Adam Smith's inquiry into the nature and causes of the death of nations

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Ryan Patrick Hanley
{"title":"Adam Smith's inquiry into the nature and causes of the death of nations","authors":"Ryan Patrick Hanley","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12760","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>The year 1776 saw the publication of two of the Enlightenment's landmark texts: Edward Gibbon's multivolume <i>History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire</i>, and Adam Smith's multivolume <i>Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations</i>. Each was the work of an erudite scholar deeply learned in ancient and modern history. Each reflected its author's intimate conversance with the 18th century's leading theories of political economy and moral philosophy. And each in time would launch an intellectual revolution in its particular branch of social science. Yet for all this, the two works also share a further, less well appreciated similarity: both are inquiries into the causes of the decline and demise of nations.</p><p>Today we tend to associate this inquiry with Gibbon more than Smith. The Smith we have come to know is a theorist of growth and “the natural progress of opulence” and not a theorist of decline (WN 3.1).<sup>1</sup> Yet while his insights into growth undeniably constitute his most recognized contribution to the emergence of modern political economy, reading Smith exclusively as a theorist of growth can lead us to miss the sophistication of his inquiry into the causes of national decline. What follows thus reverses the causal arrow that has led other scholars to read Gibbon by way of Smith's influence (e.g., Pocock, <span>1999</span>, pp. 309–329, <span>2003</span>, pp. 372–399), and instead revisits Smith through the lens of Gibbon's key political problem in order to bring to the fore Smith's understudied inquiry into the causes of national decline and fall.</p><p>The chief benefit of this reading lies in how it clarifies an underappreciated paradox at the core of Smith's project.<sup>2</sup> At the heart of this paradox lies Smith's understanding of the necessary tension between national opulence and national power. Put simply, Smith taught that national opulence is ultimately inimical to national power; the paradox, in short, is that the very growth that political economy seeks to promote ultimately proves counter to the nation's political interests.<sup>3</sup> Thus even as “the great object of the political economy of every country, is to increase the riches and power of that country” (WN 2.5.31), Smith repeatedly would argue that the discrete project of increasing a country's riches subverts the discrete project of increasing a country's power. Smith furthermore believed that this paradox was both natural and necessary. This is especially clear in the way he frames the paradox in his lectures on jurisprudence: “it <i>must</i> happen that the improvement of the arts and commerce <i>must</i> make a great declension in the force and power of the republic in all cases” (LJA iv.81; italics added). Or again: “wherever therefore arts and commerce engage the citizens, either as artisans or master tradesmen, the strength and the force of the city <i>must</i> be very much diminished” (LJA iv.85; italics added). And again, progress in the useful arts, together with “commerce, the attendant on all these, <i>necessarily</i> undo the strength and cause the power to vanish of such a state till it be swallowed up by some neighboring state” (LJA iv.80-81; italics added).</p><p>What is especially striking in this last formulation is Smith's insistence not only that national opulence and national power are “necessarily” in tension, but that the ultimate end or resolution of this tension is the collapse of the nation. Here and elsewhere Smith frames this in existential terms as a matter of the nation's annihilation. He takes this approach, one presumes, in order to emphasize the magnitude of the potential threat; a teacher of rhetoric and renowned rhetorician in his own right, Smith's use of rhetoric in his framing of moral and political problems in his economic writings is well appreciated today (see, e.g., Herzog, <span>2013</span>; Ortmann &amp; Walraevans, <span>2022</span>, pp. 31–65). Yet the present essay's focus is less on how rhetorical concerns may have shaped Smith's methods of presenting his paradox, but rather on the substantive mechanisms Smith sees as driving the decline of commercial societies.<sup>4</sup></p><p>In an effort to unpack Smith's understanding of these mechanisms, in what follows I treat them under two distinct headings: mechanisms giving rise to external vulnerabilities and mechanisms giving rise to internal vulnerabilities. By disaggregating these two distinct processes, I aim to demonstrate the role of each in Smith's inquiry into national decline, and also to contribute to a central debate in the specialized scholarship. Recent Smith scholars have increasingly become interested in the role of the concept of corruption in his thought, and have helpfully documented its significance in Smith's moral philosophy and his political theory.<sup>5</sup> What follows seeks to add to this by demonstrating that Smith in fact distinguished between two discrete types of corruption in wealthy societies. Each type, he believed, can be traced to the progress of opulence, and each type he saw as having identifiable political consequences. But while one type renders the nation susceptible to external threats to its existence, the other renders a nation susceptible to internal threats to its existence. What follows takes up Smith's analysis of these challenges serially, and, in so doing, aims to show how Smith directly connects each of these threats to a specific type of corruption, as well as how he traces each of these types of corruption more generally to the progress of opulence.</p><p>Smith's concerns with regard to the external threats to which commercial opulence renders advanced nations susceptible is rooted in one of the fundamental principles of his political theory: the primacy of national defense. Smith very explicitly claims “defense” is “much more important than opulence” (WN 4.2.30). And while the specific context of this claim demands recognition—it comes in a discussion of the 1660 Acts of Navigation, in the course of which Smith presents an exception to his otherwise generally unqualified support for free trade (see Collins, <span>2022</span>)—the idea at its heart reappears at several places in his political thought, and in particular his accounts of the origins and ends of political society. Smith repeatedly argues that society's origin lies in an attempt to provide effective defense against external invaders. The original impetus for mutual association in the age of hunters was a concern for “mutual safety” and “mutual defense” (LJB 19, 27–28) so that allies “might be at hand to give one another assistance and protection against the common enemy” (LJA iv.36-37; cf. LJA iv.64). This need to secure means of mutual defense against invasion only grows as society progresses. Tracing the transition from the “savage” hunters to the next evolutionary stage of “barbarian” shepherds in which government and property rights were born (Fleischacker, <span>2004</span>, pp. 174–202; Hont, <span>2009</span>; Schliesser, <span>2017</span>, pp. 170–181), Smith continues to insist on the primacy of mutual defense, noting that villages of shepherds too “combine together under their different heads to support one another against the attacks of others” (LJA iv.38). Smith continues to emphasize the role of law and government in providing for “domestic peace” as well as “security from the foreign invader” as society progresses (LJB 210). And this concern reaches its apogee in advanced commercial societies, in which “the first duty of the sovereign” is “that of protecting the society from the violence and invasion of other independent societies” (WN 5.1.a.1; cf. WN 5.1.a.42 and WN 4.9.51), leading Smith forthrightly to insist that “the most important part of the expense of government” is “that of defense and protection” (WN 4.7.b.20; cf. LJB 6).<sup>6</sup></p><p>Smith's concern with securing the means of providing for effective external defense is thus a primary focus of both his historical analysis of the progress of opulence as well as his normative political theory. This is well appreciated today. What is less well appreciated is the degree of Smith's concern with regard to the ways in which the progress of opulence in a nation in fact makes it more rather than less difficult for a nation to secure the means of defending itself and thereby fulfill the first duty of the sovereign. Smith's claim on this front is that even as government works to secure the conditions of peace that make the growth of commerce and national opulence possible, the growth of opulence which good government makes possible ultimately subverts the peace and stability of government by compromising national defense. Smith's positions on this front are to be found in what he says as well as in what he fails to say. Smith in fact says next to nothing about the ways in which national opulence might benefit defense; conspicuously absent from his discussion, for example, is any treatment of how a broader tax base can generate revenue increases that can augment defense spending. On this front, Smith limits himself to a single (albeit crucial) paragraph on the technological advantages enjoyed by militaries of advanced civilized societies (WN 5.1.a.44). Instead, he focuses on how the growth of national opulence renders the nation susceptible to destabilizing violence from both without and within.</p><p>Both of these forms of destabilizing violence Smith traces to the corruption that he believes to be the necessary consequence of commercial progress. In a series of passages that have received and continue to receive significant scholarly attention, Smith traced “the effects of a commercial spirit on the government, temper, and manners of a people, whether good or bad, and the proper remedies” (LJB 224).<sup>7</sup> Here and elsewhere Smith frequently presents these effects as moral effects, using the language of “temper” and “manners” and “virtue” and “character” to describe them. This moral language is especially evident in his study of the “poor man's son” in TMS, which notoriously presents power and riches as “enormous and operose machines contrived to produce a few trifling conveniences to the body”—machines “ready at every moment to burst into pieces, and to crush into ruins their unfortunate possessor” (TMS 4.1.8; see, e.g., Hill, <span>2017</span>). But Smith was not just a moralist, and alongside—indeed embedded within—his study of the moral effects of commercial corruption is an appreciation of the political and economic causes and effects of these evident moral changes.</p><p>Smith's arresting assessment of the moral consequences of specialized, divided labor has rightly received a great deal of recent attention. Of particular scholarly interest has been Smith's proposed political response to this problem, and in particular the degree of public funding he in fact envisioned for the educational systems he proposed to offset corruption.<sup>8</sup> Yet this focus on the nature and extent of his envisioned cure has left two elements of his diagnosis understudied. One concerns the degree to which Smith regards this corrupting process as a natural and indeed necessary process; Smith here again thus insists that these ills “necessarily” emerge “in the great body of the people” of “every improved and civilized society” if government fails to intervene. The second is that Smith sees this corruption as taking several discrete forms. Smith envisions not just some general corruption of character, but a corruption specifically of the “intellectual” virtues, the “social” virtues, and the “martial” virtues.</p><p>This disaggregation is important because even as Smith traces the corruption of all three of these types of virtues back to the repetitive nature of specialized labor, he goes on to argue that the political problems consequent to the corruption of the martial virtues are distinct from the political problems consequent to the corruption of the intellectual virtues. Specifically, where the corruption of the martial virtues increases the nation's susceptibility to threats from without, the corruption of the intellectual virtues increases its susceptibility to threats from within. Smith's treatment of the way in which the corruption of the martial virtues renders a nation susceptible to external violence is especially striking. Smith is as explicit as he can be that “the security of every society must always depend, more or less, upon the martial spirit of the great body of the people” (WN 5.1.f.59). To compromise the martial spirit of the nation—as Smith clearly thinks commercial progress does—is thus to compromise the strength and security of the nation. And in developing his arguments on this front, Smith makes three distinct claims.</p><p>The first is the most obvious: namely, that the vitiation of martial spirit and martial virtue incapacitates opulent citizens to defend their opulent states. Wealthy citizens, quite simply, are ineffective warriors—a point Smith would repeatedly make in his published and unpublished writings. In his jurisprudence lectures, Smith thus argues that “another bad effect of commerce is that it sinks the courage of mankind, and tends to extinguish martial spirit” (see also Heilbroner, <span>1973</span>, p. 254). This is so, he explains, because “in all commercial countries the division of labor is infinite, and every ones thoughts are employed about one particular thing”: maximizing returns on one's labor. But Smith also sees something tragic here: “among the bulk of the people military courage diminishes” as a direct result of their focus on lucrative employment. And thus “by having their minds constantly employed on the arts of luxury, they grow effeminate and dastardly” (LJB 331)—a denunciation that is in keeping with views Smith expresses elsewhere regarding how certain types of luxury lead to “dissolution of manners” (TMS 1.2.3.4).</p><p>Smith's critique of the effects of luxury on the martial virtues is also in keeping with a familiar classical republican tradition on whose tropes he here very clearly draws.<sup>9</sup> But to these conventional republican critiques of the effects of opulence and luxury Smith adds a second, far more original critique that goes well beyond traditional republican concerns.<sup>10</sup> Herein lies his second key claim: that the increased susceptibility of advanced commercial societies to foreign invasion owes not only to the way in which labor specialization might compromise martial spirit and martial virtue, but also to the ways in which the division of labor compromises military readiness and recruitment. In making this claim, Smith subtly but importantly shifts away from republican concerns with virtue and character to a more original set of insights into how the progress of opulence decisively shapes (and indeed for the worse) national institutions.</p><p>Here, in accounting for how the population of commercial societies can grow even as its “number of fighting people” shrinks, Smith reiterates both the core concept of his paradox of national opulence and national power, and the degree to which this inverse relation is in fact “necessary.” But Smith also goes on to show that not only is it not in the individual's interest to leave behind their lucrative pursuits to go out into the field, it is also not in the nation's economic interests. “In a state where arts, manufacturing, and handicrafts are brought to perfection,” the state “cannot dispense with the laborers in this manner without the total loss of business and the destruction of the state” (LJA iv.79). Thus, another level of the paradox: not only does the structure of the labor institutions of a commercial society disincentivize military service and thereby compromise the nation's capacities for defense, but compelling artisans to leave their bench and serve in the military necessarily hampers the national economy in ways that themselves hasten the “destruction of the state.”</p><p>To bolster his argument, Smith cites several empirical case studies. One is the fall of Rome, which he traces directly to that moment when the Romans “arrived at a considerable degree of improvement both in arts and commerce” and consequently became “less fond of going out to war” (LJB 46–47; LJA iv.88; cf. LJA iv.99), aware that they “made more by their trades than by going to war” (LJB 49; LJA iv.103). Another is the fall of China to the Tartars. Ming China, he insists, was a classic instance of an advanced nation in which “the division of labor and luxury have arrived at a very high pitch” and whose “conquest is easy” as a result (LJB 332); thus, his cautionary tale of the conquest of “the indolent, effeminate, and full fed nations of the southern parts of Asia” by the “active, hardy, and hungry Tartars of the north” (WN 5.1.g.1; see Hanley, <span>2014</span>). A third case is the Britain of Smith's own day. Smith clearly found troubling the Jacobite Rebellion of 1745, when “four or 5 thousand naked unarmed Highlanders took possession of the improved parts of this country without any opposition from the unwarlike inhabitants” (LJB 331; cf. LJB 159). This would have never happened in a previous age: “200 years ago such an attempt would have roused the spirit of the nation” for their “ancestors were brave and warlike, their minds were not enervated by cultivating arts and commerce, and they were already with spirit and vigor to resist the most formidable foe” (LJB 331–332)—a claim that provides the essential referent for Smith's otherwise seemingly incongruent but crucially significant claim in <i>Wealth of Nations</i> that “it is now more than two hundred years since the beginning of the reign of Elizabeth, a period as long as the course of human prosperity usually endures” (WN 3.4.20).</p><p>In sum, allowing workers to work and not fight is prejudicial to the nation's military strength, but compelling them to fight and not work is prejudicial to the nation's economic strength. To all this, Smith can imagine only one solution: a commercial state must have the “wisdom” in peacetime to fund and train armies of professional soldiers (Hanley, <span>2014</span>, pp. 378–379). Smith's well-known defense of the superiority of standing armies to militias then is not only an intervention in a long-standing republican debate (see Montes, <span>2009</span>) but an institutional response to a fundamental political problem unique to commercial modernity. It is in this context that we need to read his claim that in “an opulent and civilized nation,” a standing army “can alone defend such a nation against the invasion of a poor and barbarous neighbor” such that “the civilization of any country can be perpetuated, or even preserved for any considerable time” (WN 5.1.a.39).</p><p>National opulence provokes invasion at the same time it renders wealthy nations incapable of resisting invasion. And thus, the tragic and necessary upshot: “improvement in arts and cultivation unfit the people from going to war, so that the strength is greatly diminished and it falls a sacrifice to some of their neighbors” (LJA iv.91).</p><p>Our focus to this point has been on the external threats to national security and integrity that Smith associates with the progress of commercial opulence. But Smith also insists that advanced commercial nations are subject to internal threats—threats he here again will identify as the direct consequence of the progress of opulence. And especially striking in Smith's analysis of these internal threats is their structural similarity with the external threats. For even as Smith makes clear that the locus of these threats has shifted from external to internal, the essential dynamic at their root remains the perennial tension between rich and poor, and the constant potential for violence latent in this tension.</p><p>These are striking passages that demand to be read in several contexts. They first are to be read as evidence for Smith's fundamental belief that government exists to secure property rights.<sup>12</sup> Yet this, while true, does not in itself account for one of the most crucial elements of the passage: the degree to which Smith believes that civil society exists not simply to preserve property rights, but also or especially to preserve those inequalities of property, and specifically those moderate rather than extreme inequalities he elsewhere claims are indispensable to commercial progress. This is an important element of Smith's argument that has been helpfully brought out in recent work on Smith and inequality,<sup>13</sup> and has also been noted in recent work on Smith's debts to Rousseau.<sup>14</sup> But for all this, there is another less well appreciated context for these passages. For when we set Smith's theory of the origins and ends of the government as they pertain to the first duty of the sovereign next to his account of the origins and ends of government as they pertain to the second duty of the sovereign, what becomes evident is that the fundamental constant in Smith's theory of government is the omnipresent threat of violence between rich and poor. Taken together, this attests not merely to Smith's deep sense of the fragility of civilization, but also to the degree of his awareness of two distinct threats to our fragile civilization: the external threats posed by poor nations to rich nations and the internal threats posed by poor individuals to rich individuals.</p><p>Smith's worry about the magnitude of these threats helps explain his sustained focus in both <i>The Theory of Moral Sentiments</i> and <i>Wealth of Nations</i> on the mechanisms of social order. TMS thus presents intersubjective exchanges of sympathy as fostering “the harmony of society” (TMS 1.1.4.7) and justice as the principal means of preventing social bonds from being “broke asunder” by “mutual resentment and animosity” (TMS 2.2.3.3), culminating in “the disorder and confusion of society” (TMS 2.2.3.8) that threatens to render society itself “a scene of bloodshed and disorder” (TMS 7.4.36; cf. TMS 2.2.3.6-7). Yet while these aspects of Smith's social theory are well-known, less well appreciated is his vision of the role played by commercial opulence in this destabilizing process. Smith's concerns here turn on how commercial progress reconfigures traditional social orders, and indeed often for the better. In his account of feudalism in <i>Wealth of Nations</i>, he famously argues that the introduction of commerce and manufactures created opportunities for economic and geographic mobility of which the least well-off were the greatest beneficiaries; “introduction of arts, commerce, and luxury” (LJA iv.157; cf. LJA iv.72; LJB 59), it is argued, severed the bonds of dependence and introduced “a revolution of the greatest importance to the public happiness” (WN 3.4.17).<sup>15</sup> So too, “the gradual improvements of arts, manufactures and commerce, the same causes which destroyed the power of the great barons” also subverted the traditional authority of the clergy (WN 5.1.g.25; cf. WN 5.1.g.22), and also realigned authority structures in the shepherding age (WN 5.1.b.7).</p><p>In each of these instances, Smith very clearly presents the introduction of commerce and opulence as a beneficial act of creative destruction that subverts traditional authority structures and social hierarchies in ways to be welcomed. Yet elsewhere he calls attention to a darker side of this subversion, noting that the progress of opulence can also change the balance of power between social orders in potentially destabilizing ways. In his lectures on rhetoric, he gives the example of the ancient Athenians. The Athenians were once “the most enterprising and active people in all Greece,” but “commerce and luxury entirely altered the state of affairs,” giving “the lowest an opportunity of raising themselves to an equality with the nobles; and the nobles an easy way of reducing themselves to the state of the meanest citizen” (LRBL 150; Sagar, <span>2022</span>, p. 198). Further, “commerce, as it introduced trade or manufacture into all the members of the state made them unwilling to attend the courts” (LRBL 151). Civic obligations thus came to be neglected amid the spread of commercial opportunity, as men who saw their labor richly rewarded became “very unwilling to leave their work for an employment which brought them no profit” (LRBL 151). The progress of commercial opulence in Athens thus proved inimical to civil participation and service, with the result that the burdens of judicial service were shifted from the rich on to the poor.</p><p>Smith elsewhere says that the same is true of the military: “when arts and luxury have in the natural progress of things been introduced into the state, and considerable improvements have been made in these, the rich and better sort of people will no longer engage in the service” (LJA iv.87-88; cf. LJA iv.93-94). The growth of commercial opulence fundamentally alters the composition of the military by drawing the “rich and better sort of people” away, creating a vacuum to be filled by others: “whenever luxury comes in after commerce and arts,” the “only people who could go out to war in this state would be the very lowest and most worthless of the people” (LJA iv.84; cf. LJA iv.169). Military service then comes to be no longer the province of “gentlemen” but rather a “mob” composed of mercenaries drawn from “the dregs of the people” (LJB 40; see also LJA iv.93). Smith finds this tragic; where once the nation was “defended by men of honor,” when “improvement of arts and manufacturers was thought an object deserving the attention of the higher ranks, the defense of the state naturally became the province of the lower.” Thus, his conclusion: “when arts and commerce are still farther advanced and begin to be very lucrative, it falls to the meanest to defend the state”—and this, he pointedly notes, is “our present condition in Great Britain” (LJB 335).</p><p>Smith uses these claims in part to point out the danger of trusting the defense of the opulent nation to mercenaries. Yet this is only part of his worry. Smith is not only troubled by the ways in which the abdication of military service by the wealthy weakens the military but also by the way in which this abdication leads to a dramatic shift in the distribution of social power, as the military becomes an institution of the poor. Smith cannot but see this as a worrisome development given his belief that “upon the ability of each particular order of society to maintain its own power, privileges, and immunities, against the encroachments of every other, depend the stability of the particular constitution,” and that a constitution is “necessarily more or less altered, whenever any of its subordinate parts is either raised above or depressed below whatever had been its former rank and condition” (TMS 6.2.2.9). Thus, even as Smith clearly welcomed social mobility, he also recognized the possibility of social instability in abrupt changes in “the established balance among the different orders and societies into which the state is divided” (TMS 6.2.2.10; see also TMS 6.2.1.20; Hill, <span>2006</span>, p. 643).</p><p>Commerce's rebalancing of social power thus not only has direct effects on specific public institutions, but also on the ways in which certain social classes have access to and control over such institutions. Put in the terms of the previous section's review of external threats to security, Smith's concerns with regard to the realignment of social orders might be classified as an institutional or structural concern. But also as before, Smith identifies a moral concern on the internal front as well as an institutional concern. And also once again, he presents these moral concerns as a direct result of the progress of the division of labor. The key difference is that even as these concerns spring from a common root, the internal political problem to which they give rise is distinct from the external threats consequent to the corruption of the martial virtues.</p><p>Smith's key claim on this front is captured in one of his most striking and sweeping generalizations: “in every commercial nation the low people are exceedingly stupid” (LJB 329). The stupidity and “mental mutilation” (WN 5.1.f.60) consequent to the progress of the division of labor is of course one of the most striking elements of Smith's account of public education in the final book of the <i>Wealth of Nations</i>. But why does Smith think this mental mutilation is in fact a necessary condition in “every commercial nation,” and why exactly does he take this stupidity to be a political problem?<sup>16</sup></p><p>Here Smith lays out a side of the corruption endemic to the division of labor that is distinct from the corruption of the martial virtues. For what worries him here is not the cowardice of commercial citizens but their intellectual incapacity to judge either their moral duties in private life or the interests of the nation in public life.<sup>17</sup></p><p>Smith will soon after return to the political implications of this incapacity for judgment. In so doing, he shows that the political problem to which the corruption of the intellectual virtues gives rise is distinct from the political problem to which the corruption of the martial virtues gives rise. For while the corruption of the martial virtues renders a nation susceptible to external threats, the corruption of the intellectual virtues renders a nation susceptible to internal threats, and above all, the threats posed by a very particular sort of domestic political actor. Smith presents these threats at the end of his well-known proposal for public education at taxpayer expense. But what demands further attention is the way in which Smith presents stupidity and the corruption of the intellectual virtues as at once the product of commercial progress and also an existential threat to the integrity and stability of the state.</p><p>The corruption of the intellectual virtues threatens “the safety of government” in “free countries” by giving rise to the threat of “the most dreadful disorders.” Specifically, the corruption of judgment makes the general populace uniquely susceptible to a particular type of domestic or homegrown threat: that of self-interested religious actors who would seek to manipulate the people of “ignorant nations” via “the delusions of enthusiasm and superstition,” and self-interested party leaders and politicians who promote “faction and sedition” in order to advance their own interests. Smith elsewhere strikingly attests to the destabilizing dangers of “violent religious controversy” and “violent political faction” (WN 5.1.g.7) and insists that “the animosity of hostile factions, whether civil or ecclesiastical” is “by far the greatest” of “all the corruptors of moral sentiments” (TMS 3.3.43). It is for this reason that Smith thinks that just as only a state-funded standing army can defend opulent commercial nations from the attacks of foreign enemies to which the corruption of martial virtues makes it susceptible, only a state-funded system of education can prevent opulent states from succumbing to the domestic enemies to which the corruption of its intellectual virtues renders it susceptible.</p><p>The foregoing has sought to call attention to a paradox at the core of Smith's thought which deserves more attention than it has received. At the heart of this paradox lies Smith's understanding of the dialectical relationship between wealth and power. Restated simply: achievement of national opulence, the aim of political economy, is necessarily inimical to the maintenance of national power. The growth of opulence specifically renders nations simultaneously susceptible—to use Smith's locution in <i>The Theory of Moral Sentiments</i>—to threats posed by “hostile nations” without, and to threats posed by “hostile factions” within (TMS 3.3.43).</p><p>Smith's treatment of this paradox and his placement of it at the center of his political theory reveals him to be a more sophisticated political theorist than he has sometimes been taken to be. It has long been appreciated that Smith was at once a champion of both wealth and virtue. For many years, scholars treated these seemingly competing strands within his thought in terms of “liberalism” and “republicanism.”<sup>18</sup> But in retrospect, any effort to claim Smith for either liberalism or republicanism seems as much a non-starter as the old debate over the ostensible tension between <i>The Theory of Moral Sentiments</i> and <i>Wealth of Nations</i> canonized as Das Adam Smith Problem. In both cases, what is interesting and enduring is not whether he was committed to one good or another, but rather how he synthesized them in a unified comprehensive theory. Showing that Smith both welcomed and was worried by the consequences of the progress of national opulence (see also Rasmussen, <span>2008</span>) has been an aim of this study.</p><p>Yet even if this inquiry has been successful in uncovering the consistency of Smith's thought, it leaves another question unanswered: namely, that of what nations and national leaders ought to do in the face of this paradox. Smith himself repeatedly suggests that the proper end of political inquiry is political action. In <i>The Theory of Moral Sentiments</i>, he tells us that “political disquisitions, if just, and reasonable, and practicable, are of all the works of speculation the most useful” (TMS 4.1.11), and in his lectures on rhetoric, he insists that “the design of historical writing is not merely to entertain.” Good history does more: it “sets before us the more interesting and important events of human life, points out the causes by which these events were brought about and by this means points out to us by what manner and method we may produce similar good effects or avoid similar bad ones” (LRBL 90; see also 106, 111). If so, one might reasonably ask what lessons he expected his audience to take away from his own inquiry into and examples of national decline and fall.</p><p>The answer, I think, is twofold. First, Smith helpfully and hopefully emphasizes—especially in his published writings—that political actors are not the victims of fate but in fact can help to steer outcomes via a self-aware application of national policies. Faith that political actors can use their agency to maximize the possibility of desirable outcomes is after all central to Smith's project as a public writer; had Smith no faith in agency, his very authorship of the <i>Wealth of Nations</i> and its attack on British mercantile trade policy would be difficult to explain. So too, the emphasis in the <i>Wealth of Nations</i> on institutions (and its calls for a standing army and a public education system in particular) suggests an optimistic faith in the capacities of “the wisdom of the state” and “the science of the legislator” to mitigate politically destabilizing threats, and a worry that if practical action is “neglected,” then indeed “disorder will ensue” (LJB 310).<sup>19</sup></p><p>At the same time, Smith's optimism must not be confused with idealism. Smith very clearly believed in human agency. But alongside his hopeful attestations of the efficacy of political action, he also insists that human action can only delay but never circumvent the inevitable. This worry is especially prominent in the jurisprudence lectures. Here, as we have seen, Smith is far from sanguine about the capacities of institutional solutions, repeatedly insisting that every government “seems to have a certain and fixed end which concludes it” (LJA iv.99), and darkly calling attention to “that fated dissolution that awaits every state and constitution whatever” (LJB 46). These explicit and repeated assertions of the inexorability of national decline and fall run counter to claims that Smith rejected “endist eschatologies” (Hill, <span>2019</span>, p. 119, 122), and that his thought operated independently of “the assumption that corruption and decline is the inevitable fate of all political communities” (Sagar, <span>2022</span>, p. 148). On the contrary, Smith's sustained articulation of the “causes” by which “states necessarily come to an end” (LJA iv.74-75) suggests that he was quite capable of imagining national decline and fall, and that he spoke of necessary national collapse far more explicitly and frequently than of the possibility of permanent escape from such necessity.</p><p>The fact that these concerns are especially pronounced in the jurisprudence lectures raises important interpretive questions. Among them: Does the difference in the tone of the lectures as compared to the published account in the <i>Wealth of Nations</i> suggest a change in substantive position on the efficacy of the institutional solutions? Or is it perhaps the case that the difference in tone can be accounted for by either exaggerations or misattributions of the transcribers, or (to my mind more likely) Smith's awareness of the differences in his audiences? This might explain why Smith, in a published book written for legislators and policymakers and influencers, would emphasize the efficacy of institutional proposals, and so conspicuously celebrate the “the powerful arm of the civil magistrate” (WN 5.1.b.2), the “wisdom of the state” (WN 5.1.a.14), and “government” and its “pains” (WN 5.1.f.50) as all that stand between civilization and its collapse, even as the lectures develop a consistently more sober (indeed somber) view of political agency in the face of necessity. Any answer to such questions can only be speculative given the evidence available and in any case requires more extensive discussion than can be provided here. My aim here has instead been to call attention to Smith's striking though underappreciated inquiry into the processes of national decline and fall, and to show that his interest in these runs deeper than the casual dismissal of them seemingly implicit in his much-quoted remark that “there is a great deal of ruin in a nation” (CAS 262n3).<sup>20</sup> Made in the wake of General Burgoyne's Saratoga defeat, the remark tends to be taken as an effort to persuade a worried correspondent that the British Empire was robust enough to withstand losing a single battle in upstate New York. But while this accurately captures the remark's immediate context, when set in the context of his larger system, as I have sought to do here, it attests to another and darker side of Smith's political vision. In this sense Smith's 1778 remark—and indeed his inquiry into the death of nations more generally—is perhaps best read as an explication of the lesson with which his beloved teacher Hutcheson closed his own masterwork: namely that “states have within them the seeds of death and destruction”—seeds that indeed “have always occasioned the dissolution and death of every body politic” (Hutcheson, <span>1755</span>, pp. 2:377–378; cf. WN 425n53).<sup>21</sup></p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"32 1","pages":"184-197"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2024-09-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12760","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12760","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The year 1776 saw the publication of two of the Enlightenment's landmark texts: Edward Gibbon's multivolume History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, and Adam Smith's multivolume Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Each was the work of an erudite scholar deeply learned in ancient and modern history. Each reflected its author's intimate conversance with the 18th century's leading theories of political economy and moral philosophy. And each in time would launch an intellectual revolution in its particular branch of social science. Yet for all this, the two works also share a further, less well appreciated similarity: both are inquiries into the causes of the decline and demise of nations.

Today we tend to associate this inquiry with Gibbon more than Smith. The Smith we have come to know is a theorist of growth and “the natural progress of opulence” and not a theorist of decline (WN 3.1).1 Yet while his insights into growth undeniably constitute his most recognized contribution to the emergence of modern political economy, reading Smith exclusively as a theorist of growth can lead us to miss the sophistication of his inquiry into the causes of national decline. What follows thus reverses the causal arrow that has led other scholars to read Gibbon by way of Smith's influence (e.g., Pocock, 1999, pp. 309–329, 2003, pp. 372–399), and instead revisits Smith through the lens of Gibbon's key political problem in order to bring to the fore Smith's understudied inquiry into the causes of national decline and fall.

The chief benefit of this reading lies in how it clarifies an underappreciated paradox at the core of Smith's project.2 At the heart of this paradox lies Smith's understanding of the necessary tension between national opulence and national power. Put simply, Smith taught that national opulence is ultimately inimical to national power; the paradox, in short, is that the very growth that political economy seeks to promote ultimately proves counter to the nation's political interests.3 Thus even as “the great object of the political economy of every country, is to increase the riches and power of that country” (WN 2.5.31), Smith repeatedly would argue that the discrete project of increasing a country's riches subverts the discrete project of increasing a country's power. Smith furthermore believed that this paradox was both natural and necessary. This is especially clear in the way he frames the paradox in his lectures on jurisprudence: “it must happen that the improvement of the arts and commerce must make a great declension in the force and power of the republic in all cases” (LJA iv.81; italics added). Or again: “wherever therefore arts and commerce engage the citizens, either as artisans or master tradesmen, the strength and the force of the city must be very much diminished” (LJA iv.85; italics added). And again, progress in the useful arts, together with “commerce, the attendant on all these, necessarily undo the strength and cause the power to vanish of such a state till it be swallowed up by some neighboring state” (LJA iv.80-81; italics added).

What is especially striking in this last formulation is Smith's insistence not only that national opulence and national power are “necessarily” in tension, but that the ultimate end or resolution of this tension is the collapse of the nation. Here and elsewhere Smith frames this in existential terms as a matter of the nation's annihilation. He takes this approach, one presumes, in order to emphasize the magnitude of the potential threat; a teacher of rhetoric and renowned rhetorician in his own right, Smith's use of rhetoric in his framing of moral and political problems in his economic writings is well appreciated today (see, e.g., Herzog, 2013; Ortmann & Walraevans, 2022, pp. 31–65). Yet the present essay's focus is less on how rhetorical concerns may have shaped Smith's methods of presenting his paradox, but rather on the substantive mechanisms Smith sees as driving the decline of commercial societies.4

In an effort to unpack Smith's understanding of these mechanisms, in what follows I treat them under two distinct headings: mechanisms giving rise to external vulnerabilities and mechanisms giving rise to internal vulnerabilities. By disaggregating these two distinct processes, I aim to demonstrate the role of each in Smith's inquiry into national decline, and also to contribute to a central debate in the specialized scholarship. Recent Smith scholars have increasingly become interested in the role of the concept of corruption in his thought, and have helpfully documented its significance in Smith's moral philosophy and his political theory.5 What follows seeks to add to this by demonstrating that Smith in fact distinguished between two discrete types of corruption in wealthy societies. Each type, he believed, can be traced to the progress of opulence, and each type he saw as having identifiable political consequences. But while one type renders the nation susceptible to external threats to its existence, the other renders a nation susceptible to internal threats to its existence. What follows takes up Smith's analysis of these challenges serially, and, in so doing, aims to show how Smith directly connects each of these threats to a specific type of corruption, as well as how he traces each of these types of corruption more generally to the progress of opulence.

Smith's concerns with regard to the external threats to which commercial opulence renders advanced nations susceptible is rooted in one of the fundamental principles of his political theory: the primacy of national defense. Smith very explicitly claims “defense” is “much more important than opulence” (WN 4.2.30). And while the specific context of this claim demands recognition—it comes in a discussion of the 1660 Acts of Navigation, in the course of which Smith presents an exception to his otherwise generally unqualified support for free trade (see Collins, 2022)—the idea at its heart reappears at several places in his political thought, and in particular his accounts of the origins and ends of political society. Smith repeatedly argues that society's origin lies in an attempt to provide effective defense against external invaders. The original impetus for mutual association in the age of hunters was a concern for “mutual safety” and “mutual defense” (LJB 19, 27–28) so that allies “might be at hand to give one another assistance and protection against the common enemy” (LJA iv.36-37; cf. LJA iv.64). This need to secure means of mutual defense against invasion only grows as society progresses. Tracing the transition from the “savage” hunters to the next evolutionary stage of “barbarian” shepherds in which government and property rights were born (Fleischacker, 2004, pp. 174–202; Hont, 2009; Schliesser, 2017, pp. 170–181), Smith continues to insist on the primacy of mutual defense, noting that villages of shepherds too “combine together under their different heads to support one another against the attacks of others” (LJA iv.38). Smith continues to emphasize the role of law and government in providing for “domestic peace” as well as “security from the foreign invader” as society progresses (LJB 210). And this concern reaches its apogee in advanced commercial societies, in which “the first duty of the sovereign” is “that of protecting the society from the violence and invasion of other independent societies” (WN 5.1.a.1; cf. WN 5.1.a.42 and WN 4.9.51), leading Smith forthrightly to insist that “the most important part of the expense of government” is “that of defense and protection” (WN 4.7.b.20; cf. LJB 6).6

Smith's concern with securing the means of providing for effective external defense is thus a primary focus of both his historical analysis of the progress of opulence as well as his normative political theory. This is well appreciated today. What is less well appreciated is the degree of Smith's concern with regard to the ways in which the progress of opulence in a nation in fact makes it more rather than less difficult for a nation to secure the means of defending itself and thereby fulfill the first duty of the sovereign. Smith's claim on this front is that even as government works to secure the conditions of peace that make the growth of commerce and national opulence possible, the growth of opulence which good government makes possible ultimately subverts the peace and stability of government by compromising national defense. Smith's positions on this front are to be found in what he says as well as in what he fails to say. Smith in fact says next to nothing about the ways in which national opulence might benefit defense; conspicuously absent from his discussion, for example, is any treatment of how a broader tax base can generate revenue increases that can augment defense spending. On this front, Smith limits himself to a single (albeit crucial) paragraph on the technological advantages enjoyed by militaries of advanced civilized societies (WN 5.1.a.44). Instead, he focuses on how the growth of national opulence renders the nation susceptible to destabilizing violence from both without and within.

Both of these forms of destabilizing violence Smith traces to the corruption that he believes to be the necessary consequence of commercial progress. In a series of passages that have received and continue to receive significant scholarly attention, Smith traced “the effects of a commercial spirit on the government, temper, and manners of a people, whether good or bad, and the proper remedies” (LJB 224).7 Here and elsewhere Smith frequently presents these effects as moral effects, using the language of “temper” and “manners” and “virtue” and “character” to describe them. This moral language is especially evident in his study of the “poor man's son” in TMS, which notoriously presents power and riches as “enormous and operose machines contrived to produce a few trifling conveniences to the body”—machines “ready at every moment to burst into pieces, and to crush into ruins their unfortunate possessor” (TMS 4.1.8; see, e.g., Hill, 2017). But Smith was not just a moralist, and alongside—indeed embedded within—his study of the moral effects of commercial corruption is an appreciation of the political and economic causes and effects of these evident moral changes.

Smith's arresting assessment of the moral consequences of specialized, divided labor has rightly received a great deal of recent attention. Of particular scholarly interest has been Smith's proposed political response to this problem, and in particular the degree of public funding he in fact envisioned for the educational systems he proposed to offset corruption.8 Yet this focus on the nature and extent of his envisioned cure has left two elements of his diagnosis understudied. One concerns the degree to which Smith regards this corrupting process as a natural and indeed necessary process; Smith here again thus insists that these ills “necessarily” emerge “in the great body of the people” of “every improved and civilized society” if government fails to intervene. The second is that Smith sees this corruption as taking several discrete forms. Smith envisions not just some general corruption of character, but a corruption specifically of the “intellectual” virtues, the “social” virtues, and the “martial” virtues.

This disaggregation is important because even as Smith traces the corruption of all three of these types of virtues back to the repetitive nature of specialized labor, he goes on to argue that the political problems consequent to the corruption of the martial virtues are distinct from the political problems consequent to the corruption of the intellectual virtues. Specifically, where the corruption of the martial virtues increases the nation's susceptibility to threats from without, the corruption of the intellectual virtues increases its susceptibility to threats from within. Smith's treatment of the way in which the corruption of the martial virtues renders a nation susceptible to external violence is especially striking. Smith is as explicit as he can be that “the security of every society must always depend, more or less, upon the martial spirit of the great body of the people” (WN 5.1.f.59). To compromise the martial spirit of the nation—as Smith clearly thinks commercial progress does—is thus to compromise the strength and security of the nation. And in developing his arguments on this front, Smith makes three distinct claims.

The first is the most obvious: namely, that the vitiation of martial spirit and martial virtue incapacitates opulent citizens to defend their opulent states. Wealthy citizens, quite simply, are ineffective warriors—a point Smith would repeatedly make in his published and unpublished writings. In his jurisprudence lectures, Smith thus argues that “another bad effect of commerce is that it sinks the courage of mankind, and tends to extinguish martial spirit” (see also Heilbroner, 1973, p. 254). This is so, he explains, because “in all commercial countries the division of labor is infinite, and every ones thoughts are employed about one particular thing”: maximizing returns on one's labor. But Smith also sees something tragic here: “among the bulk of the people military courage diminishes” as a direct result of their focus on lucrative employment. And thus “by having their minds constantly employed on the arts of luxury, they grow effeminate and dastardly” (LJB 331)—a denunciation that is in keeping with views Smith expresses elsewhere regarding how certain types of luxury lead to “dissolution of manners” (TMS 1.2.3.4).

Smith's critique of the effects of luxury on the martial virtues is also in keeping with a familiar classical republican tradition on whose tropes he here very clearly draws.9 But to these conventional republican critiques of the effects of opulence and luxury Smith adds a second, far more original critique that goes well beyond traditional republican concerns.10 Herein lies his second key claim: that the increased susceptibility of advanced commercial societies to foreign invasion owes not only to the way in which labor specialization might compromise martial spirit and martial virtue, but also to the ways in which the division of labor compromises military readiness and recruitment. In making this claim, Smith subtly but importantly shifts away from republican concerns with virtue and character to a more original set of insights into how the progress of opulence decisively shapes (and indeed for the worse) national institutions.

Here, in accounting for how the population of commercial societies can grow even as its “number of fighting people” shrinks, Smith reiterates both the core concept of his paradox of national opulence and national power, and the degree to which this inverse relation is in fact “necessary.” But Smith also goes on to show that not only is it not in the individual's interest to leave behind their lucrative pursuits to go out into the field, it is also not in the nation's economic interests. “In a state where arts, manufacturing, and handicrafts are brought to perfection,” the state “cannot dispense with the laborers in this manner without the total loss of business and the destruction of the state” (LJA iv.79). Thus, another level of the paradox: not only does the structure of the labor institutions of a commercial society disincentivize military service and thereby compromise the nation's capacities for defense, but compelling artisans to leave their bench and serve in the military necessarily hampers the national economy in ways that themselves hasten the “destruction of the state.”

To bolster his argument, Smith cites several empirical case studies. One is the fall of Rome, which he traces directly to that moment when the Romans “arrived at a considerable degree of improvement both in arts and commerce” and consequently became “less fond of going out to war” (LJB 46–47; LJA iv.88; cf. LJA iv.99), aware that they “made more by their trades than by going to war” (LJB 49; LJA iv.103). Another is the fall of China to the Tartars. Ming China, he insists, was a classic instance of an advanced nation in which “the division of labor and luxury have arrived at a very high pitch” and whose “conquest is easy” as a result (LJB 332); thus, his cautionary tale of the conquest of “the indolent, effeminate, and full fed nations of the southern parts of Asia” by the “active, hardy, and hungry Tartars of the north” (WN 5.1.g.1; see Hanley, 2014). A third case is the Britain of Smith's own day. Smith clearly found troubling the Jacobite Rebellion of 1745, when “four or 5 thousand naked unarmed Highlanders took possession of the improved parts of this country without any opposition from the unwarlike inhabitants” (LJB 331; cf. LJB 159). This would have never happened in a previous age: “200 years ago such an attempt would have roused the spirit of the nation” for their “ancestors were brave and warlike, their minds were not enervated by cultivating arts and commerce, and they were already with spirit and vigor to resist the most formidable foe” (LJB 331–332)—a claim that provides the essential referent for Smith's otherwise seemingly incongruent but crucially significant claim in Wealth of Nations that “it is now more than two hundred years since the beginning of the reign of Elizabeth, a period as long as the course of human prosperity usually endures” (WN 3.4.20).

In sum, allowing workers to work and not fight is prejudicial to the nation's military strength, but compelling them to fight and not work is prejudicial to the nation's economic strength. To all this, Smith can imagine only one solution: a commercial state must have the “wisdom” in peacetime to fund and train armies of professional soldiers (Hanley, 2014, pp. 378–379). Smith's well-known defense of the superiority of standing armies to militias then is not only an intervention in a long-standing republican debate (see Montes, 2009) but an institutional response to a fundamental political problem unique to commercial modernity. It is in this context that we need to read his claim that in “an opulent and civilized nation,” a standing army “can alone defend such a nation against the invasion of a poor and barbarous neighbor” such that “the civilization of any country can be perpetuated, or even preserved for any considerable time” (WN 5.1.a.39).

National opulence provokes invasion at the same time it renders wealthy nations incapable of resisting invasion. And thus, the tragic and necessary upshot: “improvement in arts and cultivation unfit the people from going to war, so that the strength is greatly diminished and it falls a sacrifice to some of their neighbors” (LJA iv.91).

Our focus to this point has been on the external threats to national security and integrity that Smith associates with the progress of commercial opulence. But Smith also insists that advanced commercial nations are subject to internal threats—threats he here again will identify as the direct consequence of the progress of opulence. And especially striking in Smith's analysis of these internal threats is their structural similarity with the external threats. For even as Smith makes clear that the locus of these threats has shifted from external to internal, the essential dynamic at their root remains the perennial tension between rich and poor, and the constant potential for violence latent in this tension.

These are striking passages that demand to be read in several contexts. They first are to be read as evidence for Smith's fundamental belief that government exists to secure property rights.12 Yet this, while true, does not in itself account for one of the most crucial elements of the passage: the degree to which Smith believes that civil society exists not simply to preserve property rights, but also or especially to preserve those inequalities of property, and specifically those moderate rather than extreme inequalities he elsewhere claims are indispensable to commercial progress. This is an important element of Smith's argument that has been helpfully brought out in recent work on Smith and inequality,13 and has also been noted in recent work on Smith's debts to Rousseau.14 But for all this, there is another less well appreciated context for these passages. For when we set Smith's theory of the origins and ends of the government as they pertain to the first duty of the sovereign next to his account of the origins and ends of government as they pertain to the second duty of the sovereign, what becomes evident is that the fundamental constant in Smith's theory of government is the omnipresent threat of violence between rich and poor. Taken together, this attests not merely to Smith's deep sense of the fragility of civilization, but also to the degree of his awareness of two distinct threats to our fragile civilization: the external threats posed by poor nations to rich nations and the internal threats posed by poor individuals to rich individuals.

Smith's worry about the magnitude of these threats helps explain his sustained focus in both The Theory of Moral Sentiments and Wealth of Nations on the mechanisms of social order. TMS thus presents intersubjective exchanges of sympathy as fostering “the harmony of society” (TMS 1.1.4.7) and justice as the principal means of preventing social bonds from being “broke asunder” by “mutual resentment and animosity” (TMS 2.2.3.3), culminating in “the disorder and confusion of society” (TMS 2.2.3.8) that threatens to render society itself “a scene of bloodshed and disorder” (TMS 7.4.36; cf. TMS 2.2.3.6-7). Yet while these aspects of Smith's social theory are well-known, less well appreciated is his vision of the role played by commercial opulence in this destabilizing process. Smith's concerns here turn on how commercial progress reconfigures traditional social orders, and indeed often for the better. In his account of feudalism in Wealth of Nations, he famously argues that the introduction of commerce and manufactures created opportunities for economic and geographic mobility of which the least well-off were the greatest beneficiaries; “introduction of arts, commerce, and luxury” (LJA iv.157; cf. LJA iv.72; LJB 59), it is argued, severed the bonds of dependence and introduced “a revolution of the greatest importance to the public happiness” (WN 3.4.17).15 So too, “the gradual improvements of arts, manufactures and commerce, the same causes which destroyed the power of the great barons” also subverted the traditional authority of the clergy (WN 5.1.g.25; cf. WN 5.1.g.22), and also realigned authority structures in the shepherding age (WN 5.1.b.7).

In each of these instances, Smith very clearly presents the introduction of commerce and opulence as a beneficial act of creative destruction that subverts traditional authority structures and social hierarchies in ways to be welcomed. Yet elsewhere he calls attention to a darker side of this subversion, noting that the progress of opulence can also change the balance of power between social orders in potentially destabilizing ways. In his lectures on rhetoric, he gives the example of the ancient Athenians. The Athenians were once “the most enterprising and active people in all Greece,” but “commerce and luxury entirely altered the state of affairs,” giving “the lowest an opportunity of raising themselves to an equality with the nobles; and the nobles an easy way of reducing themselves to the state of the meanest citizen” (LRBL 150; Sagar, 2022, p. 198). Further, “commerce, as it introduced trade or manufacture into all the members of the state made them unwilling to attend the courts” (LRBL 151). Civic obligations thus came to be neglected amid the spread of commercial opportunity, as men who saw their labor richly rewarded became “very unwilling to leave their work for an employment which brought them no profit” (LRBL 151). The progress of commercial opulence in Athens thus proved inimical to civil participation and service, with the result that the burdens of judicial service were shifted from the rich on to the poor.

Smith elsewhere says that the same is true of the military: “when arts and luxury have in the natural progress of things been introduced into the state, and considerable improvements have been made in these, the rich and better sort of people will no longer engage in the service” (LJA iv.87-88; cf. LJA iv.93-94). The growth of commercial opulence fundamentally alters the composition of the military by drawing the “rich and better sort of people” away, creating a vacuum to be filled by others: “whenever luxury comes in after commerce and arts,” the “only people who could go out to war in this state would be the very lowest and most worthless of the people” (LJA iv.84; cf. LJA iv.169). Military service then comes to be no longer the province of “gentlemen” but rather a “mob” composed of mercenaries drawn from “the dregs of the people” (LJB 40; see also LJA iv.93). Smith finds this tragic; where once the nation was “defended by men of honor,” when “improvement of arts and manufacturers was thought an object deserving the attention of the higher ranks, the defense of the state naturally became the province of the lower.” Thus, his conclusion: “when arts and commerce are still farther advanced and begin to be very lucrative, it falls to the meanest to defend the state”—and this, he pointedly notes, is “our present condition in Great Britain” (LJB 335).

Smith uses these claims in part to point out the danger of trusting the defense of the opulent nation to mercenaries. Yet this is only part of his worry. Smith is not only troubled by the ways in which the abdication of military service by the wealthy weakens the military but also by the way in which this abdication leads to a dramatic shift in the distribution of social power, as the military becomes an institution of the poor. Smith cannot but see this as a worrisome development given his belief that “upon the ability of each particular order of society to maintain its own power, privileges, and immunities, against the encroachments of every other, depend the stability of the particular constitution,” and that a constitution is “necessarily more or less altered, whenever any of its subordinate parts is either raised above or depressed below whatever had been its former rank and condition” (TMS 6.2.2.9). Thus, even as Smith clearly welcomed social mobility, he also recognized the possibility of social instability in abrupt changes in “the established balance among the different orders and societies into which the state is divided” (TMS 6.2.2.10; see also TMS 6.2.1.20; Hill, 2006, p. 643).

Commerce's rebalancing of social power thus not only has direct effects on specific public institutions, but also on the ways in which certain social classes have access to and control over such institutions. Put in the terms of the previous section's review of external threats to security, Smith's concerns with regard to the realignment of social orders might be classified as an institutional or structural concern. But also as before, Smith identifies a moral concern on the internal front as well as an institutional concern. And also once again, he presents these moral concerns as a direct result of the progress of the division of labor. The key difference is that even as these concerns spring from a common root, the internal political problem to which they give rise is distinct from the external threats consequent to the corruption of the martial virtues.

Smith's key claim on this front is captured in one of his most striking and sweeping generalizations: “in every commercial nation the low people are exceedingly stupid” (LJB 329). The stupidity and “mental mutilation” (WN 5.1.f.60) consequent to the progress of the division of labor is of course one of the most striking elements of Smith's account of public education in the final book of the Wealth of Nations. But why does Smith think this mental mutilation is in fact a necessary condition in “every commercial nation,” and why exactly does he take this stupidity to be a political problem?16

Here Smith lays out a side of the corruption endemic to the division of labor that is distinct from the corruption of the martial virtues. For what worries him here is not the cowardice of commercial citizens but their intellectual incapacity to judge either their moral duties in private life or the interests of the nation in public life.17

Smith will soon after return to the political implications of this incapacity for judgment. In so doing, he shows that the political problem to which the corruption of the intellectual virtues gives rise is distinct from the political problem to which the corruption of the martial virtues gives rise. For while the corruption of the martial virtues renders a nation susceptible to external threats, the corruption of the intellectual virtues renders a nation susceptible to internal threats, and above all, the threats posed by a very particular sort of domestic political actor. Smith presents these threats at the end of his well-known proposal for public education at taxpayer expense. But what demands further attention is the way in which Smith presents stupidity and the corruption of the intellectual virtues as at once the product of commercial progress and also an existential threat to the integrity and stability of the state.

The corruption of the intellectual virtues threatens “the safety of government” in “free countries” by giving rise to the threat of “the most dreadful disorders.” Specifically, the corruption of judgment makes the general populace uniquely susceptible to a particular type of domestic or homegrown threat: that of self-interested religious actors who would seek to manipulate the people of “ignorant nations” via “the delusions of enthusiasm and superstition,” and self-interested party leaders and politicians who promote “faction and sedition” in order to advance their own interests. Smith elsewhere strikingly attests to the destabilizing dangers of “violent religious controversy” and “violent political faction” (WN 5.1.g.7) and insists that “the animosity of hostile factions, whether civil or ecclesiastical” is “by far the greatest” of “all the corruptors of moral sentiments” (TMS 3.3.43). It is for this reason that Smith thinks that just as only a state-funded standing army can defend opulent commercial nations from the attacks of foreign enemies to which the corruption of martial virtues makes it susceptible, only a state-funded system of education can prevent opulent states from succumbing to the domestic enemies to which the corruption of its intellectual virtues renders it susceptible.

The foregoing has sought to call attention to a paradox at the core of Smith's thought which deserves more attention than it has received. At the heart of this paradox lies Smith's understanding of the dialectical relationship between wealth and power. Restated simply: achievement of national opulence, the aim of political economy, is necessarily inimical to the maintenance of national power. The growth of opulence specifically renders nations simultaneously susceptible—to use Smith's locution in The Theory of Moral Sentiments—to threats posed by “hostile nations” without, and to threats posed by “hostile factions” within (TMS 3.3.43).

Smith's treatment of this paradox and his placement of it at the center of his political theory reveals him to be a more sophisticated political theorist than he has sometimes been taken to be. It has long been appreciated that Smith was at once a champion of both wealth and virtue. For many years, scholars treated these seemingly competing strands within his thought in terms of “liberalism” and “republicanism.”18 But in retrospect, any effort to claim Smith for either liberalism or republicanism seems as much a non-starter as the old debate over the ostensible tension between The Theory of Moral Sentiments and Wealth of Nations canonized as Das Adam Smith Problem. In both cases, what is interesting and enduring is not whether he was committed to one good or another, but rather how he synthesized them in a unified comprehensive theory. Showing that Smith both welcomed and was worried by the consequences of the progress of national opulence (see also Rasmussen, 2008) has been an aim of this study.

Yet even if this inquiry has been successful in uncovering the consistency of Smith's thought, it leaves another question unanswered: namely, that of what nations and national leaders ought to do in the face of this paradox. Smith himself repeatedly suggests that the proper end of political inquiry is political action. In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, he tells us that “political disquisitions, if just, and reasonable, and practicable, are of all the works of speculation the most useful” (TMS 4.1.11), and in his lectures on rhetoric, he insists that “the design of historical writing is not merely to entertain.” Good history does more: it “sets before us the more interesting and important events of human life, points out the causes by which these events were brought about and by this means points out to us by what manner and method we may produce similar good effects or avoid similar bad ones” (LRBL 90; see also 106, 111). If so, one might reasonably ask what lessons he expected his audience to take away from his own inquiry into and examples of national decline and fall.

The answer, I think, is twofold. First, Smith helpfully and hopefully emphasizes—especially in his published writings—that political actors are not the victims of fate but in fact can help to steer outcomes via a self-aware application of national policies. Faith that political actors can use their agency to maximize the possibility of desirable outcomes is after all central to Smith's project as a public writer; had Smith no faith in agency, his very authorship of the Wealth of Nations and its attack on British mercantile trade policy would be difficult to explain. So too, the emphasis in the Wealth of Nations on institutions (and its calls for a standing army and a public education system in particular) suggests an optimistic faith in the capacities of “the wisdom of the state” and “the science of the legislator” to mitigate politically destabilizing threats, and a worry that if practical action is “neglected,” then indeed “disorder will ensue” (LJB 310).19

At the same time, Smith's optimism must not be confused with idealism. Smith very clearly believed in human agency. But alongside his hopeful attestations of the efficacy of political action, he also insists that human action can only delay but never circumvent the inevitable. This worry is especially prominent in the jurisprudence lectures. Here, as we have seen, Smith is far from sanguine about the capacities of institutional solutions, repeatedly insisting that every government “seems to have a certain and fixed end which concludes it” (LJA iv.99), and darkly calling attention to “that fated dissolution that awaits every state and constitution whatever” (LJB 46). These explicit and repeated assertions of the inexorability of national decline and fall run counter to claims that Smith rejected “endist eschatologies” (Hill, 2019, p. 119, 122), and that his thought operated independently of “the assumption that corruption and decline is the inevitable fate of all political communities” (Sagar, 2022, p. 148). On the contrary, Smith's sustained articulation of the “causes” by which “states necessarily come to an end” (LJA iv.74-75) suggests that he was quite capable of imagining national decline and fall, and that he spoke of necessary national collapse far more explicitly and frequently than of the possibility of permanent escape from such necessity.

The fact that these concerns are especially pronounced in the jurisprudence lectures raises important interpretive questions. Among them: Does the difference in the tone of the lectures as compared to the published account in the Wealth of Nations suggest a change in substantive position on the efficacy of the institutional solutions? Or is it perhaps the case that the difference in tone can be accounted for by either exaggerations or misattributions of the transcribers, or (to my mind more likely) Smith's awareness of the differences in his audiences? This might explain why Smith, in a published book written for legislators and policymakers and influencers, would emphasize the efficacy of institutional proposals, and so conspicuously celebrate the “the powerful arm of the civil magistrate” (WN 5.1.b.2), the “wisdom of the state” (WN 5.1.a.14), and “government” and its “pains” (WN 5.1.f.50) as all that stand between civilization and its collapse, even as the lectures develop a consistently more sober (indeed somber) view of political agency in the face of necessity. Any answer to such questions can only be speculative given the evidence available and in any case requires more extensive discussion than can be provided here. My aim here has instead been to call attention to Smith's striking though underappreciated inquiry into the processes of national decline and fall, and to show that his interest in these runs deeper than the casual dismissal of them seemingly implicit in his much-quoted remark that “there is a great deal of ruin in a nation” (CAS 262n3).20 Made in the wake of General Burgoyne's Saratoga defeat, the remark tends to be taken as an effort to persuade a worried correspondent that the British Empire was robust enough to withstand losing a single battle in upstate New York. But while this accurately captures the remark's immediate context, when set in the context of his larger system, as I have sought to do here, it attests to another and darker side of Smith's political vision. In this sense Smith's 1778 remark—and indeed his inquiry into the death of nations more generally—is perhaps best read as an explication of the lesson with which his beloved teacher Hutcheson closed his own masterwork: namely that “states have within them the seeds of death and destruction”—seeds that indeed “have always occasioned the dissolution and death of every body politic” (Hutcheson, 1755, pp. 2:377–378; cf. WN 425n53).21

亚当·斯密对国家灭亡的性质和原因的探究
1776年出版了启蒙运动的两本里程碑式的著作:爱德华·吉本的多卷本《罗马帝国衰亡史》和亚当·斯密的多卷本《国家财富的性质和原因研究》。每本书都出自一位精通古代史和近代史的博学学者之手。每本书都反映了作者对18世纪主要政治经济学和道德哲学理论的深入了解。每一个时代都会在其特定的社会科学分支中掀起一场知识革命。尽管如此,这两部作品还有一个鲜为人知的相似之处:它们都在探究国家衰落和灭亡的原因。今天,我们更倾向于把这个问题与吉本而不是斯密联系在一起。我们所认识的史密斯是一个关于增长和“富裕的自然进程”的理论家,而不是一个关于衰落的理论家然而,尽管他对增长的洞见无疑构成了他对现代政治经济学出现的最公认的贡献,但将斯密仅仅作为一个增长理论家来解读,可能会让我们错过他对国家衰落原因的探究的复杂性。因此,接下来的内容颠倒了导致其他学者通过史密斯的影响来阅读吉本的因果箭头(例如,Pocock, 1999,第309-329页,2003,第372-399页),而是通过吉本的关键政治问题的镜头重新审视史密斯,以突出史密斯对国家衰落原因的研究不足。这篇阅读的主要好处在于,它澄清了斯密理论核心中一个未被重视的悖论这个悖论的核心在于斯密对国家富裕与国家权力之间必然存在的紧张关系的理解。简而言之,斯密教导说,国家富裕最终不利于国家权力;简而言之,这个悖论就是政治经济学寻求促进的经济增长最终被证明是与国家的政治利益背道而驰的因此,即使“每个国家政治经济学的伟大目标都是增加该国的财富和权力”(wn2.5.31),斯密也会反复论证,增加国家财富的离散项目颠覆了增加国家权力的离散项目。史密斯进一步认为,这种悖论既是自然的,也是必要的。这一点在他的法学讲座中对悖论的描述中尤为明显:“在所有情况下,艺术和商业的进步必然会使共和国的力量和权力发生巨大的衰退”(LJA iv.81;斜体)补充道。或者再一次:“因此,无论艺术和商业在哪里吸引公民,无论是作为工匠还是熟练的商人,城市的力量和力量一定会大大削弱”(LJA iv.85;斜体)补充道。再一次,实用技术的进步,加上“伴随而来的商业,必然会削弱这样一个国家的力量,并导致它的力量消失,直到它被一些邻近的国家吞并”(LJA iv.80-81;斜体)补充道。在最后一种表述中,特别引人注目的是,斯密坚持认为,不仅国家富裕和国家权力“必然”处于紧张状态,而且这种紧张关系的最终结局或解决方案是国家的崩溃。无论是在这里还是在其他地方,史密斯都用存在主义的术语来描述这个国家的毁灭。有人认为,他采取这种方式是为了强调潜在威胁的严重性;作为一名修辞学教师和著名的修辞学家,史密斯在其经济著作中对道德和政治问题的框架使用修辞学在今天受到了很好的赞赏(参见,例如,赫尔佐格,2013;Ortmann,Walraevans, 2022, pp. 31-65)。然而,本文的重点不在于修辞上的关注如何塑造了史密斯提出悖论的方法,而在于史密斯认为推动商业社会衰落的实质机制。为了解释斯密对这些机制的理解,在接下来的文章中,我将它们分为两个不同的标题:导致外部脆弱性的机制和导致内部脆弱性的机制。通过分解这两个不同的过程,我的目的是展示每个过程在史密斯对国家衰落的探究中的作用,并为专业学术的核心辩论做出贡献。近年来,研究斯密的学者们对腐败概念在斯密思想中的作用越来越感兴趣,并对其在斯密的道德哲学和政治理论中的重要意义进行了有益的记录接下来的内容试图通过证明史密斯实际上区分了富裕社会中两种不同类型的腐败来补充这一点。他认为,每一种类型都可以追溯到富裕的进步,他认为每一种类型都具有可识别的政治后果。 这种道德语言在他对经颅磁刺激中“穷人的儿子”的研究中尤为明显,众所周知,他把权力和财富描绘成“巨大而开放的机器,旨在为身体提供一些微不足道的便利”——机器“随时准备爆裂成碎片,把不幸的主人压成废墟”(经颅磁刺激4.1.8;参见,例如,Hill, 2017)。但史密斯不仅仅是一个道德家,他对商业腐败的道德影响的研究,实际上是对这些明显的道德变化的政治和经济原因和影响的欣赏。斯密对专业化、分工劳动的道德后果所作的引人注目的评价,最近理所当然地受到了大量关注。学术界特别感兴趣的是史密斯对这一问题提出的政治回应,特别是他实际上设想的为教育系统提供公共资金的程度,他提出了消除腐败的建议然而,对他设想的治疗方法的性质和程度的关注,使他的诊断中有两个因素没有得到充分的研究。一个是斯密在多大程度上认为这种腐化过程是自然的,而且确实是必要的;因此,斯密在这里再次坚持认为,如果政府不进行干预,这些弊病“必然”出现在“每一个进步和文明的社会”的“广大人民”中。第二,斯密认为这种腐败有几种不同的形式。斯密设想的不只是一般的品格败坏,而是“智力”美德、“社会”美德和“军事”美德的败坏。这种分解是很重要的,因为即使史密斯将这三种美德的腐败追溯到专业化劳动的重复性质,他继续认为,军事美德腐败所导致的政治问题与智力美德腐败所导致的政治问题是截然不同的。具体而言,武德的腐败增加了国家对外部威胁的易感性,而智德的腐败则增加了国家对内部威胁的易感性。史密斯对军事美德的腐化如何使一个国家容易受到外部暴力的影响的论述尤其引人注目。史密斯尽可能明确地指出:“每个社会的安全或多或少都必须始终依赖于广大人民群众的军事精神”(WN . 5.1.f.59)。损害国家的尚武精神——正如斯密明确认为的那样——就是损害国家的力量和安全。在这方面,史密斯提出了三个不同的观点。第一个是最明显的:即,丧失了尚武精神和尚武美德,富裕的公民就没有能力保卫他们富裕的国家。很简单,富有的公民是无效的战士——史密斯在他已发表和未发表的著作中反复强调这一点。因此,在他的法学讲座中,史密斯认为“商业的另一个坏影响是它削弱了人类的勇气,并倾向于熄灭斗志”(参见Heilbroner, 1973,第254页)。他解释说,之所以如此,是因为“在所有商业国家,劳动分工是无限的,每个人的思想都集中在一件事上”:使自己的劳动回报最大化。但史密斯在这里也看到了一些悲剧:“在大多数人中,军事勇气减少了”,这是他们专注于赚钱的工作的直接结果。因此,“由于他们的思想不断地用于奢侈的艺术,他们变得懦弱和卑鄙”(LJB 331)——这一谴责与史密斯在其他地方表达的观点一致,即某些类型的奢侈品如何导致“礼仪的消解”(TMS 1.2.3.4)。斯密对奢侈对军事美德的影响的批判,也与他所熟悉的古典共和主义传统保持一致,他在这里非常清楚地描绘了这种传统的比喻但是,除了这些传统的共和党人对富裕和奢侈的影响的批评之外,史密斯还提出了第二种更具原创性的批评,远远超出了传统共和党人的关注这就是他的第二个关键主张:发达商业社会对外国入侵的日益敏感,不仅是因为劳动专业化可能损害了尚武精神和尚武美德,还因为劳动分工损害了军事准备和征兵。在提出这一主张时,史密斯微妙而又重要地从共和党对美德和品格的关注转向了一套更原始的见解,即富裕的进步如何决定性地塑造(实际上是更糟糕的)国家机构。 在这里,在解释商业社会的人口如何在“战斗人口”减少的情况下增长时,斯密重申了他的国家富裕与国家权力悖论的核心概念,以及这种反比关系在多大程度上实际上是“必要的”。但斯密也继续表明,放弃赚钱的追求而进入这个领域,不仅不符合个人的利益,也不符合国家的经济利益。“在一个艺术、制造业和手工业达到完美的国家”,国家“不能以这种方式解雇工人,而不会造成商业的全面损失和国家的毁灭”(LJA iv.79)。因此,悖论的另一个层面是:商业社会的劳动制度结构不仅抑制了服兵役的积极性,从而损害了国家的国防能力,而且迫使工匠离开他们的工作岗位,在军队中服役,必然会以加速“国家毁灭”的方式阻碍国民经济。为了支持他的观点,史密斯引用了几个实证案例研究。其一是罗马的衰落,他将其直接追溯到罗马人“在艺术和商业方面都取得了相当程度的进步”,因此变得“不太喜欢出去打仗”(LJB 46-47;LJA iv.88;参见LJB iv.99),意识到他们“通过贸易赚的比打仗赚的多”(LJB 49;LJA iv.103)。另一个是中国沦陷于鞑靼人之手。他坚持认为,明朝的中国是一个先进国家的典型例子,“劳动分工和奢侈已经达到了很高的程度”,因此“很容易被征服”(LJB 332);因此,他的警世故事“懒散、柔弱、饱食的亚洲南部国家”被“活跃、顽强、饥饿的北方鞑靼人”征服(WN . 5.1.g.1);参见Hanley, 2014)。第三个例子是斯密时代的英国。史密斯清楚地发现1745年的詹姆斯党叛乱令人不安,当时“四五千名赤裸的手无寸铁的高地人在没有任何不好战的居民反对的情况下占领了这个国家的改良地区”(LJB 331;参阅LJB 159)。这在以前的时代是绝对不会发生的。“200年前,这样的尝试会唤醒民族的精神”,因为他们的“祖先是勇敢和好战的,他们的思想没有因培养艺术和商业而衰弱,他们已经充满了精神和活力来抵抗最强大的敌人”(LJB 331-332)——这一说法为史密斯在《国富论》中看似不一致但至关重要的说法提供了基本参考,即“自伊丽莎白统治开始至今已有两百多年,这段时间是人类繁荣进程通常持续的时间”(WN 3.4.20)。总而言之,允许工人工作而不工作不利于国家的军事实力,但强迫他们战斗而不工作则不利于国家的经济实力。对于这一切,史密斯只能想到一个解决方案:一个商业国家必须在和平时期有“智慧”来资助和训练专业士兵的军队(Hanley, 2014, pp. 378-379)。史密斯对常备军优于民兵的著名辩护,不仅是对长期存在的共和党辩论的干预(见蒙特斯,2009),而且是对商业现代性特有的基本政治问题的制度性回应。正是在这种背景下,我们需要阅读他的说法,即在“一个富裕和文明的国家”,一支常备军“可以独自保卫这样一个国家,抵御一个贫穷和野蛮的邻国的入侵”,这样“任何国家的文明都可以延续下去,甚至可以保存相当长的时间”(WN 5.1.a.39)。国家富裕招致侵略,同时也使富裕国家无力抵抗侵略。因此,悲剧和必要的结果是:“艺术和修养的提高使人们不适合参加战争,因此力量大大削弱,并为他们的一些邻居做出牺牲”(LJA iv.91)。在这一点上,我们的重点是对国家安全和诚信的外部威胁,史密斯将这些威胁与商业繁荣的进步联系在一起。但斯密也坚持认为,发达的商业国家会受到内部威胁——他在这里再次将这些威胁视为富裕进步的直接后果。在史密斯对这些内部威胁的分析中,特别引人注目的是它们与外部威胁在结构上的相似性。因为即使史密斯清楚地表明,这些威胁的中心已经从外部转移到内部,但其根源的基本动力仍然是富人和穷人之间长期的紧张关系,以及这种紧张关系中潜伏的持续的暴力潜力。这些引人注目的段落需要在不同的语境中阅读。 它们首先应该被解读为斯密基本信念的证据,即政府的存在是为了保护财产权然而,尽管这是对的,但它本身并不能解释这段话中最关键的因素之一:斯密认为公民社会的存在不仅仅是为了保护财产权,而且也尤其是为了保护财产的不平等,特别是那些适度而不是极端的不平等,他在其他地方声称这对商业进步是必不可少的。这是斯密论点的一个重要元素,在最近关于斯密与不平等的著作中得到了有益的提出来,在最近关于斯密欠卢梭的债的著作中也得到了注意。14但除了这些,这些段落还有另一个不太为人所知的背景。因为当我们把斯密关于政府的起源和目的的理论和他关于政府的起源和目的的理论作为君主的第一职责和他关于政府的起源和目的的理论作为君主的第二职责放在一起时,显而易见的是,斯密关于政府的理论的基本不变是富人和穷人之间无所不在的暴力威胁。综上所述,这不仅证明了斯密对文明脆弱性的深刻认识,也证明了他对我们脆弱的文明所面临的两种截然不同的威胁的认识程度:穷国对富国构成的外部威胁,以及穷国对富国构成的内部威胁。斯密对这些威胁的担忧有助于解释他在《道德情操论》和《国富论》中对社会秩序机制的持续关注。因此,经颅磁刺激将主体间的同情交流视为促进“社会和谐”(经颅磁刺激法1.1.4.7),将正义视为防止社会纽带因“相互怨恨和敌意”(经颅磁刺激法2.2.3.3)而“破裂”的主要手段,最终导致“社会的混乱和混乱”(经颅磁刺激法2.2.3.8),这可能使社会本身成为“流血和混乱的场景”(经颅磁刺激法7.4.36;参见TMS 2.2.3.6-7)。然而,尽管史密斯社会理论的这些方面众所周知,但他对商业富裕在这一不稳定过程中所起作用的看法却不太为人所知。在这里,史密斯关注的是商业进步如何重新配置传统的社会秩序,而且往往是向好的方向发展。在《国富论》(Wealth of Nations)中对封建主义的描述中,他提出了一个著名的观点:商业和制造业的引入为经济和地理流动创造了机会,而最不富裕的人是最大的受益者;“引进艺术、商业和奢侈品”(LJA iv.157;参见LJA iv.72;有人认为,它切断了依赖的纽带,并引入了“一场对公众幸福最重要的革命”(w3.4.17)同样,“艺术、制造业和商业的逐渐发展,摧毁了大贵族权力的同样原因”也颠覆了神职人员的传统权威(w5.1 .g.25;参见w5.1 .g.22),并重新调整了牧羊时代的权威结构(w5.1 .b.7)。在每一个例子中,斯密都非常清楚地将商业和富裕的引入作为一种有益的创造性破坏行为,以一种受欢迎的方式颠覆了传统的权威结构和社会等级。然而,在其他地方,他呼吁人们注意这种颠覆的阴暗面,指出富裕的进步也可能以潜在的不稳定方式改变社会秩序之间的权力平衡。在他的修辞学讲座中,他举了古代雅典人的例子。雅典人曾经是“全希腊最积极进取的民族”,但“商业和奢侈品完全改变了事态”,给了“最底层的人一个提升自己到与贵族平等地位的机会”;贵族们很容易把自己贬为最卑微的公民”(LRBL 150;Sagar, 2022,第198页)。此外,“商业将贸易或制造业引入国家的所有成员,使他们不愿出庭”(LRBL第151条)。因此,随着商业机会的扩散,公民义务被忽视了,因为看到自己的劳动得到丰厚回报的人变得“非常不愿意离开自己的工作去做一份没有利润的工作”(LRBL 151)。因此,雅典商业繁荣的进步被证明不利于公民参与和服务,其结果是司法服务的负担从富人转移到穷人身上。史密斯在其他地方说,军事也是如此:“当艺术和奢侈品在事物的自然发展中被引入国家,并且在这些方面取得了相当大的进步时,富有和更好的人将不再从事服务”(LJA iv.87-88;参见LJA iv.93-94)。 同样,《国富论》对制度的强调(特别是对常备军和公共教育体系的呼吁)表明了对“国家智慧”和“立法者科学”的能力的乐观信念,以减轻政治上不稳定的威胁,并担心如果实际行动被“忽视”,那么确实“混乱将随之而来”(LJB 310)。同时,不能把史密斯的乐观主义与理想主义混为一谈。斯密显然相信人的能动性。但是,在他满怀希望地证明政治行动的有效性的同时,他也坚持认为,人类的行动只能推迟而永远无法规避不可避免的事情。这种担忧在法学讲座中尤为突出。在这里,正如我们所看到的,史密斯对制度解决方案的能力并不乐观,他一再坚持认为,每个政府“似乎都有一个确定的、固定的结局”(LJA iv.99),并阴沉地呼吁人们注意“无论如何,每个国家和宪法都注定要解散”(LJB 46)。这些关于国家衰落和衰落不可避免的明确和反复的断言与斯密拒绝“末世论”的说法背道而驰(Hill, 2019,第119、122页),他的思想独立于“腐败和衰落是所有政治团体不可避免的命运的假设”(Sagar, 2022,第148页)。相反,斯密对“国家必然走向终结”(LJA iv.74-75)的“原因”的持续阐述表明,他相当有能力想象国家的衰落和衰落,而且他更明确、更频繁地谈到必要的国家崩溃,而不是永久逃离这种必要性的可能性。这些关切在法学讲座中特别突出,这一事实提出了重要的解释性问题。其中包括:这些演讲的语气与《国富论》中发表的叙述相比的不同,是否表明对体制解决方案效力的实质性立场发生了变化?或者,这种语调上的差异可能是由于转录者的夸张或错误归因,或者(在我看来更可能是)史密斯意识到听众的差异?这也许可以解释为什么斯密在一本为立法者、政策制定者和有影响力的人写的书中,会强调制度建议的效力,并如此明显地庆祝“民政官员的有力武器”(WN . 5.1.b.2),“国家的智慧”(WN . 5.1.a.14),以及“政府”及其“痛苦”(WN . 5.1.f.50),这些都是站在文明与文明崩溃之间的东西。即使在演讲中,面对必要性,政治机构的观点始终更加清醒(实际上是阴郁的)。鉴于现有的证据,对这些问题的任何答案都只能是推测性的,而且无论如何都需要进行比这里所能提供的更广泛的讨论。相反,我在这里的目的是提请人们注意斯密对国家衰亡过程的引人注目但未得到充分重视的探究,并表明他对这些问题的兴趣要比他那句被广泛引用的“一个国家有大量的毁灭”(CAS 262n3)中似乎暗示的对这些问题的漫不经心的忽视更深伯戈因将军在萨拉托加战败后发表的这番言论,往往被认为是为了说服忧心忡忡的记者,让他们相信大英帝国足够强大,可以承受在纽约州北部输掉一场战斗。但是,虽然这句话准确地抓住了这句话的直接背景,但当我把它放在他更大的体系中(正如我在这里试图做的那样),它证明了史密斯政治愿景的另一个阴暗面。从这个意义上说,史密斯1778年的评论——以及他对国家死亡的更广泛的调查——也许最好被解读为对他敬爱的老师哈钦森在他自己的杰作中总结的教训的解释:即“国家内部有死亡和毁灭的种子”——这些种子确实“总是引起每个政体的解体和死亡”(哈钦森,1755年,第2页:377 - 378;参考文献:wn425n53).21
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信