Aligning the “single law” proposal to the CRPD standard of “will and preferences”

IF 73.3 1区 医学 Q1 Medicine
World Psychiatry Pub Date : 2024-09-16 DOI:10.1002/wps.21233
Jakov Gather, Matthé Scholten
{"title":"Aligning the “single law” proposal to the CRPD standard of “will and preferences”","authors":"Jakov Gather, Matthé Scholten","doi":"10.1002/wps.21233","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Galderisi et al<span><sup>1</sup></span> provide an excellent overview of the complex ethical challenges in psychiatry. We subscribe to the authors’ criticism of mental health laws employing a “disorder + risk” schema for involuntary intervention, and their conclusion that these laws discriminate against people with a mental health condition. The authors put forward instead a “single law” proposal in which “involuntary treatment would only be permitted when the objecting person has an impairment of decision-making ability – from any cause – and if treatment is in the person's best interests”<span><sup>1</sup></span>. We strongly endorse the core of this proposal, but would like to suggest three refinements to it.</p>\n<p>First, we propose combining capacity assessment with supported decision-making, to ensure that no one is found to lack decision-making capacity before all reasonably available resources of supported decision-making have been exhausted. Second, we propose replacing the best interests standard by the substituted judgment standard, to achieve a closer alignment of substitute decisions with the will and preferences of the person concerned. Third, we suggest to explicitly define additional criteria for involuntary intervention, to avoid what we will call “the fallacious inference from substitute decision-making to coercion”. The proposed refinements are based on what we call the “combined supported decision-making model”, a model for the informed consent process that provides a non-discriminatory basis for decision-making about involuntary intervention<span><sup>2-5</sup></span>. In this commentary, we focus on the last two refinements.</p>\n<p>Galderisi et al refer to a terminological distinction used in a judgment of the German Federal Constitutional Court to show that the “single law” proposal is consistent with the general principles of the United Nations (UN) Convention on the Rights of People with Disabilities (CRPD) and the wording of Article 12, particularly its insistence that “measures relating to the exercise of legal capacity respect the rights, will and preferences of the person”. The terminological distinction is between “free will” (<i>freier Wille</i>) and “natural will” (<i>natürlicher Wille</i>), which, according to the authors, maps on to the CRPD's distinction between “will” and “preferences”.</p>\n<p>This terminological distinction plays an important role in the legal discourse around the German guardianship law (<i>Betreuungsrecht</i>), which is part of the German Civil Code and applies to all people who need support in managing their own affairs, regardless of whether they have a mental health condition<span><sup>6</sup></span>. The term “free will” (<i>freier Wille</i>) refers to the contemporaneous preferences of a person who possesses decision-making capacity regarding the decision at hand. Expressions of a person's free will must be respected by clinicians and have the status of consent or withdrawal of consent; that is, they can make interventions permissible which would otherwise be not permissible and vice versa. The term “natural will” (<i>natürlicher Wille</i>), on the other hand, refers to the contemporaneous preferences of a person who lacks decision-making capacity regarding the decision at hand. Expressions of a person's natural will must be carefully considered in medical decision-making but can, in some instances, be overridden based on other considerations, to be specified below. They amount to what is commonly described as “assent” and “dissent” in the research ethics literature. Any medical intervention against a person's natural will (i.e., any medical intervention to which the person dissents) counts as “coercive medical treatment” (<i>ärztliche Zwangsmaßnahme</i>) under German guardianship law and is hence subject to strict conditions.</p>\n<p>Galderisi et al propose that expressions of a person's natural will can only be overridden if doing so is in the person's best interests. Although the authors make clear that the standard of best interests should be interpreted subjectively in terms of the person's beliefs and values, we are concerned that it will nonetheless be understood objectively in clinical practice. The best interests standard originally derives from a paternalistic “doctor knows best” approach and – despite the authors’ careful qualifications – may be understood by clinicians in the light of what Hawkins<span><sup>7</sup></span> calls “welfare medicalism”, the persistent idea among clinicians that what is in a person's best interests is what is medically indicated in the person's situation. To avoid this potential misunderstanding, we propose replacing the best interests standard by the substituted judgment standard. This latter standard gives center stage to the person's will and preferences: it assigns to the substitute decision-maker the task of making the treatment decision that the person would have made if he/she had had decision-making capacity<span><sup>8</sup></span>.</p>\n<p>German guardianship law employs a substituted judgment standard and requires that substitute decisions be justified by reference to concrete evidence about the person's will and preferences<span><sup>6</sup></span>. The law introduces two additional concepts in this context. The first is that of the person's “previously declared will” (<i>vorausverfügter Wille</i>), denoting the preferences that a person has documented in an advance directive at a time at which he/she had decision-making capacity. Advance directives are legally binding under the German Civil Code and apply to both physical and mental health conditions. The second concept is that of the person's “presumed will” (<i>mutmaßlicher Wille</i>), denoting the preferences of a person which can be reconstructed based on the preferences and personal values and convictions that he/she expressed when he/she had decision-making capacity. In accord with the substituted judgment approach, the person's previously declared or presumed will serves as a proxy for the person's free will.</p>\n<p>Consistency with the person's previously declared or presumed will is a necessary condition for the permissibility of involuntary treatment under German guardianship law. This means that, if this consistency is not ascertained, involuntary treatment may not be carried out – even if withholding treatment is not in the objective best interests of the person. All references to the term “well-being” (<i>Wohl</i>) were omitted from the guardianship law during the latest reform to underline this, even though the term was understood subjectively before the reform<span><sup>6</sup></span>.</p>\n<p>We now turn to the fallacious inference from substituted decision-making to coercion. It is often assumed that, if a medical intervention is consistent with the person's previously declared or presumed will, that intervention may be carried out involuntarily against the person's natural will. This inference is invalid. The reason is that consistency with the person's previously declared or presumed will is a necessary but not sufficient condition for the permissibility of involuntary intervention.</p>\n<p>While Galderisi et al in no way make the fallacious inference from substituted decision-making to coercion, we believe that it is important to make explicit and emphasize that additional criteria must be fulfilled for an involuntary intervention to be justified. Besides being consistent with the person's previously declared or presumed will, an involuntary intervention must also be suitable, necessary and proportionate in order to be permissible<span><sup>9</sup></span>. An involuntary intervention is <i>suitable</i> if it is effective in preventing the person from behaving in ways that are inconsistent with his/her previously declared or presumed will. It is <i>necessary</i> if there are no less restrictive alternatives to prevent the person from behaving in these ways. It is <i>proportionate</i> if its risk-benefit profile is more favorable than that of the option of not carrying out the intervention. Only if these three criteria are met may the person's previously declared or presumed will be prioritized over his/her natural will, and the involuntary intervention be carried out. If any of these three conditions is not met, involuntary intervention is not permissible and the person's natural will or contemporaneous preferences must be followed.</p>\n<p>Implementation of the “single law” proposal would be a major step forward for psychiatry. We believe that the proposal can be brought into closer alignment with the CRPD's standard of “will and preferences” if capacity assessment is combined with supported decision-making; the best interests standard is replaced by the substituted judgment standard; and the proposed additional criteria for involuntary intervention are explicitly added.</p>","PeriodicalId":23858,"journal":{"name":"World Psychiatry","volume":"237 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":73.3000,"publicationDate":"2024-09-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"World Psychiatry","FirstCategoryId":"3","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1002/wps.21233","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"Medicine","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Galderisi et al1 provide an excellent overview of the complex ethical challenges in psychiatry. We subscribe to the authors’ criticism of mental health laws employing a “disorder + risk” schema for involuntary intervention, and their conclusion that these laws discriminate against people with a mental health condition. The authors put forward instead a “single law” proposal in which “involuntary treatment would only be permitted when the objecting person has an impairment of decision-making ability – from any cause – and if treatment is in the person's best interests”1. We strongly endorse the core of this proposal, but would like to suggest three refinements to it.

First, we propose combining capacity assessment with supported decision-making, to ensure that no one is found to lack decision-making capacity before all reasonably available resources of supported decision-making have been exhausted. Second, we propose replacing the best interests standard by the substituted judgment standard, to achieve a closer alignment of substitute decisions with the will and preferences of the person concerned. Third, we suggest to explicitly define additional criteria for involuntary intervention, to avoid what we will call “the fallacious inference from substitute decision-making to coercion”. The proposed refinements are based on what we call the “combined supported decision-making model”, a model for the informed consent process that provides a non-discriminatory basis for decision-making about involuntary intervention2-5. In this commentary, we focus on the last two refinements.

Galderisi et al refer to a terminological distinction used in a judgment of the German Federal Constitutional Court to show that the “single law” proposal is consistent with the general principles of the United Nations (UN) Convention on the Rights of People with Disabilities (CRPD) and the wording of Article 12, particularly its insistence that “measures relating to the exercise of legal capacity respect the rights, will and preferences of the person”. The terminological distinction is between “free will” (freier Wille) and “natural will” (natürlicher Wille), which, according to the authors, maps on to the CRPD's distinction between “will” and “preferences”.

This terminological distinction plays an important role in the legal discourse around the German guardianship law (Betreuungsrecht), which is part of the German Civil Code and applies to all people who need support in managing their own affairs, regardless of whether they have a mental health condition6. The term “free will” (freier Wille) refers to the contemporaneous preferences of a person who possesses decision-making capacity regarding the decision at hand. Expressions of a person's free will must be respected by clinicians and have the status of consent or withdrawal of consent; that is, they can make interventions permissible which would otherwise be not permissible and vice versa. The term “natural will” (natürlicher Wille), on the other hand, refers to the contemporaneous preferences of a person who lacks decision-making capacity regarding the decision at hand. Expressions of a person's natural will must be carefully considered in medical decision-making but can, in some instances, be overridden based on other considerations, to be specified below. They amount to what is commonly described as “assent” and “dissent” in the research ethics literature. Any medical intervention against a person's natural will (i.e., any medical intervention to which the person dissents) counts as “coercive medical treatment” (ärztliche Zwangsmaßnahme) under German guardianship law and is hence subject to strict conditions.

Galderisi et al propose that expressions of a person's natural will can only be overridden if doing so is in the person's best interests. Although the authors make clear that the standard of best interests should be interpreted subjectively in terms of the person's beliefs and values, we are concerned that it will nonetheless be understood objectively in clinical practice. The best interests standard originally derives from a paternalistic “doctor knows best” approach and – despite the authors’ careful qualifications – may be understood by clinicians in the light of what Hawkins7 calls “welfare medicalism”, the persistent idea among clinicians that what is in a person's best interests is what is medically indicated in the person's situation. To avoid this potential misunderstanding, we propose replacing the best interests standard by the substituted judgment standard. This latter standard gives center stage to the person's will and preferences: it assigns to the substitute decision-maker the task of making the treatment decision that the person would have made if he/she had had decision-making capacity8.

German guardianship law employs a substituted judgment standard and requires that substitute decisions be justified by reference to concrete evidence about the person's will and preferences6. The law introduces two additional concepts in this context. The first is that of the person's “previously declared will” (vorausverfügter Wille), denoting the preferences that a person has documented in an advance directive at a time at which he/she had decision-making capacity. Advance directives are legally binding under the German Civil Code and apply to both physical and mental health conditions. The second concept is that of the person's “presumed will” (mutmaßlicher Wille), denoting the preferences of a person which can be reconstructed based on the preferences and personal values and convictions that he/she expressed when he/she had decision-making capacity. In accord with the substituted judgment approach, the person's previously declared or presumed will serves as a proxy for the person's free will.

Consistency with the person's previously declared or presumed will is a necessary condition for the permissibility of involuntary treatment under German guardianship law. This means that, if this consistency is not ascertained, involuntary treatment may not be carried out – even if withholding treatment is not in the objective best interests of the person. All references to the term “well-being” (Wohl) were omitted from the guardianship law during the latest reform to underline this, even though the term was understood subjectively before the reform6.

We now turn to the fallacious inference from substituted decision-making to coercion. It is often assumed that, if a medical intervention is consistent with the person's previously declared or presumed will, that intervention may be carried out involuntarily against the person's natural will. This inference is invalid. The reason is that consistency with the person's previously declared or presumed will is a necessary but not sufficient condition for the permissibility of involuntary intervention.

While Galderisi et al in no way make the fallacious inference from substituted decision-making to coercion, we believe that it is important to make explicit and emphasize that additional criteria must be fulfilled for an involuntary intervention to be justified. Besides being consistent with the person's previously declared or presumed will, an involuntary intervention must also be suitable, necessary and proportionate in order to be permissible9. An involuntary intervention is suitable if it is effective in preventing the person from behaving in ways that are inconsistent with his/her previously declared or presumed will. It is necessary if there are no less restrictive alternatives to prevent the person from behaving in these ways. It is proportionate if its risk-benefit profile is more favorable than that of the option of not carrying out the intervention. Only if these three criteria are met may the person's previously declared or presumed will be prioritized over his/her natural will, and the involuntary intervention be carried out. If any of these three conditions is not met, involuntary intervention is not permissible and the person's natural will or contemporaneous preferences must be followed.

Implementation of the “single law” proposal would be a major step forward for psychiatry. We believe that the proposal can be brought into closer alignment with the CRPD's standard of “will and preferences” if capacity assessment is combined with supported decision-making; the best interests standard is replaced by the substituted judgment standard; and the proposed additional criteria for involuntary intervention are explicitly added.

使 "单一法律 "提案符合《残疾人权利公约》的 "意愿和偏好 "标准
加尔德里西等人1 对精神病学所面临的复杂伦理挑战进行了精彩的概述。我们赞同作者对采用 "障碍+风险 "模式进行非自愿干预的精神健康法律的批评,以及他们认为这些法律歧视精神疾病患者的结论。作者提出了一个 "单一法律 "的建议,即 "只有当反对者因任何原因导致决策能力受损,并且治疗符合其最大利益时,才允许非自愿治疗 "1 。首先,我们建议将能力评估与辅助决策结合起来,以确保在用尽所有可合理利用的辅助决策资源之前,不会发现任何人缺乏决策能力。第二,我们建议用替代判断标准取代最佳利益标准,使替代决定更符合当事人的意愿和偏好。第三,我们建议明确界定非自愿干预的附加标准,以避免我们称之为 "从替代决策到胁迫的谬误推论"。建议的改进措施是以我们所说的 "综合辅助决策模式 "为基础的,该模式是知情同 意程序的一种模式,它为非自愿干预的决策提供了一个非歧视性的基础2-5 。Galderisi 等人提到了德国联邦宪法法院在一份判决中使用的术语区别,以表明 "单一法律 "提案符合联合国《残疾人权利公约》(CRPD)的一般原则和第 12 条的措辞,特别是该条坚持 "与行使法律能力有关的措施应尊重个人的权利、意愿和偏好"。这种术语上的区别在围绕德国监护法(Betreuungsrecht)的法律讨论中发挥了重要作用,该法是德国民法典的一部分,适用于所有在管理自己事务方面需要帮助的人,无论他们是否有精神健康问题6。自由意志"(freier Wille)一词指的是具有决策能力的人对当前决定的当时选择。临床医生必须尊重一个人的自由意愿,并使其具有同意或撤回同意的地位;也就是说,自由意愿可以使原本不允许的干预行为变得允许,反之亦然。另一方面,"自然意愿"(natürlicher Wille)一词指的是缺乏决策能力的人对当前决定的当时偏好。在医疗决策过程中,必须仔细考虑一个人的自然意愿表达,但在某些情况下,基于其他考虑因素,也可以推翻其自然意愿表达,具体说明如下。它们相当于研究伦理文献中通常所说的 "同意 "和 "反对"。根据德国监护法,任何违背个人自然意愿的医疗干预(即个人不同意的任何医疗干预)都属于 "强制医疗"(ärztliche Zwangsmaßnahme),因此必须遵守严格的条件。尽管作者明确指出,最佳利益标准应根据当事人的信仰和价值观进行主观解释,但我们担心在临床实践中仍会对其进行客观理解。最佳利益标准最初源于家长式的 "医生知道什么是最好的 "方法,而且--尽管作者小心翼翼地进行了限定--临床医生可能会根据 Hawkins7 所称的 "福利医疗主义 "来理解最佳利益标准,即临床医生始终认为,符合当事人最佳利益的做法就是在当事人的情况下具有医学意义的做法。为了避免这种潜在的误解,我们建议用替代判断标准取代最佳利益标准。后一种标准将当事人的意愿和偏好置于中心位置:它将做出当事人如果有决策能力时会做出的治疗决定的任务分配给替代决策者8。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
World Psychiatry
World Psychiatry Nursing-Psychiatric Mental Health
CiteScore
64.10
自引率
7.40%
发文量
124
期刊介绍: World Psychiatry is the official journal of the World Psychiatric Association. It aims to disseminate information on significant clinical, service, and research developments in the mental health field. World Psychiatry is published three times per year and is sent free of charge to psychiatrists.The recipient psychiatrists' names and addresses are provided by WPA member societies and sections.The language used in the journal is designed to be understandable by the majority of mental health professionals worldwide.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信