore in need of “solace” and what he calls “extrapoliticism”; epicureanism was, supposedly, exemplary in this respect for the many in Rome (Green <span>2016</span>, 7–16, chaps. 4–5).</p><p>McCormick and Vergara take a different direction, both concerned with the institutionalization of the power of the many against the few, despite fine distinctions between their proposals. They are inspired by Rome and the Italian republics, as well as, in the latter's case, Hannah Arendt and Rosa Luxemburg.</p><p>McCormick (<span>2011</span>, vii, 1–2, chaps. 4–6) demands an “extra-electoral model of elite accountability and popular empowerment.” These would be offices that exclude the rich from eligibility, the use of lottery alongside elections as procedures for appointments of magistrates, and “political trials” in which the whole citizenry takes part. This is what his Machiavellian democracy amounts to: allowing for more control of citizens over “political <i>and</i> socioeconomic elites.” Note that, against Gramsci's hopes, he nevertheless dismisses the possibility that elite rule can ever be altogether superseded (McCormick <span>2011</span>, 190, note 15). In turn, Vergara tries to elaborate plebeian remedies against systemic corruption and intensified oligarchization, though, like McCormick, she does think it is really impossible to overcome the division between the few and the many, apparently ever. This requires, according to her, institutions that are exclusive to plebeians and capable of exerting “veto” power over measures stemming from representatives and of censoring them directly, but also of initiating legislation, unchaining constituent power from below from time to time, as well as exercising the surveillance of political offices through delegates, who could impeach officials while forcing them to adopt the assemblies’ decisions. Extended local assemblies (councils) and tribunates, configuring a “plebeian branch” of liberal democracy (today not really a democracy in her view, we are forced to conclude, as, as seen above, its institutions pertain only to the elites). This branch seems to consist, at the same time, in “the people-as-network,” hence giving life to a decentered and heterogeneous political “collectivity” (Vergara <span>2020</span>, 3–5, chap. 9).</p><p>In addition, generally equating the “poor”—to which he gives pride of place—and the “plebs” (as well as the “multitude”), Kalyvas defends a democracy of the poor, radical in that the many would have preponderance. The division between the poor and the rich is, however, mostly instrumental, aiming to increase the power of the former, hence not consisting of an essentializing socioeconomic feature. This radical democracy of the poor is not attached to a “specific form,” with many different historical manifestations: Plebeian sovereignty is compatible with large direct assemblies, the council system, federated communes, and a network of voluntary primary associations; it may include the lottery, rotation, and recall; popular juries and courts; delegation and imperative mandates; and tyrannicide and insurrectional rights. Although less specific than what is proposed by McCormick and Vergara, his pallet is broader. Finally, Arlen (<span>2019</span>) takes a similar direction regarding diagnosis and the mobilization of Aristotle and the Greek tradition rather than Rome or the Italian republics, with a vindication of the poor too. He claims that the demos should be thought of with a “tripartite status as many, free, and poor.” It should be organized to counter “oligarchic harms,” with the many hence needing their own exclusive assemblies. Moreover, with reference to John Stuart Mill, Arlen (<span>2023</span>) has embraced the role of social movements and reforms against “plutocratic encroachment” within the framework of “liberal plebeianism.”</p><p>Although Kalyvas has thus far refused the wholesale elimination of the wealth differentials in the democracy of the poor, McCormick and Vergara, as well as Arlen, offer political solutions only, without really molesting the rich, the upper classes, including eventually stripping them of their wealth and property (Green was slightly bolder in this regard, though those other authors may have in mind, not really spelled out, legislative measures that imply a more radical redistribution of wealth). Moreover, they do not show us how to get to these plebeian institutions. Vergara tries to sketch a path but falls short of a plausible answer: Such institutions would be revolutionary but not in need of “an outright revolution” to be implemented. A combination of existing mechanisms and a “New Prince”—which, strangely, is not defined, either as an individual, social movements, or a political party—would be capable of pushing this through. She does not really consider the resistance such a move by the many would raise from the few. Luxemburg, for one, and in contrast, was acutely aware of such problems. Besides, such assemblies might as well be vulnerable to manipulation by the rich and powerful. Nor can one understand why solutions would be merely political insofar as socioeconomic inequality is absolutely crucial in Vergara's diagnosis of the contemporary political decay. After pointing out these shortcomings, Bagg (<span>2022</span>, 405–06, 409) suggests that plebeians’ collective power demands the traditional mass party. He does not elaborate on the issue, though, moreover a very contentious one in a society that has consistently rejected large hierarchical organizations.</p><p>Curiously, apart from Vergara's work, in her dialogue with Luxemburg and Arendt, the older socialist/communist/anarchist tradition of revolutionary councils—above all the Paris Commune and the Russian 1905 and 1917 Soviets—is barely brought up in these analyses of plebeianism (with Breaugh tackling the former through the lens of largely fleeting “experience”). These were, of course, attempts at direct democracy. The plebeians who organized them—factory and service workers, peasants and artisans, seconded by middle-class people and revolutionary intellectuals—strove to overcome representative democracy. These experiments failed, for different reasons, and the ones that survived were taken over by party “cadre” oligarchies. Today this looks like a blocked path, which has left us with liberal representative democracy as our ultimate horizon, despite time and again local experiences of direct democracy having ephemerally surfaced. We should not, however, take this as a foreclosed conclusion, even though these experiences should not be reified either.</p><p>Can we thus not reinvent democracy, controlling the power of political professionals, of whatever type, or even replacing them someday, altogether or by more contingent political incumbents, hence blocking the development of political oligarchies, which the moreover unlikely and at this stage probably ineffective nationalization of the “means of production” will never self-correct? Cannot anti-oligarchic plebeian democracy underpin the collective appropriation of the whole of social life, to start with the modern political dimension and its eventual dissolution, perhaps through something that is today often characterized as the “commons?” Can the political mass party, with its hierarchical and oligarchic historical tradition and perhaps inevitable largely vertical structuration, ever be resurrected as an instrument of the many? We cannot give these questions a clear answer, hopefully as yet. And yes, we need to be political realists, as Green and Vergara state, in that this is a very hard change to make. But these are issues worth pondering and a path we need to tread. It goes without saying that the socioeconomic issues related to wealth and property that the socialist–communist tradition raised and tried to solve are as important as the political ones, although I have stressed the differentiation of the political dimension. Concrete political systems and regimes are structured by their entanglement and how they mutually influence each other, a process in which capitalism enjoys enormous weight. Nor should they be overlooked in any sort of transformed, really fair social form we can project into the future. After all, if liberal plebeianism is a legitimate position, so is a socialist strand of plebeianism, which in a sense aims at its own abolition, even if this may work more as an immanently regulatory democratic perspective, nevertheless possibly to be achieved in the long-run future, along with a deep transformation in the overall structure of social life.</p><p>Theoretically, it remains to stress that criticizing oligarchy does not mean jettisoning the whole idea of representation and “representative democracy” from either a plebiscitary authoritarian or an “extra-parliamentary” position. In the first case, we know what has happened. The direct personification of the people in the most extreme-right “leader” the world has ever seen led to a wholesale catastrophe. This has, of course, nothing to do with democracy. In the second case, there was indeed something naïve, not in the deserved criticism of liberal democratic systems, but because simply getting rid of representation cannot be even envisaged today as a solution. The eternal return of representation is what councils in all revolutionary processes have produced, under the disguise of “delegation” sometimes, with, in contrast, individual revolutionaries and parties becoming new oligarchic elements of political power in the process of system change and the build-up of authoritarian collectivism. Moreover, the complexity of contemporary societies is an inescapable reality. That said, let me now resume some key issues of this article and derive some further conclusions from them.</p><p>I have tried to argue here that the imaginary, institutions, practices, and dynamics of political modernity, hence of politics as such, must be seen mainly as autonomous from society at large, particularly from economic interests. These have been at the core of liberalism (once it accepted its abstract rationalist universalism was insufficient to grasp and, in particular, tackle political processes) and Marxism (regardless of whether the economy only in the “last instance” influenced politics, what has been actually weakened in favor of more economist views lately). Many of the political crises of recent years are at heart political crises as such, not a consequence of class projects, though these have hurt and contributed to citizen cum plebeian dissatisfaction. The increasingly oligarchic character of contemporary political systems in much of the world—and the problems that may emerge in party-state regimes may eventually express this too—is responsible for these upheavals. It has been confronted by a plebeian mobilization that shows people's disaffection vis-à-vis politicians—power holders or ruling collectivities, in fact, since they have no special qualities such as the term “elite” was intended to convey.</p><p>When we examine concrete situations, we must take the entwinement among economic, political, and social power into account, without collapsing and conflating different dimensions, especially the political dimension. However, to fully understand a political regime, the diverse possibilities (this is never univocal) of connection between power holders, that is, ruling collectivities on the one hand, and (dominant or subaltern) classes and other societal and state collectivities on the other, must be contemplated and investigated. In the case of advanced political oligarchy, a looming political regime, finance capital, and global corporations (now probably including big tech) have stood out, but this must not be seen as exclusive or inevitable. What is more, the specific connections between them must be identified, demonstrated, and conceptualized rather than taken for granted (mere elective affinity of views and indirect inferences of influence will not do).</p><p>Besides, the discussion of oligarchy may allow us to recover some older themes of political thought. If Vergara is correct and insightful when she brings up the more general idea of corruption as decay, a characteristic that increasingly seems to mark the role of political agents is ordinary corruption, defined according to liberal thought and modern state institutions (the illegal appropriation of public resources by state and societal individuals and collectivities, that is, <i>neopatrimonialism</i>). In addition, the visibility of corruption has produced and evinced the malaise that affects plebeians and has led to recent political mobilizations. Yet, if we take the republican tradition more broadly, oligarchy may be linked today to a much more encompassing definition of corruption: the decadence of political institutions and values, in republican terms, which is also a far-reaching phenomenon of our time and includes, of course, that liberal, more limited definition of corruption (Araújo <span>2013</span>). This has to do with the restriction of democracy and the unaccountability of so-called political “elites”—which are not “elites” in any sense, though personal demonization is not the case either, as it is first of all the actual structure of political systems that matters. To be sure, all regimes can be corrupted in both senses. Nevertheless, beyond the role of the judiciary, particularly in modern liberal republics, it is within the affirmation of democracy that both sorts of corruption may be counterposed against the consolidation of advanced liberal oligarchy (as as wel as of advanced autocracy and their mixed forms).</p><p>Beyond such particularly awkward moments, in order also that radical democracy as a regime—which, based on immanent critique, may become a regulatory ideal against which to measure actual democratic regimes—does not remain oblivious to the oligarchic dynamic of power and is projected as a way to contain it, we must, first of all, recognize the issue of political power in its specificity. Only then can we properly think of emancipation, exercising a permanent critique, practical as well, of actual democracies, implying true democratization and control of those on top political positions. Leninist and social democratic politicians may not like the idea that they respond, when in office and when not, largely, albeit often not exclusively or overwhelmingly, when “sinister interests” prevail, to their desires and projects, including acquiring and keeping political power, with its attendant benefits in other spheres. Nevertheless, for most people, this should be—and increasingly tends to be—seen as a crucial factor in the distribution of power in the modern and perhaps a postmodern civilization. Those who engage in politics, especially when occupying official elective positions, should be aware of these problems, with the aim to fight against them. Urbinati's (<span>2014</span>) dialogic model of representation—which does not correspond at all to contemporary practices—would be a step in this direction. The proposals thrown up in recent discussions of oligarchy and plebeianism—councils, assemblies, and tribunates, among others—may also contribute to democratic advancements, with the proviso that they may be implemented only as a result of probably fierce and nasty clashes. Our political imagination can in any case further develop, giving more power to plebeians, workers, the poor, and the multitude—in other words, the subaltern many who have always been the bedrock of democratic demands and advancements.</p><p>We may never approach absolute isonomy or democracy. In this regard, plebeianism may never disappear since rulers and the ruled imply a division difficult to utterly overcome. However, the horizon, the goal, and the movement toward them are exceedingly important and must be borne, in mind. This should be a core element of a critical theory of political modernity and its immanent critique, also beyond modern civilization, both at present and in whatever power arrangements the future may bring into being.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"32 2","pages":"245-254"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2025-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.70004","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.70004","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Oligarchy is back. That is, it has recently essayed to make a conceptual comeback because it has never disappeared from the way societies are ruled and, particularly and specifically in modernity, political life. What is it, though? Mostly it has remained untheorized or undertheorized in modernity, despite some critical approaches having mentioned it in connection to liberalism, such as Castoriadis’ (1999, 153ff), whereas others, within democratic liberalism, pointed to it as a stage in the development of liberalism that would have been already superseded, such as Santos (2013). This article precisely aims to engage with it in modernity and critically assess its relation to democracy, including its relation to plebeianism.

Since apparently the Persians, but more consistently with the Greeks and above all Aristotle, oligarchy entered the vocabulary of power and rule (or “government”), having a sort of half-life in Medieval times, when monarchical power and the papacy held center stage in the discussions about power. Oligarchy re-emerged in the Renaissance, for instance, in Machiavelli, and early modern thinking, including Montesquieu, but was eventually sidelined by a different sort of vocabulary in which the ancient tradition of “forms of rule” (or “government”) played no role. Yet the theories of “elites,” especially Mosca and Pareto, as well as liberal approaches, provided new names for this old phenomenon, which could not be entirely overlooked, actually hypostatizing it as a universal and inexorable phenomenon (Urbinati 2010). Only here and there, with limited consequences, were such ideas resumed by modern thinkers. The state, representation, and other concepts took the place of the forms of rule within a new caesura regarding the discourse about power and the emergence of a specific dimension in modernity, the political one.

Despite the analysis of the oligarchization of the inner life of political parties as a distinctive phenomenon, particularly in Michels’ (1911/2009) classic work about the German Social Democratic Party (which refrains from discussing oligarchy as a form of government or rule), that is, as strictly political, oligarchy has primarily been understood according to Aristotle's (1996) definition, that is, as the self-oriented rule of the few. These are, in fact and at the same time, the rich—thus configuring a “plutocracy.” This is also McCormick's (2011) and Winters’ (2011) perspective, the main references for contemporary discussions, as well as that of other recent authors such as Arlen (2019, 2023), Vergara (2020), and Bagg (2022), as well as Kalyvas (2019), with an opposition between the oligarchy and the “poor.”1

Winters stresses that oligarchs are concerned with and dedicate themselves to the “defence of property,” which is based, differently from Rome, on “strong property rights.” On the other hand, oligarchs do not usually hold office (when they do, “vanity” is often the reason why). In any case, they have developed—by means that he does not actually clarify—an “Income Defense Industry,” hiding wealth, evading taxes, and using “complex tax shelters.” Oligarchs, Winters (2011, xi–xvi, 7–8) argues, are to be seen as individuals (not, for instance, corporations). As he elaborates his arguments, Winters states that—in variance with Aristotle, he suggests, though he also stresses, in a different passage, that the latter links power and wealth—he does not think that oligarchy is simply the rule of the few: He is keen to emphasize its “material foundations,” with wealth inequality producing extreme political inequality (Winters 2011, 3, 27). Winters does recognize that there are other sources of power, based on political rights, official positions, coercive and mobilizational power, along with material power. Official positions are separated out in the modern state; that is to say, they do not directly derive from wealth, he points out. On the other hand, oligarchs are able to exert huge influence on such officials. Although he is mainly interested in what he calls “civil oligarchy” (which depends on a system of laws), Winters (2011, 34ff, 209, chaps. 2–5) proposed a typology of oligarchies (warring, ruling, sultanistic, tamed, and wild, along with the “civil” variant, which is the outstandingly modern one). Finally, Winters stresses the difference between the concepts of oligarchy and “elite,” which obscured, in the case of Mosca and Pareto, the role of wealth since it was too encompassing. The issue would have also been misunderstood by Michels when he defined the German Social Democratic Party as oligarchic. In contradistinction, from the Soviet Union to Cuba, we actually found elite rule, but such societies should not be characterized as oligarchic since wealth played no role in them (Winters 2011, 8, 275–77).

In turn, McCormick is much more ambiguous in his characterization of oligarchy. He mixes without greater worry oligarchy and elites (“socioeconomic and political”) (McCormick 2011, 1, 13–17, 167), without really defining each of them very clearly, though wealth always appears as a major issue for the characterization of their power (with, sometimes, “class” and “class consciousness” being mentioned without any specification). Actually, during most of the book, McCormick barely speaks of oligarchies except with reference to Rome and the Italian Renaissance republics, and mostly as he discusses Machiavelli's work. It is really only in the chapter about “Post-electoral democracies” that McCormick more systematically works with the idea of oligarchy—yet mainly to contrast it with reformed, hence properly democratic, republics (McCormick 2011, chaps. 6–7).

The same mix between “elites” and “oligarchy” appears in Vergara's work. We have experienced—seemingly in the last decades—a systematic decay—“systemic corruption”—of the liberal representative government. It manifests itself in the “oligarchization” of power in society (configuring a “trend”). A small minority has accumulated and monopolized wealth, with dire political consequences. The power of the few has increasingly become exclusive; they have become the sole rulers, against the interests of the many, with the elites left to comfortably “police themselves.” She strongly asserts that liberal representative democracies are not mixed regimes—they are rather “monocratic,” with, simply, a “separation of functions.” Although she had previously mentioned the oligarchization of power in society, she eventually states her main concern: “Political power is today de facto oligarchic” (Vergara 2020, 1–4). Although the latter assertion is largely correct, I believe the former is not. A reason for this different assessment will be given later in this article.

Both McCormick and Vergara are above all intent on defending a plebeian perspective. Their depiction of oligarchy is thus less systematic than Winter's. I will return to plebeianism toward the end of the article. For now, let us critically discuss these authors’ views of oligarchies and elites.

I do not entirely want to deny their descriptions and conceptualizations, yet I think they are often reductive or confusing. It would be ludicrous to overlook how wealth sways political life and how the rich have numerous channels through which they reach out to politicians and influence or even harness their actions according to their objectives. They are surely concerned with the defense of their property, wealth, and income (which are, incidentally, different phenomena). We need, however, to develop a more precise view of oligarchy in modernity, with its specificity, hence also going beyond the loose idea of “elites” (which, moreover, cannot but be infused with underlying positive resonances, recalling aristocracies to mind). Despite the prominence of concentrated economic power, I want to argue that we have to see oligarchy in terms of political power as such. In Aristotle's time, there was a close articulation among material, military, and, for lack of a better word, say, “governmental” power. Rule tightly weaved all these elements together. In modernity, there came about nevertheless a differentiation of the political dimension from other social dimensions, whereas socioeconomic classes are now more central in the material, socioeconomic dimension. The political dimension—likewise the economic one—has acquired its own logic and sources of power. That much is recognized by Winters, as we saw above, though we will need to introduce further distinctions to properly grasp this dimension. In particular, we need to draw the proper conclusions from this differentiation, which Winters only partly does. Finally, McCormick's reference to social classes must be properly articulated, especially regarding modernity.

When I speak of oligarchy in this article, it is therefore basically to political oligarchy that I refer. We could speak of economic oligarchies in order to single out the wealthiest people in one country and, at this stage, even in the whole world, even though dominant economic classes are larger than this cohort of superrich people. More approximatively, we could perhaps point to oligarchies in other areas of human activities, from the arts to sports and beyond. But, of utmost importance to political dynamics, I want to discuss specifically how political power—state-based but with connections in political processes in society at large—is shaped in modernity and how this is established through the rule of the political few. Although political power has also been characterized by the growing importance of wealth, we cannot directly derive this trend, which Vergara correctly identifies, from the influence of wealth, though this is also a cause and effect of political oligarchization. The socioeconomic and political powerful agents who McCormick often joins together in one breath need to be distinguished—not to belittle the role of property and wealth, which are more than just a crucial aspect of class relations in modern societies based on capitalism, but to support a proper understanding of how they relate to political power in its specificity.

This outlook will allow us to see how political power is organized in this specific dimension and is exercised by political collectivities. That is to say, we will observe how it assumes a peculiar form in modernity but also in the attempts to move beyond it, which we can call authoritarian collectivism, where the few also ruled (in a more integral alternative social formation) and rule (after an economic transition to capitalism). We will be able thereby to discuss how pro-capitalist, pro-business political collectivities operate and how left-wing forces are usually traversed by oligarchic tendencies, too, constituting oligarchic structures, which have been transferred from parties to state structures and vice versa. How this combines with elements of the rule of the one—autocratic—and of the many—democratic—can then be discussed. We will, in addition, see how those who do not share in the exercise of power should be defined as “plebeians”—politically, that is—and the contemporary political dynamic, in which the verticality of the exercise of (oligarchic) political power is time and again rejected (Breaugh 2007; McCormick 2011; Green 2016; Vergara 2020; Ramírez 2022), which others prefer to treat foremost through the category of the “poor” (Kalyvas 2019; Arlen 2019).

In the next sections, (1) I further elaborate on the differentiation of the political dimension and discuss the relations among oligarchy, elites, and social classes; (2) I then systematically define the concepts of political system and political regimes, as well as carry out a discussion of the forms of rule in modernity (mainly under liberalism) and postmodernity (authoritarian collectivism), with dynamic elements; (3) finally, I take up the problem of political plebeianism, as well as of the “poor” and related concepts, which leads me to discuss the remedies recently proposed to address these issues; (4) a conclusion follows. I should note, before moving further, that, although strongly engaged with political theory, this is a work of political sociology, which I actually deem of great relevance to furthering the contemporary debate on oligarchy and plebeianism.

There was no politics as such before modernity. Power was undoubtedly an issue that existentially cut across all civilizations and specific social formations (specific “societies”). Neither social life nor social relations, vertical or horizontal, exist without it. Domination and ruling, with their hierarchical verticality, became indeed connected to the state. However, how diverse “sources” of power combined differed significantly from the sort of arrangement modernity brought about. We do not need to accept the idea that an evolution led from simple, undifferentiated societies to complex ones, where differentiation dominated and implied new mechanisms of coordination. There have been many paths in social evolution and development, different combinations of material, ruling, and spiritual power, which do not allow for a flat picture of a unilinear process. Nevertheless, in what henceforth became the “West,” modernity slowly emerged, and the political dimension differentiated out.3 It contained a way of organizing power that initially should be domesticated and perhaps disguised, with any new political features as such disappearing in any case. This was so because the political representative system—both legislative and, even more so, executive—was supposed to merely maintain pristine civil—less so political—rights for all the citizens who had decided to build this new state apparatus, fundamentally based on abstract law. For the observance of law and to keep those pristine rights, legal and repressive forces (eventually a differentiated-out police) linked to the executive and the judiciary had a crucial role to play, which was tin a sense passive, aiming at the maintenance of pristine relations between abstract citizens. As it unfolded, political modernity became increasingly politicized, with the concrete issues of social life invading that abstract dimension in what regards both citizens and state, with at the same time an expansion and democratization of political modernity. This configured an expansive trend regarding the combination of republicanism and liberalism that was hegemonic in modernity (since the 1970s, reversed in the direction of renewed oligarchization, which formally kept democratic institutions).

It is true that we partly use the same vocabulary as the Greeks and the Romans, particularly “politics,” “citizenship,” and the “public,” along with those forms of rule. However, several of these terms meant absolutely different things now and then. Just take “politics,” a central concept in Greece and in modernity. In Aristotle (1996, especially 72ff), in such a “political” framework it is not only, and perhaps not even mainly, the exercise of power that is at stake. As Hegel (1820/1986) perceived, he was referring to an “ethical totality” (Sittlichkeit)—which included the oikos and the family, to start with—as well as values and the belonging to a city—the polis—the only place and circumstance where life was meaningful and genuinely human. Those forms of rule or government—monarchy and tyranny, aristocracy and oligarchy, and isonomy and democracy—directly pointed to the exercise of power, as such not “political,” a word reserved for a more encompassing reality (that of the “polis” in general). The first term of the pair was meant to be positive, virtuous, as rulers would be concerned with the common good; the second, in contrast, was negative, as they would rule according to their self-interest. Aristotle was much more aware than most writers until the beginning of modernity of the role of material interests and power concerning those forms of government or rule, yet the polis was much more than that.

With Machiavelli, we started to speak of naked power, the state, and a particular dimension of the former's exercise. This was consolidated with Hobbes and subsequent authors. Note as well that such forms of rule or government have been seen, from Aristotle through Montesquieu to the “framers” of the United States Constitution and beyond, often as composite, that is, as mixed forms, in which the rule of the one, of the few, and of the many may combine in varied ways. Actually, many authors—such as Aristotle, Machiavelli, and those US “framers”—favored such mixed forms, which they deemed more stable and as embodying the advantages of different principles. The framers were happy to see, hovering above their limited democracy, a “natural aristocracy” of the spirit, as they fancied themselves (Jefferson 1813/1959; moreover, before him and with a direct influence upon his views, see Harrington 1656/1992, 23; see also McCormick 2011, for the Italian Renaissance, especially Guicciardini).

This move also required a reflection on how power—specifically political, now—would be organized, who would rule, and how these persons would rule or govern. The answer developed piecemeal, in theory and practice. The North American War of Independence (replicated but with much less global impact in the south of the continent) and the French Revolution still made use, in a good measure, of the old, classical teachings. New concepts were crafted too, some already found to some extent in the Medieval vocabulary, though in other registers, such as “representation,” to deal with the complexity of the new civilization; or, with its modern meaning crafted slightly earlier, the “state,” to refer to the machine of rule. Nevertheless, what had been, until the beginning of modernity, the standard vocabulary and typology to deal with forms of rule or government—the rule or government of the one, the few, and the many—gave way to democracy, “representative” but for some currents, as a demand, “direct” too, “dictatorship” (meaning something else than it did for the Romans), and eventually more euphemistic, supposedly technical terms such as Dahl's (1960/1963) “closed hegemonies,” “competitive oligarchies,” “inclusive hegemonies,” and “polyarchy”—with henceforth a legion of directly empirically based typologies.

Yet classical ideas somehow lived on, sparsely and incompletely, in some approaches. This was the case, for instance, of Michels’ aforementioned work. They were present in Schmitt's (1928/1993, 292–303) analyses, in particular when he discussed how elections embodied an aristocratic principle, in contrast to the Greek lot and the plebiscitary acclamation he envisaged for his model of (supposedly) “democracy” (see also Manin 1997). “Extra-parliamentary” fierce criticisms of the political system and its insulation from the citizenry also resumed the classical vocabulary (see Agnoli 1967/1990), which was, time and again, applied, curiously, by some analysis of “real socialism” (Tucker 1963; Cohen 1985; Author, 2024). But a major conceptual shift had actually taken place.

The concepts of aristocracy and oligarchy ended up giving way to the rule or government of the “elites” (Mosca 1895/1923; Pareto 1916/1923) when analysts were wont to speak of power differentials, with liberals usually uncomfortable with the looming need to recognize that in their representative democracy there were rulers and the ruled. At the same time, liberal theories concerned with political modernity increasingly tended to see politics as a representation of societal interests (which were either more “universal” as to representatives, as Burke stressed, or particularized ones, as Marx and later liberals such as Dahl pointed out).

To be sure, utilitarian liberalism was aware of what Bentham (1822/1988, 115–122) called “sinister interests” (of lawyers and judges as well as politicians), a sort of interest deviously aiming at one's happiness (“utility”). It was nevertheless seen as connected to the rule of the one or the few. Once the many ruled (through the few, though!), Bentham thought interests—with the universal public good in command—would be aligned appropriately, such as in the United States. He was wrong, though. More control may be achieved, but sectional interests will remain in what amounts to a sort of mixed government insofar as the political system distinguishes between those who govern and the governed, rulers and the ruled, as I further argue below. Partly surely influenced by Rousseau, Robespierre, though accepting the representative principle, he himself a parliamentarian, was aware of the problem and denounced its creeping relevance. In contradistinction to Burke, for instance, Robespierre suggested, as solutions to the autonomization of the interests of the representatives vis-à-vis the citizens who elected them, a number of measures: virtue, more frequent elections, the at least potentially frequent turnover of parliamentarians, hence the immersion of representatives in the people at least for a length of time, along with open public deliberation and the interdiction of participation in the executive of members of parliament (Mathiez 1920/2018, 33–38). Whether the “incorruptible” followed his own advice during his time in office begs the question.4

A further, though brief, discussion of Marxist perspectives as well as a Weberian one that resumes some of its perspectives is in order, as especially the former current has given particular attention to the relation between wealth, property, and income, on the one hand, and political power, on the other; and, of course, to social classes, a concept that cannot be properly replaced by oligarchy (which ends up as a mere synonym for the superrich, also a vague though sensitizing descriptive notion). Political theorists of oligarchy, blending indistinguishably political and economic power, often totally overlook this crucial literature. But they do that at their own peril, as these have been the authors who have really tried to grasp—though drawing upon the concept of social class rather than economic oligarchy or elites—the connection between wealth and property, on the one hand, and political power, on the other—mostly the state in general in their theories, which is also a shortcoming.

Marx and Engels (1848/1978) originally—in a manifesto that referred to a period in which the electoral franchise was extremely restricted—affirmed that the state was a “committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie” (though their conceptions became increasingly more complex and nuanced as modernity advanced and their thought matured). Almost a century later, although Gramsci (1929-35/2001) stressed the class character of the (enlarged) state and “hegemony,” he did recognize, on the other hand, that usually the ruling classes did not govern directly, maintaining a more distant relation with politics. In the even later Marxist debate, Miliband (1969) argued that the ruling classes did govern directly but was sharply criticized by Poulantzas (1978), who developed a more mediated theory that regarded the state as a “field of struggles” between the classes, jettisoning the simpler idea that it was the executive “committee” of the bourgeois, to start with due to its complexity. Offe's (1972/1973, 1986) perspective was even more mediated: the main concern of the state and politicians was the reproduction of their own power, for which the smooth accumulation of capital was necessary, implying therefore an inevitable adjustment to the interests and demands of capitalists rather than their direct representation. Resuming Poulantzas’ views, Jessop (2008) almost dissociated the state from capitalist classes or classes, though without denying their concrete intertwinement. This had been a step more radically taken by Block (1977) several years before, according to whom (at variance with a class-instrumentalist perspective and going beyond Offe's older works) the responsivity of “state managers” to fragmented capitalists’ interests rests on their own eagerness to remain in power.

We thus see that the tendency within Marxism is to look at politics and the state as conditioned by social classes and (“in the last instance”) the economy, but also that a rather nuanced standpoint was eventually articulated (although there is in these authors hardly an adequate distinction between the state and the political system, which is very important and on which I shall elaborate below). The so-called instrumentalist perspective was ditched. I think this was a very positive development. That is to say, Marxism went far beyond Marx and Engels’ original views, partly historically justified only, which at this point in history are false. This is not to deny that the rich—or the bourgeoisie, however we define it in the era of corporate capitalism—have enormous influence in politics—especially and visibly in the United States; but this influence is indirect, while capitalists—or businesspeople more generally—must grapple with the interests of professional politicians, as well as of bureaucrats (in which, for instance, the European Union excels).

The Weberian tradition, especially with Mann (1993), also came to recognize the links between social classes and the state, hence between wealth and politics, but did not subordinate the latter to the former either, though their solutions (cf. Mann's social “crystallizations” within the state) are elusive. This should be borne in mind in the further development of this article. Such sociological understanding is not inimical to the idea that wealth is a determinant of politics and that the very rich are intent on defending their properties and assets, which they are. It points, however, to a view in which the complexities of modern and especially contemporary society are taken into account. This is, on the other hand, very different from what elitist theories suggest, in which the specific mechanisms of the generation and reproduction of power often tend to disappear and an inevitability of, positively conceived, power differentials is supposed and explained away. Moreover, to be sure, the direct weight of the rich (bourgeoisies or economic oligarchies) upon the political system varies in space-time—from country to country and in different periods—something not to be lost from sight when more empirically oriented analyses are undertaken, which shall not be the case here.

More recently, the professionalization of politics and of political systems has been put under scrutiny. It has allowed for the transition of the kind of politician who, in Weber's (1919/1988) classical terms, lives “for politics” to those who live “off politics.” Traditional oligarchies are hence also overcome, but, as such, this does not alter the oligarchic character of political systems, with politicians very much aware of their specificity and own interests, including enriching themselves since many or even most of them were not really rich before entering politics (Borchert and Zeiss 2003). This transition developed along with the democratization of political systems through mass parties, but it is by no means incompatible with processes that entail de-democratization.

At this stage, the question should thus be unambiguously stated: It is the exercise of power in rather autonomous ways and the customary defense of political power privileges that is at stake for political oligarchies, even though they are frequently closely aligned with the dominant classes (conceptually defined), the rich (phenomenologically perceived and described), and the like, or are actually part of them. If dominant classes and the rich are concerned with property as well as income and wealth, and authoritarian collectivist oligarchies are concerned with maintaining their power, from which the control of the corporate property they enjoyed derived, in liberal systems of rule, control of political power also has an independent logic, separate from the economic dimension, that is, wealth and property (with state capitalism combining both logics). This arrangement is directly related to the modern differentiation of the political dimension and does not depend directly on the wishes of political officials—professional politicians—who may even be uncomfortable with it. It also implies an internal logic related to acquiring and maintaining power, regarding self-interest, and beliefs in the limited imaginary of liberal democracy or oligarchy. This rests on a lot of ideology—this concept understood as the structuration of a universe of meaning that, usually including some varied level of plausibility or truth, hides part of reality and furnishes specious justifications for its problematic or especially ugly aspects. This is even more true of the mix between party-state rule and capitalism today.

Michels was in particular very concerned with how oligarchization developed within organizations—mass organizations, envisaged as a means to achieve the opposite objective, namely, democratization. If liberals have consistently, at least until recently, looked the other way regarding the oligarchic elements of liberal democracy, that closure of power was one of the problems and impasses that workers’ parties and the tradition of workers’ councils tried to tackle. The fact that oligarchized organizations pushed for overall democratization—and largely succeeded—and organized popular participation does not make them non-oligarchic. What is more, this oligarchic character harbored innumerable problems that either did surface with a vengeance in the postrevolutionary period or eventually marred the very possibility of further democratization and true reformism. This is a crucial paradox—Michel's paradox, we can call it—that accompanied political modernity in the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries. At least in this form, it is no longer with us, although organizations and especially large national parties, let alone the international sphere, imply such reiterated complication, with, simultaneously, a demand for democratization and the rule of the few, which has become paramount today.5 There has been—today we can clearly see, though many refuse to face it—a rather naive belief in Marxism, according to which once the state and political power disappeared, as a consequence of the end of private property, the problem would also wither away. The working classes would, moreover, control the process and prevent its developing distortions (an issue that made Bolsheviks nervous, though excessive self-confidence led them to wish the problem away—see, for instance, clearly, Bukharin 1925). They all chose to overlook a problem Bakunin (1873/1990) had early on pointed out, with direct reference to Marx.

Oligarchic rule may not be universal and inevitable. It is, however, very hard to overcome in any sort of overall social arrangement.

In order to further elaborate on the differentiation of the political dimension in modernity and grasp some further aspect of oligarchic rule, I must now systematically tackle the concept of political system, which I have thus far employed without properly defining it, as well as the concept of political regime.6 The state has been seen, in too many approaches and analyses, as the site of the exercise of political power. But this is problematic. Both concepts, of the state and of political systems, referring to different issues, must be retained. Although any part of the state may be politicized at any moment, the core of politics is actually the political system, basically the legislative and executive powers, where law is produced and decisions are taken. Politicians, today mostly elected though not always, operate in the political system, whereas bureaucrats occupy non-elective positions. To be sure, this distinction is relative, but most of the state is most of the time politically rather neutral, such as the courts and the at present extremely differentiated administrative apparatus, including the army, though it is permeated by ideologies and political preferences, and in moments of crisis or due to politicians’ decisions its formal neutrality can quickly change. Oligarchic power is exercised fundamentally in and through those two specific elements of the political system. Under liberal representative democracy, elected officials control these spaces, with a more vertical arrangement obtaining in party-state systems. If this is the state aspect of the political system, we must, however, also point to a societal political system, which organizes interests, values, and a societal agenda, in any case often in direct contact with the state political system, although at times it is strongly repressed. Unions, associations, non-profit, and non-governmental organizations are its pillars. The political system, with its two sides, is cast here with an analytical rather than a descriptive perspective.

Political systems are, moreover, concretely organized through different types of political regimes. Political regimes imply different relations between the state and the societal political system, different degrees of articulation between the executive and the legislative, the contours of both, the intensity of surveillance and repression, as well as whether the one, the few, or the many are those who rule (or whether a mixed arrangement obtains). As stated above, typologies of political regimes are legion and may include traditional oligarchy, traditional autocracy, democracy, fascism, bureaucratic military dictatorship, and many other variants for capitalist societies, whereas autocracy and oligarchy were the staples of those who studied “communist” societies. We may say that, from the second half of the twentieth century onward, liberal representative democracy prevailed, but also that since the 1970s a process of re-oligarchization, leading to what we may call advanced liberal oligarchy, has gained momentum (advanced autocracy developing as well—for instance, in Russia, despite its even thinner democratic façade, with aurocratic elements appearing in many places, for instance in the US). Liberal representative democracy has always been a mixed regime, combining polyarchic elements (freedom of speech, manifestation and organization, open contestation, and the free participation of the many) and oligarchic ones (the control of the state political system and, from there, of much of the machine of the state as well as the media and even of other parts of the societal political system, such as non-profit and non-governmental organizations).

It has been the development of its oligarchy core to the detriment of its democratic elements—including the strengthening and closing of the state political system to the detriment of its societal counterpart—that largely explains the concerns of the authors who in the last decades returned to the study of oligarchy. In contrast, whereas the party-state remains in place in many countries, the teachings of the authors who had studied them have seemingly been forgotten. Although there was formerly a democratizing expansion, today we face a strong de-democratizing trend. Wealth plays a role in this developing situation, with politicians and dominant classes intertwined in these new developments, which, moreover, lessen the relevance of the societal political system, in whose opinions and demands political oligarchies are not interested—and may as well try to suppress. Along with de-democratization, neoliberal policies, or at best what can be defined as social liberal policies, have been opposed to universalizing social policies, at best catering for the poor.

If liberal representative democracy is indeed a mixed regime—contra Vergara's understanding of it as “monocratic”—we should not belittle its democratic aspects—which she apparently does. We should stick to this evaluation despite the stronghold exercised by oligarchic agents and institutions as well as the influence of the rich—the capitalist class, to be precise, today often its fractions linked to finance capital, and more recently big tech, as Marxist authors have in different ways emphasized. Those democratic aspects are a crucial acquisition of modernity, in tandem with the development of social rights and the like, through fierce political struggles between the many and the few. They must be resumed, and those political and social aspects further strengthened, including the subsumption of private property to the interests and needs of the citizenry at large.

Some political agents, including professional politicians, would indeed like to overcome this oligarchic character, something very hard to happen as this arrangement is obdurate and very difficult to change, especially at this point in time, when there is little stable citizen mobilization. Superseding it would require, besides, proper alternatives if new forms of the exercise of power were to prevail. The only real alterative ever tried—the power of revolutionary councils—has thus far failed. Besides, the party-state rule has even less room for democracy, if at all: it is purely oligarchic or even autocratic. It is not a mixed regime.

Although oligarchic rule has been reinforced, socio-political dynamics have included another trend. The autonomization, individual and collective, of individuals in the recent decades has gone hand in hand and apace with disaffection with their national political systems, including formerly mass political parties. Although there are powerful underlying social processes contributing in this direction, in particular “disembedding processes” that “free” individuals from political links and force them to autonomously take decisions, it is the self-determination of individuals as political agents and a deep political malaise that stand at the core of such developments. Since the 2000s, we have observed this trend worldwide, with different authors trying to grasp who these agents are and how to mobilize them for social emancipation (Bringel and Domingues 2015; Domingues 2024, chap. 8; Urbinati 2020).

This has had an impact, more or less direct, on political theory andpolitical sociology. A strand parallel to the discussion of oligarchy has thus emerged, even if it is rather the identification of oligarchic rule that was an initial motivation for its further development, whereby both issues appear entangled. This strand has featured the assertion of plebeianism in different forms. Some insist on more subjective perspectives, others on institutional reforms that would provide democracy with a plebeian correction.

In the first case, we find Breaugh and Green. Breaugh (2007, xv–xxiii) speaks of the “experience” of the “plebs” as that of “…achieving dignity through political agency” and reconstructs historical moments of collective mobilization born out of the “desire for freedom.” Plebeianism is for him not an identity but rather the “political event” of the constitution of a “political subject.” It cannot, however, be sustained for any length of time. In turn, Green speaks of the “shadow of unfairness,” which leads ordinary citizens—who are actually second-class citizens—to feel at a “remove” from politics since the many—in contradistinction to the powerful few—do not, and cannot, have any expectation of real political influence. While representation is “opaque” and beyond accountability, the distance from politics for most citizens is compounded, in ways Green does not really explain, by the intrusion of socioeconomic inequalities—plutocracy—in the civic space. Against an exclusively “sunny” view of liberal representative democracy, he stresses its shadows (Green 2016, 3–7). Against this predicament, Green suggests that in “plebeian democracy” (for which he looks especially at Rome for precedents), second-class citizens should learn to engage in various forms of “principled vulgarity” regarding discursivity and gladly embrace some level of “reasonable envy,” “arbitrariness,” and “rancor.” Although he stresses the need for “special regulatory treatment” of the powerful, particularly regarding the wealthy as well as redistributive measures and “protective” strategies for plebeians, Green does not think the situation is really amenable to far-reaching change. This is why he demands a sort of positive political realism. Although he supports liberal democracy, a proven political system in which “free and equal citizenship” has a real, albeit limited, place and in which we can further emancipation to some extent, he claims that politics is unlikely to be a source of happiness for plebeians. They are therefore in need of “solace” and what he calls “extrapoliticism”; epicureanism was, supposedly, exemplary in this respect for the many in Rome (Green 2016, 7–16, chaps. 4–5).

McCormick and Vergara take a different direction, both concerned with the institutionalization of the power of the many against the few, despite fine distinctions between their proposals. They are inspired by Rome and the Italian republics, as well as, in the latter's case, Hannah Arendt and Rosa Luxemburg.

McCormick (2011, vii, 1–2, chaps. 4–6) demands an “extra-electoral model of elite accountability and popular empowerment.” These would be offices that exclude the rich from eligibility, the use of lottery alongside elections as procedures for appointments of magistrates, and “political trials” in which the whole citizenry takes part. This is what his Machiavellian democracy amounts to: allowing for more control of citizens over “political and socioeconomic elites.” Note that, against Gramsci's hopes, he nevertheless dismisses the possibility that elite rule can ever be altogether superseded (McCormick 2011, 190, note 15). In turn, Vergara tries to elaborate plebeian remedies against systemic corruption and intensified oligarchization, though, like McCormick, she does think it is really impossible to overcome the division between the few and the many, apparently ever. This requires, according to her, institutions that are exclusive to plebeians and capable of exerting “veto” power over measures stemming from representatives and of censoring them directly, but also of initiating legislation, unchaining constituent power from below from time to time, as well as exercising the surveillance of political offices through delegates, who could impeach officials while forcing them to adopt the assemblies’ decisions. Extended local assemblies (councils) and tribunates, configuring a “plebeian branch” of liberal democracy (today not really a democracy in her view, we are forced to conclude, as, as seen above, its institutions pertain only to the elites). This branch seems to consist, at the same time, in “the people-as-network,” hence giving life to a decentered and heterogeneous political “collectivity” (Vergara 2020, 3–5, chap. 9).

In addition, generally equating the “poor”—to which he gives pride of place—and the “plebs” (as well as the “multitude”), Kalyvas defends a democracy of the poor, radical in that the many would have preponderance. The division between the poor and the rich is, however, mostly instrumental, aiming to increase the power of the former, hence not consisting of an essentializing socioeconomic feature. This radical democracy of the poor is not attached to a “specific form,” with many different historical manifestations: Plebeian sovereignty is compatible with large direct assemblies, the council system, federated communes, and a network of voluntary primary associations; it may include the lottery, rotation, and recall; popular juries and courts; delegation and imperative mandates; and tyrannicide and insurrectional rights. Although less specific than what is proposed by McCormick and Vergara, his pallet is broader. Finally, Arlen (2019) takes a similar direction regarding diagnosis and the mobilization of Aristotle and the Greek tradition rather than Rome or the Italian republics, with a vindication of the poor too. He claims that the demos should be thought of with a “tripartite status as many, free, and poor.” It should be organized to counter “oligarchic harms,” with the many hence needing their own exclusive assemblies. Moreover, with reference to John Stuart Mill, Arlen (2023) has embraced the role of social movements and reforms against “plutocratic encroachment” within the framework of “liberal plebeianism.”

Although Kalyvas has thus far refused the wholesale elimination of the wealth differentials in the democracy of the poor, McCormick and Vergara, as well as Arlen, offer political solutions only, without really molesting the rich, the upper classes, including eventually stripping them of their wealth and property (Green was slightly bolder in this regard, though those other authors may have in mind, not really spelled out, legislative measures that imply a more radical redistribution of wealth). Moreover, they do not show us how to get to these plebeian institutions. Vergara tries to sketch a path but falls short of a plausible answer: Such institutions would be revolutionary but not in need of “an outright revolution” to be implemented. A combination of existing mechanisms and a “New Prince”—which, strangely, is not defined, either as an individual, social movements, or a political party—would be capable of pushing this through. She does not really consider the resistance such a move by the many would raise from the few. Luxemburg, for one, and in contrast, was acutely aware of such problems. Besides, such assemblies might as well be vulnerable to manipulation by the rich and powerful. Nor can one understand why solutions would be merely political insofar as socioeconomic inequality is absolutely crucial in Vergara's diagnosis of the contemporary political decay. After pointing out these shortcomings, Bagg (2022, 405–06, 409) suggests that plebeians’ collective power demands the traditional mass party. He does not elaborate on the issue, though, moreover a very contentious one in a society that has consistently rejected large hierarchical organizations.

Curiously, apart from Vergara's work, in her dialogue with Luxemburg and Arendt, the older socialist/communist/anarchist tradition of revolutionary councils—above all the Paris Commune and the Russian 1905 and 1917 Soviets—is barely brought up in these analyses of plebeianism (with Breaugh tackling the former through the lens of largely fleeting “experience”). These were, of course, attempts at direct democracy. The plebeians who organized them—factory and service workers, peasants and artisans, seconded by middle-class people and revolutionary intellectuals—strove to overcome representative democracy. These experiments failed, for different reasons, and the ones that survived were taken over by party “cadre” oligarchies. Today this looks like a blocked path, which has left us with liberal representative democracy as our ultimate horizon, despite time and again local experiences of direct democracy having ephemerally surfaced. We should not, however, take this as a foreclosed conclusion, even though these experiences should not be reified either.

Can we thus not reinvent democracy, controlling the power of political professionals, of whatever type, or even replacing them someday, altogether or by more contingent political incumbents, hence blocking the development of political oligarchies, which the moreover unlikely and at this stage probably ineffective nationalization of the “means of production” will never self-correct? Cannot anti-oligarchic plebeian democracy underpin the collective appropriation of the whole of social life, to start with the modern political dimension and its eventual dissolution, perhaps through something that is today often characterized as the “commons?” Can the political mass party, with its hierarchical and oligarchic historical tradition and perhaps inevitable largely vertical structuration, ever be resurrected as an instrument of the many? We cannot give these questions a clear answer, hopefully as yet. And yes, we need to be political realists, as Green and Vergara state, in that this is a very hard change to make. But these are issues worth pondering and a path we need to tread. It goes without saying that the socioeconomic issues related to wealth and property that the socialist–communist tradition raised and tried to solve are as important as the political ones, although I have stressed the differentiation of the political dimension. Concrete political systems and regimes are structured by their entanglement and how they mutually influence each other, a process in which capitalism enjoys enormous weight. Nor should they be overlooked in any sort of transformed, really fair social form we can project into the future. After all, if liberal plebeianism is a legitimate position, so is a socialist strand of plebeianism, which in a sense aims at its own abolition, even if this may work more as an immanently regulatory democratic perspective, nevertheless possibly to be achieved in the long-run future, along with a deep transformation in the overall structure of social life.

Theoretically, it remains to stress that criticizing oligarchy does not mean jettisoning the whole idea of representation and “representative democracy” from either a plebiscitary authoritarian or an “extra-parliamentary” position. In the first case, we know what has happened. The direct personification of the people in the most extreme-right “leader” the world has ever seen led to a wholesale catastrophe. This has, of course, nothing to do with democracy. In the second case, there was indeed something naïve, not in the deserved criticism of liberal democratic systems, but because simply getting rid of representation cannot be even envisaged today as a solution. The eternal return of representation is what councils in all revolutionary processes have produced, under the disguise of “delegation” sometimes, with, in contrast, individual revolutionaries and parties becoming new oligarchic elements of political power in the process of system change and the build-up of authoritarian collectivism. Moreover, the complexity of contemporary societies is an inescapable reality. That said, let me now resume some key issues of this article and derive some further conclusions from them.

I have tried to argue here that the imaginary, institutions, practices, and dynamics of political modernity, hence of politics as such, must be seen mainly as autonomous from society at large, particularly from economic interests. These have been at the core of liberalism (once it accepted its abstract rationalist universalism was insufficient to grasp and, in particular, tackle political processes) and Marxism (regardless of whether the economy only in the “last instance” influenced politics, what has been actually weakened in favor of more economist views lately). Many of the political crises of recent years are at heart political crises as such, not a consequence of class projects, though these have hurt and contributed to citizen cum plebeian dissatisfaction. The increasingly oligarchic character of contemporary political systems in much of the world—and the problems that may emerge in party-state regimes may eventually express this too—is responsible for these upheavals. It has been confronted by a plebeian mobilization that shows people's disaffection vis-à-vis politicians—power holders or ruling collectivities, in fact, since they have no special qualities such as the term “elite” was intended to convey.

When we examine concrete situations, we must take the entwinement among economic, political, and social power into account, without collapsing and conflating different dimensions, especially the political dimension. However, to fully understand a political regime, the diverse possibilities (this is never univocal) of connection between power holders, that is, ruling collectivities on the one hand, and (dominant or subaltern) classes and other societal and state collectivities on the other, must be contemplated and investigated. In the case of advanced political oligarchy, a looming political regime, finance capital, and global corporations (now probably including big tech) have stood out, but this must not be seen as exclusive or inevitable. What is more, the specific connections between them must be identified, demonstrated, and conceptualized rather than taken for granted (mere elective affinity of views and indirect inferences of influence will not do).

Besides, the discussion of oligarchy may allow us to recover some older themes of political thought. If Vergara is correct and insightful when she brings up the more general idea of corruption as decay, a characteristic that increasingly seems to mark the role of political agents is ordinary corruption, defined according to liberal thought and modern state institutions (the illegal appropriation of public resources by state and societal individuals and collectivities, that is, neopatrimonialism). In addition, the visibility of corruption has produced and evinced the malaise that affects plebeians and has led to recent political mobilizations. Yet, if we take the republican tradition more broadly, oligarchy may be linked today to a much more encompassing definition of corruption: the decadence of political institutions and values, in republican terms, which is also a far-reaching phenomenon of our time and includes, of course, that liberal, more limited definition of corruption (Araújo 2013). This has to do with the restriction of democracy and the unaccountability of so-called political “elites”—which are not “elites” in any sense, though personal demonization is not the case either, as it is first of all the actual structure of political systems that matters. To be sure, all regimes can be corrupted in both senses. Nevertheless, beyond the role of the judiciary, particularly in modern liberal republics, it is within the affirmation of democracy that both sorts of corruption may be counterposed against the consolidation of advanced liberal oligarchy (as as wel as of advanced autocracy and their mixed forms).

Beyond such particularly awkward moments, in order also that radical democracy as a regime—which, based on immanent critique, may become a regulatory ideal against which to measure actual democratic regimes—does not remain oblivious to the oligarchic dynamic of power and is projected as a way to contain it, we must, first of all, recognize the issue of political power in its specificity. Only then can we properly think of emancipation, exercising a permanent critique, practical as well, of actual democracies, implying true democratization and control of those on top political positions. Leninist and social democratic politicians may not like the idea that they respond, when in office and when not, largely, albeit often not exclusively or overwhelmingly, when “sinister interests” prevail, to their desires and projects, including acquiring and keeping political power, with its attendant benefits in other spheres. Nevertheless, for most people, this should be—and increasingly tends to be—seen as a crucial factor in the distribution of power in the modern and perhaps a postmodern civilization. Those who engage in politics, especially when occupying official elective positions, should be aware of these problems, with the aim to fight against them. Urbinati's (2014) dialogic model of representation—which does not correspond at all to contemporary practices—would be a step in this direction. The proposals thrown up in recent discussions of oligarchy and plebeianism—councils, assemblies, and tribunates, among others—may also contribute to democratic advancements, with the proviso that they may be implemented only as a result of probably fierce and nasty clashes. Our political imagination can in any case further develop, giving more power to plebeians, workers, the poor, and the multitude—in other words, the subaltern many who have always been the bedrock of democratic demands and advancements.

We may never approach absolute isonomy or democracy. In this regard, plebeianism may never disappear since rulers and the ruled imply a division difficult to utterly overcome. However, the horizon, the goal, and the movement toward them are exceedingly important and must be borne, in mind. This should be a core element of a critical theory of political modernity and its immanent critique, also beyond modern civilization, both at present and in whatever power arrangements the future may bring into being.

寡头政治、民主与平民主义:一个政治概念
寡头政治又回来了。也就是说,它最近试图在概念上卷土重来,因为它从未从社会的统治方式中消失,尤其是在现代政治生活中。那是什么呢?大多数情况下,它在现代性中仍未被理论化或理论化,尽管一些批评方法将其与自由主义联系起来,如Castoriadis (1999, 153ff),而其他人,在民主自由主义内部,指出它是自由主义发展的一个阶段,可能已经被取代,如Santos(2013)。本文的目的正是在现代性中与它接触,并批判性地评估它与民主的关系,包括它与平民主义的关系。显然,从波斯人开始,但更一致的是希腊人,尤其是亚里士多德,寡头政治进入了权力和统治(或“政府”)的词汇,在中世纪有一段半衰期,当时君主制和教皇权是关于权力的讨论的中心舞台。寡头政治在文艺复兴时期重新出现,例如,在马基雅维利和包括孟德斯鸠在内的早期现代思想中,但最终被一种不同的词汇所边缘化,在这种词汇中,古代传统的“统治形式”(或“政府”)没有发挥任何作用。然而,“精英”理论,尤其是莫斯卡和帕雷托,以及自由主义方法,为这一古老的现象提供了新的名称,这一现象不能完全被忽视,实际上将其作为一种普遍和不可阻挡的现象(Urbinati 2010)。只有在某些地方,这些思想才被现代思想家重新采用,其影响有限。国家、代表制和其他概念在一个关于权力的话语和现代性中一个特定维度——政治维度——的出现的新停顿中取代了统治形式。尽管将政党内部生活的寡头化作为一种独特的现象进行了分析,特别是米歇尔斯(1911/2009)关于德国社会民主党的经典著作(该书避免将寡头政治作为一种政府或统治形式进行讨论),也就是说,作为严格的政治,寡头政治主要是根据亚里士多德(1996)的定义来理解的,即少数人的自我导向统治。事实上,这些人同时也是富人——因此形成了一种“财阀统治”。这也是麦考密克(2011)和温特斯(2011)的观点,当代讨论的主要参考,以及其他最近的作者,如阿伦(2019年,2023年),维加拉(2020年)和巴格(2022年),以及卡利瓦斯(2019年),寡头和“穷人”之间的对立。温特斯强调,寡头们关心并致力于“保护财产”,这与罗马不同,是基于“强有力的财产权”。另一方面,寡头通常不会掌权(当他们掌权时,“虚荣心”往往是原因)。无论如何,他们已经发展了一种“收入防御工业”,隐藏财富,逃税,使用“复杂的避税手段”。温特斯(2011,xi-xvi, 7-8)认为,寡头应该被视为个人(而不是,例如,公司)。在阐述他的论点时,温特斯指出——与亚里士多德不同,他认为,尽管他在另一段话中也强调,后者将权力和财富联系在一起——他并不认为寡头政治只是少数人的统治:他热衷于强调其“物质基础”,即财富不平等会产生极端的政治不平等(温特斯2011,3,27)。温特斯确实认识到,除了物质权力之外,还有其他权力来源,包括政治权利、官方职位、强制性和动员性权力。在现代国家中,官职是分开的;他指出,这也就是说,它们并不直接来自财富。另一方面,寡头能够对这些官员施加巨大的影响。尽管他主要感兴趣的是他所谓的“公民寡头政治”(这取决于一个法律体系),温特斯(2011年,34页,209页)。2-5)提出了一种寡头政治的类型学(交战型、统治型、苏丹型、驯服型和野性型,以及“文明型”变体,这是非常现代的一种)。最后,温特斯强调了寡头政治和“精英”概念之间的区别,在莫斯卡和帕累托的例子中,这两个概念模糊了财富的作用,因为财富的作用太大了。当米歇尔斯将德国社会民主党定义为寡头政治时,他也会误解这个问题。相比之下,从苏联到古巴,我们实际上发现了精英统治,但这些社会不应该被定性为寡头统治,因为财富在其中没有发挥任何作用(Winters 2011, 8,275 - 77)。反过来,麦考密克对寡头政治的描述更加模糊。 他声称,民众应该被认为具有“多、自由和贫穷的三方地位”。它应该被组织起来对抗“寡头的危害”,因此许多人需要他们自己的排他性集会。此外,参考约翰·斯图尔特·密尔,阿伦(2023)在“自由平民主义”的框架内接受了社会运动和反对“财阀侵占”的改革的作用。尽管卡利瓦斯迄今为止拒绝在穷人的民主制度中全面消除贫富差距,麦考密克和维加拉以及艾伦只提供了政治解决方案,没有真正骚扰富人和上层阶级,包括最终剥夺他们的财富和财产(格林在这方面稍微大胆一些,尽管其他作者可能会想到,而不是真正详细说明,立法措施意味着更激进的财富再分配)。此外,它们也没有告诉我们如何进入这些平民机构。维加拉试图勾勒出一条道路,但没有给出一个合理的答案:这样的机构将是革命性的,但不需要“彻底的革命”来实施。现有机制和“新君主”的结合——奇怪的是,“新君主”既没有被定义为个人,也没有被定义为社会运动,也没有被定义为政党——将有能力推动这一进程。她并没有真正考虑到这样的举动会引起多数人对少数人的抵制。卢森堡则相反,她敏锐地意识到了这些问题。此外,这样的议会也可能容易受到富人和有权有势者的操纵。人们也无法理解,既然社会经济不平等在维加拉对当代政治衰败的诊断中绝对至关重要,为什么解决方案仅仅是政治上的。在指出这些缺点之后,Bagg(2022, 405 - 06,409)提出,平民的集体力量需要传统的群众性政党。不过,他没有详细说明这个问题,而且在一个一直拒绝大型等级组织的社会中,这是一个非常有争议的问题。奇怪的是,除了维加拉的作品之外,在她与卢森堡和阿伦特的对话中,革命委员会中更古老的社会主义/共产主义/无政府主义传统——尤其是巴黎公社和俄国1905年和1917年的苏维埃——几乎没有在这些对平民主义的分析中被提及(Breaugh通过大部分短暂的“经验”镜头来处理前者)。当然,这些都是直接民主的尝试。组织他们的平民——工厂和服务业工人、农民和工匠,在中产阶级和革命知识分子的支持下——努力克服代议制民主。由于不同的原因,这些实验都失败了,而那些幸存下来的实验则被党内的“干部”寡头所接管。今天,这条道路似乎被堵住了,尽管直接民主的地方经验一次又一次地短暂出现,但我们最终还是把自由代议制民主作为我们的终极视野。然而,我们不应该把这作为一个止赎的结论,即使这些经验也不应该具体化。因此,我们能不能重新发明民主,控制任何类型的政治专业人士的权力,甚至有一天取代他们,全部或更偶然的政治现任者,从而阻止政治寡头的发展,更不可能的是,在这个阶段,“生产资料”的国有化可能是无效的,永远不会自我纠正?难道反寡头的平民民主不能支撑整个社会生活的集体占有,从现代政治维度开始,并最终通过今天通常被描述为“公地”的东西解散吗?这个具有等级制度和寡头政治历史传统、或许不可避免的主要垂直结构的政党,能否作为多数人的工具而复活?我们目前还不能给这些问题一个明确的答案。是的,正如格林和维加拉所说,我们需要成为政治上的现实主义者,因为这是一个很难做出的改变。但这些都是值得深思的问题,也是我们需要走的道路。不用说,社会主义-共产主义传统提出并试图解决的与财富和财产有关的社会经济问题与政治问题同样重要,尽管我已经强调了政治维度的区分。具体的政治制度和政权是由它们之间的纠缠以及它们如何相互影响而构成的,在这个过程中,资本主义享有巨大的影响力。我们也不应该忽视任何一种转型的、真正公平的社会形式,我们可以将其投射到未来。 毕竟,如果自由平民主义是一种合法的立场,那么平民主义的社会主义分支也是一种合法的立场,它在某种意义上旨在废除自己,即使这可能更多地作为一种内在的监管民主观点,然而,在长期的未来,随着社会生活整体结构的深刻变革,可能会实现。从理论上讲,仍然需要强调的是,批评寡头政治并不意味着从公民投票的专制主义或“议会外”的立场上抛弃代议制和“代议制民主”的整个理念。在第一种情况下,我们知道发生了什么。世界上最极右的“领导人”将人民直接人格化,导致了一场大规模的灾难。当然,这与民主毫无关系。在第二种情况下,确实有一些东西naïve,不是在自由民主制度应得的批评中,而是因为简单地摆脱代议制在今天甚至不能被设想为一种解决方案。代表的永恒回归是委员会在所有革命过程中所产生的东西,有时在“委托”的伪装下,与之相反,个人革命者和政党在制度变革和专制集体主义的建立过程中成为政治权力的新寡头因素。此外,当代社会的复杂性是一个不可避免的现实。话虽如此,现在让我继续本文的一些关键问题,并从中得出一些进一步的结论。我在这里试图论证,政治现代性的想象、制度、实践和动态,因此政治本身,必须主要被视为独立于整个社会,特别是经济利益的。这些都是自由主义的核心(一旦它接受了抽象的理性主义普遍主义不足以掌握,特别是解决政治过程)和马克思主义(不管经济是否只在“最后一刻”影响政治,这实际上已经被削弱了,最近更倾向于经济学家的观点)。近年来的许多政治危机本质上都是政治危机本身,而不是阶级计划的结果,尽管这些计划伤害并助长了公民和平民的不满。当今世界许多国家政治体系的日益寡头化特征,以及党国政权中可能出现的问题,最终也可能表现出这一点,这是造成这些动荡的原因。它面临的是一场平民动员,显示了人们对-à-vis政客的不满——事实上,他们是权力持有者或统治集体,因为他们没有“精英”一词所要传达的特殊品质。当我们审视具体情况时,我们必须考虑到经济、政治和社会权力之间的纠缠,而不是瓦解和混淆不同的维度,特别是政治维度。然而,为了充分理解一个政治制度,必须考虑和调查权力持有者之间的各种可能性(这从来都不是明确的)联系,即,一方面是统治集体,另一方面是(统治或次等)阶级和其他社会和国家集体。在发达的政治寡头政治中,一个迫在眉睫的政治政权、金融资本和全球公司(现在可能包括大型科技公司)已经脱颖而出,但这不应被视为排他性或不可避免的。更重要的是,它们之间的具体联系必须被识别、证明和概念化,而不是想当然地认为(仅仅是观点的选择性亲和力和间接的影响推断是不行的)。此外,对寡头政治的讨论可以让我们恢复一些古老的政治思想主题。如果Vergara在提出腐败是腐朽的更普遍的观点时是正确的和有洞察力的,那么根据自由主义思想和现代国家制度(国家和社会个人和集体非法占用公共资源,即新权贵主义),一个似乎越来越多地标志着政治代理人角色的特征是普通腐败。此外,腐败的可见性产生并证明了影响到平民的不安,并导致了最近的政治动员。然而,如果我们更广泛地接受共和传统,寡头政治今天可能与一个更广泛的腐败定义联系在一起:用共和的术语来说,政治制度和价值观的衰落,这也是我们这个时代的一个深远现象,当然也包括自由主义的、更有限的腐败定义(Araújo 2013)。 这与民主的限制和所谓的政治“精英”的不负责任有关——他们在任何意义上都不是“精英”,尽管个人的妖魔化也不是这种情况,因为首先重要的是政治制度的实际结构。可以肯定的是,所有的政权都可能在两方面都腐败。然而,除了司法的作用之外,特别是在现代自由主义共和国中,在民主的肯定中,这两种腐败都可以与先进的自由寡头政治(以及先进的专制政体及其混合形式)的巩固相抗衡。除了这些特别尴尬的时刻之外,为了让激进民主作为一种政体——基于内在批判,它可能成为衡量实际民主政体的监管理想——不会对权力的寡头动态视而不见,并被视为遏制权力的一种方式,我们必须首先认识到政治权力的特殊性。只有这样,我们才能正确地思考解放,对实际的民主进行持久的批判,这意味着真正的民主化和对高层政治职位的控制。列宁主义和社会民主主义的政治家可能不喜欢这样的想法:当“邪恶的利益”占上风时,他们在执政和下台时,大部分(尽管往往不是全部或压倒性的)对他们的欲望和计划做出反应,包括获取和保持政治权力,以及在其他领域附带的利益。然而,对于大多数人来说,这应该——而且越来越倾向于——被视为现代文明,也许是后现代文明中权力分配的一个关键因素。那些从政的人,特别是那些担任官方选举职位的人,应该意识到这些问题,并以反对这些问题为目标。乌尔比纳蒂(2014)的对话式再现模式——完全不符合当代实践——将是朝这个方向迈出的一步。最近关于寡头政治和平民主义的讨论中提出的建议——委员会、议会和保民法庭等等——也可能有助于民主的进步,但附带条件是,这些建议只有在可能激烈而肮脏的冲突中才能实施。我们的政治想象力在任何情况下都可以进一步发展,赋予平民、工人、穷人和大众更多的权力——换句话说,那些一直是民主要求和进步的基石的下层民众。我们可能永远不会接近绝对的独立或民主。在这方面,平民主义可能永远不会消失,因为统治者和被统治者意味着一种难以完全克服的分裂。然而,视野、目标和朝着它们前进的过程是极其重要的,必须牢记在心。这应该是政治现代性批判理论及其内在批判的核心要素,也应该超越现代文明,无论是在当前还是在未来可能形成的任何权力安排中。 他毫无顾虑地将寡头政治和精英(“社会经济和政治”)混合在一起(麦考密克2011,1,13-17,167),但并没有非常明确地定义它们中的每一个,尽管财富总是作为表征其权力的主要问题(有时,“阶级”和“阶级意识”在没有任何说明的情况下被提及)。事实上,在这本书的大部分时间里,麦考密克除了提到罗马和意大利文艺复兴时期的共和国外,几乎没有提到寡头政治,而且主要是在讨论马基雅维利的作品时。只有在“后选举民主”一章中,麦考密克才更系统地研究了寡头政治的概念,但主要是将其与改革后的民主共和国进行对比(麦考密克2011年,第6章)。6 - 7)。“精英”和“寡头”之间的混合也出现在维加拉的作品中。在过去的几十年里,我们经历了自由代议制政府的系统性衰败——“系统性腐败”。它表现为社会权力的“寡头化”(形成一种“趋势”)。少数人积累并垄断了财富,带来了可怕的政治后果。少数人的权力变得越来越排外;他们已经成为了唯一的统治者,违背了大多数人的利益,精英们只能舒舒服服地“自我管理”。她强烈地断言,自由的代议制民主并不是混合政体——它们更像是“单一政体”,只是“职能分离”。虽然她之前提到了社会权力的寡头化,但她最终表达了她的主要担忧:“今天的政治权力实际上是寡头的”(Vergara 2020, 1-4)。虽然后一种说法在很大程度上是正确的,但我认为前者是错误的。本文稍后将给出这种不同评估的原因。麦考密克和维加拉首先都致力于捍卫平民的观点。因此,他们对寡头政治的描述不如温特的系统。我将在文章的最后回到平民主义。现在,让我们批判性地讨论这些作者对寡头政治和精英的看法。我并不想完全否定它们的描述和概念化,但我认为它们常常是简化的或令人困惑的。忽视财富如何影响政治生活,以及富人如何通过众多渠道接触政治家,影响甚至根据自己的目标操纵他们的行动,将是荒谬的。他们当然关心保护自己的财产、财富和收入(顺便说一句,这是不同的现象)。然而,我们需要对现代性中的寡头政治发展出一种更精确的观点,以及它的特殊性,从而也超越了“精英”这个松散的概念(此外,这个概念不能不被注入潜在的积极共鸣,让人想起贵族)。尽管集中的经济权力很突出,我想说的是我们必须从政治权力的角度来看待寡头政治。在亚里士多德的时代,物质权力、军事权力,以及(因为找不到更好的词)“政府”权力之间有着紧密的联系。规则将所有这些因素紧密地交织在一起。在现代性中,政治维度与其他社会维度出现了分化,而社会经济阶层现在在物质社会经济维度中更为重要。政治层面——同样是经济层面——已经获得了自己的逻辑和权力来源。正如我们在上面看到的那样,温特斯认识到了这一点,尽管我们需要引入进一步的区分来正确地理解这个维度。特别是,我们需要从这种差异中得出适当的结论,而温特斯只是部分地做到了这一点。最后,麦考密克对社会阶级的提及必须得到恰当的阐述,尤其是在现代性方面。因此,当我在本文中谈到寡头政治时,我指的基本上是政治寡头政治。我们可以说经济寡头是为了挑出一个国家最富有的人,在这个阶段,甚至是在整个世界,尽管占主导地位的经济阶层比这群超级富豪要大。更近似地说,我们或许可以指出,从艺术到体育等人类活动的其他领域也存在寡头统治。但是,对政治动力学最为重要的是,我想具体讨论政治权力——以国家为基础,但与整个社会的政治进程有联系——是如何在现代性中形成的,以及这是如何通过政治少数人的统治建立起来的。虽然政治权力的特点也是财富的重要性日益增加,但我们不能直接从财富的影响中推导出维加拉正确指出的这种趋势,尽管这也是政治寡头化的因果关系。 麦考密克经常把社会经济和政治上的强大力量联系在一起,需要加以区分——不是要贬低财产和财富的作用,它们不仅仅是基于资本主义的现代社会中阶级关系的一个重要方面,而是要支持对它们与政治权力的具体关系的正确理解。这种观点将使我们看到政治权力是如何在这个特定的维度中组织起来的,是如何由政治集体来行使的。也就是说,我们将观察它如何在现代性中呈现出一种特殊的形式,以及在超越它的尝试中,我们可以称之为威权集体主义,其中少数人也统治(在更完整的替代社会形态中)和统治(在经济向资本主义过渡之后)。因此,我们将能够讨论亲资本主义、亲商业的政治集体是如何运作的,以及左翼力量通常是如何被寡头倾向所穿越的,也构成了寡头结构,寡头结构已经从政党转移到国家结构,反之亦然。如何将其与一个人的专制统治和许多人的民主统治结合起来,然后可以讨论。此外,我们将看到那些不参与权力行使的人应该如何被定义为“平民”——政治上,这是——以及当代政治动态,在这种动态中,(寡头)政治权力的垂直行使一次又一次被拒绝(Breaugh 2007;麦考密克2011;绿色2016;范盖拉2020;Ramírez 2022),其他人更喜欢通过“穷人”的类别来对待他们(Kalyvas 2019;阿伦2019)。在接下来的章节中,(1)我将进一步阐述政治维度的分化,并讨论寡头、精英和社会阶层之间的关系;(2)系统地界定了政治制度和政体的概念,并讨论了现代性(主要是自由主义)和后现代(威权集体主义)的统治形式,其中包含了动态因素;(3)最后,我讨论了政治平民主义问题,以及“穷人”和相关概念,这使我讨论了最近提出的解决这些问题的补救措施;(4)得出结论。在进一步讨论之前,我应该指出,尽管这本书与政治理论密切相关,但它是一本政治社会学的著作,我认为它实际上与推动当代关于寡头政治和平民主义的辩论非常相关。在现代化之前,没有这样的政治。权力无疑是一个贯穿所有文明和特定社会形态(特定“社会”)的问题。社会生活和社会关系,无论是纵向的还是横向的,都离不开它。统治和统治,凭借其等级的垂直性,确实与国家联系在一起。然而,不同的权力“来源”如何结合在一起,与现代性所带来的那种安排有很大不同。我们不需要接受这样一种观点,即进化导致了从简单的、没有差别的社会到复杂的社会,在复杂的社会中,差别占主导地位,并意味着新的协调机制。社会进化和发展的道路有很多,物质力量、统治力量和精神力量的不同组合,不允许一个单一的线性过程的平面图像。然而,在后来成为“西方”的地方,现代性慢慢出现,政治维度也分化出来它包含了一种组织权力的方式,这种方式最初应该是驯化的,也许是伪装的,任何新的政治特征无论如何都会消失。之所以如此,是因为政治代议制——无论是立法的还是行政的——被认为仅仅是为了维护所有决定建立这个基本基于抽象法律的新国家机器的公民的原始公民权利,而不是政治权利。为了遵守法律和保持这些原始的权利,与行政和司法部门联系在一起的法律和镇压力量(最终是区分开来的警察)发挥着至关重要的作用,这在某种意义上是被动的,旨在维持抽象公民之间的原始关系。随着它的展开,政治现代性变得越来越政治化,社会生活的具体问题侵入了公民和国家的抽象维度,与此同时,政治现代性的扩张和民主化。这形成了一种共和主义和自由主义相结合的扩张趋势,这种趋势在现代性中占主导地位(自20世纪70年代以来,在形式上保留民主制度的新寡头化方向上发生了逆转)。的确,我们在一定程度上使用与希腊人和罗马人相同的词汇,特别是“政治”、“公民身份”和“公众”,以及这些形式的统治。 然而,其中一些术语的意思有时完全不同。以“政治”为例,这是希腊和现代社会的一个核心概念。在亚里士多德(1996,特别是72页)中,在这样一个“政治”框架中,危险的不仅仅是,甚至可能不是主要是权力的行使。黑格尔(1820/1986)认为,他指的是一种“伦理总体”(Sittlichkeit)——首先包括家庭和家庭——以及价值观和对城市的归属——即政治——生活是有意义的、真正人性的唯一场所和环境。这些形式的统治或政府——君主政体和暴政,贵族政体和寡头政体,独立政体和民主政体——直接指向权力的行使,而不是“政治的”,这个词是为更广泛的现实(即一般的“城邦”)保留的。这对夫妇的第一个任期应该是积极的、有道德的,因为统治者会关心公共利益;相反,第二种则是消极的,因为他们会根据自己的利益来统治。亚里士多德比大多数作家都更清楚物质利益和权力在政府或统治形式中的作用,直到现代性开始,但城邦远不止于此。有了马基雅维利,我们开始谈论赤裸裸的权力、国家,以及前者行使的一个特定维度。这在霍布斯和后来的作者那里得到了巩固。还要注意的是,从亚里士多德到孟德斯鸠,再到美国宪法的“制定者”,这些形式的统治或政府经常被看作是复合的,即混合的形式,其中一人的统治,少数人的统治和多数人的统治可以以不同的方式结合在一起。事实上,许多作家——如亚里士多德、马基雅维利和那些美国“制宪者”——都喜欢这种混合形式,他们认为这种形式更稳定,体现了不同原则的优势。制宪者很高兴看到,在他们有限的民主之上,盘旋着一种精神上的“自然贵族”,正如他们所想象的那样(杰弗逊1813/1959;此外,在他之前并对他的观点有直接影响的,见Harrington 1656/1992, 23;参见麦考密克2011,意大利文艺复兴时期,特别是Guicciardini)。这一举措还需要反思权力——尤其是政治权力——如何组织,谁来统治,这些人将如何统治或治理。这个答案在理论和实践上都是零敲碎打的。北美独立战争(在大陆南部被复制,但对全球的影响要小得多)和法国大革命仍然在很大程度上使用了古老的经典教义。新的概念也被创造出来了,有些在某种程度上已经在中世纪的词汇中找到了,尽管是在其他领域,比如“代表”,以应对新文明的复杂性;或者,按照稍早一点的现代含义,“国家”指的是统治机器。然而,在现代性开始之前,处理统治或政府形式的标准词汇和类型——一个人的统治或政府,少数人的统治或政府——让位给了民主,“代议制”,但对某些潮流来说,作为一种要求,“直接”也是,“独裁”(意思与罗马人不同),最终更委婉,被认为是技术术语,如达尔(1960/1963)的“封闭霸权”,“竞争性寡头”,“包容性霸权”和“多元政治”——从今往后有了一大批直接基于经验的类型学。然而,在某些方法中,古典思想以某种方式零星地、不完整地延续了下来。例如,米歇尔斯前面提到的工作就是这种情况。他们出现在施密特(1928/1993,292-303)的分析中,特别是当他讨论选举如何体现贵族原则时,与希腊的命运和他为(据说)“民主”模式所设想的全民公决欢呼形成对比(参见1997)。“议会外”对政治制度及其与公民隔离的激烈批评也恢复了古典词汇(见Agnoli 1967/1990),奇怪的是,这些词汇一次又一次地被一些对“现实社会主义”的分析所应用(Tucker 1963;科恩1985;作者,2024)。但一个重大的观念转变实际上已经发生了。贵族和寡头政治的概念最终让位于“精英”的统治或政府(Mosca 1895/1923;帕累托(Pareto, 1916/1923),当时分析人士习惯于谈论权力差异,而自由派通常不愿意承认在他们的代议制民主中存在统治者和被统治者。与此同时,与政治现代性有关的自由主义理论越来越倾向于将政治视为社会利益的代表(如伯克所强调的那样,政治代表更“普遍”,或如马克思和后来的自由主义者如达尔所指出的那样,政治代表更具体)。 可以肯定的是,功利主义自由主义意识到边沁(1822/1988,115-122)所说的“邪恶利益”(律师、法官和政治家),一种以个人幸福(“效用”)为目标的利益。然而,它被视为与一人或少数人的统治有关。边沁认为,一旦多数人统治(尽管是通过少数人统治!),以普遍公共利益为主导的利益就会适当地协调一致,比如在美国。然而,他错了。更多的控制可能会实现,但就政治制度区分统治者和被统治者,统治者和被统治者而言,派系利益将继续存在于一种混合政府中,我将在下面进一步论证。罗伯斯庇尔虽然接受代议制原则,但他自己也是一名国会议员,一定程度上受到卢梭的影响,他意识到了这个问题,并谴责了它的隐晦相关性。例如,与伯克形成对比的是,罗伯斯庇尔提出,作为代表对-à-vis选举他们的公民的利益自治的解决方案,有一些措施:美德,更频繁的选举,至少可能频繁的议员更替,因此代表至少在一段时间内融入人民,以及公开的公众审议和禁止参与议会成员的行政活动(Mathiez 1920/2018, 33-38)。在他任职期间,这位“廉洁的人”是否遵循了他自己的建议,这是个问题。虽然简短,但进一步讨论马克思主义观点和韦伯观点是有秩序的,尤其是前者特别关注财富、财产和收入与政治权力之间的关系;当然,对于社会阶层来说,这个概念是不能被寡头政治所取代的(寡头政治最终只是超级富豪的同义词,也是一个模糊但敏感的描述性概念)。寡头政治的政治理论家,将政治和经济权力不可区分地混合在一起,往往完全忽视了这一重要文献。但他们这样做是在冒自己的风险,因为这些作者确实试图抓住财富和财产之间的联系,一方面,而不是经济寡头或精英的概念,另一方面,政治权力,在他们的理论中,主要是国家,这也是一个缺点。马克思和恩格斯(1848/1978)最初——在一份宣言中,提到了一个选举特权受到极端限制的时期——肯定了国家是“管理整个资产阶级共同事务的委员会”(尽管随着现代性的进步和他们思想的成熟,他们的概念变得越来越复杂和微妙)。近一个世纪后,尽管葛兰西(1929-35/2001)强调了(扩大的)国家和“霸权”的阶级特征,但另一方面,他确实认识到,统治阶级通常并不直接统治,与政治保持着更遥远的关系。在后来的马克思主义辩论中,米利班德(1969)认为,统治阶级确实直接统治,但受到普兰查斯(1978)的尖锐批评。普兰查斯发展了一种更为调解的理论,认为国家是阶级之间的“斗争场”,抛弃了更简单的观点,即国家是资产阶级的执行“委员会”,因为它的复杂性。Offe(1972/1973, 1986)的观点更为中立:国家和政治家的主要关注点是他们自己权力的再生产,为此,资本的顺利积累是必要的,因此,这意味着不可避免地要对资本家的利益和要求进行调整,而不是直接代表资本家。Jessop(2008)恢复了Poulantzas的观点,几乎将国家与资产阶级或阶级分离开来,尽管没有否认它们之间具体的纠缠。这是布洛克(1977)在几年前采取的更为激进的一步,根据他的观点(与阶级工具主义的观点不同,超越了Offe的旧作品),“国家管理者”对分散的资本家利益的反应取决于他们自己保持权力的渴望。因此,我们看到,马克思主义内部的趋势是将政治和国家视为受社会阶级和(“最后”)经济的制约,但也最终阐明了一个相当微妙的立场(尽管这些作者几乎没有充分区分国家和政治制度,这是非常重要的,我将在下面详细说明)。所谓的工具主义观点被抛弃了。我认为这是一个非常积极的发展。 这就是说,马克思主义远远超出了马克思和恩格斯原来的观点,只是部分地在历史上得到了证明,而在历史上这是错误的。这并不是否认富人——或者资产阶级,不管我们在公司资本主义时代如何定义它——对政治有着巨大的影响,尤其是在美国;但这种影响是间接的,而资本家——或者更普遍的商人——必须与职业政治家和官僚(例如欧盟在这方面表现突出)的利益作斗争。韦伯传统,尤其是曼恩(1993),也开始认识到社会阶级和国家之间的联系,因此也认识到财富和政治之间的联系,但也没有将后者从属于前者,尽管它们的解决方案(参见曼恩在国家内部的社会“结晶”)是难以捉摸的。在本文的进一步发展中应该牢记这一点。这样的社会学理解并不反对财富是政治的决定因素,以及非常富有的人意图保护他们的财产和资产,他们确实如此。然而,它指出了一种考虑到现代特别是当代社会复杂性的观点。另一方面,这与精英主义理论所暗示的非常不同,精英主义理论认为,权力产生和再生产的具体机制往往趋于消失,并且积极地设想了权力差异的必然性,并加以解释。此外,可以肯定的是,富人(资产阶级或经济寡头)对政治制度的直接影响在时空上是不同的——从一个国家到另一个国家,在不同的时期——当进行更以经验为导向的分析时,这一点不会从我们的视线中消失,但这里的情况并非如此。最近,政治和政治制度的职业化受到了审查。它允许了那种政治家的转变,用韦伯(1919/1988)的经典术语来说,“为政治而活”到那些“依靠政治而活”的人。因此,传统的寡头政治也被克服了,但是,这并没有改变政治制度的寡头特征,政治家们非常清楚他们的特殊性和自己的利益,包括充实自己,因为他们中的许多人甚至大多数人在进入政界之前并不真正富有(Borchert和Zeiss 2003)。这种过渡是随着通过群众政党实现政治制度民主化而发展起来的,但它绝不与需要去民主化的进程不相容。在这个阶段,这个问题应该明确地说明:政治寡头的危险在于以相当自主的方式行使权力,以及习惯性地捍卫政治权力特权,尽管他们经常与统治阶级(概念上定义的)、富人(现象学上的感知和描述)等紧密联系在一起,或者实际上是他们的一部分。如果统治阶级和富人关心的是财产、收入和财富,而专制的集体主义寡头关心的是维持他们的权力,他们对公司财产的控制由此而来,那么在自由主义的统治体系中,对政治权力的控制也有一个独立的逻辑,与经济维度分离,即财富和财产(国家资本主义结合了这两种逻辑)。这种安排与现代政治维度的分化直接相关,而不直接取决于政治官员——职业政治家——的意愿,他们甚至可能对此感到不舒服。它还暗示了一种与获取和维持权力有关的内在逻辑,关于自身利益,以及对自由民主或寡头政治的有限想象的信仰。这依赖于很多意识形态——这个概念被理解为一个意义宇宙的结构,通常包括一些不同程度的合理性或真理,隐藏了部分现实,并为其有问题或特别丑陋的方面提供似是而非的理由。今天党国统治与资本主义的结合更是如此。米歇尔斯特别关注寡头化如何在组织内部发展,即群众组织,被设想为实现相反目标的一种手段,即民主化。如果自由主义者一直(至少直到最近)对自由民主中的寡头因素视而不见,那么权力的关闭就是工人政党和工人委员会传统试图解决的问题和僵局之一。寡头组织推动了全面的民主化——并且在很大程度上取得了成功——以及有组织的民众参与,这一事实并没有使它们成为非寡头组织。 更重要的是,这种寡头政治的特征隐藏着无数的问题,这些问题要么在后革命时期以复仇的方式浮出水面,要么最终破坏了进一步民主化和真正的改革主义的可能性。这是一个至关重要的悖论——我们可以称之为米歇尔悖论——它伴随着19世纪末和20世纪的政治现代性。至少以这种形式,它已不再存在于我们之中,尽管各组织,特别是大型的国家政党,更不用说国际领域,暗示着这种反复的复杂性,同时要求民主化和少数人统治,这在今天已成为最重要的今天我们可以清楚地看到,尽管许多人拒绝面对这一点,但对马克思主义有一种相当天真的信仰,根据这种信仰,一旦国家和政治权力消失,作为私有财产终结的结果,这个问题也会消失。此外,工人阶级将控制这一过程,防止其发展的扭曲(这一问题使布尔什维克感到紧张,尽管过度的自信使他们希望问题消失——例如,布哈林在1925年明确指出)。他们都选择忽视巴枯宁(1873/1990)早就指出的一个问题,并直接提到了马克思。寡头统治可能不是普遍的和不可避免的。然而,在任何一种全面的社会安排中,这是很难克服的。为了进一步阐述现代性中政治维度的分化,并进一步掌握寡头统治的某些方面,我现在必须系统地处理政治制度的概念,以及政治制度的概念,我迄今为止没有适当地定义它在太多的方法和分析中,国家被视为行使政治权力的场所。但这是有问题的。涉及不同问题的国家和政治制度这两个概念必须保留。虽然国家的任何部分都可能在任何时候被政治化,但政治的核心实际上是政治制度,基本上是立法权和行政权,法律是在这里产生的,决策是在这里做出的。如今,政治家大多是通过选举产生的,但并不总是如此,他们在政治体系中运作,而官僚则占据着非选举产生的职位。可以肯定的是,这种区别是相对的,但大多数时候,国家在政治上是相当中立的,比如法院和目前极度分化的行政机构,包括军队,尽管它渗透着意识形态和政治偏好,在危机时刻或由于政治家的决定,其形式上的中立可能会迅速改变。寡头政治的权力从根本上是通过政治体系的这两个特定要素来行使的。在自由代议制民主制度下,选举产生的官员控制着这些空间,而在党国制度下,这种安排更为垂直。如果这是政治体系的国家层面,那么我们也必须指出社会政治体系,它组织利益、价值观和社会议程,在任何情况下都经常与国家政治体系直接接触,尽管有时它受到强烈压制。工会、协会、非营利组织和非政府组织是其支柱。政治制度及其两面性,在这里是以分析而非描述的视角来描述的。此外,政治制度是通过不同类型的政治制度具体组织起来的。政治制度意味着国家和社会政治制度之间的不同关系,行政和立法之间的不同程度的联系,两者的轮廓,监视和镇压的强度,以及是一个人,少数人还是许多人是统治者(或者是否获得混合安排)。我们可以说,从20世纪下半叶开始,自由代议制民主盛行,但也可以说,自20世纪70年代以来,一个重新寡头化的过程,导致了我们所谓的先进的自由寡头政治,获得了动力(先进的专制也在发展——例如,在俄罗斯,尽管它的民主外衣更薄,在许多地方,例如在美国,出现了官僚元素)。 自由代议制民主一直以来都是一种混合政体,结合了多寡头的因素(言论、表现和组织自由、公开辩论和多数人的自由参与)和寡头的因素(控制国家政治体系,并由此控制大部分国家机器和媒体,甚至控制社会政治体系的其他部分,如非营利组织和非政府组织)。寡头政治核心的发展损害了民主因素——包括国家政治体系的加强和关闭损害了社会政治体系——这在很大程度上解释了过去几十年回归寡头政治研究的作者们的担忧。相比之下,虽然党国制度在许多国家仍然存在,但研究这些制度的作者们的教诲似乎已经被遗忘了。虽然以前有民主化的扩张,但今天我们面临着强烈的去民主化趋势。财富在这种发展形势中扮演着重要角色,政治家和统治阶级在这些新的发展中交织在一起,而且,这降低了社会政治制度的相关性,政治寡头们对其意见和要求不感兴趣,甚至可能试图压制。随着去民主化,新自由主义政策,或者充其量可以被定义为社会自由主义政策,一直反对社会政策的普遍化,充其量是迎合穷人。如果自由代议制民主确实是一种混合政体——与维加拉对它的“单一政体”的理解相反——我们就不应该轻视它的民主方面——她显然是这么做的。我们应该坚持这一评价,尽管寡头代理人和机构以及富人的影响——确切地说,是资产阶级,今天往往与金融资本,以及最近的大型科技公司联系在一起,正如马克思主义作家以不同的方式强调的那样。这些民主方面是现代性的重要收获,与社会权利等的发展相结合,通过多数人和少数人之间激烈的政治斗争。它们必须恢复,这些政治和社会方面必须进一步加强,包括把私有财产纳入广大公民的利益和需要。一些政治代理人,包括职业政治家,确实想要克服这种寡头特征,这是很难发生的,因为这种安排是顽固的,很难改变,特别是在这个时间点上,当没有稳定的公民动员。此外,如果要采用新的权力行使形式,就需要有适当的替代办法来取代它。迄今为止,唯一真正的替代方案——革命委员会的权力——已经失败了。此外,党国统治的民主空间更小,如果有的话:它纯粹是寡头统治,甚至是专制统治。这不是一个混合政权。尽管寡头统治得到了加强,但社会政治动态也包含了另一种趋势。近几十年来,个人的个人和集体自治与对其国家政治制度,包括以前的群众性政党的不满齐头并进。虽然有强大的潜在社会进程在这个方向上作出贡献,特别是使个人从政治联系中“解放”出来并迫使他们自主作出决定的“脱离嵌入的进程”,但这种发展的核心是个人作为政治代理人的自决和一种深刻的政治不安。自2000年代以来,我们在全球范围内观察到这一趋势,不同的作者试图掌握这些代理人是谁,以及如何动员他们进行社会解放(Bringel和Domingues 2015;《多明格斯2024》第八章;Urbinati 2020)。这对政治理论和政治社会学产生了或多或少直接的影响。由此出现了一条与寡头政治讨论平行的线索,即使它更确切地说是对寡头统治的认同,这是其进一步发展的最初动机,由此两个问题似乎纠缠在一起。这条线以不同形式的平民主义主张为特色。一些人坚持更主观的观点,另一些人则坚持制度改革,以平民的方式纠正民主。在第一种情况下,我们找到了Breaugh和Green。Breaugh (2007, xv-xxiii)将“平民”的“经验”称为“……通过政治代理获得尊严”,并重建了源于“对自由的渴望”的集体动员的历史时刻。对他来说,平民主义不是一种身份,而是一个“政治主体”构成的“政治事件”。然而,它不可能持续任何时间。 反过来,格林谈到了“不公平的阴影”,它导致普通公民——实际上是二等公民——感到被“远离”了政治,因为与少数有权势的人相比,大多数人没有,也不可能期望真正的政治影响力。虽然代表权是“不透明的”,而且超出了责任范围,但对于大多数公民来说,与政治的距离是复杂的,以格林没有真正解释的方式,社会经济不平等的侵入-财阀统治-在公民空间。反对自由代议制民主的“阳光”观点,他强调其阴影(Green 2016, 3-7)。针对这种困境,格林建议,在“平民民主”中(他特别关注罗马的先例),二等公民应该学会参与各种形式的“有原则的粗俗”,并乐于接受某种程度的“合理嫉妒”、“专断”和“怨恨”。虽然他强调有必要对权贵进行“特殊监管待遇”,特别是对富人,以及对平民的再分配措施和“保护”策略,但格林并不认为这种情况真的可以进行深远的改变。这就是为什么他要求一种积极的政治现实主义。虽然他支持自由民主主义,一种被证明的政治制度,在这种制度中,“自由和平等的公民身份”有一个真实的(尽管是有限的)位置,我们可以在某种程度上进一步解放,但他声称政治不太可能是平民幸福的源泉。因此,他们需要“安慰”和他所谓的“外政治”;在这方面,享乐主义被认为是罗马许多人的典范(Green 2016, 7-16,第6章)。4 - 5)。麦考密克和维加拉采取了不同的方向,尽管他们的建议之间存在细微的差异,但他们都关注多数人反对少数人的权力的制度化。他们的灵感来自罗马和意大利共和国,以及汉娜·阿伦特和罗莎·卢森堡。麦考密克(2011),7,1-2,章。4-6)要求“精英问责和大众赋权的选举外模式”。这些措施包括:将富人排除在竞选资格之外的公职,在任命地方法官的过程中使用彩票和选举,以及让全体公民参与的“政治审判”。这就是他的马基雅维利式民主:允许公民对“政治和社会经济精英”有更多的控制权。请注意,与葛兰西的希望相反,他否认了精英统治可以被完全取代的可能性(McCormick 2011, 190,注释15)。反过来,维加拉试图详细阐述平民对系统性腐败和加剧的寡头统治的补救措施,尽管,像麦考密克一样,她确实认为克服少数人和多数人之间的分歧是不可能的,显然是永远不可能的。根据她的说法,这需要专门为平民设立的机构,能够对代表提出的措施行使“否决权”,并对其进行直接审查,但也可以发起立法,不时地从下面释放选民的权力,并通过代表对政治办公室进行监督,代表可以弹劾官员,同时迫使他们采纳议会的决定。扩展了地方议会(议会)和保民法庭,构成了自由民主的“平民分支”(在她看来,今天不是真正的民主,我们不得不得出结论,因为,如上所述,它的制度只属于精英)。这一分支似乎同时包含在“人即网络”中,因此赋予了一个分散和异质的政治“集体”生命(Vergara 2020, 3-5,第9章)。此外,他将“穷人”——他认为这是最重要的——和“平民”(以及“大众”)划等号,捍卫穷人的民主,激进地认为多数人将占主导地位。然而,穷人和富人之间的划分主要是工具性的,旨在增加前者的权力,因此不包含本质上的社会经济特征。这种穷人的激进民主并不依附于一种“特定形式”,有许多不同的历史表现:平民主权与大型直接议会、议会制度、联邦公社和自愿初级协会网络是相容的;它可能包括抽签、轮换和召回;受欢迎的陪审团和法庭;授权和强制性授权;还有弑君和叛乱的权利。虽然没有McCormick和Vergara提出的那么具体,但他的观点更广泛。最后,Arlen(2019)在诊断和动员亚里士多德和希腊传统而不是罗马或意大利共和国方面采取了类似的方向,同时也为穷人辩护。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信