Misuse of Guidelines Could Disadvantage and Harm Patients

IF 3.6 2区 医学 Q1 MEDICINE, GENERAL & INTERNAL
Ernest W Lau, Hendrik Bonnemeier, Benito Baldauf
{"title":"Misuse of Guidelines Could Disadvantage and Harm Patients","authors":"Ernest W Lau,&nbsp;Hendrik Bonnemeier,&nbsp;Benito Baldauf","doi":"10.1111/jebm.12666","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Guidelines are increasingly regarded as the “reference standards” in clinical decision making. Randomized controlled trials (RCTs) top the evidence hierarchy used in guidelines synthesis. If the RCTs show positive results, their inclusion and exclusion criteria become the treatment's indications (Class I–II). Contrariwise, the characteristics for the subgroups who experience more harm than benefit become the contra-indications (Class III). RCTs involving human participants could not be designed to show a treatment is ineffective or harmful by the Declaration of Helsinki [<span>1</span>]. All the contra-indications known for a treatment are from either totally unexpected outcomes from RCTs or rare adverse events that only emerge under long term surveillance.</p><p>RCTs were developed to provide reliable objective assessment of the effectiveness of medical treatments [<span>2</span>]. Because most medical treatments are only modestly effective, very large sample sizes and prolonged follow-up are needed for adequate statistical powers to detect treatment effects, making RCTs prohibitively expensive to run. To maximize the chance of “positive” results, RCTs set very stringent inclusion and exclusion criteria so that only patients most likely to benefit and least likely to suffer harm from the investigated treatments are enrolled. RCTs are mostly funded by commercial companies even if they are conducted by academic institutes and healthcare facilities. The stated reason of many RCTs is to compare the safety and efficacy of treatment options for a disease to help patients. The unstated reason that compels and motivates companies to fund costly RCTs is the legal requirement for regulatory approval before they could market medical products. Benefiting patients and protecting them from harm come as the incidental consequences of companies’ fiduciary duties to their shareholders. The tool (RCTs) used by companies to serve their own interests is “co-opted” by learned societies for synthesizing guidelines intended to help doctors make clinical decisions. The “misuse” of any tool for unintended purposes would likely result in sub-optimal outcomes.</p><p>While RCTs might excel in “internal validity,” they disappoint in “external validity”—their results might not be generalizable to patient populations outside [<span>3, 4</span>]. About 80% of RCTs excluded ≥50% the patients screened for enrollment [<span>5</span>]. For the excluded (unstudied) patients, the RCTs are “agnostic” on their benefit: risk balance for the treatment (Figure 1a). No evidence for benefit (Figure 1a) is not equivalent to evidence of no benefit (Figure 1b). Many patient groups are under-represented in RCTs for factors (e.g. age, co-morbidities, etc.) or protected characteristics (gender, ethnicity, etc.) which may not influence their response to a treatment. A default assumption of no benefit for all patient groups omitted from RCTs would unfairly deprive numerous potential beneficiaries of life-saving or improving treatments. It would be a gross misuse of guidelines with a huge potential of causing health inequality to justify denial of treatments to patients purely on the basis of no evidence of benefit because they have been “excluded,” “neglected” in RCTs for nonmedical reasons [<span>6</span>]. Moreover, the treatment effects demonstrated in RCTs might not be replicated in patients outside the tightly controlled settings anyway. “Real world evidence” based on “real world data” is needed to confirm the safety and efficacy of treatments “proven” in RCTs in widespread clinical use [<span>7</span>].</p><p>An indication class in guidelines gives a rough estimate of the “average probability” that a patient would derive more benefit than harm from a treatment, but a good clinical outcome is not guaranteed. Within the same guideline indication class, some patients would benefit more than others, and some patients might even suffer harm rather than benefit. The indication classes listed in guidelines give the false impression that benefit: risk balance of a treatment falls into discrete categories separated by “quantum” leaps. In reality, the benefit: risk balance of a treatment more likely forms a continuum. Guidelines are misused if a patient's likely clinical response and treatment decision are “pigeonholed” into one of these rigid categories like the proverbial “Procrustean bed” [<span>8</span>]. Patients in distinct guidelines indication categories may differ marginally rather than substantially in their benefit: risk balances. Personalized medicine aims to tailor treatments more “precisely” for patients as individuals rather than “generic” members of a cohort [<span>9</span>]. Personalization of treatments could also be assessed in RCTs [<span>10</span>].</p><p>The nonequivalence of no evidence of benefit and evidence of no benefit extends to medical conditions so rare that enough patients for RCTs or registries could not be found. In such a situation, “expert opinions” (EO) [<span>11</span>] and “limited data” (LD) from physiological and mechanistic studies might be the only evidence available [<span>12</span>]. The American College of Cardiology and American Heart Association system of recommendation classes EO and LD as the lowest (least reliable) Level of Evidence (LOE) C, with the proviso that:</p><p>“A recommendation with LOE C does not imply the recommendation is weak. Many important clinical questions addressed in guidelines do not lend themselves to clinical trials. Although RCTs are unavailable, there may be a very clear clinical consensus that a particular test or therapy is useful or effective.”</p><p>The qualification “<i>a very clear clinical consensus</i>” is not precisely defined (e.g. how many or what proportion of experts need to agree; how are these experts chosen [<span>11</span>]) and conduces to disagreement. The 2013 version of the Declaration of Helsinki permits a physician to use a nonproven intervention to help a patient when no alternative therapies exist or existent therapies are ineffective, with due informed consent and expert opinions [<span>1</span>]. Without instances of “off-label” use of nonproven treatments, “<i>a very clear clinical consensus</i>” would never emerge. To deny patients access to and denounce doctors for trialing a potentially beneficial but nonproven treatment would be a misuse of guidelines.</p><p>LOE C-EO is based on “expert opinions” [<span>11</span>], which are by definition subjective and hence may vary among different groups/people at any one time and shift within the same group/person over time. The “primacy” of the opinions of the few selected (or self-selected) experts involved in guidelines synthesis over those held by the much larger pool of their peers not so involved should not be automatic. Doctors not involved in guidelines synthesis should still be allowed to pass their own personal “expert opinions” in assessing the benefit: risk balance of a treatment for patients under their care, forming a new level of evidence LOE C#-EO (Figure 1c). The merit of an opinion rests on the verity of its premises, validity of its logical deductions, and not the identity or status of its proponents. Doctors managing patients clinically know many nuanced aspects of their medical histories not easily captured in RCTs and reflected in guidelines and may also have fewer conflicts of interest. They also bear full professional and legal responsibilities for their clinical decisions. Patients should be informed of the full spectrum of professional opinions on their management options even if and especially when there is disagreement among doctors.</p><p>The indications for a treatment in clinical guidelines typically focus on the characteristics of the patient. However, provider factors (center's volume; operator's experience) could also influence the outcomes to a treatment, especially when the treatment is an invasive intervention. RCTs give the outcomes for an invasive procedure averaged over many centers and operators. The indication classification in clinical guidelines may thus not be reflective of the likely clinical outcome if a patient receives the treatment from a particular provider. High volume centers and operators tend to produce better outcomes than low volume centers and operators, even on frail and challenging patients. Providers’ experience and confidence in their ability to execute an invasive procedure successfully is likely to influence and even determine their willingness to offer the treatment to patients [<span>13</span>]. Providers may exist in competition rather than collaboration and hence are reluctant to cross-refer even if that would be in the patients’ best interests. Doctors have the duty to inform patients of these caveats about invasive treatments when discussing management options. Clinical guidelines typically do not include provider factors in the indications for a treatment.</p><p>Clinical guidelines are not legally binding. While they would be taken into consideration, compliance with and deviation from guidelines would not automatically result in exoneration or punishment by the court [<span>14, 15</span>]. The legal system operates its own standards for determining medical negligence and malpractice. Doctors could and need to exercise judgement in their use of guidelines.</p><p>All tools have their proper uses but could produce unintended results if misused. Guidelines are clinical decision support tools to help clinicians improve the outcomes for patients through “better” decisions. However, if a good outcome is the ultimate goal, the decision leading to it cannot be judged on its own without taking into account its execution. A “sound” decision could be ruined by “botched” implementation; a “unsound” decision could be salvaged by “masterful” execution. Rule compliance is a mean to the end (a good clinical outcome) and should not become the end itself. What the patient cares about is the outcome and not the process. Narrow interpretation and rigid application of clinical guidelines without taking into account the many caveats expounded above is a misuse that could disadvantage and even harm patients.</p><p>The authors declare no conflicts of interest.</p>","PeriodicalId":16090,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Evidence‐Based Medicine","volume":"17 4","pages":"705-707"},"PeriodicalIF":3.6000,"publicationDate":"2024-12-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11684497/pdf/","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Evidence‐Based Medicine","FirstCategoryId":"3","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jebm.12666","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"MEDICINE, GENERAL & INTERNAL","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Guidelines are increasingly regarded as the “reference standards” in clinical decision making. Randomized controlled trials (RCTs) top the evidence hierarchy used in guidelines synthesis. If the RCTs show positive results, their inclusion and exclusion criteria become the treatment's indications (Class I–II). Contrariwise, the characteristics for the subgroups who experience more harm than benefit become the contra-indications (Class III). RCTs involving human participants could not be designed to show a treatment is ineffective or harmful by the Declaration of Helsinki [1]. All the contra-indications known for a treatment are from either totally unexpected outcomes from RCTs or rare adverse events that only emerge under long term surveillance.

RCTs were developed to provide reliable objective assessment of the effectiveness of medical treatments [2]. Because most medical treatments are only modestly effective, very large sample sizes and prolonged follow-up are needed for adequate statistical powers to detect treatment effects, making RCTs prohibitively expensive to run. To maximize the chance of “positive” results, RCTs set very stringent inclusion and exclusion criteria so that only patients most likely to benefit and least likely to suffer harm from the investigated treatments are enrolled. RCTs are mostly funded by commercial companies even if they are conducted by academic institutes and healthcare facilities. The stated reason of many RCTs is to compare the safety and efficacy of treatment options for a disease to help patients. The unstated reason that compels and motivates companies to fund costly RCTs is the legal requirement for regulatory approval before they could market medical products. Benefiting patients and protecting them from harm come as the incidental consequences of companies’ fiduciary duties to their shareholders. The tool (RCTs) used by companies to serve their own interests is “co-opted” by learned societies for synthesizing guidelines intended to help doctors make clinical decisions. The “misuse” of any tool for unintended purposes would likely result in sub-optimal outcomes.

While RCTs might excel in “internal validity,” they disappoint in “external validity”—their results might not be generalizable to patient populations outside [3, 4]. About 80% of RCTs excluded ≥50% the patients screened for enrollment [5]. For the excluded (unstudied) patients, the RCTs are “agnostic” on their benefit: risk balance for the treatment (Figure 1a). No evidence for benefit (Figure 1a) is not equivalent to evidence of no benefit (Figure 1b). Many patient groups are under-represented in RCTs for factors (e.g. age, co-morbidities, etc.) or protected characteristics (gender, ethnicity, etc.) which may not influence their response to a treatment. A default assumption of no benefit for all patient groups omitted from RCTs would unfairly deprive numerous potential beneficiaries of life-saving or improving treatments. It would be a gross misuse of guidelines with a huge potential of causing health inequality to justify denial of treatments to patients purely on the basis of no evidence of benefit because they have been “excluded,” “neglected” in RCTs for nonmedical reasons [6]. Moreover, the treatment effects demonstrated in RCTs might not be replicated in patients outside the tightly controlled settings anyway. “Real world evidence” based on “real world data” is needed to confirm the safety and efficacy of treatments “proven” in RCTs in widespread clinical use [7].

An indication class in guidelines gives a rough estimate of the “average probability” that a patient would derive more benefit than harm from a treatment, but a good clinical outcome is not guaranteed. Within the same guideline indication class, some patients would benefit more than others, and some patients might even suffer harm rather than benefit. The indication classes listed in guidelines give the false impression that benefit: risk balance of a treatment falls into discrete categories separated by “quantum” leaps. In reality, the benefit: risk balance of a treatment more likely forms a continuum. Guidelines are misused if a patient's likely clinical response and treatment decision are “pigeonholed” into one of these rigid categories like the proverbial “Procrustean bed” [8]. Patients in distinct guidelines indication categories may differ marginally rather than substantially in their benefit: risk balances. Personalized medicine aims to tailor treatments more “precisely” for patients as individuals rather than “generic” members of a cohort [9]. Personalization of treatments could also be assessed in RCTs [10].

The nonequivalence of no evidence of benefit and evidence of no benefit extends to medical conditions so rare that enough patients for RCTs or registries could not be found. In such a situation, “expert opinions” (EO) [11] and “limited data” (LD) from physiological and mechanistic studies might be the only evidence available [12]. The American College of Cardiology and American Heart Association system of recommendation classes EO and LD as the lowest (least reliable) Level of Evidence (LOE) C, with the proviso that:

“A recommendation with LOE C does not imply the recommendation is weak. Many important clinical questions addressed in guidelines do not lend themselves to clinical trials. Although RCTs are unavailable, there may be a very clear clinical consensus that a particular test or therapy is useful or effective.”

The qualification “a very clear clinical consensus” is not precisely defined (e.g. how many or what proportion of experts need to agree; how are these experts chosen [11]) and conduces to disagreement. The 2013 version of the Declaration of Helsinki permits a physician to use a nonproven intervention to help a patient when no alternative therapies exist or existent therapies are ineffective, with due informed consent and expert opinions [1]. Without instances of “off-label” use of nonproven treatments, “a very clear clinical consensus” would never emerge. To deny patients access to and denounce doctors for trialing a potentially beneficial but nonproven treatment would be a misuse of guidelines.

LOE C-EO is based on “expert opinions” [11], which are by definition subjective and hence may vary among different groups/people at any one time and shift within the same group/person over time. The “primacy” of the opinions of the few selected (or self-selected) experts involved in guidelines synthesis over those held by the much larger pool of their peers not so involved should not be automatic. Doctors not involved in guidelines synthesis should still be allowed to pass their own personal “expert opinions” in assessing the benefit: risk balance of a treatment for patients under their care, forming a new level of evidence LOE C#-EO (Figure 1c). The merit of an opinion rests on the verity of its premises, validity of its logical deductions, and not the identity or status of its proponents. Doctors managing patients clinically know many nuanced aspects of their medical histories not easily captured in RCTs and reflected in guidelines and may also have fewer conflicts of interest. They also bear full professional and legal responsibilities for their clinical decisions. Patients should be informed of the full spectrum of professional opinions on their management options even if and especially when there is disagreement among doctors.

The indications for a treatment in clinical guidelines typically focus on the characteristics of the patient. However, provider factors (center's volume; operator's experience) could also influence the outcomes to a treatment, especially when the treatment is an invasive intervention. RCTs give the outcomes for an invasive procedure averaged over many centers and operators. The indication classification in clinical guidelines may thus not be reflective of the likely clinical outcome if a patient receives the treatment from a particular provider. High volume centers and operators tend to produce better outcomes than low volume centers and operators, even on frail and challenging patients. Providers’ experience and confidence in their ability to execute an invasive procedure successfully is likely to influence and even determine their willingness to offer the treatment to patients [13]. Providers may exist in competition rather than collaboration and hence are reluctant to cross-refer even if that would be in the patients’ best interests. Doctors have the duty to inform patients of these caveats about invasive treatments when discussing management options. Clinical guidelines typically do not include provider factors in the indications for a treatment.

Clinical guidelines are not legally binding. While they would be taken into consideration, compliance with and deviation from guidelines would not automatically result in exoneration or punishment by the court [14, 15]. The legal system operates its own standards for determining medical negligence and malpractice. Doctors could and need to exercise judgement in their use of guidelines.

All tools have their proper uses but could produce unintended results if misused. Guidelines are clinical decision support tools to help clinicians improve the outcomes for patients through “better” decisions. However, if a good outcome is the ultimate goal, the decision leading to it cannot be judged on its own without taking into account its execution. A “sound” decision could be ruined by “botched” implementation; a “unsound” decision could be salvaged by “masterful” execution. Rule compliance is a mean to the end (a good clinical outcome) and should not become the end itself. What the patient cares about is the outcome and not the process. Narrow interpretation and rigid application of clinical guidelines without taking into account the many caveats expounded above is a misuse that could disadvantage and even harm patients.

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

Abstract Image

误用指南可能对患者造成不利和伤害。
指南越来越被视为临床决策的“参考标准”。随机对照试验(RCTs)在指南合成中使用的证据等级中居首位。如果随机对照试验显示阳性结果,其纳入和排除标准成为治疗的适应症(Class I-II)。相反,危害大于益处的亚组的特征成为禁忌症(III类)。根据《赫尔辛基宣言》,涉及人类参与者的随机对照试验不能设计成表明治疗无效或有害。已知治疗的所有禁忌症要么来自随机对照试验的完全意想不到的结果,要么来自只有在长期监测下才出现的罕见不良事件。随机对照试验的发展是为了对医学治疗的有效性提供可靠的客观评估[b]。由于大多数医学治疗的效果一般,因此需要非常大的样本量和长时间的随访才能获得足够的统计能力来检测治疗效果,这使得随机对照试验的运行成本过高。为了最大限度地提高“阳性”结果的机会,随机对照试验设定了非常严格的纳入和排除标准,以便只招募最有可能从所研究的治疗中受益、最不可能遭受伤害的患者。随机对照试验大多由商业公司资助,即使它们是由学术机构和医疗机构进行的。许多随机对照试验的原因是为了比较一种疾病的治疗方案的安全性和有效性,以帮助患者。迫使和激励公司为昂贵的随机对照试验提供资金的未明说的原因是,在销售医疗产品之前,法律要求获得监管机构的批准。造福患者并保护他们免受伤害,是公司对股东负有受托责任的附带结果。公司为自己的利益而使用的工具(随机对照试验)被学术团体“吸收”为综合指南,旨在帮助医生做出临床决策。“误用”任何工具来达到意想不到的目的都可能导致次优结果。虽然随机对照试验可能在“内部效度”方面表现出色,但在“外部效度”方面却令人失望——它们的结果可能无法推广到外部的患者群体[3,4]。约80%的rct排除了≥50%的入组筛选患者。对于被排除(未研究)的患者,随机对照试验对其获益:治疗的风险平衡是“不可知论”的(图1a)。无益处证据(图1a)并不等同于无益处证据(图1b)。许多患者群体在随机对照试验中代表性不足,因为这些因素(如年龄、合并症等)或受保护的特征(性别、种族等)可能不会影响他们对治疗的反应。对所有被排除在随机对照试验之外的患者群体都没有获益的默认假设,将不公平地剥夺许多潜在的救命或改善治疗的受益者。如果仅仅因为患者在随机对照试验中因非医学原因被“排除”、“忽视”,而在没有任何益处的证据的基础上拒绝对患者进行治疗,这将是对指南的严重滥用,极有可能造成健康不平等。此外,随机对照试验中显示的治疗效果可能无法在严格控制环境之外的患者中复制。需要基于“真实世界数据”的“真实世界证据”来确认在广泛临床应用的随机对照试验中“证明”的治疗方法的安全性和有效性[10]。指南中的适应症分类给出了一个粗略的“平均概率”估计,即患者从治疗中获得的益处大于伤害,但不能保证良好的临床结果。在相同的指南适应症类别中,有些患者会比其他患者受益更多,有些患者甚至可能遭受伤害而不是受益。指南中列出的适应症类别给人一种错误的印象,即治疗的益处:风险平衡属于由“量子”飞跃分隔的离散类别。实际上,治疗的好处:风险平衡更可能形成一个连续体。如果患者可能的临床反应和治疗决定被“归类”到这些严格的类别中,比如众所周知的“普洛克斯坦床”(Procrustean bed),指南就会被滥用。不同指南指征类别的患者在获益风险平衡方面可能存在轻微差异,而不是实质性差异。个性化医疗旨在更“精确”地为个体患者量身定制治疗方案,而不是为队列中的“普通”成员量身定制治疗方案。治疗的个性化也可以在随机对照试验bbb中进行评估。无益处证据和无益处证据的不等价性延伸到非常罕见的疾病,以至于无法找到足够的患者进行随机对照试验或登记。在这种情况下,来自生理和机制研究的“专家意见”(EO)和“有限数据”(LD)可能是唯一可用的证据([12])。 美国心脏病学会和美国心脏协会将EO和LD推荐为最低(最不可靠)的证据水平(LOE) C,附带条件是:“具有LOE C的推荐并不意味着推荐是弱的。指南中提到的许多重要临床问题并不适合临床试验。虽然没有随机对照试验,但可能有一个非常明确的临床共识,即特定的测试或治疗是有用或有效的。”“非常明确的临床共识”的资格没有精确定义(例如,需要多少或多大比例的专家同意;这些专家是如何被挑选出来的?2013年版的《赫尔辛基宣言》(Declaration of Helsinki)允许医生在没有替代疗法或现有疗法无效的情况下,使用未经证实的干预措施来帮助患者,但需征得患者的知情同意和专家意见。如果没有“标签外”使用未经证实的治疗方法的例子,“一个非常明确的临床共识”就永远不会出现。拒绝患者使用并谴责医生试验一种可能有益但未经证实的治疗方法,将是对指导方针的误用。love C-EO基于“专家意见”,根据定义,这是主观的,因此可能在任何时候在不同的群体/人之间有所不同,并且随着时间的推移在同一群体/人内部发生变化。参与指南合成的少数被选中(或自我选择)的专家的意见的“首要地位”,不应该是自动的,而不是由更多的同行持有的意见。不参与指南合成的医生仍应被允许通过他们个人的“专家意见”来评估他们所照顾的患者的治疗的收益:风险平衡,形成一个新的证据水平loec# -EO(图1c)。一种意见的价值在于其前提的真实性,其逻辑推论的有效性,而不在于其支持者的身份或地位。临床管理患者的医生了解患者病史的许多细微方面,这些方面不容易在随机对照试验中被捕捉到,也不容易在指南中得到反映,而且可能也较少有利益冲突。他们也对他们的临床决定承担全部的专业和法律责任。患者应该被告知关于他们的管理选择的所有专业意见,即使特别是当医生之间存在分歧时。临床指南中治疗的适应症通常侧重于患者的特征。然而,供应商因素(中心的数量;操作者的经验)也会影响治疗的结果,特别是当治疗是一种侵入性干预时。随机对照试验给出了侵入性手术在许多中心和运营商之间的平均结果。因此,临床指南中的适应症分类可能不能反映患者接受特定提供者治疗的可能临床结果。大容量的中心和运营商往往比小容量的中心和运营商产生更好的结果,即使是虚弱和有挑战性的病人。提供者成功实施侵入性手术的经验和信心可能会影响甚至决定他们向患者提供治疗的意愿。供应商可能存在于竞争而不是合作中,因此不愿意交叉转诊,即使这符合患者的最大利益。在讨论治疗方案时,医生有责任告知患者这些关于侵入性治疗的注意事项。临床指南通常不包括治疗指征中的提供者因素。临床指南没有法律约束力。虽然会考虑到这些准则,但遵守或偏离准则并不会自动导致法院免除或惩罚[14,15]。法律体系有自己的医疗过失和医疗事故判定标准。医生可以也需要在使用指南时进行判断。所有工具都有其适当的用途,但如果使用不当,可能会产生意想不到的结果。指南是临床决策支持工具,帮助临床医生通过“更好”的决策来改善患者的预后。然而,如果一个好的结果是最终目标,那么在不考虑其执行情况的情况下,就不能单独判断导致这个结果的决定。一个“合理的”决定可能会被“拙劣的”执行毁掉;一个“不合理”的决定可以通过“娴熟”的执行来挽救。遵守规则是达到目的的手段(良好的临床结果),不应成为目的本身。病人关心的是结果,而不是过程。对临床指南的狭隘解释和严格应用,而不考虑上述许多警告,是一种误用,可能使患者处于不利地位,甚至伤害患者。作者声明无利益冲突。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
Journal of Evidence‐Based Medicine
Journal of Evidence‐Based Medicine MEDICINE, GENERAL & INTERNAL-
CiteScore
11.20
自引率
1.40%
发文量
42
期刊介绍: The Journal of Evidence-Based Medicine (EMB) is an esteemed international healthcare and medical decision-making journal, dedicated to publishing groundbreaking research outcomes in evidence-based decision-making, research, practice, and education. Serving as the official English-language journal of the Cochrane China Centre and West China Hospital of Sichuan University, we eagerly welcome editorials, commentaries, and systematic reviews encompassing various topics such as clinical trials, policy, drug and patient safety, education, and knowledge translation.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信