Practical assent in The Practical Self by Anil Gomes†

IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Léa Salje
{"title":"Practical assent in The Practical Self by Anil Gomes†","authors":"Léa Salje","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13041","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p><i>The Practical Self</i> is a Kantian book three times over. First, it is, in many parts, a book <i>about</i> Kant; the overarching aim of the book is to revive and if possible to complete the Kantian and Cartesian projects of moving from the resources available to the self-conscious thinker to the establishment of the existence of an objective external world — and to do this, Gomes must critically work through various moves from those earlier attempts. Secondly, Gomes takes, in several parts, key arguments and concepts from Kant's critical and practical philosophy as live argumentative tools for his own purposes. But even in the parts of the book not directly concerned with Kant's proprietary argumentative ends and means, this is a deeply Kantian book in flavour — that is the third Kantianism of the book. At every turn, we see unabashedly full-strength claims how things must be, given other ways things must in turn be, or the elimination of ways things cannot be, or ways in which we cannot but think of them as being.</p><p>Put altogether, it's natural to think that the result of all of this will be a book that is aloof or inaccessible; beyond reach or regard by those of us who don't normally swim in Kantian waters. Nothing could be a less apt description of this book. In Gomes' hands, the Kantian and Cartesian grand projects find a tractably sober presentation; the selected moves from Kant and other historical figures are given lucid and unharried exposition; the active Kantian concepts and argumentative tools are deployed in ways that shed dependence on the more arcane aspects of the Kantian framework; and the fierce standards of argument make for an exceptionally exciting read — on every page, one feels, there is something to jump up and down about.</p><p>Of the many points in the book ripe for discussion, my response will focus on the first positive turn in the book – an argument that comes in the chapter on Faith (Chapter 4), in which Gomes argues that we have a distinctively practical reason to assent to the claim that we are the agents of our own thoughts. In what follows I'll first set out the context in which this argument comes up in the book, then I'll set out the argument itself, and I'll end by raising a number of critical questions for it.</p><p>First, then, some stage-setting. In order to proceed in his project of moving from the resources available to the self-conscious thinker to the establishment of an objectively existing world, Gomes must address Lichtenberg's complaint that the most the self-conscious thinker can posit is that ‘there is thinking’, on the model of ‘there is lightning’; ‘One should say <i>it is thinking</i>, just as one says, <i>it is lightning</i>. To say <i>cogito</i> is already too much as soon as one translates it as I am thinking.’ (Lichtenberg K76, cited in Gomes p.131). What emerges from his insightful extended discussion of Lichtenberg in Chapter 3 is an original understanding of what it would take to answer the challenge: we must provide grounds for thinking of ourselves as the agents of our own thoughts. Merely to show that there is a unified location – a self – at which the thoughts are happening is not enough – for all that, the thoughts might still merely strike at that unified self like lightning. No, to answer Lichtenberg we must produce grounds for the claim that we are not just unified loci of our thoughts, but the <i>agents</i> of our thoughts. This demand comes in two versions: we must show that we can render the idea of ourselves as mental agents <i>intelligible</i> to ourselves, and we must show that we are <i>epistemically entitled</i> to think of ourselves as such. It is this second version of the demand that will be important in what follows.</p><p>By the time he reaches Chapter 4 Gomes already takes himself to have shown that this demand cannot be met through either experience or <i>a priori</i> conceptual mastery; as he says, ‘Our status as agents does not show up in our experience of the world. And there is nothing conceptually incoherent about the idea that we might be the mere passive recipients of all our thoughts.’ (p.102) What, then? His answer: faith, in the Kantian sense of practical assent. There are some claims, the idea is, that we are required to practically assent to, because they precondition the attainability of an end that we are required to set ourselves. The attitude we end up adopting is not one of belief – or at least, not so long as we think of belief as a state that aims at the truth of a given matter on the basis of some theoretically justifying evidence; ‘if what it is to be a belief is constitutively tied up with the aim of truth in such a way that only considerations which bear on the truth of a claim count towards believing the claim, then assent on practical grounds cannot be a form of belief.’ (p.111). The attitude we end up adopting, rather, is a sui generis state of <i>Fürwahrhalten</i>, or holding-for-true, which we take up for distinctively practical reasons. The closest folk psychological counterpart Gomes gives us for reference is that of <i>acceptance</i> of a claim, which we may do for practical reasons that do not straightforwardly reflect theoretical justification for thinking it is true.</p><p>Arguments of the kind Gomes has in mind here are not transcendental arguments – indeed, the rational derivation of states of practical assent is explicitly <i>contrasted</i> in this chapter with the strategy made available by transcendental arguments. With a bit of a squint, however, I have found it useful to think of the two argument-forms as having something of an overall outline in common. A transcendental argument begins with a claim that all parties are inclined to agree on, and then identifies a substantive precondition of that starting claim that one of the parties initially wanted to deny. The dialectical force of the argument, then, is that of showing that so long as one's interlocutor wants to hold on to the accepted starting claim, she is already precommitted to the very substantive claim that had been in contention. The practical version of this argument-shape goes as follows: it begins with an end that everyone must set themselves, and then identifies a substantive claim that preconditions the attainability of that end. Since we can only set ourselves ends that we take to be attainable (various caveats aside1), the practical requirement to set ourselves the end in question carries over through closure to a practical requirement to accept the substantive precondition on its attainability. So as in the case of a transcendental argument, the dialectical force here is not designed to move a sceptic or to provide justification for the substantive claim on its own terms. It is to demonstrate to one's interlocutor that she must already be precommitted to that claim, given its conditioning role in the attainability of an end that she does, because she must, accept. As Gomes puts it, ‘If it is a condition on setting an end that we take it to be attainable and we are required to assent to any claim which is a condition on the attainability of a required end, then a claim will be practically required when it is a condition on the attainability of some end which we are required to set.’ (p.115).</p><p>From here, the argument gets going relatively quickly. If we are required to set ourselves the end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world then we must take it to be possible for us to do so. Otherwise, Gomes argues, we are not rational in setting ourselves the end. (Something in this vicinity is surely plausible: I cannot rationally set myself the end of being in seven places at once, since that is not something I take it that I can do.) But if it is possible for me to settle these questions – which is, notice, an <i>active</i> enterprise – then I must be the agent of my thoughts, which is to say that at least some of my thoughts must fall under my agency. And here we reach the Lichtenberg-busting endpoint of the argument. I am practically required to have faith in my own mental agency, because it preconditions the attainability of an end that I must set myself – that is, that of settling questions about the quality or appropriateness of the first order beliefs and experiences that make up my perspective on the world.</p><p>A final observation about this argument. Premise one is surprisingly strong. Not only is this an end that we all happen to have, or are inclined to have, or typically have; this is an end that we self-conscious thinkers <i>must</i> have. What's more, Gomes makes it clear that the modal force of this requirement is something in the neighbourhood of (or perhaps just is) the categorical imperative. It would not, for instance, suffice for this to be an end that we find ourselves saddled with as a contingent matter of cognitive evolutionary biology. It must be an end that we are required to have, as a matter of necessity, in a way that flows from our nature as self-conscious thinkers. Why so strong? To avoid the charge of wishful thinking. If we replaced the end in this premise with any end that any one of us merely happened to have, then this argument-form would appear to legitimise a sort of bootstrapping of epistemic entitlement wherever we would find it congenial to have. Suppose, for instance, that I happen to have the end of learning Japanese in three months; for that to be attainable I am practically required to assent to the claim that I am a whizz at learning languages. But, of course, that would be nothing but wishful thinking – a rationally bankrupt form of reasoning that Gomes needs to hold at a distance from whatever the form of reasoning is that provides him with his anti-Lichtenbergian grounds. Strengthening the end in question to one that we do not simply choose, but one that we <i>must</i> set ourselves is his way of avoiding this pitfall. It is part of what gives this form of reasoning the sort of stability, or anti-accidentality, that avoids its collapse into localised instances of wishful thinking.4</p><p>There is, I think, something tantalising about this argument. Surely it is right that there are certain claims that find ourselves liable to accept, not because of the evidence we find in their favour, but because without them we couldn't make sense of the things that we do or that we try to do. And what's more, we are surely <i>right</i> to accept such claims for such reasons: it doesn't smack of acting incautiously or carelessly, but rather evinces an epistemically mature spirit of commonsense — we <i>must</i> accept these claims, or else we wouldn't be able to get going on anything else. What is intriguing about this argument is that it doesn't merely leave matters there, pointing to a little-noticed but psychologically plausible and motivationally intelligible distinctive kind of attitude that we sometimes hold towards claims for practical reasons. This argument goes further in elucidating the <i>epistemic entitlement</i> we have for those claims – in saying how it is that it can be epistemically well-grounded to hold such an attitude for such reasons. For Gomes, this is part of what is needed in answering the Lichtenbergian challenge. But more broadly, this is a tantalising aim, because if we could properly epistemically ground the attitude of practical assent, it may be that this is a notion that could profitably be taken up into mainstream philosophy of mind and epistemology, as a way of helping to characterise parts of the mind that don't quite fit the more traditional truth-holding attitudes of belief or (evidentially grounded) knowledge.</p><p>I take it that the entitlement in question originates from the force (whatever it is) of the requirement that we must set ourselves the end in question in premise one, which carries over through closure via an interim step of the end's supposed attainability, to a substantive claim that conditions that attainability. We are entitled in accepting that final claim to whatever degree and in whatever mode in which we were originally entitled to set ourselves that end — which, as we saw, is an end that we must <i>necessarily</i> set ourselves, so (the idea might be) are surely entitled in doing so. Recall too the theoretical significance of that necessity claim: Gomes prevents his argument from collapsing into a charter for wishful thinking by strengthening the end mentioned in the first premise to one that we <i>must</i> set ourselves, rather than looking to the hurly-burly of individual ends that we happen to set ourselves. So the key to understanding the entitlement that is present in the good case, and isn't in the case of localised wishful thinking, has something to do with the strengthening of that first premise to the identification of a necessary end rather than a merely contingent one.</p><p>Here's a starting worry about this strategy: there is an anti-tragedy assumption guiding this strengthening move that (ironically) leaves it open that the move itself rests on a piece of wishful thinking. Why think it impossible that there could be an end that we must all set ourselves, that we don't even take to be attainable? A quick clarification before I press this question further. There are at least two ways of reading the key verb, <i>settling</i>, that features in this required end, which are naturally read as implying different levels of demandingness. It might be read in the progressive, as something that we must be <i>in the course of doing</i>, or it might be read as an achievement verb – as an undertaking that we must succeed in completing. The attainability of the end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world is much more plausible read the first way, so that's how I propose to read it – viz., as having no inbuilt commitment to our achieving the settling of our questions, only to our undertaking to settle them.</p><p>My question now is: what is it exactly about the move from contingent to necessary ends that is supposed to immunise that end from the possibility that it is not, in fact, attainable, and that our commitment to any claim that would seem to render it attainable is nothing more than a case of wishful thinking? (An instructive comparison here is with Montaigne's argument that faith in God is universal – there are no atheists on their deathbeds – but for that very reason faith is psychologically shallow because improperly motivated. Here the requirement that we must all have faith is precisely taken to indicate a <i>lack</i> of epistemic credentials.5) Another way of putting the challenge is that there is a <i>must implies can</i> principle underlying the strengthening move – but we are left without an account of why this is a principle we should accept.</p><p>Perhaps the answer will come from details about the modal force, nature and source of the necessity of setting the end. I won't pursue that option here because I'm not exactly sure how to fill in this part of the picture. The requirement to set ourselves this end emerges, for Gomes, from the observation that self-conscious judgments tend to arise in the context of stretches of telic cognitive activity, which can all be properly characterised under this broader end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. But this still leaves us with unanswered questions about the force, source and nature of the requirement that results. In what sense, exactly, <i>must</i> I set myself this end, on the basis that I <i>in fact</i> seem to comply with it in many cases? In what sense does the modal claim follow from the descriptive, and what sort of requirement does it generate?</p><p>Without a way of filling in this part of the picture, things risk looking even worse for the strengthening move than might at first have seemed. Not only is it unclear why and whether a move from a contingent to a necessary end gives the resulting attitude of practical assent the epistemic credibility Gomes needs to have it play the theoretical role it does in his argument. It strikes me that a move to positing a required end precisely <i>weakens</i> our rational responsibilities with respect to it, and so too the epistemic credentials of any attitude that results – thus making it <i>less</i> likely that the resulting attitude is safe from the charge of wishful thinking. After all, in cases where I select an end from a multitude of options – <i>I will learn Japanese in three months!</i> – it is incumbent on me to check the end for attainability before committing, and I can be properly rationally criticized where those checks are not sufficiently robust. These checks underwrite the sort of move Gomes has in mind between steps 1 and 2 in the argument above — from the setting of an end to its implied perceived attainability; if I didn't take it to be attainable, I would not be rational in setting the end. Contrast this with a case where I find myself with an end because it is one that I <i>must</i> have. My due diligence with respect to checking its attainability now seems neither here nor there. It's an end that I must have, regardless of how attainable I take it to be. To illustrate: suppose that I find myself facing a forced choice between climbing down an unclimbable mountain or certain and immediate death by exposure.6 There is really no choice here at all – I cannot but give the unattainable a go. Am I rationally criticisable in doing so? My strong intuition is that I am not. If this is right, then in just these cases – the cases in which the end is not locally chosen, but <i>required</i> of us in some way – we have reason to reopen the move from 1 to 2 in Gomes' argument above. In other words, the fact that we posit a required end no longer implies, by the standards of rationality, that we take it to be attainable.</p><p>Suppose I'm right that the strengthening move doesn't, as Gomes had hoped, automatically immunise his argument against the charge of wishful thinking. This wouldn't settle, but would merely reopen the question whether the end he identifies is in one that we (must) set ourselves, and if so whether it is an end that we take to be attainable. Perhaps he can still get what he wants – which is to say, epistemically entitled assent to our own mental agency – if it turns out that the identified end <i>is</i> apparently attainable, even if the move to rendering that end a necessary one hasn't by itself ruled out the possibility that it isn't. My question now is: do we have independent reason to think that Gomes's identified end – that of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world – is one that self-conscious thinkers of our kind in fact set for ourselves?</p><p>I think we have overintellectualisation reasons for suspicion that it isn't – or, at least, that it isn't for all self-conscious thinkers of our kind. To see this, notice that Gomes is inviting us to adopt a third order psychological attitude. At the first order are the beliefs and experiences that constitute one's perspective on the world. At the second are the evaluative stances we take towards those first order beliefs and experiences. The suggestion from Gomes is that we ascend yet another level, at which we set ourselves the end of engaging in this second order evaluative mental activity. This is certainly something that some of us can do when in the right frame of mind — in a seminar room, say, or in a pensive mood. And Gomes is surely right when he says that this is what Descartes' enquirer is in the business of doing. I even think it is something that some of us may be <i>prone</i> to do – especially those whose perspective on the world is routinely challenged. But can all of us do it? Can children? Can the intellectually impoverished or the cognitively diminished? It certainly isn't obvious that the answer is ‘yes’ for all thinkers who would count as self-conscious. The capacity to reflect on our own first order thoughts and experiences (conceptually guaranteed for all self-conscious thinkers) doesn't automatically imply a capacity to reflect on that second order capacity at the third order.</p><p>Of course, the question whether we can do it rests in large part on what would take for us to count as having done it. Gomes is explicit that the setting of an end in the relevant Kantian sense involves the active <i>willing</i> of the end, or <i>deciding to pursue it</i>, so part of what it takes is an occurrent mental event of willing an end with a particular content (rather than something more dispositional, say). He says, ‘Ends which are the object of our will are ends which we have decided upon: ends that we <i>will</i> and do not merely wish.’ (p.91) If this is really what it takes, it is a high bar to meet; speaking for myself, I'm not sure I have ever actively willed this end, even if reflecting on my perspective is something I often do. Likewise, the presumed attainability of the end is one that must be positively assented to on Gomes' view – naturally read as entertaining of a thought about its attainability – rather than a mere absence of assent in its unattainability. Again, it seems to me that this is asking rather a lot. I also find myself with questions about how often we have to will the end. Once in a lifetime? Must we reaffirm it once in a while? And how much attempted evaluative activity at the second order would suffice for the end's attainment?</p><p>While these are genuine questions I have about how Gomes' argument is supposed to work, I don't doubt that there will be ways of answering them that will make the envisaged psychology of the end-setting a better fit for the sorts of limited self-conscious thinkers we are. Even supposing such adjustments can be made, however, there is another sort of question lingering in the background, this time a normative one: is this an end we <i>ought</i> to set ourselves? Is it one we would wish for ourselves or our loved ones?</p><p>Let's walk through the levels again: we spend much of our time at the first order, immersed in beliefs about and experiences of the world, alongside other first order attitudes. It's no doubt beneficial to our functioning that have the capacity to keep an eye on the quality of this first order perspective on the world – that we are, at the very least, dispositionally able to take a higher-order evaluative stance towards it. But except in certain special circumstances – unless, for instance, we are engaged in an exploratory exercise in the method of radical doubt – it <i>doesn't</i> seem especially beneficial to our functioning to reside at that second order too resolutely. Take Second-order-Sam. Sam has thoughts about the world just like the rest of us. She believes it to be raining, that Trump is the greatest current threat to geo-political stability, and that cats make better pets than dogs. She has well-functioning sensory systems, and experiences her immediate physical environment just fine. The special thing about Sam, however, is the immense importance she places on her second order evaluative attitudes. Rarely does a first order thought about or experience of the world pass through her mind, but she bolts up to the second order to review whether it's a good thing to think, or a good experience to have. What do we think of Sam? I don't think it's a stretch to say that this describes a less-than-optimal set of mental facts: Sam comes across as a little neurotic, somewhat self-alienated, and probably exhausted. Suppose now that – looking for guidance about how she should organise her mental life – she comes to us for advice. And suppose that rather than encouraging her to spend a bit more time dwelling at the first order as any good mindfulness app would do, we urge her to rise up another level. We tell her: not only is it good that she places such importance on second-order evaluation of her first order states, but she should set the performance of that second-order evaluative activity as her end. This is, I think we can all agree, bad advice. The general lesson here is that even if the fact that we have the capacity for second-order evaluative mental activity seems like a good feature of our psychologies, this is a far cry from thinking that it would be good for us to explicitly set ourselves the end of engaging in this second-order activity.</p><p>Now, of course, there will be ways of softening the filled-out story of what Gomes' end-setting involves that needn't land him in anything like this caricature. His suggestion is surely not that we occupy this third order perspective <i>all the time</i>, nor that the end we set is <i>always to be settling questions</i> at the second order. What the example of Second-order Sam brings out is not that it is always bad to reflect on what we think and experience, only that it's bad to do it too much, and perhaps this can be dealt with by reading a tacit proportionality qualifier into Gomes' posited end – perhaps the end is <i>sometimes</i>, or <i>when appropriate</i> to settle questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. Or perhaps it will be cleared up once we have more information about the force, nature and source of the requirement in question. The thing is that by now it looks to me like we have all the materials on the table from Gomes to account for everything we need without appeal to anything like the claim that we are required to set ourselves – to actively <i>will</i> – a certain end with respect to our second-order mental activity. That is, that this second order activity is something we self-conscious creatures in fact sometimes do; and it is a good thing that we sometimes do it. What would be missing if we left things there?</p><p>Let me summarise where we've got to. There is something tantalising about Gomes' argument in which he has us derive a special sort of epistemically entitled practical assent in our own mental agency from the supposed practical requirement each of us is under to set ourselves the end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. It is tantalising in the context of Gomes' own project – this is what he needs to neutralise Lichtenbergian worries – but there is also a broader prospect in the offing of characterising a distinctive kind of epistemically well-grounded attitude of practical assent that we might find other uses for in our philosophical theorising about our minds. I have raised a number of challenges to that argument: specifically, I have questioned whether the necessity of the end immunises it against the charge of wishful thinking, and have given a few reasons for resisting the idea that this end is really one that we do or must set ourselves – at least, where that end is interpreted in the strong terms given by Gomes.</p><p>Still, I find there to be something compelling about the notion of an attitude of epistemically well-grounded practical assent, something worth seeing if we can make stand on its own feet. I want to end with a pair of lightning sketches of two ways forward that might allow us to preserve that notion, released from some of the stronger Kantian aspects of its presentation as offered by Gomes.</p><p>The first would be to uncouple the rational status of the attitude of practical assent from any claim to a positive epistemic status. The attitude is still <i>reasons-responsive</i> – it's just that the reasons being responded to are of a practical rather than a theoretical or evidential nature. This would be a concessive move forward – it would be to give up on the idea that we have any special epistemic entitlement to hold these claims as true. But we are rational in doing so, and that is not nothing. That we are rational in accepting such claims may be enough to satisfy the intuition that we are not being epistemically reckless or irresponsible in their acceptance. But it would not be enough to show that their epistemology is any better grounded than that of prudentially justified claims, including those claims it is psychologically beneficial for us to hold as true – and at this point, we might worry we have collapsed the idea we wanted to hold on to that there is a distinct category of practical assent that can be held apart from mere wishful thinking or prudentially beneficial acceptance.</p><p>For those with this worry, the second option will be to insist that practical assent isn't just a rational attitude. Over and above its rationality, the attitude is one with positive epistemic status – we are positively entitled to hold these claims as true. In a way, this is a much more natural position to hold; there is something uncomfortable about the idea that I might occupy an attitude of holding-for-true towards some claim which conforms to the norms of rationality, but to which I am not epistemically entitled. (Am I in the right or in the wrong here?). But of course, <i>where we get this epistemic entitlement from</i> in this second sketch is the big question. As Gomes shows us, it cannot be from the familiar sources of theoretical justification – that would turn this distinctively practical attitude into something quite different. My own (not very Kantian) inclination would be to turn to a virtue epistemological framework, that makes it much harder to pull apart the norms of rationality and questions of epistemological well-groundedness. These are, as we might put it, the sorts of attitudes a virtuous epistemic agent would hold in these situations, or they are the products of the subject's well-functioning intellectual traits. But whether or not Gomes would be tempted by this option, it seems to me that this question about how epistemic entitlement gets into the picture is the big question that needs answering if he is properly to fend off the Lichtenbergian challenge that we lack entitlement to think of ourselves as the agents of our own thinking. It is not a question I have found the answer to on the page in <i>The Practical Self</i>. But it is, I think, an extremely tantalising question that lies right at the heart of this book.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"33 2","pages":"762-769"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2025-05-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13041","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13041","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The Practical Self is a Kantian book three times over. First, it is, in many parts, a book about Kant; the overarching aim of the book is to revive and if possible to complete the Kantian and Cartesian projects of moving from the resources available to the self-conscious thinker to the establishment of the existence of an objective external world — and to do this, Gomes must critically work through various moves from those earlier attempts. Secondly, Gomes takes, in several parts, key arguments and concepts from Kant's critical and practical philosophy as live argumentative tools for his own purposes. But even in the parts of the book not directly concerned with Kant's proprietary argumentative ends and means, this is a deeply Kantian book in flavour — that is the third Kantianism of the book. At every turn, we see unabashedly full-strength claims how things must be, given other ways things must in turn be, or the elimination of ways things cannot be, or ways in which we cannot but think of them as being.

Put altogether, it's natural to think that the result of all of this will be a book that is aloof or inaccessible; beyond reach or regard by those of us who don't normally swim in Kantian waters. Nothing could be a less apt description of this book. In Gomes' hands, the Kantian and Cartesian grand projects find a tractably sober presentation; the selected moves from Kant and other historical figures are given lucid and unharried exposition; the active Kantian concepts and argumentative tools are deployed in ways that shed dependence on the more arcane aspects of the Kantian framework; and the fierce standards of argument make for an exceptionally exciting read — on every page, one feels, there is something to jump up and down about.

Of the many points in the book ripe for discussion, my response will focus on the first positive turn in the book – an argument that comes in the chapter on Faith (Chapter 4), in which Gomes argues that we have a distinctively practical reason to assent to the claim that we are the agents of our own thoughts. In what follows I'll first set out the context in which this argument comes up in the book, then I'll set out the argument itself, and I'll end by raising a number of critical questions for it.

First, then, some stage-setting. In order to proceed in his project of moving from the resources available to the self-conscious thinker to the establishment of an objectively existing world, Gomes must address Lichtenberg's complaint that the most the self-conscious thinker can posit is that ‘there is thinking’, on the model of ‘there is lightning’; ‘One should say it is thinking, just as one says, it is lightning. To say cogito is already too much as soon as one translates it as I am thinking.’ (Lichtenberg K76, cited in Gomes p.131). What emerges from his insightful extended discussion of Lichtenberg in Chapter 3 is an original understanding of what it would take to answer the challenge: we must provide grounds for thinking of ourselves as the agents of our own thoughts. Merely to show that there is a unified location – a self – at which the thoughts are happening is not enough – for all that, the thoughts might still merely strike at that unified self like lightning. No, to answer Lichtenberg we must produce grounds for the claim that we are not just unified loci of our thoughts, but the agents of our thoughts. This demand comes in two versions: we must show that we can render the idea of ourselves as mental agents intelligible to ourselves, and we must show that we are epistemically entitled to think of ourselves as such. It is this second version of the demand that will be important in what follows.

By the time he reaches Chapter 4 Gomes already takes himself to have shown that this demand cannot be met through either experience or a priori conceptual mastery; as he says, ‘Our status as agents does not show up in our experience of the world. And there is nothing conceptually incoherent about the idea that we might be the mere passive recipients of all our thoughts.’ (p.102) What, then? His answer: faith, in the Kantian sense of practical assent. There are some claims, the idea is, that we are required to practically assent to, because they precondition the attainability of an end that we are required to set ourselves. The attitude we end up adopting is not one of belief – or at least, not so long as we think of belief as a state that aims at the truth of a given matter on the basis of some theoretically justifying evidence; ‘if what it is to be a belief is constitutively tied up with the aim of truth in such a way that only considerations which bear on the truth of a claim count towards believing the claim, then assent on practical grounds cannot be a form of belief.’ (p.111). The attitude we end up adopting, rather, is a sui generis state of Fürwahrhalten, or holding-for-true, which we take up for distinctively practical reasons. The closest folk psychological counterpart Gomes gives us for reference is that of acceptance of a claim, which we may do for practical reasons that do not straightforwardly reflect theoretical justification for thinking it is true.

Arguments of the kind Gomes has in mind here are not transcendental arguments – indeed, the rational derivation of states of practical assent is explicitly contrasted in this chapter with the strategy made available by transcendental arguments. With a bit of a squint, however, I have found it useful to think of the two argument-forms as having something of an overall outline in common. A transcendental argument begins with a claim that all parties are inclined to agree on, and then identifies a substantive precondition of that starting claim that one of the parties initially wanted to deny. The dialectical force of the argument, then, is that of showing that so long as one's interlocutor wants to hold on to the accepted starting claim, she is already precommitted to the very substantive claim that had been in contention. The practical version of this argument-shape goes as follows: it begins with an end that everyone must set themselves, and then identifies a substantive claim that preconditions the attainability of that end. Since we can only set ourselves ends that we take to be attainable (various caveats aside1), the practical requirement to set ourselves the end in question carries over through closure to a practical requirement to accept the substantive precondition on its attainability. So as in the case of a transcendental argument, the dialectical force here is not designed to move a sceptic or to provide justification for the substantive claim on its own terms. It is to demonstrate to one's interlocutor that she must already be precommitted to that claim, given its conditioning role in the attainability of an end that she does, because she must, accept. As Gomes puts it, ‘If it is a condition on setting an end that we take it to be attainable and we are required to assent to any claim which is a condition on the attainability of a required end, then a claim will be practically required when it is a condition on the attainability of some end which we are required to set.’ (p.115).

From here, the argument gets going relatively quickly. If we are required to set ourselves the end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world then we must take it to be possible for us to do so. Otherwise, Gomes argues, we are not rational in setting ourselves the end. (Something in this vicinity is surely plausible: I cannot rationally set myself the end of being in seven places at once, since that is not something I take it that I can do.) But if it is possible for me to settle these questions – which is, notice, an active enterprise – then I must be the agent of my thoughts, which is to say that at least some of my thoughts must fall under my agency. And here we reach the Lichtenberg-busting endpoint of the argument. I am practically required to have faith in my own mental agency, because it preconditions the attainability of an end that I must set myself – that is, that of settling questions about the quality or appropriateness of the first order beliefs and experiences that make up my perspective on the world.

A final observation about this argument. Premise one is surprisingly strong. Not only is this an end that we all happen to have, or are inclined to have, or typically have; this is an end that we self-conscious thinkers must have. What's more, Gomes makes it clear that the modal force of this requirement is something in the neighbourhood of (or perhaps just is) the categorical imperative. It would not, for instance, suffice for this to be an end that we find ourselves saddled with as a contingent matter of cognitive evolutionary biology. It must be an end that we are required to have, as a matter of necessity, in a way that flows from our nature as self-conscious thinkers. Why so strong? To avoid the charge of wishful thinking. If we replaced the end in this premise with any end that any one of us merely happened to have, then this argument-form would appear to legitimise a sort of bootstrapping of epistemic entitlement wherever we would find it congenial to have. Suppose, for instance, that I happen to have the end of learning Japanese in three months; for that to be attainable I am practically required to assent to the claim that I am a whizz at learning languages. But, of course, that would be nothing but wishful thinking – a rationally bankrupt form of reasoning that Gomes needs to hold at a distance from whatever the form of reasoning is that provides him with his anti-Lichtenbergian grounds. Strengthening the end in question to one that we do not simply choose, but one that we must set ourselves is his way of avoiding this pitfall. It is part of what gives this form of reasoning the sort of stability, or anti-accidentality, that avoids its collapse into localised instances of wishful thinking.4

There is, I think, something tantalising about this argument. Surely it is right that there are certain claims that find ourselves liable to accept, not because of the evidence we find in their favour, but because without them we couldn't make sense of the things that we do or that we try to do. And what's more, we are surely right to accept such claims for such reasons: it doesn't smack of acting incautiously or carelessly, but rather evinces an epistemically mature spirit of commonsense — we must accept these claims, or else we wouldn't be able to get going on anything else. What is intriguing about this argument is that it doesn't merely leave matters there, pointing to a little-noticed but psychologically plausible and motivationally intelligible distinctive kind of attitude that we sometimes hold towards claims for practical reasons. This argument goes further in elucidating the epistemic entitlement we have for those claims – in saying how it is that it can be epistemically well-grounded to hold such an attitude for such reasons. For Gomes, this is part of what is needed in answering the Lichtenbergian challenge. But more broadly, this is a tantalising aim, because if we could properly epistemically ground the attitude of practical assent, it may be that this is a notion that could profitably be taken up into mainstream philosophy of mind and epistemology, as a way of helping to characterise parts of the mind that don't quite fit the more traditional truth-holding attitudes of belief or (evidentially grounded) knowledge.

I take it that the entitlement in question originates from the force (whatever it is) of the requirement that we must set ourselves the end in question in premise one, which carries over through closure via an interim step of the end's supposed attainability, to a substantive claim that conditions that attainability. We are entitled in accepting that final claim to whatever degree and in whatever mode in which we were originally entitled to set ourselves that end — which, as we saw, is an end that we must necessarily set ourselves, so (the idea might be) are surely entitled in doing so. Recall too the theoretical significance of that necessity claim: Gomes prevents his argument from collapsing into a charter for wishful thinking by strengthening the end mentioned in the first premise to one that we must set ourselves, rather than looking to the hurly-burly of individual ends that we happen to set ourselves. So the key to understanding the entitlement that is present in the good case, and isn't in the case of localised wishful thinking, has something to do with the strengthening of that first premise to the identification of a necessary end rather than a merely contingent one.

Here's a starting worry about this strategy: there is an anti-tragedy assumption guiding this strengthening move that (ironically) leaves it open that the move itself rests on a piece of wishful thinking. Why think it impossible that there could be an end that we must all set ourselves, that we don't even take to be attainable? A quick clarification before I press this question further. There are at least two ways of reading the key verb, settling, that features in this required end, which are naturally read as implying different levels of demandingness. It might be read in the progressive, as something that we must be in the course of doing, or it might be read as an achievement verb – as an undertaking that we must succeed in completing. The attainability of the end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world is much more plausible read the first way, so that's how I propose to read it – viz., as having no inbuilt commitment to our achieving the settling of our questions, only to our undertaking to settle them.

My question now is: what is it exactly about the move from contingent to necessary ends that is supposed to immunise that end from the possibility that it is not, in fact, attainable, and that our commitment to any claim that would seem to render it attainable is nothing more than a case of wishful thinking? (An instructive comparison here is with Montaigne's argument that faith in God is universal – there are no atheists on their deathbeds – but for that very reason faith is psychologically shallow because improperly motivated. Here the requirement that we must all have faith is precisely taken to indicate a lack of epistemic credentials.5) Another way of putting the challenge is that there is a must implies can principle underlying the strengthening move – but we are left without an account of why this is a principle we should accept.

Perhaps the answer will come from details about the modal force, nature and source of the necessity of setting the end. I won't pursue that option here because I'm not exactly sure how to fill in this part of the picture. The requirement to set ourselves this end emerges, for Gomes, from the observation that self-conscious judgments tend to arise in the context of stretches of telic cognitive activity, which can all be properly characterised under this broader end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. But this still leaves us with unanswered questions about the force, source and nature of the requirement that results. In what sense, exactly, must I set myself this end, on the basis that I in fact seem to comply with it in many cases? In what sense does the modal claim follow from the descriptive, and what sort of requirement does it generate?

Without a way of filling in this part of the picture, things risk looking even worse for the strengthening move than might at first have seemed. Not only is it unclear why and whether a move from a contingent to a necessary end gives the resulting attitude of practical assent the epistemic credibility Gomes needs to have it play the theoretical role it does in his argument. It strikes me that a move to positing a required end precisely weakens our rational responsibilities with respect to it, and so too the epistemic credentials of any attitude that results – thus making it less likely that the resulting attitude is safe from the charge of wishful thinking. After all, in cases where I select an end from a multitude of options – I will learn Japanese in three months! – it is incumbent on me to check the end for attainability before committing, and I can be properly rationally criticized where those checks are not sufficiently robust. These checks underwrite the sort of move Gomes has in mind between steps 1 and 2 in the argument above — from the setting of an end to its implied perceived attainability; if I didn't take it to be attainable, I would not be rational in setting the end. Contrast this with a case where I find myself with an end because it is one that I must have. My due diligence with respect to checking its attainability now seems neither here nor there. It's an end that I must have, regardless of how attainable I take it to be. To illustrate: suppose that I find myself facing a forced choice between climbing down an unclimbable mountain or certain and immediate death by exposure.6 There is really no choice here at all – I cannot but give the unattainable a go. Am I rationally criticisable in doing so? My strong intuition is that I am not. If this is right, then in just these cases – the cases in which the end is not locally chosen, but required of us in some way – we have reason to reopen the move from 1 to 2 in Gomes' argument above. In other words, the fact that we posit a required end no longer implies, by the standards of rationality, that we take it to be attainable.

Suppose I'm right that the strengthening move doesn't, as Gomes had hoped, automatically immunise his argument against the charge of wishful thinking. This wouldn't settle, but would merely reopen the question whether the end he identifies is in one that we (must) set ourselves, and if so whether it is an end that we take to be attainable. Perhaps he can still get what he wants – which is to say, epistemically entitled assent to our own mental agency – if it turns out that the identified end is apparently attainable, even if the move to rendering that end a necessary one hasn't by itself ruled out the possibility that it isn't. My question now is: do we have independent reason to think that Gomes's identified end – that of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world – is one that self-conscious thinkers of our kind in fact set for ourselves?

I think we have overintellectualisation reasons for suspicion that it isn't – or, at least, that it isn't for all self-conscious thinkers of our kind. To see this, notice that Gomes is inviting us to adopt a third order psychological attitude. At the first order are the beliefs and experiences that constitute one's perspective on the world. At the second are the evaluative stances we take towards those first order beliefs and experiences. The suggestion from Gomes is that we ascend yet another level, at which we set ourselves the end of engaging in this second order evaluative mental activity. This is certainly something that some of us can do when in the right frame of mind — in a seminar room, say, or in a pensive mood. And Gomes is surely right when he says that this is what Descartes' enquirer is in the business of doing. I even think it is something that some of us may be prone to do – especially those whose perspective on the world is routinely challenged. But can all of us do it? Can children? Can the intellectually impoverished or the cognitively diminished? It certainly isn't obvious that the answer is ‘yes’ for all thinkers who would count as self-conscious. The capacity to reflect on our own first order thoughts and experiences (conceptually guaranteed for all self-conscious thinkers) doesn't automatically imply a capacity to reflect on that second order capacity at the third order.

Of course, the question whether we can do it rests in large part on what would take for us to count as having done it. Gomes is explicit that the setting of an end in the relevant Kantian sense involves the active willing of the end, or deciding to pursue it, so part of what it takes is an occurrent mental event of willing an end with a particular content (rather than something more dispositional, say). He says, ‘Ends which are the object of our will are ends which we have decided upon: ends that we will and do not merely wish.’ (p.91) If this is really what it takes, it is a high bar to meet; speaking for myself, I'm not sure I have ever actively willed this end, even if reflecting on my perspective is something I often do. Likewise, the presumed attainability of the end is one that must be positively assented to on Gomes' view – naturally read as entertaining of a thought about its attainability – rather than a mere absence of assent in its unattainability. Again, it seems to me that this is asking rather a lot. I also find myself with questions about how often we have to will the end. Once in a lifetime? Must we reaffirm it once in a while? And how much attempted evaluative activity at the second order would suffice for the end's attainment?

While these are genuine questions I have about how Gomes' argument is supposed to work, I don't doubt that there will be ways of answering them that will make the envisaged psychology of the end-setting a better fit for the sorts of limited self-conscious thinkers we are. Even supposing such adjustments can be made, however, there is another sort of question lingering in the background, this time a normative one: is this an end we ought to set ourselves? Is it one we would wish for ourselves or our loved ones?

Let's walk through the levels again: we spend much of our time at the first order, immersed in beliefs about and experiences of the world, alongside other first order attitudes. It's no doubt beneficial to our functioning that have the capacity to keep an eye on the quality of this first order perspective on the world – that we are, at the very least, dispositionally able to take a higher-order evaluative stance towards it. But except in certain special circumstances – unless, for instance, we are engaged in an exploratory exercise in the method of radical doubt – it doesn't seem especially beneficial to our functioning to reside at that second order too resolutely. Take Second-order-Sam. Sam has thoughts about the world just like the rest of us. She believes it to be raining, that Trump is the greatest current threat to geo-political stability, and that cats make better pets than dogs. She has well-functioning sensory systems, and experiences her immediate physical environment just fine. The special thing about Sam, however, is the immense importance she places on her second order evaluative attitudes. Rarely does a first order thought about or experience of the world pass through her mind, but she bolts up to the second order to review whether it's a good thing to think, or a good experience to have. What do we think of Sam? I don't think it's a stretch to say that this describes a less-than-optimal set of mental facts: Sam comes across as a little neurotic, somewhat self-alienated, and probably exhausted. Suppose now that – looking for guidance about how she should organise her mental life – she comes to us for advice. And suppose that rather than encouraging her to spend a bit more time dwelling at the first order as any good mindfulness app would do, we urge her to rise up another level. We tell her: not only is it good that she places such importance on second-order evaluation of her first order states, but she should set the performance of that second-order evaluative activity as her end. This is, I think we can all agree, bad advice. The general lesson here is that even if the fact that we have the capacity for second-order evaluative mental activity seems like a good feature of our psychologies, this is a far cry from thinking that it would be good for us to explicitly set ourselves the end of engaging in this second-order activity.

Now, of course, there will be ways of softening the filled-out story of what Gomes' end-setting involves that needn't land him in anything like this caricature. His suggestion is surely not that we occupy this third order perspective all the time, nor that the end we set is always to be settling questions at the second order. What the example of Second-order Sam brings out is not that it is always bad to reflect on what we think and experience, only that it's bad to do it too much, and perhaps this can be dealt with by reading a tacit proportionality qualifier into Gomes' posited end – perhaps the end is sometimes, or when appropriate to settle questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. Or perhaps it will be cleared up once we have more information about the force, nature and source of the requirement in question. The thing is that by now it looks to me like we have all the materials on the table from Gomes to account for everything we need without appeal to anything like the claim that we are required to set ourselves – to actively will – a certain end with respect to our second-order mental activity. That is, that this second order activity is something we self-conscious creatures in fact sometimes do; and it is a good thing that we sometimes do it. What would be missing if we left things there?

Let me summarise where we've got to. There is something tantalising about Gomes' argument in which he has us derive a special sort of epistemically entitled practical assent in our own mental agency from the supposed practical requirement each of us is under to set ourselves the end of settling questions about the propriety of our perspective on the world. It is tantalising in the context of Gomes' own project – this is what he needs to neutralise Lichtenbergian worries – but there is also a broader prospect in the offing of characterising a distinctive kind of epistemically well-grounded attitude of practical assent that we might find other uses for in our philosophical theorising about our minds. I have raised a number of challenges to that argument: specifically, I have questioned whether the necessity of the end immunises it against the charge of wishful thinking, and have given a few reasons for resisting the idea that this end is really one that we do or must set ourselves – at least, where that end is interpreted in the strong terms given by Gomes.

Still, I find there to be something compelling about the notion of an attitude of epistemically well-grounded practical assent, something worth seeing if we can make stand on its own feet. I want to end with a pair of lightning sketches of two ways forward that might allow us to preserve that notion, released from some of the stronger Kantian aspects of its presentation as offered by Gomes.

The first would be to uncouple the rational status of the attitude of practical assent from any claim to a positive epistemic status. The attitude is still reasons-responsive – it's just that the reasons being responded to are of a practical rather than a theoretical or evidential nature. This would be a concessive move forward – it would be to give up on the idea that we have any special epistemic entitlement to hold these claims as true. But we are rational in doing so, and that is not nothing. That we are rational in accepting such claims may be enough to satisfy the intuition that we are not being epistemically reckless or irresponsible in their acceptance. But it would not be enough to show that their epistemology is any better grounded than that of prudentially justified claims, including those claims it is psychologically beneficial for us to hold as true – and at this point, we might worry we have collapsed the idea we wanted to hold on to that there is a distinct category of practical assent that can be held apart from mere wishful thinking or prudentially beneficial acceptance.

For those with this worry, the second option will be to insist that practical assent isn't just a rational attitude. Over and above its rationality, the attitude is one with positive epistemic status – we are positively entitled to hold these claims as true. In a way, this is a much more natural position to hold; there is something uncomfortable about the idea that I might occupy an attitude of holding-for-true towards some claim which conforms to the norms of rationality, but to which I am not epistemically entitled. (Am I in the right or in the wrong here?). But of course, where we get this epistemic entitlement from in this second sketch is the big question. As Gomes shows us, it cannot be from the familiar sources of theoretical justification – that would turn this distinctively practical attitude into something quite different. My own (not very Kantian) inclination would be to turn to a virtue epistemological framework, that makes it much harder to pull apart the norms of rationality and questions of epistemological well-groundedness. These are, as we might put it, the sorts of attitudes a virtuous epistemic agent would hold in these situations, or they are the products of the subject's well-functioning intellectual traits. But whether or not Gomes would be tempted by this option, it seems to me that this question about how epistemic entitlement gets into the picture is the big question that needs answering if he is properly to fend off the Lichtenbergian challenge that we lack entitlement to think of ourselves as the agents of our own thinking. It is not a question I have found the answer to on the page in The Practical Self. But it is, I think, an extremely tantalising question that lies right at the heart of this book.

阿尼尔·戈麦斯《实践自我》中的实践同意
《实践自我》是一本康德式的书。首先,在很多地方,它是一本关于康德的书;这本书的首要目标是恢复,并在可能的情况下完成康德和笛卡尔的项目,即从自我意识思想家的可用资源转向建立客观外部世界的存在——为了做到这一点,戈麦斯必须批判性地从早期的尝试中采取各种行动。其次,戈麦斯将康德的批判哲学和实践哲学中的关键论点和概念作为他自己目的的活生生的论证工具。但即使在书中与康德专有的论证目的和手段没有直接关系的部分,这也是一本充满康德主义色彩的书,这是本书的第三个康德主义。在每一个转折中,我们都毫不掩饰地看到,事物必须如此,而事物又必须如此,或者消除事物不可能存在的方式,或者我们不能不认为它们存在的方式。总而言之,我们很自然地认为,这一切的结果将是一本冷漠或难以接近的书;超出了我们这些通常不在康德的水域里游泳的人所能触及或关注的范围。形容这本书再合适不过了。在戈麦斯的笔下,康德式和笛卡尔式的宏大计划找到了一种可追溯的冷静呈现;从康德和其他历史人物的选择举动给出了清晰和不受影响的解释;活跃的康德概念和论证工具的部署方式摆脱了对康德框架中更神秘的方面的依赖;激烈的争论标准使得这本书读起来特别令人兴奋——每一页都让人觉得有什么东西值得上蹿下跳。在书中许多值得讨论的观点中,我的回应将集中在书中第一个积极的转变——信仰一章(第4章)中的一个论点,在这个论点中,戈麦斯认为,我们有一个独特的实际理由来同意我们是自己思想的代理人的说法。在接下来的内容中,我将首先列出这个论点在书中出现的背景,然后我将列出这个论点本身,最后我将为它提出一些关键问题。首先,要做一些舞台布置。为了继续他的项目,从自我意识思想家的可用资源转移到建立一个客观存在的世界,戈麦斯必须解决利希滕贝格的抱怨,即自我意识思想家最多可以假设的是“有思考”,在“有闪电”的模型上;“我们应该说这是在思考,就像我们说这是闪电一样。当一个人把它翻译成我在思考的时候,说“我在思考”已经太多了。(Lichtenberg K76,引自《Gomes》第131页)。在第三章中,他对李希滕贝格进行了深入而深刻的讨论,并对如何应对这一挑战提出了独到的见解:我们必须提供理由,将自己视为自己思想的代理人。仅仅表明思想发生在一个统一的位置——一个自我——是不够的——尽管如此,思想可能仍然只是像闪电一样击中那个统一的自我。不,要回答李希滕伯格的问题,我们必须提出理由来证明我们不仅是思想的统一位点,而且是思想的代理人。这个要求有两个版本:我们必须证明,我们可以使我们自己作为精神能动者的观念对我们自己来说是可理解的;我们必须证明,我们在认识论上有权这样认为自己。这第二个版本的需求将在接下来的内容中发挥重要作用。当他读到第四章的时候,戈麦斯已经证明了这个要求既不能通过经验也不能通过先天的概念掌握来满足;正如他所说,“我们作为代理人的身份不会在我们对世界的体验中显现出来。”我们可能只是我们所有思想的被动接受者这一观点在概念上并没有什么不连贯的地方。”(第102页)然后呢?他的回答是:信仰,康德意义上的实践同意。有一些主张,其理念是,我们实际上必须同意,因为它们以我们必须为自己设定的目标的可达性为前提。我们最终采取的态度不是信仰的态度——或者至少,只要我们认为信仰是一种基于某些理论证明的证据,旨在实现给定事物真理的状态,我们就不会这样认为;"如果信仰与真理的目的在本质上是联系在一起的这样一来,只有考虑到一个主张的真实性才算相信这个主张,那么基于实践的同意就不能成为信仰的一种形式。”(p.111)。相反,我们最终采取的态度是一种特立独行的<s:1> rwahrhalten,即坚持为真,我们采取这种态度是出于特殊的实际原因。 戈麦斯给我们提供的最接近的民间心理对应是接受一种说法,我们这样做可能是出于实际原因,而不是直接反映出认为它是正确的理论依据。戈麦斯在这里所说的论证并不是先验论证——事实上,实践同意状态的理性推导在本章中与先验论证提供的策略进行了明确的对比。然而,我发现,把这两种论证形式看作是具有某种共同的总体轮廓是有用的。先验论证开始于一个各方都倾向于同意的主张,然后确定这个开始主张的实质性前提,而这个前提是一方最初想要否认的。因此,论证的辩证力量表明,只要对话者想要坚持已被接受的开始主张,她就已经预先承诺了争论中的非常实质性的主张。这种论证形式的实际版本是这样的:它从一个每个人都必须为自己设定的目标开始,然后确定一个实质性的主张,这个主张以该目标的可达性为先决条件。既然我们只能为自己设定我们认为可以实现的目标(不考虑各种警告),那么为自己设定目标的实际要求就会通过封闭而延续为接受其可实现性的实质性先决条件的实际要求。因此,在先验论证的情况下,辩证的力量在这里不是被设计来移动一个怀疑论者,或以它自己的条件为实质主张提供证明。这是为了向对话者证明她一定已经预先承诺了这个主张,考虑到它在实现一个目标时的条件作用,因为她必须接受这个目标。正如戈麦斯所说,如果设定一个目标的条件是我们认为它是可以实现的我们被要求同意任何一个要求这是一个要求的目标的可实现性的条件,那么当一个要求是一个我们被要求设定的目标的可实现性的条件时,这个要求实际上是必要的。”(p.115)。从这里开始,争论进行得相对较快。如果我们被要求以解决关于我们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题为目的,那么我们必须认为我们有可能这样做。否则,戈麦斯认为,我们为自己设定目标是不理性的。(类似的事情肯定是合理的:我不能理性地给自己设定一个同时出现在七个地方的结局,因为我认为这不是我能做到的。)但是,如果我有可能解决这些问题——请注意,这是一项积极的事业——那么我必须是我的思想的代理人,也就是说,至少我的一些思想必须在我的代理之下。在这里,我们到达了利希滕伯格理论的极限。实际上,我被要求对自己的精神能动性有信心,因为它以我必须为自己设定的目标的可达性为先决条件——也就是说,解决有关构成我对世界的看法的第一阶信念和经验的质量或适当性的问题。关于这个论点的最后一点观察。前提一非常有力。这不仅是我们碰巧拥有,或倾向于拥有,或通常拥有的结局;这是我们自觉的思想家必须拥有的目标。更重要的是,Gomes清楚地表明,这个要求的模态力量是在绝对命令的附近(或者可能只是)。例如,这不足以作为我们发现自己作为认知进化生物学的偶然事件而背负的一个结局。它必须是一个我们必须拥有的目标,作为一种必然性,以一种从我们作为自我意识思想家的本性中流出的方式。为什么这么坚强?为了避免被指责为一厢情愿。如果我们把这个前提中的目的替换成我们每个人碰巧拥有的任何目的,那么这个论证形式就会使一种我们认为合适的认知权利的引导合法化。例如,假设我恰好在三个月内学完了日语;为了达到这个目标,我实际上必须承认我是学习语言的能手。但是,当然,这只不过是一厢情愿的想法——一种理性破产的推理形式,戈麦斯需要与任何为他提供反利希滕伯格理由的推理形式保持距离。他避免这个陷阱的方法是,把问题中的目标强化为一个我们不是简单地选择,而是我们必须自己设定的目标。 这是赋予这种形式的推理某种稳定性或反偶然性的部分原因,从而避免其崩溃为一厢情愿的局部实例。我认为,这个论点有些诱人之处。当然,我们容易接受某些主张是对的,不是因为我们找到了有利于它们的证据,而是因为没有它们,我们就无法理解我们正在做的事情或我们试图做的事情。更重要的是,我们肯定是正确的,因为这样的理由接受这样的主张:这并不意味着不小心或漫不经心,而是表明了一种认知上成熟的常识精神——我们必须接受这些主张,否则我们将无法继续进行其他任何事情。这个论点的有趣之处在于,它并没有仅仅把问题放在那里,它指出了一种很少被注意到,但在心理上是合理的,在动机上是可理解的独特态度,我们有时会出于实际原因对主张持这种态度。这个论点进一步阐明了我们对这些主张的认识论权利,说明了为什么在认识论上有充分的根据,以这样的理由持有这样的态度。对于戈麦斯来说,这是应对利希滕伯格挑战所需要的一部分。但更广泛地说,这是一个诱人的目标,因为如果我们能正确地以认识论为基础,实践同意的态度,也许这是一个可以被纳入主流心灵哲学和认识论的概念,作为一种帮助描述心灵部分的方式,这些部分不太符合更传统的信仰真理态度或(以证据为基础的)知识。我认为,所讨论的权利源于我们必须在前提一中将自己设定为所讨论的目的这一要求的力量(不管它是什么),这一要求通过结束,通过假定的目的可实现性的临时步骤,延续到一个实质性的主张,即条件的可实现性。我们有权接受最终的主张,无论在何种程度上,以何种方式,我们最初有权为自己设定这个目的,正如我们所看到的,这是一个我们必须为自己设定的目的,所以(这个想法可能是)当然有资格这样做。我们还可以回想一下这一必然性主张的理论意义:戈麦斯将第一个前提中提到的目标强化为我们必须为自己设定的目标,而不是着眼于我们碰巧为自己设定的那些杂乱无章的个人目标,从而避免了他的论证坍塌为一厢情愿的宪章。所以理解权利的关键在于它存在于好情况中,而不是局限于一厢情愿的想法中,这与强化第一个前提有关即确定一个必要的目的而不仅仅是偶然的目的。对于这一策略,我们首先要担心的是:有一种反悲剧的假设引导着这一强化举措,(具有讽刺意味的是),这一举措本身就是一种一厢情愿的想法。为什么认为不可能有一个我们都必须为自己设定的目标,而我们甚至认为这是不可能实现的呢?在我进一步追问这个问题之前,先做一个简短的澄清。至少有两种解读关键动词“安顿”的方式,它在这个要求的结尾中表现出来,自然地被解读为暗示不同程度的要求。它可以被理解为进行时,作为我们必须在做的事情,或者它可以被理解为一个成就动词,作为我们必须成功完成的任务。关于我们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题的最终解决的可达成性,从第一种角度来看,是更合理的,这就是我的解读方式,也就是说,我们没有内在的承诺去解决我们的问题,只有我们的承诺去解决它们。我现在的问题是:从偶然的目的到必然的目的的转变,究竟是什么使这个目的免受事实上无法实现的可能性的影响,以及我们对任何似乎可以使其实现的主张的承诺,只不过是一厢情愿的想法?(这里有一个有益的比较是蒙田的论点,即对上帝的信仰是普遍的——没有临终的无神论者——但正是因为这个原因,信仰在心理上是肤浅的,因为动机不恰当。5)另一种提出挑战的方式是,在加强行动的基础上有一个必须意味着可以的原则——但我们没有解释为什么这是一个我们应该接受的原则。也许答案将来自于设置结尾必要性的情态力量、性质和来源的细节。 这里我就不讨论这个选项了,因为我不太确定如何填充这部分图片。对戈麦斯来说,为自己设定这一目标的要求来自于这样一种观察,即自我意识判断往往出现在telic认知活动的延伸背景中,这些活动都可以在解决有关我们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题这一更广泛的目标下得到恰当的描述。但是,这仍然给我们留下了关于产生需求的力量、来源和性质的悬而未决的问题。我究竟应该在什么意义上给自己设定这个目标,因为事实上我似乎在许多情况下都是这样做的?在什么意义上模态主张是从描述性的推导出来的,它产生了什么样的要求?如果没有办法填补这一部分,情况可能会因走强而变得比最初看起来更糟。不仅不清楚为什么以及是否从偶然到必要的目的的转变会产生实践同意的态度,Gomes需要让它发挥理论作用,它在他的论点中确实如此。令我震惊的是,假设一个需要的目的的举动,恰恰削弱了我们对它的理性责任,也削弱了由此产生的任何态度的认识论凭据——从而使由此产生的态度不太可能免受一厢情愿的指责。毕竟,如果我从众多选择中选择一个目标,我将在三个月内学会日语!-在提交之前检查结果的可达性是我义不容辞的责任,如果这些检查不够健全,我可以合理地受到批评。这些支票支持了Gomes在上述论证中的步骤1和步骤2之间的移动——从设置结局到其隐含的感知可达性;如果我不认为它是可以实现的,我就不会理性地设定结局。与此形成对比的是,我发现自己有一个目标,因为这是我必须拥有的目标。我对检查其可达性的尽职调查现在似乎既不在这里也不在那里。这是我必须达到的目标,不管我认为它有多容易实现。举例来说:假设我发现自己面临着一个被迫的选择,要么爬下一座无法攀登的山,要么肯定会立即死亡在这里真的没有选择——我只能给无法实现的尝试。我这样做是理性的批评吗?我强烈的直觉告诉我,我不是。如果这是正确的,那么在这些情况下——在这些情况下,结局不是本地选择的,而是以某种方式要求我们的——我们有理由重新审视上文戈麦斯论证中从1到2的转变。换句话说,我们假定一个必要的目的,这一事实,根据理性的标准,不再意味着我们认为它是可以达到的。假设我是对的,正如戈麦斯所希望的那样,加强行动不会自动使他的论点免受一厢情愿的指责。这并不能解决问题,而只会重新提出这样一个问题:他所确定的目的是否属于我们(必须)自己设定的目的,如果是的话,这是否是一个我们认为可以实现的目的。也许他仍然可以得到他想要的——也就是说,在认识论上有权同意我们自己的精神能动性——如果事实证明,被识别的目的显然是可以实现的,即使把这个目的变成必要的这一举动本身并没有排除它不可能实现的可能性。我现在的问题是:我们是否有独立的理由认为,戈麦斯所确定的目标——解决有关我们看待世界的角度是否恰当的问题——实际上是我们这种有自我意识的思想家为自己设定的目标?我认为,我们有过度理智的理由怀疑它不是——或者,至少,它不适合我们这种有自我意识的思想家。要明白这一点,请注意,戈麦斯正在邀请我们采取第三阶心理态度。第一级是构成一个人对世界的看法的信念和经验。第二种是我们对第一阶信念和经验的评价立场。戈麦斯的建议是,我们提升了另一个层次,在这个层次上,我们把自己置于参与这种二级评估性心理活动的终点。这当然是我们中的一些人在心态合适的时候可以做的事情——比如在会议室里,或者在沉思的时候。当戈麦斯说这就是笛卡尔的询问者所要做的事情时,他当然是对的。我甚至认为我们中的一些人可能会倾向于这样做——尤其是那些对世界的看法经常受到挑战的人。但我们所有人都能做到吗?孩子吗?智力贫乏或认知能力下降吗?当然,对于所有具有自我意识的思考者来说,答案都是肯定的,这并不明显。 反思我们自己第一阶思想和经验的能力(概念上保证所有自我意识的思考者)并不自动意味着反思第三阶二阶能力的能力。当然,我们能否做到这一点的问题在很大程度上取决于我们怎样才能算做到了。Gomes明确指出,在康德的意义上,结局的设定涉及到对结局的积极意愿,或者决定追求它,所以它所需要的部分是一种发生的心理事件,即对特定内容的结局的意愿(而不是更倾向于某种东西)。他说,作为我们意志对象的目的是我们已经决定的目的,是我们要的,而不仅仅是希望的。(第91页)如果这真的是必须的,这是一个很高的门槛;就我自己而言,我不确定我是否曾经积极地想要达到这个目的,尽管反思自己的观点是我经常做的事情。同样地,在戈麦斯看来,假定的目标的可达性是一个必须得到积极赞同的观点——自然地被解读为一种关于其可达性的有趣想法——而不仅仅是对其不可达性缺乏赞同。再一次,在我看来,这是相当多的要求。我也会问自己,我们要多久结束一次。一生一次?我们必须偶尔重申一下吗?在第二阶段,多少尝试的评价活动足以达到目的?虽然这些都是我对戈麦斯的论点应该如何运作的真实问题,但我不怀疑会有办法回答这些问题,使设想的结局心理学更适合我们这种有限的自我意识思考者。然而,即使假定可以作出这样的调整,还有另一种问题在背后徘徊,这是一个规范性的问题:这是我们应该为自己设定的目标吗?这是我们希望我们自己或我们所爱的人得到的吗?让我们再看一遍这些层次:我们花了很多时间在第一阶,沉浸在关于世界的信念和经验中,与其他第一阶态度一起。毫无疑问,这对我们的功能是有益的,我们有能力关注这个世界的第一阶视角的质量,至少,我们有能力对它采取更高阶的评估立场。但是,除非在某些特殊情况下- -例如,除非我们以激进怀疑的方法进行探索性练习- -过于坚决地停留在第二层次似乎对我们的功能并没有特别有益。Second-order-Sam。山姆和我们一样对世界有自己的看法。她认为正在下雨,特朗普是当前地缘政治稳定的最大威胁,猫比狗更适合当宠物。她的感官系统运转良好,对周围环境的体验也很好。然而,山姆的特别之处在于,她非常重视自己的二级评价态度。她的头脑中很少有第一阶的想法或对世界的体验,但她会迅速进入第二阶,以回顾这是否是一件值得思考的事情,或者是一种值得拥有的体验。我们觉得山姆怎么样?我认为说这描述了一组不太理想的心理事实并不夸张:山姆给人的印象是有点神经质,有点自我疏远,可能精疲力竭。现在假设她来找我们寻求建议——她想知道应该如何组织自己的精神生活。假设我们不是像任何好的正念应用程序那样鼓励她花更多的时间停留在第一阶,而是敦促她上升到另一个层次。我们告诉她:她如此重视对一阶状态的二阶评价是件好事,而且她应该把二阶评价活动的表现作为自己的目的。我想大家都同意,这是个糟糕的建议。总的教训是,即使我们有能力进行二阶评价性心理活动这一事实似乎是我们心理的一个很好的特征,但这与认为我们明确地将自己置于参与二阶活动的目的是好的想法相去很远。现在,当然,有一些方法可以软化戈麦斯的结局设定所涉及的充实的故事,而不必让他陷入这种讽刺的境地。他的建议当然不是说我们总是占据第三层次的视角,也不是说我们设定的目标总是解决第二层的问题。 二阶山姆的例子并不是说反思我们的想法和经历总是不好的,只是反思太多是不好的,也许这可以通过在戈麦斯假设的目的中解读一个默认的比例限定词来解决——也许目的有时是,或者在适当的时候解决关于我们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题。或者一旦我们有了更多关于这个要求的力量、性质和来源的信息,这个问题就会得到解决。问题是,到目前为止,在我看来,我们已经有了从奥运会上得到的所有材料来解释我们所需要的一切,而不需要诉诸任何类似于要求我们为自己设定——积极地意志——关于我们的二级心理活动的某种目的的主张。也就是说,这种二级活动实际上是我们这些有自我意识的生物有时会做的事情;我们有时这样做是一件好事。如果我们把东西留在那里,会失去什么?让我总结一下我们到哪里了。在戈麦斯的论证中有一些很诱人的东西他让我们从我们自己的精神代理中推导出一种特殊的认识论上被称为实践的同意,从假设的实践要求中我们每个人都在为解决关于我们对世界的看法是否恰当的问题而设定自己的目标。在戈麦斯自己的项目背景下,这是诱人的——这是他需要消除利希滕伯格式担忧的东西——但也有一个更广阔的前景,即将描绘出一种独特的、在认识论上有充分基础的实践同意态度,我们可能会在我们关于我们的思想的哲学理论中找到其他用途。我对这个论点提出了一些挑战:具体地说,我质疑目的的必要性是否使它免受一厢情愿的指责,并给出了一些理由来抵制这样一种观点,即这个目的确实是我们所做的或必须为自己设定的——至少,在这个目的被戈麦斯用强烈的术语解释的地方。尽管如此,我还是发现,在认识论上有充分基础的实践同意的态度这个概念中,有一些令人信服的东西,值得一看,如果我们能站稳脚跟的话。我想以两种可能让我们保留这一概念的两种前进方式的速写来结束我的演讲,从Gomes提供的一些更强烈的康德主义的方面中解脱出来。首先是将实践同意态度的理性地位与任何对积极认知地位的主张分开。他们的态度仍然是理性回应——只是被回应的理性是实践性的,而不是理论性或证据性的。这将是一个让步的进步,这将是放弃我们有任何特殊的认知权利来认为这些主张是正确的想法。但我们这样做是理性的,这并非一无是处。我们理性地接受这样的主张可能足以满足我们的直觉,即我们在接受这些主张时并非在认识论上鲁莽或不负责任。但这不足以证明他们的认识论比审慎证明的认识论更有根据,包括那些对我们心理上有益的主张,在这一点上,我们可能会担心,我们已经打破了我们想要坚持的观点,即有一种独特的实践同意,可以与一厢情愿的想法或审慎有益的接受分开。对于那些有这种担忧的人来说,第二个选择将是坚持认为,实际的同意不仅仅是一种理性的态度。在其合理性之上,这种态度是一种具有积极认知地位的态度——我们有积极的资格认为这些主张是正确的。在某种程度上,这是一个更自然的立场;我可能会对一些符合理性规范的主张采取一种坚持为真的态度,但我在认识论上没有资格这样做,这让我感到不舒服。(在这里我是对的还是错的?)当然,我们从哪里得到这第二张草图的认识论权利是一个大问题。正如戈麦斯向我们展示的那样,不可能从我们熟悉的理论论证来源——把这种独特的实践态度变成完全不同的东西。我自己的(不是很康德的)倾向于转向美德认识论框架,这使得将理性规范和认识论的基础问题分开变得更加困难。我们可以说,这些是一个有道德的认知主体在这种情况下所持的态度,或者说,它们是主体功能良好的智力特征的产物。 但无论戈麦斯是否会被这个选择所吸引,在我看来,如果他能正确地抵御利希滕伯格式的挑战,即我们缺乏将自己视为自己思维代理人的权利,那么关于认知权利如何进入这一问题是一个需要回答的大问题。这不是一个我在《实际的自我》中找到答案的问题。但我认为,这是一个极其诱人的问题,正是这本书的核心所在。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
11.10%
发文量
82
期刊介绍: ''Founded by Mark Sacks in 1993, the European Journal of Philosophy has come to occupy a distinctive and highly valued place amongst the philosophical journals. The aim of EJP has been to bring together the best work from those working within the "analytic" and "continental" traditions, and to encourage connections between them, without diluting their respective priorities and concerns. This has enabled EJP to publish a wide range of material of the highest standard from philosophers across the world, reflecting the best thinking from a variety of philosophical perspectives, in a way that is accessible to all of them.''
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信