Misinterpreting Negativism: on Peter E. Gordon's A Precarious Happiness: Adorno and the Sources of Normativity

IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Fabian Freyenhagen
{"title":"Misinterpreting Negativism: on Peter E. Gordon's A Precarious Happiness: Adorno and the Sources of Normativity","authors":"Fabian Freyenhagen","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13005","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Adorno scholarship has come a long way in the last twenty years. His philosophy was long overshadowed by the accusation of being too negative. This accusation was made not just from outside of the Frankfurt School research tradition, but crucially also within it, especially from Jürgen Habermas, often portrayed as the leading figure of its “2nd generation”. In Habermas's case the accusation took different forms—sometimes it is about Adorno's theory lacking the standing for social critique; sometimes it is about its lacking normative foundations; and sometimes it is about performative contradiction (between the content of saying that the social world is thoroughly distorted by ideology and the act of saying that). The upshot is meant to be the same in each case: we need a positive normative resource which then provides the standard with which to criticise our social world. That led then to various debates about what that positive standard should be—communicative action, recognition/social freedom, or the right to justification (to name three prominent answers by Habermas, Honneth, and Forst respectively). Especially in the last two decades, there has been more push-back against the accusation (and the purported positive standards). Some—including (full disclosure!) I—have insisted that Adorno's taking a negativistic stance is defensible and, indeed, preferable to the supposedly positive alternatives.</p><p>It is into this context that Gordon seeks to intervene, with his newest book. He rejects the negativistic revival of Adorno, despite accepting that the textual evidence for a negativist interpretation appear to be strong (p. 5). Like Habermas, he thinks we need a positive standard for social critique, but, unlike Habermas, Gordon thinks that such a positive standard can be found in Adorno's work. He is not alone in thinking this – Gordon Finlayson and Martin Seel are among the earlier examples of interpretations which ascribe a positive core to Adorno's philosophy. What is more specific to Gordon, is that he suggests that the ‘source’ of normativity of Adorno's critical theory of society is a ‘maximalist demand for happiness’ in the broad sense of human flourishing (pp. xvi-xviii and <i>passim</i>, especially Chapter 2). It is this demand that animates Adorno's materialist ‘ethics of vulnerability’ (pp. 15, 196–197). The demand for happiness is immanent in the social world, notably in certain experiences and elements that have anticipatory character (pp. 46, 56–57, 70, 210), pointing to complete flourishing and alluding to the good even in the distorted instances of happiness that the wrong social world affords us (pp. 54–57, 70–71). In this way, precarious happiness (or precarious experience of happiness) gives us a glimpse of complete, comprehensive happiness; and is the source for immanent social critique.</p><p>Gordon clearly thinks that an orientation towards human flourishing has much to recommend it, albeit he does not offer an independent justification of it in this book. In part, this is because he recognises that Adorno rejected demands for normative foundation (pp. xvii, 213–214). While Gordon ultimately hopes that Adorno's account of precarious happiness can be brought ‘into alignment with a theory of intersubjectivist justification’, he notes that this ‘lies well beyond the purview of this book’ (p. 215).</p><p>I will concentrate here on discussing critically Gordon's rejection of negativism. This rejection is pivotal to Gordon's re-interpretation of Adorno in the book (and the lectures on which it is based). Other topics get covered—such as Adorno's take on emphatic concepts (Chapter 2) and aesthetics (especially Chapters 5–6)—but they are all coloured by the rejection of negativism, which is the book's ‘chief argument’ (xvii).</p><p>A lot depends, unsurprisingly, what is meant by negativism. While there are some fairly agreed meanings in the relevant literature, there is also a tendency to conflate negativism with other positions or concepts. Indeed, the danger of being shipwrecked on such conflations and confusions is real, as unfortunately demonstrated by Gordon's book.</p><p>Together these three main forms combine in a way that seems to make Adorno's radical critique of the modern social world possible: it is a bad social world in which we can know what is bad (and, as we will see later, <i>only</i> the bad), but this knowledge suffices to demand that the social world be overcome (and for being motivated to work towards overcoming it).</p><p>Gordon does not really engage with metaethical negativism, although, in the final analysis, I think this is where the action is (I come back to this below). His main worries, on the face of it, attach to ascribing substantive (and epistemic) negativism to Adorno. It is not always clear what exactly he is objecting to; and there is quite a bit slippage between different options. I will reconstruct and discuss three different variants in turn.</p><p>First, Gordon worries that ascribing substantive (and epistemic) negativism to Adorno is inconsistent with Adorno's commitment that the modern capitalist world is not a seamless totality but ridden by contradictions (pp. 18–20). I agree that Adorno is committed to the latter, but this is entirely compatible with ascribing substantive negativism to him. For the claim that the social world is deeply problematic ethically speaking does not exclude that it is contradictory. Indeed, one of the reasons for thinking that this world is problematic might well be (and in Adorno's case, arguably, is) that it is, and cannot but be, ridden by contradictions, such as, a contradiction between exploiting labour power and our natural world to the maximum and having to reproduce them. Such a claim is compatible with negativism, especially (as, again, is, arguably, the case for Adorno) when the persistence of these contradictions has negative effects on human beings. A substantive negativist, including a substantive negativist such as Adorno, can accept that society is ridden by contradictions; that there are experiences that are in tension with continuing the status quo (notably experiences of suffering from it); that social critique can build on these experiences and, thus, be immanent (in Gordon's sense); and that this can translate into acts of resistance or even attempts at radical social change. In short, saying that society instantiates the bad, is not the same as saying that it is a seamless totality; and saying that we have (and need) only access to knowledge of the bad in that society, is compatible with saying that it is contradictory, and that people experience this and strive to overcome society.</p><p>It should be obvious that none of the forms of negativism characterised above—neither epistemic nor substantive nor metaethical—implies, requires, or equates to this sort of Gnosticism. In this context, it may help to state clearly that negativism is not the same as pessimism, while Gnosticism is a form of absolute pessimism. One can think that we only can and do know what is bad about our social world and that it is a thoroughly bad social world, but still think that this bad social world can be criticised and overcome, and even be optimistic that it will be overcome. The former—epistemic and substantive negativism—are about what can be known in a specific situation and a normative judgement about that situation; the latter—affirming the possibility of being able to criticise and overcome the bad social world—is a modal claim about leaving that situation, and making it is entirely compatible with the epistemic and normative judgement. Think of an analogy (inspired by a negativist poem by Brecht): if I am in a burning house, I might think that this house is so thoroughly on fire that it cannot be salvaged and that, while I might not know what is outside the house positively, I can and do know that burning alive is a bad that we should avoid, and take this as a sufficient reason to leave the house; and I can think all this, while also thinking that it is, indeed, possible to leave the house and be optimistic that this can be achieved, despite its being difficult in various ways, given that it is so thoroughly on fire.</p><p>Third, Gordon is concerned that ascribing substantive or epistemic negativism to Adorno commits him to total normative scepticism, while such scepticism is neither independently warranted nor plausible as interpretation of what Adorno writes (pp. 6, 18, 25, 91–92). Here, Gordon's lack of real engagement with metaethical negativism becomes a problem. For unless one rejected metaethical negativism, there is no reason to think that a substantive or epistemic negativist must be a total normative sceptic. Indeed, those who have proposed a negativist reading of Adorno's works, have maintained that normative substance remains: a minimalist ethics of resistance, centred around his new categorical imperative ‘to arrange [our] thoughts and actions so that Auschwitz will not repeat itself, so that nothing similar will happen’ (Adorno <span>1973</span>: 365; see Freyenhagen <span>2013</span>: Chapters 5–6). And Gordon clearly knows that negativist readings of Adorno include ethical and other normative substance (pp. 16–17).</p><p>What might be driving his opposition is that he thinks we can and need to ascribe to Adorno more than a minimalist ethics (pp. 70, 197).<sup>1</sup> In response, it is first important to note that even a minimalist ethics is not the same as total normative scepticism. So, it is unwarranted to think—as Gordon suggests—that ascribing substantive or epistemic negativism to Adorno commits Adorno to total normative scepticism.</p><p>Moreover, one crucially important aspect of the negativism (and minimalist ethics) ascribed to Adorno is continuously overlooked by Gordon: it has a historical index. The claim is not that, according to Adorno, human beings can never know what the good is. Instead, the claim is that in our current socio-historical situation, we cannot know it. Why not? It is so for broadly Aristotelian and Hegelian reasons: the good is indexed to humanity, and we can only know the good once humanity is (fully) realised in a social formation, rather than existing in unrealised and crippled form, which is the case with our current social world (and also with past societies).</p><p>However, this historically indexed epistemic limitation is not an insurmountable (practical or philosophical) problem for us today. The negative characterisation—knowing what inhumanity is—suffices (epistemically and metaethically) for the view that our current social world should be resisted and overcome. In a future free association of the free, we could then know what humanity is (realised as it would be then), which would allow us to know what the good is, and would provide the necessary ingredients for a more than minimalist ethics—for not just a <i>minima moralia</i>, but a <i>magna moralia</i>. For now, we must and can make do with the former.</p><p>This means that, in a specific, limited way, negativism is compatible with ascribing to Adorno a <i>demand</i> for human flourishing and with the postulate that there is an unrealised potential. The problem with Gordon's account is that he thinks that statements about potential or about pointing beyond the bad social world or about elements with anticipatory character must be incompatible with negativism (for example, pp. 23, 26), while, in fact, in a specific qualified form they are perfectly compatible with it (as seen in the previous paragraph and explicated further below). Moreover, the problem is that he moves from rightly ascribing statements to Adorno in that specific qualified form to ascribing to him statements in a form that is incompatible with Adorno's works, such as speaking of a (positive) glimpse of the right life, momentary or otherwise (p. 57). For Adorno has it that ‘In the right condition, … all things would differ only a little from the way they are; but <i>not the least</i> can be conceived now as it would be then’ (1973: 299; my emphasis).</p><p>As I will return to below, it might help to understand such a negativist—and, I submit, Adorno—as operating with a <i>tripartite</i> (bad, neutral, good), rather than a two-part (bad, good) <i>normative logic</i>: the contrary of the bad is a state of a certain kind of survival, but that state still falls short of the good; when we know the bad, we might know what such state of survival is, but we have not gained yet sufficient insight into the good to know it positively; still, knowing what the good is not (i.e., knowing what the bad is), will go a long way in knowing what to avoid and what to do, and we can still allude to and aim for something beyond the state of survival, even if we cannot positively say what it is. (Consider a parallel to the World Health Organization's famous definition of health, which is also tripartite: health is not merely the absence of illness and infirmity, but a state of complete physical, mental and social well-being. Even without knowing what such complete state would be, medicine and society can do a lot to alleviate or cure disease and infirmity; and we can thereby allude to and work towards gaining knowledge of this complete state of wellbeing and towards making it a reality.)</p><p>Gordon's own characterisation comes sometimes close to this form of negativism, such as when drawing the following lesson from Adorno's new categorical imperative: ‘material suffering becomes the negative standard against which all possible happiness must find its measure’ (p. 203); and commenting ‘the concept of happiness resembles a Kantian postulate’ (p. 95). Here the avoidance of material suffering (and a second Auschwitz) is seen as a necessary condition for happiness, and given normative and metaethical priority over the good (whatever happiness is, it is <i>not that</i>). And the talk of postulate is telling: Kant's whole point about freedom, God, and (immortality of) the soul as postulates was that we can have no knowledge of their inner workings or nature; that they transcend the bounds of what we can make sense of. Similarly with negativism and the good—with the one key difference being the historical index in case of negativism; contrary to the ahistorical, a priori status of Kant's epistemic block.</p><p>Epistemic negativism in Adorno's case is, then, not scepticism about the (possible) existence of positive norms. It is not a metaphysical thesis and especially not an ahistorical thesis. Instead, it is a thesis about what we can know in a particular socio-historical situation—a thesis that is compatible not just with the existence of positive norms, but also with (possible future) knowledge of such norms in a different (possible future) socio-historical situation.</p><p>On the other hand, Gordon thinks it is mistaken to assume that ‘no imperfect version of x can count as an x’, that no ‘imperfect experience of the good can really count as a genuine instance of the good’ (p. 85). He thinks that this is mistaken because the human world in general is marked by damage, such that the first quotation above would then rule out any access to the genuine good. And because Gordon thinks that Adorno recognises this about the ‘constitution of the human world’ (p. 90), Gordon ultimately thinks that despite the ‘compromised’ nature of happiness (or experiences thereof) in today's wrong social world (p. 195), Adorno accepts that they are genuine instances of happiness (or genuine experience thereof)—fleeting, precarious, but genuine. This suggests that Gordon implicitly resolves the inconsistency between ascribing to Adorno both the view that ‘distorted happiness is not genuine happiness at all’ and the view ‘that distorted happiness is in a precarious fashion genuine happiness’, by siding with the latter.</p><p>This strikes me as a mistake. As emphasised above, Adorno is making a historically indexed claim about the constitution of a particular social world (and not one about the constitution of the human world as such). Moreover, Gordon again conflates two points: accepting the claim about lacking access to genuine happiness with the claim that the imperfect experiences ‘must wholly lack any merit’ (p. 90) in virtue of not sufficing to give us access to genuine happiness. Even if the experiences do not give us access to the real (positive) thing (‘genuine happiness’), this does not mean they are without merit. Among other merits they might have, is one that Gordon himself notes: such experiences may serve as an anticipation or ‘trace’ of a universal fulfilment that is not yet at hand, but should be. They may serve, in other words, as utopian impulse that things should be different, albeit not as positive glimpses of how it would be then.</p><p>Overall, it, perhaps, makes best sense of Gordon's position that he rejects metaethical negativism, and this is why he cannot see that epistemic and substantive negativism does not lead to total normative scepticism (and that negativism is compatible with alluding to potential for a realised humanity and its genuine happiness). Yet, while rejecting meta-ethical negativism makes his position more intelligible, the problem is then that Gordon seems to simply assume what needs to be shown: that metaethical negativism is untenable.</p><p>The closest Gordon comes to providing the beginning of an argument against meta-ethical negativism is when he complains that we need ‘contrasting normative standards’ to be able to identify the false, wrong or bad as false, wrong, or bad. This is a known objection to meta-ethical negativism, but there is an existing response in the literature: we might indeed require contrasts for identifying something as bad, but different degrees (and dimensions) of badness suffice for this (Freyenhagen <span>2013</span>: 225–228). Similarly, a tripartite logic (bad, neutral, good) can allow identification of the bad without knowledge of the good. There is no rejoinder in Gordon's book to this existing response on behalf of (meta-ethical) negativism. Instead, his rejection of the latter mainly seems to function as a background assumption, much as it does with Habermas and others.</p><p>Generally, one of the main concerns I had while reading Gordon's book is the lack of questioning of the framing imposed by Habermas and those following in his wake onto debates about Adorno. Implicitly ruling out metaethical negativism is one aspect of this. Another aspect is to accept that social critique must be about measuring using a standard (for example, p. 117)—thinking of the social critic as akin to a surveyor who ultimately relies on the standard meter traditionally kept in Paris. Gordon does not even mention that this is a contestable and indeed contested picture of social critique. In the literature, there are other ways of thinking about social critique, including about Adorno's version thereof (see, notably, Vogelmann <span>2017</span>).</p><p>In sum, (Adorno's) negativism is neither the same as nor committed to (i) a view of society as seamless totality without contradictions; (ii) pessimism; (iii) Gnosticism; (iv) total normative scepticism; or (v) the view that human beings can never know the good. Yet, Gordon, in this book, conflates or confuses negativism with one, the other, or all of them—and that then fuels the worries he directs at negativism, when, actually, these are orthogonal to it.</p><p>Gordon identifies this not explicitly as a challenge to negativism, but others do so (Hemmerich <span>2024</span>); and we can understand what he says to include this challenge.</p><p>So, what warrant could there be for the Asymmetry Thesis that we can know inhumanity (and the bad) but not humanity (and the human good) in our social world, given Adorno's global description of that world as delusional? As far as I can tell, Adorno does not explicitly or directly address that challenge. There is some evidence that he thinks that the negative connects to visceral bodily reactions that can be rationalised away in our conscious engagement with them or out of which we might even be habituated to some extent, but which cannot be completely eliminated and to which we would do well to remain responsive. This is (part of) what Adorno means when saying, after introducing the new categorical imperative, that ‘It is in the unvarnished materialistic motive only that morality survives’; or when, earlier in <i>Negative Dialectics</i>, he affirms that ‘Woe speaks: “Go.”’ (1973: 365, 203).</p><p>However, in a way that just transposes the challenge: it is not clear why we should accept that only woe speaks ‘go’ in our social world and not also that joy speaks ‘come’; or that we have only visceral reactions (in this social world) to the negative, but not to the positive (or at least none which we can make legitimate use of in a critical theory of society). So, the Asymmetry Thesis seems to remain unwarranted.</p><p>It is here where Gordon's book might—somewhat inadvertently—provide a hint to a possible solution. Gordon emphasises that Adorno's account of flourishing is ‘<i>comprehensive</i> in the sense that it envisions a state of affairs that would satisfy all human needs and desires at once’ (p. 97; Gordon's italics; see also p. 99); and in the sense of applying ‘across the full range of Adorno's philosophical interests’ (p. 193), notably encompassing aesthetics, and thereby human needs and desires to do with aesthetics. One way to put this point, would be to say that Adorno is a certain kind of holist about the (human) good—whatever it is, the good must fit together as a comprehensive multi-dimensional whole. (This might have to do with the Aristotelian-Hegelian background of his thought, and the long tradition of thinking of the virtues as forming a unity, such that it would be wrong to ask about what courage is in complete isolation of asking what generosity, prudence, etc. are.)</p><p>Against the background of such holism, the Asymmetry Thesis might become more plausible and defensible, especially if we also add the Hegelian point about not being able to anticipate something philosophically that has not yet taken on social reality (about the owl of the Miverva's only flying after the day's work is done). Adorno might be read to say either that the bad forms itself a comprehensive whole, but we have encountered it already as realised in social reality (notably in Auschwitz), and hence can know the bad; or that the bad does not form a comprehensive whole but only the good does, such that knowledge of the bad can be partial, even while knowledge of the good cannot be partial. Either way, the good qua comprehensive whole has not yet been realised in social reality (past or present). Whatever partial elements of the good we might encounter in our current or past social worlds, it cannot be anticipated philosophically how these fit together into a comprehensive whole, before it becomes social reality qua comprehensive whole in a possible future social world. And for this reason, we can only know the bad, but not the good in our social world. That world is one which prevents the formation of the comprehensive whole that is the (human) good. We have reason to want to overcome our social world in virtue of this fundamental defect and the evils that come with it. There is no need to appeal to anything positive—be it communicative action or even precarious happiness. Instead of lamenting the epistemic limitations of our current historical situation and seeking harbour where there is none, we should embrace the freedom of thought to negate all and head for the open ocean.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 4","pages":"1353-1360"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9000,"publicationDate":"2024-09-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13005","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.13005","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Adorno scholarship has come a long way in the last twenty years. His philosophy was long overshadowed by the accusation of being too negative. This accusation was made not just from outside of the Frankfurt School research tradition, but crucially also within it, especially from Jürgen Habermas, often portrayed as the leading figure of its “2nd generation”. In Habermas's case the accusation took different forms—sometimes it is about Adorno's theory lacking the standing for social critique; sometimes it is about its lacking normative foundations; and sometimes it is about performative contradiction (between the content of saying that the social world is thoroughly distorted by ideology and the act of saying that). The upshot is meant to be the same in each case: we need a positive normative resource which then provides the standard with which to criticise our social world. That led then to various debates about what that positive standard should be—communicative action, recognition/social freedom, or the right to justification (to name three prominent answers by Habermas, Honneth, and Forst respectively). Especially in the last two decades, there has been more push-back against the accusation (and the purported positive standards). Some—including (full disclosure!) I—have insisted that Adorno's taking a negativistic stance is defensible and, indeed, preferable to the supposedly positive alternatives.

It is into this context that Gordon seeks to intervene, with his newest book. He rejects the negativistic revival of Adorno, despite accepting that the textual evidence for a negativist interpretation appear to be strong (p. 5). Like Habermas, he thinks we need a positive standard for social critique, but, unlike Habermas, Gordon thinks that such a positive standard can be found in Adorno's work. He is not alone in thinking this – Gordon Finlayson and Martin Seel are among the earlier examples of interpretations which ascribe a positive core to Adorno's philosophy. What is more specific to Gordon, is that he suggests that the ‘source’ of normativity of Adorno's critical theory of society is a ‘maximalist demand for happiness’ in the broad sense of human flourishing (pp. xvi-xviii and passim, especially Chapter 2). It is this demand that animates Adorno's materialist ‘ethics of vulnerability’ (pp. 15, 196–197). The demand for happiness is immanent in the social world, notably in certain experiences and elements that have anticipatory character (pp. 46, 56–57, 70, 210), pointing to complete flourishing and alluding to the good even in the distorted instances of happiness that the wrong social world affords us (pp. 54–57, 70–71). In this way, precarious happiness (or precarious experience of happiness) gives us a glimpse of complete, comprehensive happiness; and is the source for immanent social critique.

Gordon clearly thinks that an orientation towards human flourishing has much to recommend it, albeit he does not offer an independent justification of it in this book. In part, this is because he recognises that Adorno rejected demands for normative foundation (pp. xvii, 213–214). While Gordon ultimately hopes that Adorno's account of precarious happiness can be brought ‘into alignment with a theory of intersubjectivist justification’, he notes that this ‘lies well beyond the purview of this book’ (p. 215).

I will concentrate here on discussing critically Gordon's rejection of negativism. This rejection is pivotal to Gordon's re-interpretation of Adorno in the book (and the lectures on which it is based). Other topics get covered—such as Adorno's take on emphatic concepts (Chapter 2) and aesthetics (especially Chapters 5–6)—but they are all coloured by the rejection of negativism, which is the book's ‘chief argument’ (xvii).

A lot depends, unsurprisingly, what is meant by negativism. While there are some fairly agreed meanings in the relevant literature, there is also a tendency to conflate negativism with other positions or concepts. Indeed, the danger of being shipwrecked on such conflations and confusions is real, as unfortunately demonstrated by Gordon's book.

Together these three main forms combine in a way that seems to make Adorno's radical critique of the modern social world possible: it is a bad social world in which we can know what is bad (and, as we will see later, only the bad), but this knowledge suffices to demand that the social world be overcome (and for being motivated to work towards overcoming it).

Gordon does not really engage with metaethical negativism, although, in the final analysis, I think this is where the action is (I come back to this below). His main worries, on the face of it, attach to ascribing substantive (and epistemic) negativism to Adorno. It is not always clear what exactly he is objecting to; and there is quite a bit slippage between different options. I will reconstruct and discuss three different variants in turn.

First, Gordon worries that ascribing substantive (and epistemic) negativism to Adorno is inconsistent with Adorno's commitment that the modern capitalist world is not a seamless totality but ridden by contradictions (pp. 18–20). I agree that Adorno is committed to the latter, but this is entirely compatible with ascribing substantive negativism to him. For the claim that the social world is deeply problematic ethically speaking does not exclude that it is contradictory. Indeed, one of the reasons for thinking that this world is problematic might well be (and in Adorno's case, arguably, is) that it is, and cannot but be, ridden by contradictions, such as, a contradiction between exploiting labour power and our natural world to the maximum and having to reproduce them. Such a claim is compatible with negativism, especially (as, again, is, arguably, the case for Adorno) when the persistence of these contradictions has negative effects on human beings. A substantive negativist, including a substantive negativist such as Adorno, can accept that society is ridden by contradictions; that there are experiences that are in tension with continuing the status quo (notably experiences of suffering from it); that social critique can build on these experiences and, thus, be immanent (in Gordon's sense); and that this can translate into acts of resistance or even attempts at radical social change. In short, saying that society instantiates the bad, is not the same as saying that it is a seamless totality; and saying that we have (and need) only access to knowledge of the bad in that society, is compatible with saying that it is contradictory, and that people experience this and strive to overcome society.

It should be obvious that none of the forms of negativism characterised above—neither epistemic nor substantive nor metaethical—implies, requires, or equates to this sort of Gnosticism. In this context, it may help to state clearly that negativism is not the same as pessimism, while Gnosticism is a form of absolute pessimism. One can think that we only can and do know what is bad about our social world and that it is a thoroughly bad social world, but still think that this bad social world can be criticised and overcome, and even be optimistic that it will be overcome. The former—epistemic and substantive negativism—are about what can be known in a specific situation and a normative judgement about that situation; the latter—affirming the possibility of being able to criticise and overcome the bad social world—is a modal claim about leaving that situation, and making it is entirely compatible with the epistemic and normative judgement. Think of an analogy (inspired by a negativist poem by Brecht): if I am in a burning house, I might think that this house is so thoroughly on fire that it cannot be salvaged and that, while I might not know what is outside the house positively, I can and do know that burning alive is a bad that we should avoid, and take this as a sufficient reason to leave the house; and I can think all this, while also thinking that it is, indeed, possible to leave the house and be optimistic that this can be achieved, despite its being difficult in various ways, given that it is so thoroughly on fire.

Third, Gordon is concerned that ascribing substantive or epistemic negativism to Adorno commits him to total normative scepticism, while such scepticism is neither independently warranted nor plausible as interpretation of what Adorno writes (pp. 6, 18, 25, 91–92). Here, Gordon's lack of real engagement with metaethical negativism becomes a problem. For unless one rejected metaethical negativism, there is no reason to think that a substantive or epistemic negativist must be a total normative sceptic. Indeed, those who have proposed a negativist reading of Adorno's works, have maintained that normative substance remains: a minimalist ethics of resistance, centred around his new categorical imperative ‘to arrange [our] thoughts and actions so that Auschwitz will not repeat itself, so that nothing similar will happen’ (Adorno 1973: 365; see Freyenhagen 2013: Chapters 5–6). And Gordon clearly knows that negativist readings of Adorno include ethical and other normative substance (pp. 16–17).

What might be driving his opposition is that he thinks we can and need to ascribe to Adorno more than a minimalist ethics (pp. 70, 197).1 In response, it is first important to note that even a minimalist ethics is not the same as total normative scepticism. So, it is unwarranted to think—as Gordon suggests—that ascribing substantive or epistemic negativism to Adorno commits Adorno to total normative scepticism.

Moreover, one crucially important aspect of the negativism (and minimalist ethics) ascribed to Adorno is continuously overlooked by Gordon: it has a historical index. The claim is not that, according to Adorno, human beings can never know what the good is. Instead, the claim is that in our current socio-historical situation, we cannot know it. Why not? It is so for broadly Aristotelian and Hegelian reasons: the good is indexed to humanity, and we can only know the good once humanity is (fully) realised in a social formation, rather than existing in unrealised and crippled form, which is the case with our current social world (and also with past societies).

However, this historically indexed epistemic limitation is not an insurmountable (practical or philosophical) problem for us today. The negative characterisation—knowing what inhumanity is—suffices (epistemically and metaethically) for the view that our current social world should be resisted and overcome. In a future free association of the free, we could then know what humanity is (realised as it would be then), which would allow us to know what the good is, and would provide the necessary ingredients for a more than minimalist ethics—for not just a minima moralia, but a magna moralia. For now, we must and can make do with the former.

This means that, in a specific, limited way, negativism is compatible with ascribing to Adorno a demand for human flourishing and with the postulate that there is an unrealised potential. The problem with Gordon's account is that he thinks that statements about potential or about pointing beyond the bad social world or about elements with anticipatory character must be incompatible with negativism (for example, pp. 23, 26), while, in fact, in a specific qualified form they are perfectly compatible with it (as seen in the previous paragraph and explicated further below). Moreover, the problem is that he moves from rightly ascribing statements to Adorno in that specific qualified form to ascribing to him statements in a form that is incompatible with Adorno's works, such as speaking of a (positive) glimpse of the right life, momentary or otherwise (p. 57). For Adorno has it that ‘In the right condition, … all things would differ only a little from the way they are; but not the least can be conceived now as it would be then’ (1973: 299; my emphasis).

As I will return to below, it might help to understand such a negativist—and, I submit, Adorno—as operating with a tripartite (bad, neutral, good), rather than a two-part (bad, good) normative logic: the contrary of the bad is a state of a certain kind of survival, but that state still falls short of the good; when we know the bad, we might know what such state of survival is, but we have not gained yet sufficient insight into the good to know it positively; still, knowing what the good is not (i.e., knowing what the bad is), will go a long way in knowing what to avoid and what to do, and we can still allude to and aim for something beyond the state of survival, even if we cannot positively say what it is. (Consider a parallel to the World Health Organization's famous definition of health, which is also tripartite: health is not merely the absence of illness and infirmity, but a state of complete physical, mental and social well-being. Even without knowing what such complete state would be, medicine and society can do a lot to alleviate or cure disease and infirmity; and we can thereby allude to and work towards gaining knowledge of this complete state of wellbeing and towards making it a reality.)

Gordon's own characterisation comes sometimes close to this form of negativism, such as when drawing the following lesson from Adorno's new categorical imperative: ‘material suffering becomes the negative standard against which all possible happiness must find its measure’ (p. 203); and commenting ‘the concept of happiness resembles a Kantian postulate’ (p. 95). Here the avoidance of material suffering (and a second Auschwitz) is seen as a necessary condition for happiness, and given normative and metaethical priority over the good (whatever happiness is, it is not that). And the talk of postulate is telling: Kant's whole point about freedom, God, and (immortality of) the soul as postulates was that we can have no knowledge of their inner workings or nature; that they transcend the bounds of what we can make sense of. Similarly with negativism and the good—with the one key difference being the historical index in case of negativism; contrary to the ahistorical, a priori status of Kant's epistemic block.

Epistemic negativism in Adorno's case is, then, not scepticism about the (possible) existence of positive norms. It is not a metaphysical thesis and especially not an ahistorical thesis. Instead, it is a thesis about what we can know in a particular socio-historical situation—a thesis that is compatible not just with the existence of positive norms, but also with (possible future) knowledge of such norms in a different (possible future) socio-historical situation.

On the other hand, Gordon thinks it is mistaken to assume that ‘no imperfect version of x can count as an x’, that no ‘imperfect experience of the good can really count as a genuine instance of the good’ (p. 85). He thinks that this is mistaken because the human world in general is marked by damage, such that the first quotation above would then rule out any access to the genuine good. And because Gordon thinks that Adorno recognises this about the ‘constitution of the human world’ (p. 90), Gordon ultimately thinks that despite the ‘compromised’ nature of happiness (or experiences thereof) in today's wrong social world (p. 195), Adorno accepts that they are genuine instances of happiness (or genuine experience thereof)—fleeting, precarious, but genuine. This suggests that Gordon implicitly resolves the inconsistency between ascribing to Adorno both the view that ‘distorted happiness is not genuine happiness at all’ and the view ‘that distorted happiness is in a precarious fashion genuine happiness’, by siding with the latter.

This strikes me as a mistake. As emphasised above, Adorno is making a historically indexed claim about the constitution of a particular social world (and not one about the constitution of the human world as such). Moreover, Gordon again conflates two points: accepting the claim about lacking access to genuine happiness with the claim that the imperfect experiences ‘must wholly lack any merit’ (p. 90) in virtue of not sufficing to give us access to genuine happiness. Even if the experiences do not give us access to the real (positive) thing (‘genuine happiness’), this does not mean they are without merit. Among other merits they might have, is one that Gordon himself notes: such experiences may serve as an anticipation or ‘trace’ of a universal fulfilment that is not yet at hand, but should be. They may serve, in other words, as utopian impulse that things should be different, albeit not as positive glimpses of how it would be then.

Overall, it, perhaps, makes best sense of Gordon's position that he rejects metaethical negativism, and this is why he cannot see that epistemic and substantive negativism does not lead to total normative scepticism (and that negativism is compatible with alluding to potential for a realised humanity and its genuine happiness). Yet, while rejecting meta-ethical negativism makes his position more intelligible, the problem is then that Gordon seems to simply assume what needs to be shown: that metaethical negativism is untenable.

The closest Gordon comes to providing the beginning of an argument against meta-ethical negativism is when he complains that we need ‘contrasting normative standards’ to be able to identify the false, wrong or bad as false, wrong, or bad. This is a known objection to meta-ethical negativism, but there is an existing response in the literature: we might indeed require contrasts for identifying something as bad, but different degrees (and dimensions) of badness suffice for this (Freyenhagen 2013: 225–228). Similarly, a tripartite logic (bad, neutral, good) can allow identification of the bad without knowledge of the good. There is no rejoinder in Gordon's book to this existing response on behalf of (meta-ethical) negativism. Instead, his rejection of the latter mainly seems to function as a background assumption, much as it does with Habermas and others.

Generally, one of the main concerns I had while reading Gordon's book is the lack of questioning of the framing imposed by Habermas and those following in his wake onto debates about Adorno. Implicitly ruling out metaethical negativism is one aspect of this. Another aspect is to accept that social critique must be about measuring using a standard (for example, p. 117)—thinking of the social critic as akin to a surveyor who ultimately relies on the standard meter traditionally kept in Paris. Gordon does not even mention that this is a contestable and indeed contested picture of social critique. In the literature, there are other ways of thinking about social critique, including about Adorno's version thereof (see, notably, Vogelmann 2017).

In sum, (Adorno's) negativism is neither the same as nor committed to (i) a view of society as seamless totality without contradictions; (ii) pessimism; (iii) Gnosticism; (iv) total normative scepticism; or (v) the view that human beings can never know the good. Yet, Gordon, in this book, conflates or confuses negativism with one, the other, or all of them—and that then fuels the worries he directs at negativism, when, actually, these are orthogonal to it.

Gordon identifies this not explicitly as a challenge to negativism, but others do so (Hemmerich 2024); and we can understand what he says to include this challenge.

So, what warrant could there be for the Asymmetry Thesis that we can know inhumanity (and the bad) but not humanity (and the human good) in our social world, given Adorno's global description of that world as delusional? As far as I can tell, Adorno does not explicitly or directly address that challenge. There is some evidence that he thinks that the negative connects to visceral bodily reactions that can be rationalised away in our conscious engagement with them or out of which we might even be habituated to some extent, but which cannot be completely eliminated and to which we would do well to remain responsive. This is (part of) what Adorno means when saying, after introducing the new categorical imperative, that ‘It is in the unvarnished materialistic motive only that morality survives’; or when, earlier in Negative Dialectics, he affirms that ‘Woe speaks: “Go.”’ (1973: 365, 203).

However, in a way that just transposes the challenge: it is not clear why we should accept that only woe speaks ‘go’ in our social world and not also that joy speaks ‘come’; or that we have only visceral reactions (in this social world) to the negative, but not to the positive (or at least none which we can make legitimate use of in a critical theory of society). So, the Asymmetry Thesis seems to remain unwarranted.

It is here where Gordon's book might—somewhat inadvertently—provide a hint to a possible solution. Gordon emphasises that Adorno's account of flourishing is ‘comprehensive in the sense that it envisions a state of affairs that would satisfy all human needs and desires at once’ (p. 97; Gordon's italics; see also p. 99); and in the sense of applying ‘across the full range of Adorno's philosophical interests’ (p. 193), notably encompassing aesthetics, and thereby human needs and desires to do with aesthetics. One way to put this point, would be to say that Adorno is a certain kind of holist about the (human) good—whatever it is, the good must fit together as a comprehensive multi-dimensional whole. (This might have to do with the Aristotelian-Hegelian background of his thought, and the long tradition of thinking of the virtues as forming a unity, such that it would be wrong to ask about what courage is in complete isolation of asking what generosity, prudence, etc. are.)

Against the background of such holism, the Asymmetry Thesis might become more plausible and defensible, especially if we also add the Hegelian point about not being able to anticipate something philosophically that has not yet taken on social reality (about the owl of the Miverva's only flying after the day's work is done). Adorno might be read to say either that the bad forms itself a comprehensive whole, but we have encountered it already as realised in social reality (notably in Auschwitz), and hence can know the bad; or that the bad does not form a comprehensive whole but only the good does, such that knowledge of the bad can be partial, even while knowledge of the good cannot be partial. Either way, the good qua comprehensive whole has not yet been realised in social reality (past or present). Whatever partial elements of the good we might encounter in our current or past social worlds, it cannot be anticipated philosophically how these fit together into a comprehensive whole, before it becomes social reality qua comprehensive whole in a possible future social world. And for this reason, we can only know the bad, but not the good in our social world. That world is one which prevents the formation of the comprehensive whole that is the (human) good. We have reason to want to overcome our social world in virtue of this fundamental defect and the evils that come with it. There is no need to appeal to anything positive—be it communicative action or even precarious happiness. Instead of lamenting the epistemic limitations of our current historical situation and seeking harbour where there is none, we should embrace the freedom of thought to negate all and head for the open ocean.

误读否定论:论彼得-E-戈登的《岌岌可危的幸福》:阿多诺与规范性的来源
阿多诺的研究在过去的二十年里取得了长足的进步。长期以来,人们指责他的哲学过于消极,这给他的哲学蒙上了阴影。这种指责不仅来自法兰克福学派研究传统之外,而且至关重要的是也来自法兰克福学派研究传统内部,尤其是经常被描绘为其“第二代”领军人物的j<s:1>根·哈贝马斯(jrgen Habermas)。在哈贝马斯的案例中,这种指责有不同的形式——有时是关于阿多诺的理论缺乏社会批判的立场;有时是因为它缺乏规范基础;有时它是关于表演矛盾(在说社会世界被意识形态彻底扭曲的内容和说的行为之间)。在每种情况下,结果都是一样的:我们需要一种积极的规范资源,然后为批评我们的社会世界提供标准。这导致了关于什么是积极标准的各种争论——交流行动,认可/社会自由,或辩护权(分别由哈贝马斯,霍尼思和福斯特提出的三个突出的答案)。尤其是在过去的二十年里,对这一指控(以及所谓的积极标准)的反击越来越多。一些包括(完全披露!)我坚持认为,阿多诺采取的消极立场是站得住脚的,事实上,比所谓的积极选择更可取。正是在这种背景下,戈登试图通过他的新书进行干预。他拒绝阿多诺的否定主义复兴,尽管他承认否定主义解释的文本证据似乎是强有力的(第5页)。与哈贝马斯一样,他认为我们需要一个积极的社会批判标准,但与哈贝马斯不同的是,戈登认为这样一个积极的标准可以在阿多诺的作品中找到。他并不是唯一一个这样想的人——戈登·芬莱森和马丁·塞尔是早期将积极核心归因于阿多诺哲学的解释的例子。对戈登来说更具体的是,他认为阿多诺的社会批判理论的规范性的“来源”是人类繁荣的广义上的“对幸福的最大需求”(第16 - 18页和激情,特别是第2章)。正是这种需求激发了阿多诺的唯物主义“脆弱性伦理”(第15页,196-197)。对幸福的需求在社会世界中是内在的,特别是在某些具有预期特征的经历和元素中(第46页,56-57页,70页,210页),指向完全的繁荣,甚至在错误的社会世界提供给我们的扭曲的幸福实例中也暗指善(第54-57页,70 - 71页)。通过这种方式,不稳定的幸福(或不稳定的幸福体验)让我们瞥见了完整、全面的幸福;是内在社会批判的源泉。戈登显然认为,以人类繁荣为导向有很多可取之处,尽管他没有在本书中为其提供独立的理由。在某种程度上,这是因为他认识到阿多诺拒绝了对规范基础的要求(第17页,213-214)。虽然戈登最终希望阿多诺对不稳定幸福的描述能够“与主体间主义辩护理论相一致”,但他指出,这“远远超出了本书的范围”(第215页)。我将集中讨论戈登对否定主义的批判。这种拒绝是戈登在书中(以及它所依据的讲座)重新解释阿多诺的关键。其他的主题也被涵盖了——比如阿多诺对强调概念的看法(第2章)和美学(尤其是第5-6章)——但它们都被否定主义所影响,这是本书的“主要论点”(xvii)。这在很大程度上取决于否定主义的含义,这并不奇怪。虽然在相关文献中有一些相当一致的含义,但也有将否定主义与其他立场或概念混为一谈的倾向。事实上,正如戈登的书所不幸证明的那样,在这种合并和混乱中遇难的危险是真实存在的。这三种主要形式结合在一起,似乎使阿多诺对现代社会世界的激进批判成为可能:这是一个坏的社会世界,我们可以知道什么是坏的(并且,正如我们稍后将看到的,只有坏的),但这种知识足以要求克服社会世界(并被激励为克服它而努力)。戈登并没有真正参与到元伦理否定主义中,尽管,在最后的分析中,我认为这就是行动所在(我将在下面回到这一点)。从表面上看,他的主要担忧是将实质(和认知)否定主义归咎于阿多诺。他到底反对什么并不总是很清楚;在不同的选择之间有相当多的滑动。我将依次重构和讨论三种不同的变体。 首先,戈登担心,将实质性(和认识论)否定主义归咎于阿多诺,与阿多诺的承诺不一致,即现代资本主义世界不是一个无缝的整体,而是充满矛盾(第18-20页)。我同意阿多诺致力于后者,但这与将实质否定主义归于他是完全相容的。因为从道德上讲,社会世界存在严重问题的说法并不排除它是矛盾的。事实上,认为这个世界有问题的原因之一很可能是(在阿多诺的情况下,可以说是),它是,也不能不是,被矛盾所困扰,比如,最大限度地剥削劳动力和我们的自然世界,并不得不再生产它们之间的矛盾。这种主张与否定主义是相容的,特别是当这些矛盾的持续存在对人类产生负面影响时(再一次,阿多诺的情况也是如此)。一个实质否定主义者,包括像阿多诺这样的实质否定主义者,可以接受社会是充满矛盾的;有些经历与维持现状的紧张关系(尤其是痛苦的经历);社会批判可以建立在这些经验的基础上,因此是内在的(在戈登的意义上);这可以转化为抵抗行为,甚至是激进社会变革的尝试。简而言之,说社会是坏的实例,并不等于说它是一个无缝的整体;说我们只有(并且需要)了解那个社会中不好的一面,与说它是矛盾的,人们经历了这些,并努力克服这个社会是相容的。显而易见的是,上述否定主义的形式——无论是认识论的、实质性的还是元伦理学的——都没有暗示、要求或等同于这种诺斯替主义。在这种情况下,它可能有助于明确指出,否定主义是不一样的悲观主义,而诺斯替主义是一种形式的绝对悲观主义。一个人可以认为,我们只能并且确实知道我们的社会世界有什么不好,这是一个彻底的坏的社会世界,但仍然认为这个坏的社会世界可以被批评和克服,甚至乐观地认为它将被克服。前者——认知否定主义和实体否定主义——是关于在特定情况下可以知道什么以及对该情况的规范性判断;后者——肯定批评和克服坏社会世界的可能性——是一种关于离开这种情况的模态主张,并使其与认识论和规范性判断完全兼容。想想一个类比(灵感来自布莱希特的一首消极主义诗):如果我在一所着火的房子里,我可能会认为这所房子已经完全着火了,无法被拯救,尽管我可能不确定房子外面是什么,但我可以而且确实知道,活活烧死是我们应该避免的一件坏事,并以此作为离开房子的充分理由;我能想到这一切,同时我也认为,确实有可能离开这所房子,并对这一目标的实现持乐观态度,尽管它在各个方面都很困难,因为它已经彻底着火了。第三,戈登担心,将实质否定主义或认知否定主义归因于阿多诺,会使他陷入完全的规范性怀疑主义,而这种怀疑主义既不能独立地证明,也不能作为对阿多诺所写内容的合理解释(第6、18、25、91-92页)。在这里,戈登缺乏对元伦理否定主义的真正参与成为一个问题。因为除非一个人拒绝元伦理的否定主义,否则没有理由认为一个实体的或认识的否定主义者一定是一个完全的规范的怀疑论者。事实上,那些提出对阿多诺作品进行否定主义阅读的人,坚持认为规范性实质仍然存在:一种极简主义的抵抗伦理,以他新的绝对命令为中心,“安排[我们的]思想和行动,使奥斯维辛不会重演,这样就不会发生类似的事情”(阿多诺1973:365;参见Freyenhagen 2013:第5-6章)。戈登清楚地知道,阿多诺的否定主义解读包括伦理和其他规范性物质(第16-17页)。促使他反对的原因可能是,他认为我们可以而且需要将阿多诺归因于一种极简主义伦理(第70,197页)作为回应,首先要注意的是,即使是极简主义伦理学也不等于完全的规范怀疑主义。因此,我们没有理由认为——正如戈登所建议的那样——把实质否定主义或认识论否定主义归咎于阿多诺,会使阿多诺陷入完全的规范怀疑主义。此外,阿多诺否定主义(和极简主义伦理学)的一个至关重要的方面一直被戈登所忽视:它有一个历史指标。根据阿多诺的说法,这并不是说人类永远不可能知道什么是善。 另一方面,戈登认为“x的不完美版本不能算作x”,“对善的不完美体验不能算作善的真实实例”的假设是错误的(第85页)。他认为这是错误的,因为人类世界一般都以破坏为标志,因此上面的第一句引言会排除任何通往真正善的途径。因为戈登认为阿多诺承认了“人类世界的构成”(第90页),戈登最终认为,尽管在当今错误的社会世界中,幸福(或其体验)的“妥协”本质(第195页),但阿多诺承认它们是幸福(或其真正体验)的真实实例——短暂的、不稳定的,但真实的。这表明,戈登含蓄地解决了阿多诺“扭曲的幸福根本不是真正的幸福”和“扭曲的幸福以一种不稳定的方式是真正的幸福”这两种观点之间的矛盾,他站在后者一边。我觉得这是一个错误。正如上文所强调的,阿多诺正在对一个特定社会世界的构成(而不是人类世界本身的构成)提出一个历史索引的主张。此外,戈登再次将两点混为一谈:接受缺乏获得真正幸福的途径的说法,以及声称不完美的经历“必须完全缺乏任何价值”(第90页),因为它不足以让我们获得真正的幸福。即使这些经历不能让我们获得真正的(积极的)东西(“真正的幸福”),这并不意味着它们没有价值。在它们可能具有的其他优点中,有一点是戈登自己指出的:这样的经历可能作为一种尚未实现但应该实现的普遍实现的预期或“痕迹”。换句话说,它们可能是一种乌托邦式的冲动,认为事情应该有所不同,尽管不是对未来的积极展望。总的来说,也许最能说明戈登的立场的是,他拒绝元伦理否定主义,这就是为什么他看不到认知和实质否定主义不会导致完全的规范性怀疑主义(否定主义与暗指实现人性及其真正幸福的潜力是相容的)。然而,虽然拒绝元伦理否定主义使他的立场更容易理解,但问题是,戈登似乎只是假设了需要证明的东西:元伦理否定主义是站不住脚的。戈登最接近于提出反对元伦理否定主义的论点的开始是,他抱怨说,我们需要“对比的规范性标准”,以便能够将假、错或坏区分为假、错或坏。这是对元伦理否定主义的一个众所周知的反对意见,但在文献中有一个现有的回应:我们可能确实需要对比来识别某些东西是坏的,但不同程度(和维度)的坏就足够了(Freyenhagen 2013: 225-228)。类似地,三方逻辑(坏的、中性的、好的)可以在不知道好的情况下识别坏的。在戈登的书中,对这种代表(元伦理)否定主义的现有回应没有任何反驳。相反,他对后者的拒绝似乎主要是作为一种背景假设,就像对哈贝马斯和其他人一样。总的来说,我在阅读戈登的书时主要担心的一个问题是,对哈贝马斯和那些追随他的人对阿多诺的辩论所施加的框架缺乏质疑。含蓄地排除元伦理否定主义是其中一个方面。另一方面是接受社会批评必须使用标准进行测量(例如,第117页)——认为社会批评就像一个测量员,最终依赖传统上保存在巴黎的标准仪表。戈登甚至没有提到这是一幅有争议的社会批判图景。在文献中,还有其他思考社会批判的方式,包括阿多诺的版本(值得注意的是,见Vogelmann 2017)。总之,(阿多诺的)否定主义既不等同于也不致力于(1)将社会视为没有矛盾的无缝整体的观点;(2)悲观;(3)诺斯替教;(iv)完全的规范性怀疑主义;或者(v)认为人类永远不可能知道善的观点。然而,戈登在这本书中,将否定主义与其中一种、另一种或所有否定主义混为一谈或混淆了——这助长了他对否定主义的担忧,而实际上,这些担忧是互不相关的。戈登并没有明确指出这是对否定主义的挑战,但其他人也这么认为(Hemmerich 2024);我们可以理解他说的话包含了这个挑战。 那么,鉴于阿多诺将我们的社会描述为妄想,我们可以知道我们的社会世界中的非人性(和坏),但不知道人性(和人类的善)的不对称命题有什么根据呢?据我所知,阿多诺并没有明确或直接地应对这一挑战。有一些证据表明,他认为负面情绪与身体的本能反应有关,这些反应可以在我们有意识地与它们接触时被合理化,或者我们甚至可能在某种程度上习惯了这些反应,但这些反应不能完全消除,我们最好保持反应。这就是(部分)阿多诺在介绍了新的绝对命令之后所说的,“只有在未经修饰的唯物主义动机中,道德才能生存”;或者,在《否定辩证法》的前面,他肯定,“祸患说:”去吧。”(1973:365,203)。然而,在某种程度上,这只是改变了挑战:我们不清楚为什么我们应该接受在我们的社交世界中只有悲伤说“去”,而不是快乐说“来”;或者说,我们(在这个社会世界里)对消极事物只有本能的反应,而对积极事物却没有本能的反应(或者至少没有本能反应,我们可以在社会批判理论中合理地利用)。因此,不对称理论似乎仍然没有根据。正是在这里,戈登的书可能——多少有些不经意——提供了一个可能的解决方案的提示。戈登强调,阿多诺对繁荣的描述是“全面的,因为它设想了一种能够立即满足人类所有需求和欲望的事态”(第97页;戈登的斜体;参见第99页);在“跨越阿多诺哲学兴趣的全部范围”(第193页)的意义上,特别是包括美学,从而包括人类与美学有关的需求和欲望。可以这么说,阿多诺是一个关于(人类)善的整体主义者——不管它是什么,善必须作为一个全面的多维整体结合在一起。(这可能是由于他的思想背景是亚里士多德-黑格尔式的,又由于他长期以来认为美德是统一的传统,所以,如果只问勇气是什么,而不问慷慨、谨慎等是什么,那就错了。)在这种整体论的背景下,不对称命题可能会变得更加可信和站得住脚,特别是如果我们还加上黑格尔的观点,即不能在哲学上预测尚未采取社会现实的事情(关于Miverva的猫头鹰只在一天的工作结束后飞行)。阿多诺可能会说,坏的形式本身是一个全面的整体,但我们已经遇到了它,在社会现实中实现了(特别是在奥斯维辛),因此可以知道坏的;或者说,恶不能构成一个全面的整体,只有善才能构成,因此,对恶的认识可能是片面的,而对善的认识却不能是片面的。无论如何,在过去或现在的社会现实中,良好的全面整体尚未实现。无论我们在当前或过去的社会世界中遇到的是什么部分的善,在它成为社会现实之前,我们无法从哲学上预测这些善是如何结合成一个全面的整体的,在一个可能的未来社会世界中成为一个全面的整体。由于这个原因,我们只能知道社会上的坏,而不能知道好的。这个世界阻碍了(人类)善的全面整体的形成。我们有理由想要凭借这个根本缺陷和随之而来的邪恶来克服我们的社会世界。没有必要诉诸任何积极的东西——无论是交流行为还是不稳定的幸福。我们不应该哀叹当前历史状况的认识局限,不应该在没有避风港的地方寻找避风港,而应该拥抱否定一切的思想自由,驶向广阔的海洋。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
11.10%
发文量
82
期刊介绍: ''Founded by Mark Sacks in 1993, the European Journal of Philosophy has come to occupy a distinctive and highly valued place amongst the philosophical journals. The aim of EJP has been to bring together the best work from those working within the "analytic" and "continental" traditions, and to encourage connections between them, without diluting their respective priorities and concerns. This has enabled EJP to publish a wide range of material of the highest standard from philosophers across the world, reflecting the best thinking from a variety of philosophical perspectives, in a way that is accessible to all of them.''
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信