Anil Gomes's The Practical Self

IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Bill Brewer
{"title":"Anil Gomes's The Practical Self","authors":"Bill Brewer","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13021","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Gomes's rich and compelling book revolves around an extended line of argument for the thesis that a self-conscious subject must be one object amongst many in an objective world: self-consciousness entails objectivity. Others have offered arguments for the same conclusion; but, in contrast with his own, Gomes finds all of these wanting. After setting out my own understanding of Gomes's central argument, I will raise a series of concerns about each of its key moves.</p><p>This is an original and significant line of argument. In what follows, I raise five critical questions about it: two each about premises 1 and 2, and one about premise 3. I develop two of these in detail, into fully-formed objections to Gomes's argument; the others I leave almost to fend for themselves against his case for the thesis that self-consciousness entails objectivity.\n </p><p>By way of clarification of the content of premise 1, Gomes contrasts the <i>cognitive agency</i> in question with a corresponding <i>passivity</i> in <i>perception</i>. Here is what I think he means in the perceptual case. We select and initiate projects, like counting the stripes on a zebra, discerning which chair seat is closest in colour to the carpet, and so on. We focus and modulate our attention appropriately over time in order to execute them as best we can, checking and going back if necessary as we proceed. But which specific experiences and beliefs we find ourselves with at the end of the day is entirely outside of our control; <i>and so it should be</i>, if the result is to be determined by how things really are rather than by our own preferences and prejudices. We set the question and direct our attention and capacities to pursue it; the facts settle the answer.</p><p>Isn't it just the same with paradigmatically intellectual projects too, though, such as counting the primes between 0 and 100, or working out how best to accommodate all a child's friends at a sleepover without provoking too much over-excitement or antagonism, and so on? We pursue the project and keep our attention on the relevant considerations, taking each stage in turn, checking and going back if necessary as we proceed. But, again, which beliefs we find ourselves with at the end of the day is entirely outside of our control; <i>and so it should be</i> if the result is to be determined by how things really are rather than by our own preferences and prejudices. Just as in the case of perception, we set the question and direct our attention and capacities to pursue it; the facts settle the answer.</p><p>Perceptually: ‘is there a dark blue chair in the room? … ‘yes'; and, analogously, intellectually: ‘is there a prime between 37 and 43?’ … ‘yes'. Realism about the domain of enquiry in both cases surely legislates in favour of our ultimate passivity with respect to the outcome. So it is unclear to me precisely what the cognitive activity that Gomes is interested in comes to. Certainly, the comparison with perception suggests similarity rather than difference in this respect.</p><p>At points, Gomes suggests that the demand for cognitive agency, and our acceptance of it, stems from our ongoing commitment to revise and adjust our perspective on the world in the light of new evidence, or simply in the light of reconsideration by reflecting on the propriety of our current views. But, again, it seems to me misleading to suggest that this involves anything like an active intervention directly on those views themselves, moving our beliefs around as we might rearrange our furniture, as it were. Rather, it's a matter of recommitting ourselves to attending carefully and systematically to all the considerations, perceptual or intellectual, that are pertinent to having our beliefs either reconfirmed or revised <i>in the light of the facts</i>, in a way that is once again ultimately outside our control and settled by reality rather than by us.</p><p>I do not say there aren't many and various interesting differences between perceiving and thinking; but I don't find the contrast specifically illuminating in elaborating what Gomes takes to be our crucial cognitive agency as self-conscious beings. The direct objection arising out of Q1, then, is that Anil's relatively passing appeal to a contrast with the passivity of perception is insufficient as it stands to elaborate the target notion of cognitive agency. A more general challenge is for Anil to specify more precisely what it is that the first premise of his central argument asserts any self-conscious subject must accept about the acquisition and maintenance of their beliefs, either by developing the contrast between reasoning and perceiving further, or in some other way.\n </p><p>Here I have a relatively cheap point, but still one worth making, I think.</p><p>Given the difficulties we have just seen in formulating precisely the notion of cognitive agency that is supposed to be necessary for self-consciousness, it is surely correspondingly implausible to insist that every self-conscious subject must, simply as such, accept, understand, or know that they are a cognitive agent in just this sense. Of course, this raises the question precisely how intellectually demanding <i>acceptance</i> of cognitive agency is supposed to be. On the assumption suggested by my reading of Gomes's discussion at least, that this requires grasp of the proposition involved in asserting the cognitive agency in question, then the cheap point surely stands as a further challenge to the first premise of Anil's main argument for the thesis that self-consciousness entails objectivity.\n </p><p>If I am, as Gomes insists, an agent in working out how best to accommodate all a child's friends at a sleepover, say, then I take it that that is something that I am doing intentionally, and so something that I know that I am doing in the way in which I generally know what I am doing intentionally. I certainly don't have a worked-out account of such knowledge in intention. But it is a widely accepted phenomenon. And why is it not the source of my acceptance of my cognitive agency whenever I am actively thinking in the relevant sense?</p><p>Perhaps Gomes distinguishes specific such knowledge, in any particular case of our exercise of cognitive agency, from the acceptance that he is primarily concerned with, namely, that I am, quite generally, the agent of my thinking. But even acknowledging that distinction, it might be replied that any such general acceptance we arrive at is derived from the more specific individual instances that we have through our knowledge in intention in specific cases. So, without an independent objection to that route, the critical point remains.\n </p><p>As I understand it, Gomes's argument here is this.\n </p><p>I can see reasons to doubt both substantive premises: (F2) &amp; (F3).</p><p>Against F2, we can surely take on projects that we do not explicitly accept as attainable (by me/us, here, now, in this way,…?) at all. Even the weaker claim that taking on a project depends upon not regarding it as absolutely unattainable may be too strong in certain cases. Crash-landing into the sea in an aeroplane, for example, I may commit myself to the project of swimming to safety on a distant, just-visible island, however unattainable I take my successfully reaching safety to be. In any case, the gap between taking on a project and positively accepting it as attainable surely increases the more extended, demanding, and complex the project in question happens to be. Examples that help to make the point might be solving the P vs NP problem; or arriving at a stable solution to the Middle East Crisis. In such cases, the subject may well embark on an extended, complex, and extremely demanding enterprise without accepting its attainability, by them, or even by anyone, and certainly not necessarily its attainability by them in the way they are going about it. Still, this is the project they take on. So extended complex cases of this kind constitute counterexamples to Anil's F2.</p><p>A first reply might be to attempt to close the gap between taking on such projects and the subject's acceptance of their attainability by insisting that the project in question in such cases is only ever to <i>try</i> – to solve the P vs NP problem; or to arrive at a stable solution to the Middle East Crisis – and trying may well be something that the subject accepts is attainable. But this strikes me as forced. Trying just <i>is</i> taking on the project itself – of actually solving the P vs NP problem, or of actually arriving at a stable solution to the Middle East crisis and doing everything possible to attain it, whether or not this is eventually successful. So, the gap remains, especially, as I say, in such extended and complex cases.</p><p>In the light of cases of this kind, a second reply would be to insist that premise F2 is supposed to apply only to brief, simple projects, and so only to each of a series of successive manageable sub-projects of any more complex and extended overall project of the kind we have been considering. It is not obvious to me why we should accept F2 even in this qualified form; but in order to set out all the pieces of my challenge to Gomes's case for the claim that self-conscious thinking depends upon faith in cognitive agency, I turn instead at this point to consider F3.</p><p>Given that cognitive agency is understood as what is involved in self-conscious thinking but absent in perceiving, and that we often accept that the ends of perceptual projects are attainable, accepting that the ends of such projects are attainable cannot in general require our acceptance of our agency in the relevant sense. Suppose I set myself the project of discerning the colour of the eyes of the person in front of me. In suitable circumstances, of good lighting, of the person being close enough to me with eyes wide open, and so on, I may surely accept that this is attainable. Yet, since the project is purely perceptual, it involves no cognitive agency of the kind that Gomes is concerned with. Hence my taking it on cannot involve any acceptance of such cognitive agency – at least on the assumption that I have been working with throughout, following Gomes, that such acceptance is factive. This case therefore constitutes a counterexample to the general claim a subject's accepting that the end of a project they take on is attainable depends upon their accepting their cognitive agency in doing so.</p><p>The critical point here is especially clear with respect to the simple component sub-projects of any more extended and complex task, where the analogy between cases of thinking and perceiving is stronger. That's to say, it <i>may</i> be that a subject's accepting that some complex project is attainable involves commitment to the idea that they have some control over the order and initiation of the various sub-projects that will, all being well, eventually accomplish it. But, in relation to its individual simple sub-projects, their commitment to their attainability seems to presuppose little more than the conviction that, if they direct their attention to these in the right way, the correct answer will be forthcoming, and will arrive out of their control, determined by the relevant facts rather than by their own preferences and prejudices, as it should be.</p><p>It may be objected to this discussion that it depends upon something like an early modern conception of <i>demonstration</i>, in the sense of extended, directed reasoning, as an appropriate sequence of <i>intuitions</i>, in the sense of simple intellectual perceptions. It does indeed depend on a conception of thinking along these lines, with the distinction between extended complex projects and their manageable simple sub-projects. But, first, this early modern distinction between simple intuition, and extended complex demonstration, in these senses, seems to me independently defensible, although it may be applicable only relative to an individual subject on a given occasion of reasoning. Second, and more importantly for present purposes, the basic distinction has been introduced precisely to make the best possible case individually for each of Gomes's F2 and F3. The fundamental problem for his overall argument for the claim that self-conscious thinking depends upon faith in cognitive agency is that this evidently rests on an equivocation as a result.</p><p>For atomic sub-tasks, premise F2 <i>may</i> be correct; but premise F3 is surely false. Our taking them on may presuppose acceptance that they are at least <i>likely</i> to come off: we <i>will</i> find ourselves with a conviction one way or another settling the question at hand. But such acceptance involves no commitment to our agency in respect of that specific outcome. Indeed, it is more likely to involve recognition that the answer will just come to us.</p><p>For complex extended projects composed of multiple such components, on the other hand, premise F2 is surely false. We can, and do, take on many such ambitious projects without antecedently accepting that they are attainable (by us, here, now, in this way, at all, …?). Furthermore, the only acceptance of agency required by acceptance of attainability is that equally involved in extended perceptual tasks that are precisely the contrast with cases of active thinking that Gomes aims to establish: acceptance, that is to say, that we have some control over the order and initiation of their various component sub-activities.</p><p>So, although there may be <i>some</i> projects for which both F2 and F3 are true, they are not both true for all projects in which we aim to settle some specific question in the light of the relevant considerations for and against, as Gomes's argument requires. His argument for the claim that self-conscious thinking depends upon faith in cognitive agency is therefore invalid.</p><p>These reflections, and those under my first question above – whether self-consciousness really requires cognitive agency in Gomes's sense at all – suggest that the problem may lie in his attempt to articulate the cognitive agency he is interested in by <i>contrast</i> with perception. Perhaps the point is just that, in both cases, we actively select the questions we pose, and pursue them by attending in perception and in thought to the relevant considerations by which they are passively settled, in successful cases, by the facts. It is far from clear that any of this requires an acceptance of our agency in this regard that can only be based upon faith in the way Gomes suggests, though.\n </p><p>The alternative, that Gomes apparently leaves entirely open, is that faith in cognitive agency, <i>in those self-conscious beings who are related to an objective world of other thinkers</i>, may in some cases be sustained by their interpersonal practices of holding each other accountable for their thinking. That he does indeed endorse something close to this view himself is suggested by his characterization of objective engagement as ‘central’, although not strictly necessary, for the faith in cognitive agency that he argues is in turn essential to self-consciousness. In that case, any relation to an objective world to be derived from a thinker's being self-conscious is that assumed from the start in regarding them as de facto situated in an interpersonal world of other such thinkers whom they hold accountable, and who hold them accountable, for their thinking.</p><p>Gomes is scrupulous in subjecting others' arguments from self-consciousness to objectivity to rigorous objection. Yet, if this understanding of his account is accurate, then his own argument is simply invalid. A self-conscious thinker <i>may</i> in principle have faith in their cognitive agency unsustained by any engagement with an objective world of other thinkers, which constitutes a direct counterexample to the final stage of that argument. So, by the standards he applies to others, his own case is also wanting.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"33 2","pages":"757-761"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2025-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13021","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13021","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Gomes's rich and compelling book revolves around an extended line of argument for the thesis that a self-conscious subject must be one object amongst many in an objective world: self-consciousness entails objectivity. Others have offered arguments for the same conclusion; but, in contrast with his own, Gomes finds all of these wanting. After setting out my own understanding of Gomes's central argument, I will raise a series of concerns about each of its key moves.

This is an original and significant line of argument. In what follows, I raise five critical questions about it: two each about premises 1 and 2, and one about premise 3. I develop two of these in detail, into fully-formed objections to Gomes's argument; the others I leave almost to fend for themselves against his case for the thesis that self-consciousness entails objectivity.

By way of clarification of the content of premise 1, Gomes contrasts the cognitive agency in question with a corresponding passivity in perception. Here is what I think he means in the perceptual case. We select and initiate projects, like counting the stripes on a zebra, discerning which chair seat is closest in colour to the carpet, and so on. We focus and modulate our attention appropriately over time in order to execute them as best we can, checking and going back if necessary as we proceed. But which specific experiences and beliefs we find ourselves with at the end of the day is entirely outside of our control; and so it should be, if the result is to be determined by how things really are rather than by our own preferences and prejudices. We set the question and direct our attention and capacities to pursue it; the facts settle the answer.

Isn't it just the same with paradigmatically intellectual projects too, though, such as counting the primes between 0 and 100, or working out how best to accommodate all a child's friends at a sleepover without provoking too much over-excitement or antagonism, and so on? We pursue the project and keep our attention on the relevant considerations, taking each stage in turn, checking and going back if necessary as we proceed. But, again, which beliefs we find ourselves with at the end of the day is entirely outside of our control; and so it should be if the result is to be determined by how things really are rather than by our own preferences and prejudices. Just as in the case of perception, we set the question and direct our attention and capacities to pursue it; the facts settle the answer.

Perceptually: ‘is there a dark blue chair in the room? … ‘yes'; and, analogously, intellectually: ‘is there a prime between 37 and 43?’ … ‘yes'. Realism about the domain of enquiry in both cases surely legislates in favour of our ultimate passivity with respect to the outcome. So it is unclear to me precisely what the cognitive activity that Gomes is interested in comes to. Certainly, the comparison with perception suggests similarity rather than difference in this respect.

At points, Gomes suggests that the demand for cognitive agency, and our acceptance of it, stems from our ongoing commitment to revise and adjust our perspective on the world in the light of new evidence, or simply in the light of reconsideration by reflecting on the propriety of our current views. But, again, it seems to me misleading to suggest that this involves anything like an active intervention directly on those views themselves, moving our beliefs around as we might rearrange our furniture, as it were. Rather, it's a matter of recommitting ourselves to attending carefully and systematically to all the considerations, perceptual or intellectual, that are pertinent to having our beliefs either reconfirmed or revised in the light of the facts, in a way that is once again ultimately outside our control and settled by reality rather than by us.

I do not say there aren't many and various interesting differences between perceiving and thinking; but I don't find the contrast specifically illuminating in elaborating what Gomes takes to be our crucial cognitive agency as self-conscious beings. The direct objection arising out of Q1, then, is that Anil's relatively passing appeal to a contrast with the passivity of perception is insufficient as it stands to elaborate the target notion of cognitive agency. A more general challenge is for Anil to specify more precisely what it is that the first premise of his central argument asserts any self-conscious subject must accept about the acquisition and maintenance of their beliefs, either by developing the contrast between reasoning and perceiving further, or in some other way.

Here I have a relatively cheap point, but still one worth making, I think.

Given the difficulties we have just seen in formulating precisely the notion of cognitive agency that is supposed to be necessary for self-consciousness, it is surely correspondingly implausible to insist that every self-conscious subject must, simply as such, accept, understand, or know that they are a cognitive agent in just this sense. Of course, this raises the question precisely how intellectually demanding acceptance of cognitive agency is supposed to be. On the assumption suggested by my reading of Gomes's discussion at least, that this requires grasp of the proposition involved in asserting the cognitive agency in question, then the cheap point surely stands as a further challenge to the first premise of Anil's main argument for the thesis that self-consciousness entails objectivity.

If I am, as Gomes insists, an agent in working out how best to accommodate all a child's friends at a sleepover, say, then I take it that that is something that I am doing intentionally, and so something that I know that I am doing in the way in which I generally know what I am doing intentionally. I certainly don't have a worked-out account of such knowledge in intention. But it is a widely accepted phenomenon. And why is it not the source of my acceptance of my cognitive agency whenever I am actively thinking in the relevant sense?

Perhaps Gomes distinguishes specific such knowledge, in any particular case of our exercise of cognitive agency, from the acceptance that he is primarily concerned with, namely, that I am, quite generally, the agent of my thinking. But even acknowledging that distinction, it might be replied that any such general acceptance we arrive at is derived from the more specific individual instances that we have through our knowledge in intention in specific cases. So, without an independent objection to that route, the critical point remains.

As I understand it, Gomes's argument here is this.

I can see reasons to doubt both substantive premises: (F2) & (F3).

Against F2, we can surely take on projects that we do not explicitly accept as attainable (by me/us, here, now, in this way,…?) at all. Even the weaker claim that taking on a project depends upon not regarding it as absolutely unattainable may be too strong in certain cases. Crash-landing into the sea in an aeroplane, for example, I may commit myself to the project of swimming to safety on a distant, just-visible island, however unattainable I take my successfully reaching safety to be. In any case, the gap between taking on a project and positively accepting it as attainable surely increases the more extended, demanding, and complex the project in question happens to be. Examples that help to make the point might be solving the P vs NP problem; or arriving at a stable solution to the Middle East Crisis. In such cases, the subject may well embark on an extended, complex, and extremely demanding enterprise without accepting its attainability, by them, or even by anyone, and certainly not necessarily its attainability by them in the way they are going about it. Still, this is the project they take on. So extended complex cases of this kind constitute counterexamples to Anil's F2.

A first reply might be to attempt to close the gap between taking on such projects and the subject's acceptance of their attainability by insisting that the project in question in such cases is only ever to try – to solve the P vs NP problem; or to arrive at a stable solution to the Middle East Crisis – and trying may well be something that the subject accepts is attainable. But this strikes me as forced. Trying just is taking on the project itself – of actually solving the P vs NP problem, or of actually arriving at a stable solution to the Middle East crisis and doing everything possible to attain it, whether or not this is eventually successful. So, the gap remains, especially, as I say, in such extended and complex cases.

In the light of cases of this kind, a second reply would be to insist that premise F2 is supposed to apply only to brief, simple projects, and so only to each of a series of successive manageable sub-projects of any more complex and extended overall project of the kind we have been considering. It is not obvious to me why we should accept F2 even in this qualified form; but in order to set out all the pieces of my challenge to Gomes's case for the claim that self-conscious thinking depends upon faith in cognitive agency, I turn instead at this point to consider F3.

Given that cognitive agency is understood as what is involved in self-conscious thinking but absent in perceiving, and that we often accept that the ends of perceptual projects are attainable, accepting that the ends of such projects are attainable cannot in general require our acceptance of our agency in the relevant sense. Suppose I set myself the project of discerning the colour of the eyes of the person in front of me. In suitable circumstances, of good lighting, of the person being close enough to me with eyes wide open, and so on, I may surely accept that this is attainable. Yet, since the project is purely perceptual, it involves no cognitive agency of the kind that Gomes is concerned with. Hence my taking it on cannot involve any acceptance of such cognitive agency – at least on the assumption that I have been working with throughout, following Gomes, that such acceptance is factive. This case therefore constitutes a counterexample to the general claim a subject's accepting that the end of a project they take on is attainable depends upon their accepting their cognitive agency in doing so.

The critical point here is especially clear with respect to the simple component sub-projects of any more extended and complex task, where the analogy between cases of thinking and perceiving is stronger. That's to say, it may be that a subject's accepting that some complex project is attainable involves commitment to the idea that they have some control over the order and initiation of the various sub-projects that will, all being well, eventually accomplish it. But, in relation to its individual simple sub-projects, their commitment to their attainability seems to presuppose little more than the conviction that, if they direct their attention to these in the right way, the correct answer will be forthcoming, and will arrive out of their control, determined by the relevant facts rather than by their own preferences and prejudices, as it should be.

It may be objected to this discussion that it depends upon something like an early modern conception of demonstration, in the sense of extended, directed reasoning, as an appropriate sequence of intuitions, in the sense of simple intellectual perceptions. It does indeed depend on a conception of thinking along these lines, with the distinction between extended complex projects and their manageable simple sub-projects. But, first, this early modern distinction between simple intuition, and extended complex demonstration, in these senses, seems to me independently defensible, although it may be applicable only relative to an individual subject on a given occasion of reasoning. Second, and more importantly for present purposes, the basic distinction has been introduced precisely to make the best possible case individually for each of Gomes's F2 and F3. The fundamental problem for his overall argument for the claim that self-conscious thinking depends upon faith in cognitive agency is that this evidently rests on an equivocation as a result.

For atomic sub-tasks, premise F2 may be correct; but premise F3 is surely false. Our taking them on may presuppose acceptance that they are at least likely to come off: we will find ourselves with a conviction one way or another settling the question at hand. But such acceptance involves no commitment to our agency in respect of that specific outcome. Indeed, it is more likely to involve recognition that the answer will just come to us.

For complex extended projects composed of multiple such components, on the other hand, premise F2 is surely false. We can, and do, take on many such ambitious projects without antecedently accepting that they are attainable (by us, here, now, in this way, at all, …?). Furthermore, the only acceptance of agency required by acceptance of attainability is that equally involved in extended perceptual tasks that are precisely the contrast with cases of active thinking that Gomes aims to establish: acceptance, that is to say, that we have some control over the order and initiation of their various component sub-activities.

So, although there may be some projects for which both F2 and F3 are true, they are not both true for all projects in which we aim to settle some specific question in the light of the relevant considerations for and against, as Gomes's argument requires. His argument for the claim that self-conscious thinking depends upon faith in cognitive agency is therefore invalid.

These reflections, and those under my first question above – whether self-consciousness really requires cognitive agency in Gomes's sense at all – suggest that the problem may lie in his attempt to articulate the cognitive agency he is interested in by contrast with perception. Perhaps the point is just that, in both cases, we actively select the questions we pose, and pursue them by attending in perception and in thought to the relevant considerations by which they are passively settled, in successful cases, by the facts. It is far from clear that any of this requires an acceptance of our agency in this regard that can only be based upon faith in the way Gomes suggests, though.

The alternative, that Gomes apparently leaves entirely open, is that faith in cognitive agency, in those self-conscious beings who are related to an objective world of other thinkers, may in some cases be sustained by their interpersonal practices of holding each other accountable for their thinking. That he does indeed endorse something close to this view himself is suggested by his characterization of objective engagement as ‘central’, although not strictly necessary, for the faith in cognitive agency that he argues is in turn essential to self-consciousness. In that case, any relation to an objective world to be derived from a thinker's being self-conscious is that assumed from the start in regarding them as de facto situated in an interpersonal world of other such thinkers whom they hold accountable, and who hold them accountable, for their thinking.

Gomes is scrupulous in subjecting others' arguments from self-consciousness to objectivity to rigorous objection. Yet, if this understanding of his account is accurate, then his own argument is simply invalid. A self-conscious thinker may in principle have faith in their cognitive agency unsustained by any engagement with an objective world of other thinkers, which constitutes a direct counterexample to the final stage of that argument. So, by the standards he applies to others, his own case is also wanting.

阿尼尔·戈麦斯的《实用的自我》
戈麦斯这本内容丰富、引人入胜的书围绕着一个论点展开,即一个有自我意识的主体必须是客观世界中众多客体中的一个:自我意识需要客观性。其他人也为同样的结论提供了论据;但是,与他自己相比,戈麦斯发现所有这些都是缺乏的。在阐述了我对国美核心论点的理解之后,我将对国美的每一项关键举措提出一系列担忧。这是一条新颖而有意义的论证路线。接下来,我提出了五个关键问题:两个关于前提1和前提2,一个关于前提3。我详细地阐述了其中的两点,形成了对戈麦斯观点的完整反驳;我让其他的人自生自灭,反对他的论点,即自我意识需要客观性。通过澄清前提1的内容,戈麦斯将认知代理与相应的感知被动性进行了对比。这是我认为他在感性情况下的意思。我们选择并启动项目,比如数斑马身上的条纹,辨别哪个椅子的颜色最接近地毯,等等。随着时间的推移,我们适当地集中和调整我们的注意力,以便尽我们所能地执行它们,在进行过程中检查和回顾。但是,在一天结束的时候,我们发现自己有哪些具体的经历和信念是完全不受我们控制的;如果决定结果的是事物的本来面目,而不是我们自己的偏好和偏见,那就应该如此。我们提出问题,引导我们的注意力和能力去追求它;事实证明了答案。然而,典型的智力项目不也是如此吗?比如数0到100之间的质数,或者在孩子的朋友家过夜时,如何最好地容纳所有的朋友,而不会引起太多的过度兴奋或对抗,等等。我们继续进行项目,并将注意力放在相关的考虑因素上,依次进行每个阶段,在进行过程中检查并在必要时返回。但是,再一次,我们发现自己在一天结束时拥有的信念完全不在我们的控制范围之内;如果决定结果的是事物的本来面目,而不是我们自己的偏好和偏见,那就应该如此。正如在知觉的情况下,我们提出问题,并引导我们的注意力和能力去追求它;事实证明了答案。直觉:“房间里有一把深蓝色的椅子吗?”…“是”;类似地,在智力上:“在37和43之间有素数吗?”“是的”。在这两种情况下,关于调查领域的现实主义肯定会立法支持我们对结果的最终被动。因此,我不清楚戈麦斯感兴趣的认知活动究竟是什么。当然,与感知的比较表明在这方面相似而不是不同。在某些方面,戈麦斯认为,对认知代理的需求和我们对它的接受,源于我们不断致力于根据新的证据修改和调整我们对世界的看法,或者仅仅是通过反思我们当前观点的适当性来重新考虑。但是,再一次,在我看来,这似乎是一种误导,暗示这包括任何像积极干预这些观点本身,移动我们的信念,就像我们可能重新安排我们的家具一样。更确切地说,这是一个重新承诺自己仔细和系统地关注所有考虑的问题,无论是感性的还是智力的,这些考虑与我们的信念在事实的基础上被重新确认或修改有关,以一种最终不受我们控制的方式,由现实而不是我们来解决。我并不是说感知和思考之间没有很多有趣的区别;但我觉得这种对比在阐述什么是我们作为自我意识存在的关键认知代理时并没有特别有启动性。因此,从第一个问题中产生的直接反对意见是,Anil对感知的被动性的对比的相对短暂的呼吁是不够的,因为它代表了对认知代理的目标概念的阐述。对阿尼尔来说,一个更普遍的挑战是更精确地说明他的中心论点的第一个前提是什么,即任何自我意识的主体必须接受关于他们信仰的获得和维持,要么通过进一步发展推理和感知之间的对比,要么以其他方式。这里我有一个相对便宜的观点,但我认为仍然值得提出。 鉴于我们刚才所看到的,在精确地表述自我意识所必需的认知能动者的概念时所遇到的困难,因此,坚持认为每一个自我意识主体都必须简单地接受、理解或知道他们在这种意义上是一个认知能动者,当然是不合理的。当然,这就提出了一个问题,即智力上对认知代理的接受应该是多么苛刻。根据我对Gomes讨论的阅读所提出的假设,这需要掌握断言所讨论的认知代理所涉及的命题,那么廉价点无疑是对Anil关于自我意识需要客观性这一论点的主要论点的第一个前提的进一步挑战。如果像戈麦斯所坚持的那样,我是决定如何最好地照顾一个孩子的所有朋友去朋友家过夜的代理人,那么我就认为这是我有意为之的事情,所以我知道我是在做一些我通常知道我是有意为之的事情。我当然没有一个关于这些知识在意图上的详细说明。但这是一个被广泛接受的现象。为什么当我在相关意义上积极思考时它不是我接受我的认知能动性的来源?也许,在我们运用认知代理的任何特殊情况下,戈麦斯将这种具体的知识与他主要关心的接受区分开来,也就是说,他主要关心的是,我通常是我的思想的代理。但是,即使承认这种区别,我们也可能会回答说,我们所得到的任何这种普遍的接受,都是从更具体的个体实例中得来的,这些实例是通过我们在特定情况下的意图知识而得到的。所以,在没有独立的反对意见的情况下,临界点仍然存在。在我看来,戈麦斯的观点是这样的。我可以看到怀疑这两个实质性前提的理由:(F2) &amp;(F3)。与F2相反,我们当然可以接受那些我们根本无法明确接受的项目(通过我/我们,在这里,现在,以这种方式,……?)即使在某些情况下,接受一个项目取决于不认为它是绝对无法实现的这种较弱的说法也可能过于强大。例如,当我乘坐飞机迫降在海里时,我可能会把自己投入到一个遥远的、隐约可见的岛屿上,游到安全的地方,不管我认为成功到达安全的地方是多么不可能。在任何情况下,承担一个项目和积极地接受它之间的差距肯定会随着项目的扩展、要求和复杂程度的增加而增加。帮助说明这一点的例子可能是解决P vs NP问题;或者为中东危机找到一个稳定的解决方案。在这种情况下,主体很可能开始一个扩展的、复杂的、极其苛刻的事业,而不接受它的可达性,由他们,甚至由任何人,当然不一定是由他们的方式来实现它的可达性。然而,这是他们所承担的项目。所以这种扩展的复杂情况构成了Anil F2的反例。第一个回答可能是,通过坚持认为在这种情况下,有问题的项目只是试图解决P / NP问题,试图缩小承担此类项目与主体接受其可实现性之间的差距;或者为中东危机找到一个稳定的解决方案——而这种尝试很可能是该主题接受的可以实现的事情。但我觉得这是被迫的。尝试只是承担项目本身——实际解决P / NP问题,或者实际找到中东危机的稳定解决方案,并尽一切可能实现它,无论最终是否成功。因此,差距依然存在,尤其是在如此广泛和复杂的情况下。在这种情况下,第二种回答是坚持认为前提F2只适用于简短的、简单的项目,因此只适用于我们所考虑的那种更复杂的、扩展的整体项目的一系列连续的、可管理的子项目。我不明白为什么我们要以这种限定的形式接受F2;但为了阐述我对戈麦斯关于自我意识思维依赖于对认知代理的信念的质疑,我转而考虑F3。鉴于认知能动性被理解为与自我意识思维有关但在感知中不存在的东西,而且我们经常接受感知项目的目标是可以实现的,接受这些项目的目标是可以实现的,通常并不要求我们在相关意义上接受我们的能动性。假设我给自己设定了一个项目,即辨别我面前的人眼睛的颜色。 在适当的情况下,比如光线充足,或者一个人离我足够近,眼睛睁得大大的,等等,我当然可以接受这是可以实现的。然而,由于这个项目纯粹是感性的,它不涉及戈麦斯所关注的那种认知代理。因此,我接受它并不意味着接受这种认知代理——至少在我一直在研究的假设下,在奥运会之后,这种接受是有效的。因此,这个案例构成了一个反例,反驳了一般的说法,即受试者接受他们所承担的项目的结束是可以实现的,这取决于他们在这样做时接受自己的认知代理。对于任何扩展和复杂任务的简单组件子项目,这里的关键点尤其明显,在这些子项目中,思考和感知的案例之间的相似性更强。也就是说,一个主体接受一些复杂的项目是可以实现的,这可能涉及到他们对各种子项目的顺序和启动有一定的控制,这些子项目最终会顺利完成。但是,就单个简单的子项目而言,他们对可实现性的承诺似乎只是假设了一种信念,即如果他们以正确的方式将注意力集中在这些子项目上,正确的答案就会出现,并且会超出他们的控制,由相关事实决定,而不是由他们自己的偏好和偏见决定,就像它应该的那样。有人可能会反对这种讨论,认为它依赖于某种类似早期现代的论证概念,即在扩展的、有指导的推理的意义上,作为直觉的适当序列,在简单的理智知觉的意义上。它确实依赖于沿着这些思路思考的概念,以及扩展的复杂项目和可管理的简单子项目之间的区别。但是,首先,在这些意义上,这种早期现代的简单直观和扩展的复杂论证之间的区别,在我看来似乎是独立地站得住的,尽管它可能只适用于在特定的推理场合下的个体主体。其次,就目前的目的而言,更重要的是,引入基本的区别,正是为了尽可能地为奥运会的F2和F3提供最佳的单独案例。他关于自我意识思维依赖于对认知能动性的信念这一主张的整体论证的根本问题在于,这显然是建立在模棱两可的结果之上的。对于原子子任务,前提F2可能是正确的;但前提F3肯定是错的。我们接受它们的前提可能是接受它们至少有可能成功:我们会发现自己以一种或另一种方式解决了手头的问题。但是,这种接受并不意味着对我们的代理机构就该具体结果作出承诺。事实上,它更可能涉及到这样一种认识,即答案会自然而然地出现在我们面前。另一方面,对于由多个这样的组件组成的复杂扩展项目,前提F2肯定是错误的。我们可以,而且确实,承担许多这样雄心勃勃的项目,而不是事先接受它们是可以实现的(对我们来说,在这里,现在,以这种方式,……?)此外,接受可获得性所要求的唯一的代理接受是,同样涉及到扩展的知觉任务,这恰恰与Gomes旨在建立的主动思维的情况形成对比:接受,也就是说,我们对各种组成子活动的顺序和启动有一定的控制。因此,尽管可能有一些项目F2和F3都是正确的,但它们并不都适用于所有项目,我们的目标是根据相关的利弊考虑来解决一些特定的问题,正如Gomes的论点所要求的那样。因此,他关于自我意识思维依赖于对认知代理的信念的论点是无效的。这些反思,以及我上面的第一个问题——自我意识是否真的需要戈麦斯意义上的认知代理——表明,问题可能在于他试图阐明他感兴趣的认知代理,而不是感知。也许关键在于,在这两种情况下,我们都积极地选择我们提出的问题,并通过在感知和思想中关注相关的考虑来追求它们,而这些考虑是被动地解决的,在成功的情况下,是由事实来解决的。目前还不清楚,这是否需要在这方面接受我们的机构,而这只能基于对戈麦斯所建议的方式的信任。 另一种选择,显然是戈麦斯完全开放的,是对认知代理的信仰,对那些与其他思想家的客观世界有关的有自我意识的人的信仰,在某些情况下,可能会通过他们相互对自己的想法负责的人际实践来维持。他确实赞同一些与这一观点相近的观点,这一点可以从他将客观参与描述为“核心”(尽管不是严格必要的)的特征中看出,因为他认为对认知代理的信仰反过来对自我意识至关重要。在这种情况下,任何与客观世界的关系都是从一个思想家的自我意识中衍生出来的,从一开始就假设他们事实上处于一个由其他思想家组成的人际世界中,他们对这些思想家的思想负责,这些思想家也对他们的思想负责。戈麦斯小心翼翼地将他人从自我意识到客观的论点置于严格的反对之下。然而,如果对他的描述的这种理解是准确的,那么他自己的论点就是完全无效的。原则上,自我意识的思考者可能对他们的认知代理有信心,而不需要与其他思考者的客观世界进行任何接触,这构成了该论点最后阶段的直接反例。所以,按照他对别人的标准,他自己的情况也不尽如人意。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
11.10%
发文量
82
期刊介绍: ''Founded by Mark Sacks in 1993, the European Journal of Philosophy has come to occupy a distinctive and highly valued place amongst the philosophical journals. The aim of EJP has been to bring together the best work from those working within the "analytic" and "continental" traditions, and to encourage connections between them, without diluting their respective priorities and concerns. This has enabled EJP to publish a wide range of material of the highest standard from philosophers across the world, reflecting the best thinking from a variety of philosophical perspectives, in a way that is accessible to all of them.''
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信