To walk the walk: Why we need to make things personal in public deliberation

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Markus Holdo, Zohreh Khoban
{"title":"To walk the walk: Why we need to make things personal in public deliberation","authors":"Markus Holdo,&nbsp;Zohreh Khoban","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12747","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Critical reflection and awareness-raising are nowadays part of many people's everyday lives: At workplaces and organizations, in relationships, in the media, and best-selling books, people are increasingly discussing what it means to treat each other as equals, how not to be racist, and the many ways that we still exclude or marginalize people based, for example, on gender, ethnicity, abilities, age, class, sexuality, or religious views. These conversations are not easy to have. They often proceed on a very general level, without naming names, without getting upset, and without confrontation. We are accustomed to discussing in this way: What matters is not the personal story but the general patterns; not our experiences and how we feel about them, but the objective facts and arguments; not our failures to live up to ideals and beliefs, but what some abstract “we” still need to work on. Not making it personal is supposed to ensure that everyone can feel comfortable to speak and be heard regardless of their personal history and how they live.</p><p>In democratic theory, this understanding of collective reflection as a “rational discussion” has been a central part of how scholars approach the realm of public deliberation. In Habermas’ famous phrase, participants in deliberation are supposed to respond only to the force of the better argument instead of giving importance to the status and power of the person speaking (Habermas, <span>1975, 1984</span>). While a critical component in early work on deliberation, this view has now been criticized by countless scholars (see Curato et al., <span>2019</span>; Holdo, <span>2020b</span>). Feminist and critical theorists, not the least, have argued that this idea obscures how, in the real situations in which deliberation takes place, people's views and ways of expressing themselves are always embodied—that is, always shaped by their particular locations and experiences (Hayward, <span>2004</span>; Holdo, <span>2015</span>; Olson, <span>2011</span>; Young, <span>1996, 2000</span>).</p><p>Today, many deliberative theorists acknowledge that our ways of communicating—including both speaking and listening, both expressing something and considering it—in part reflect culture and social hierarchies. This is typically seen as an argument for a more inclusive approach to the type of expressions that should be accepted in deliberation. Thus, deliberative scholars have come to embrace emotions, testimony, greetings, rhetoric, and storytelling as additions to the earlier ideal of rational discussion (see Bächtiger et al, <span>2018</span>; Elstub, <span>2010</span>).</p><p>The criticism against the early ideals of deliberative theory can, to a certain extent, be seen as a critique of a norm of disembodied objectivity: that we ought to listen and respond to what is being said while disregarding who is saying it. Emotions, testimony, and storytelling are all modes of expression that bear witness to who we are and what we have been through. In this paper, we seek to further challenge the norm of disembodied objectivity by exploring the implication of this critique for deliberative theory—which we suggest is that we need to make deliberation personal in a more radical way than deliberative theorists currently acknowledge. We argue that people should make things personal by holding each other personally accountable to a norm of embodied sincerity. In everyday language, this means, in part, to practice what one preaches. Embodied sincerity refers to speaking the views and experiences one embodies: to do what you say and say what you do. Whether, for example, a person acts in antiracist ways is critical for assessing antiracist views and whether a self-professed feminist actually takes feminist action is critical for how we understand the practical importance of their claims. Without this connection between discourse and practice, or speech and action, deliberation easily turns into a game of words—it is enough to know what views and terms others see as acceptable or progressive. But if deliberation is to serve emancipatory political action, and if deliberative theory is to stay true to its roots in critical theory, it needs to be oriented not just toward advancing rhetoric but also toward transformative social change.</p><p>Personal accountability, we argue, ought to be an essential part of any process of deliberation because it performs three critical functions: it helps assess a person's commitment to what they say, it helps understand and assess the experiences that inform a person's views, and it helps generate critical self-reflection by bringing discourse to bear on concrete practices.</p><p>Next, we discuss previous critiques of the conventional idea of rational argumentation in deliberations. These suggest that we need to embrace narrative, emotions, and identities as constitutive of deliberative processes. Our view is that these arguments seek to broaden the modes of political communication, rather than emphasizing the relationship between words and action. We then outline what we mean by personal accountability and explain what difference the shift to the ethics of personal accountability makes for how we act toward one another in conversations and how we evaluate knowledge—both our own and that of others. In the fourth section, we address several possible objections. The most important of these, we suggest, is that the consequences of acting on our beliefs and of sharing what personal experiences inform our views are not equal but vary depending on our positions in power structures. For this reason, we respond, the ethics of walking the walk needs to be seen as a situated ethics, not as an unqualified imperative. What our argument implies is not that all people should act the same or be held accountable the same way, but that all people ought to be challenged to reflect on whether they do act on their beliefs, and whether the way that they have come to believe something to be true reflects ethical and epistemological commitments to inclusion and equality, to an extent they can justify to themselves and others. Thus, we do not defend moral perfectionism or purity. Rather, as we stress in our concluding discussion, practicing the norm of embodied sincerity involves understanding whether, under the conditions we act, we might have, and ought to have, acted differently, and if and how we could act differently in the future. As a form of critical reflection, it allows people to move beyond sophisticated discussions to actions that challenge social injustices.</p><p>According to deliberative democratic theory, political decisions should be the product of fair discussions and be guided by a reciprocal give-and-take of reasons and a willingness to change one's opinion (Dahlberg, <span>2004</span>). When public deliberation succeeds, it is thought to neutralize power imbalances that give some people better chances than others to influence decisions and discussions. In a good deliberative conversation, people consider arguments on their own merits. They yield only to “the forceless force of the better argument” (Habermas, <span>1975</span>, p. 108). In theory, such deliberation would help expose structural injustices and support individuals’ emancipation (Hammond, <span>2019</span>; Rostbøll, <span>2008</span>).</p><p>During the last decades, deliberative democratic theory has moved, through several “generations” of theorists from idealistic propositions to practical exploration and empirical research (Elstub, <span>2010</span>; Elstub et al., <span>2016</span>). As part of this development, newer generations of theorists have tried to accommodate a worrisome criticism: that the original ideal of deliberative reason-giving obscures exclusions and inequalities. Critics have, for example, argued that deliberative theory maintains structural injustices by privileging universality over particularity and impartiality over partiality (Williams, <span>2000</span>; Young, <span>1996, 2000</span>). Further, some have argued that people's practical understanding and expectations of what it means to give reasons and be convincing often privilege styles of speaking that are articulate, ordered, and dispassionate over ways of speaking that are emotional, passionate, and personal (Sanders, <span>1997</span>; Young, <span>2000</span>, pp. 36–51). This, critics suggest, reproduces and legitimizes practices of discrimination and exclusion of marginalized social groups that are often viewed as being emotional rather than rational and as expressing subjective feelings instead of objectively valid arguments (see also Hayward, <span>2004</span>; Olson, <span>2011</span>).</p><p>To make deliberation more inclusive and equal, various theorists have sought to push the boundaries of what counts as reason-giving. Most notably, Iris Marion Young (<span>2000</span>, chapter 2) has introduced greeting, rhetoric, and narrative as enriching accounts of public discussion and deliberation. More recent contributions to this discussion have sought to demonstrate a need to broaden the concept of public deliberation to include forms of communication that may be seen as nonpublic or as not fitting the label “deliberation.” For example, several theorists have reasoned that deliberative democrats should accept and even embrace protest and other confrontational tactics as part of public deliberation in an unequal society (Curato, <span>2021</span>; Fung, <span>2005</span>; Holdo, <span>2020a</span>; Young, <span>2001</span>). More recently, scholars have emphasized nonverbal forms of expression as a way to express reasons. For example, Toby Rollo (<span>2017</span>) has highlighted enactive protest, exit, and silence as contributions to public debate, and Mendonça et al. (<span>2020</span>) have argued that visuals and sounds play important roles in public argumentative exchanges.</p><p>In addition to suggesting practices that widen the concept of reason-giving in deliberation, scholars have also taken an interest in strategies that can reveal how people's social location shape their claims and renegotiate the influence of marginalized participants and perspectives. According to Azmanova (<span>2012</span>, pp. 218–219), the relation between a <i>social</i> position and a <i>normative</i> position needs to be thematized in public deliberation to disclose the structural sources of injustice that are encoded within all claims that participants advance. She asserts that this can be done by giving “reasons for having reasons,” that is, by explaining how one has come to an opinion and for what reason one formed it.<sup>1</sup></p><p>We endorse the previous critiques suggesting that we need to recognize alternative modes of reasoning and take into account participants’ social locations and situated motives. However, these contributions have not connected what participants in deliberation say—their claims, objections, and proclamations—to how they live their lives, that is, whether what they <i>say</i> corresponds to what they <i>do</i>. In this paper, we explore whether such a link can help guide collective critical reflection and hold participants accountable for what they say. Compared with previous research, we take a radical step toward making deliberation more personal. Thus, we also challenge in a more fundamental way the norm of disembodied objectivity—a norm that frames deliberation as being about “public” rather than “private” issues, “rational” arguments rather than “emotional” ones, and “objectively valid” points of view that are disconnected from personal experiences. These moves turn conversations away from the ways that personal struggles, shortcomings, and blind spots affect our concrete actions in everyday life as well as in our more specific engagements, and inhibit deliberation that can emancipate through accountability, recognition, and actions that confront injustices.</p><p>The question of disembodied objectivity has long been discussed by feminist epistemologists, especially in relation to scientific research. These scholars emphasize that dominant conceptions and practices of knowledge attribution, acquisition, and justification have disadvantaged women and other subordinated groups by excluding them from inquiry, denying them epistemic authority, and producing knowledge that reinforces gender and other social hierarchies. These failures are traced to flawed conceptions of knowledge, knowers, and objectivity, which, for example, insist that objective knowledge is ascertained through a “view from nowhere” (Haraway, <span>1988</span>; Harding, <span>1995</span>). Contrary to such beliefs, but without abandoning the concept of objectivity, feminist epistemologists emphasize that what is known reflects the situation and perspective of the knower. Reflecting on that situation and perspective, they suggest, ought to be part of the process of learning (Haraway, <span>1988</span>; Harding, <span>1992</span>).</p><p>Feminist epistemologists argue that situated knowers are responsible knowers: they take responsibility for what they know and how they claim to know what they know (Haraway, <span>1988</span>). Patricia Hill Collins (<span>2000</span>) calls this an “ethic of personal accountability” (p. 284). According to her, Black feminist epistemology expects people to be personally accountable for their knowledge claims. This means that they are accountable not only for the validity of what they say but also for the personal convictions and actions that underlie or influence their positions. In line with this idea, assessments of knowledge claims must include an evaluation of an individual's character, values, and ethics. Knowledge claims from individuals who are ethically committed to their ideas carry more weight than claims from those who maintain a distance between what they say and how they live.</p><p>To demonstrate her point, Collins shares an experience from an undergraduate class session where Black female students refused to accept a prominent Black male scholar's analysis of Black feminism without some indication of his personal ethics. The students were especially interested in details of the scholar's life, such as his relationship with Black women and his social class background. According to Collins (<span>2000</span>), “they used this information to assess whether he really cared about his topic, and invoked this ethic of caring in advancing their knowledge claims about his work” (p. 285).</p><p>We suggest that theorists of deliberation should consider the implications that the ethic of personal accountability has for practices of deliberation, especially regarding the norms of sincerity and objectivity. Sincerity is usually understood by theorists of deliberation as a demand to <i>mean</i> what we say and say what we <i>mean</i> (Habermas, <span>2001</span>, p. 34). By contrast, an ethic of personal accountability appears to require <i>embodied</i> sincerity—that we <i>do</i> what we say and say what we <i>do</i>. It thus connects the spoken word to the body and action. In other words, it helps expose not just the reasonableness of people's arguments but also people's integrity in acting on them (Nili, <span>2018</span>). Rather than evaluating arguments based on their rational, universal justification, as suggested by the conventional (disembodied) norm of objectivity, embodied sincerity suggests that we assess what people say against the background of relevant aspects of their actions and ways of life: you may talk the talk, but do you walk the walk?</p><p>What difference does this shift mean for how we should act toward one another in conversations? We suggest that it affects both the kind of support a normative claim requires, as Collins herself argues, and, by implication, the importance we give to including different relevant experiences in the process of forming our views. Thus, as Collins suggests, the one who makes a normative claim needs to support it by explaining what this claim means for the speaker's way of living their lives. In addition, we suggest that it also means that speakers must pay attention to, learn from, and be held accountable to, how their claims relate to the lived experiences of others. We will explain these implications one at a time.</p><p>Collins illustrates the limits of the norm of disembodied objectivity by using the case with the students who confront the male scholar on his credibility in light of his biography and how he currently lives his life. The value of this move is that it changes what kind of merits one needs to obtain to be taken seriously. It is no longer sufficient to acquire rhetorical skills, socially appropriate language, or abstract “objective” knowledge. The important thing is not merely what he claims to believe but also whether and how he acts on that conviction. This idea contradicts the reasoning of many theorists, who think a good understanding of a problem and the ethical standing of different solutions are something valuable on their own, but it squares well with more practical thinking about social change, including antiracist thinking (Kendi, <span>2019</span>) and ideas of critical reflection in practice (Holdo, <span>2023</span>). To know something only in theory, in this view, is not to know enough. By contrast, to know something in practice is to be able to reflect critically. What personal experiences have shaped the knowledge of this male scholar? If he claims to advance feminism, how do his feminist assumptions and intentions affect his personal life? What do they require from his way of life, and does he live up to it? What consequences may discrepancies between talk and action have? How, for example, do they affect the struggle for Black women's emancipation?</p><p>There is an additional implication of this view of particular importance for public deliberation. Making things personal means questioning not only what experiences you had that informed your views but also if and how you considered the experiences of relevant others. Whose views are being silenced in this conversation and should be included? To take Collins’ example again, if you claim to support the rights of Black women, how did the experiences and views of Black women affect your understanding of how to do so? The idea of holding each other accountable for having considered experiences other than our own, and especially the experiences of people who are subject to epistemic injustices, is not exactly Collins’ point. But exploring this path is, we think, consistent with Collins’ argument for decentering political thought and critiquing Eurocentric and male-dominated discourse. It is also consistent with Collins’ emphasis on dialogue as essential for knowledge production. Collins contrasts Black feminist practices of learning through the sharing of experiences, through dialogue, to the idea of knowledge production as a process in which people separate “objective” knowledge from personal experience, or “subtract the personality of an individual from his or her ideas because they see personality as biasing those ideas” (Collins, <span>2000</span>, p. 283). Thus, knowledge requires connection with others, based on the recognition of the validity and relevance of others’ experiences. Extending this idea slightly, we suggest that knowledge that is not based on dialogue with other people whose experiences should be relevant—because they are affected by the issues under discussion or because they have engaged with them—should not have equal weight as knowledge that is. This implication is important for how we extend Collins’ ethic of accountability to theorizing public deliberation.</p><p>Our argument has similarities with how feminist critics have shown that deliberative theorists have helped mask injustices by defending a norm of impartiality. Feminist critics of the impartiality principle have suggested that urging oppressed groups to put their partial interests aside risks trapping them in the very structures they seek to dismantle (Phillips, <span>1995</span>; Williams, <span>2000</span>; Young, <span>2000</span>). While this debate concerns whether arguments need to speak to everyone's immediate experiences and interests, our concern is of a different kind: We are not concerned with the question of social difference and group representation in deliberation, but how arguments relate to deliberators' ways of life. We claim that arguing and judging must become more personal if deliberation is to serve social justice—as opposed to merely helping improve people's abilities to converse about things that they may care very little about in practice. Thus, while being concerned with a different issue than impartiality, our view shares with feminist critics of impartiality the questioning of norms that undermine objections to the domination of privileged groups.</p><p>By pointing toward an alternative standard for evaluating knowledge claims and normative claims, the ethic of personal accountability helps us articulate an ideal of embodied sincerity that disrupts the reproduction of biased and oppressive practices of knowledge production and illuminates the status quo–promoting disconnections between speech and action that such practices allow. For subordinate or dissenting groups, embodied sincerity helps hold privileged people accountable and detect ways of talking that may obstruct their emancipation. For the privileged, too, however, it offers a different kind of conversation, in which they are encouraged to reflect more deeply on how they participate in practices of domination. The latter is as important as the former since it is not always obvious what would be required of us to feel confident that we, and others, act in ways that correspond to the ethical convictions we claim to hold. Making our way of life part of exchanges of knowledge and views provides us with better possibilities to figure this out. It helps us to collectively reflect on and identify experiences and actions that matter for practicing what we preach.</p><p>While an ethic of personal accountability encourages reflection on discrepancies between views and actions, it is not sufficient to merely acknowledge that they exist. Consider an organizer of a debate or a roundtable discussion who, full of regret, states that the panel unfortunately only consists of men. Such action, we would suggest, remains an empty gesture—or a “nonperformative,” to use Ahmed's term, a speech act that “works” by allowing someone to not do what they claim to intend (Ahmed, <span>2006</span>). In contrast to such nonperformatives, the norm of embodied sincerity tracks if and how normative positions are transformed into social actions. Thus, to comply with the norm, it is not enough to merely declare an intention or observe a failure to do so. Instead, the norm requires that participants take responsibility—and hold each other accountable—for actually walking the walk. In the case of the all-male roundtable discussion, embodied deliberation with the organizer and roundtable participants would raise questions such as: why did the organizer not make sure to recruit women? Why did they not reflect more on what it means to create roundtables that are relevant and inclusive to people of different gender identities? What would it mean to practice what they preach in this situation? And if the male participants in the roundtable agree with the norm of gender parity, should they not have made their participation conditional on a mixed panel?</p><p>In sum, the ethic of personal accountability means a shift toward holding each participant in a conversation accountable by demanding to know how a person's views resonate with their way of life. It also means a shift toward the aim of personal change through self-reflection on how we can get better at practicing what we preach. In these different ways, the ethic of personal accountability pushes deliberation in an emancipatory direction.</p><p>The norm of disembodied objectivity has been so established in public discourse and the literature on public deliberation that it may seem rash to suggest replacing it with a different norm. Are we, perhaps, throwing out the baby with the bathwater by giving up disembodied objectivity for embodied sincerity? Let us consider four specific problems on which the ethic of personal accountability forces us to take a stand.</p><p>Our embodied histories always play a crucial part in public deliberation, whether participants recognize this or not. Our aim in this paper has been to argue that rather than seeking ways to reduce their role, we should make the personal a more explicit part of our conversations. But what does deliberation look like when it gives appropriate room not just to our arguments but also to our personal lives?</p><p>In this different mode of deliberation, we apply the ethic of personal accountability. This means holding each other accountable to a norm of embodied sincerity: that we not only talk the talk but also walk the walk. This addresses a common problem of public deliberation: No matter how the terms of discourse change, injustices continue to be reproduced through concrete social practices.</p><p>The norm of embodied sincerity serves the emancipatory project with which deliberative theory was, at the outset, inseparable (Dryzek, <span>2000</span>; Hammond, <span>2019</span>; Khoban, <span>2019</span>; Rostbøll, <span>2008</span>). It provides all participants with the possibility to judge the sincerity of other speakers. Do they act according to their stated views? On what experiences and other sources of knowledge do they base their views? The ethic of personal accountability invites us to reflect on our own experiences and how they inform our views, and how we need to change to practice what we say we believe.</p><p>We gave four examples of problems that bring the conflict between the two ideals, embodied sincerity and disembodied objectivity, to the fore. Further scholarship might explore the conditions under which these problems can be handled with care or avoided, and in which contexts they may make it harmful to act on an ethics of personal accountability. We have responded to each of these potential objections by showing why they do not in themselves undermine the argument for making things personal. However, the consequences of this alternative norm will depend on the specific conditions under which it is acted upon. Thus, while we argue in support of making things personal as a desirable part of public deliberation, we recognize that the values associated with it will be realized only if practiced responsibly and under conditions of trust that will not be realized overnight or in an institutional vacuum. For us, this means much more work is needed to carefully consider how deliberation can be practiced in the service of social justice.</p><p>The idea of embodied sincerity can create discomfort. It means questioning other participants’ sincerity and confronting them about the ways they fail to practice what they preach. It also means questioning biases in how we listen to others and challenging ourselves to engage collectively with our different experiences and the lessons we can learn from them. Thus, even if it seems uncomfortable, it is precisely by bringing views and knowledge claims to bear on concrete actions that deliberation can spark social change. Too often, we allow each other to talk the talk while failing to walk the walk. That is how we reproduce social injustices, how we let each other do violence to others, while we congratulate ourselves and others for knowing all the right words, marching all the right marches, and tweeting all the right tweets.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"32 1","pages":"97-109"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2024-04-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12747","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12747","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Critical reflection and awareness-raising are nowadays part of many people's everyday lives: At workplaces and organizations, in relationships, in the media, and best-selling books, people are increasingly discussing what it means to treat each other as equals, how not to be racist, and the many ways that we still exclude or marginalize people based, for example, on gender, ethnicity, abilities, age, class, sexuality, or religious views. These conversations are not easy to have. They often proceed on a very general level, without naming names, without getting upset, and without confrontation. We are accustomed to discussing in this way: What matters is not the personal story but the general patterns; not our experiences and how we feel about them, but the objective facts and arguments; not our failures to live up to ideals and beliefs, but what some abstract “we” still need to work on. Not making it personal is supposed to ensure that everyone can feel comfortable to speak and be heard regardless of their personal history and how they live.

In democratic theory, this understanding of collective reflection as a “rational discussion” has been a central part of how scholars approach the realm of public deliberation. In Habermas’ famous phrase, participants in deliberation are supposed to respond only to the force of the better argument instead of giving importance to the status and power of the person speaking (Habermas, 1975, 1984). While a critical component in early work on deliberation, this view has now been criticized by countless scholars (see Curato et al., 2019; Holdo, 2020b). Feminist and critical theorists, not the least, have argued that this idea obscures how, in the real situations in which deliberation takes place, people's views and ways of expressing themselves are always embodied—that is, always shaped by their particular locations and experiences (Hayward, 2004; Holdo, 2015; Olson, 2011; Young, 1996, 2000).

Today, many deliberative theorists acknowledge that our ways of communicating—including both speaking and listening, both expressing something and considering it—in part reflect culture and social hierarchies. This is typically seen as an argument for a more inclusive approach to the type of expressions that should be accepted in deliberation. Thus, deliberative scholars have come to embrace emotions, testimony, greetings, rhetoric, and storytelling as additions to the earlier ideal of rational discussion (see Bächtiger et al, 2018; Elstub, 2010).

The criticism against the early ideals of deliberative theory can, to a certain extent, be seen as a critique of a norm of disembodied objectivity: that we ought to listen and respond to what is being said while disregarding who is saying it. Emotions, testimony, and storytelling are all modes of expression that bear witness to who we are and what we have been through. In this paper, we seek to further challenge the norm of disembodied objectivity by exploring the implication of this critique for deliberative theory—which we suggest is that we need to make deliberation personal in a more radical way than deliberative theorists currently acknowledge. We argue that people should make things personal by holding each other personally accountable to a norm of embodied sincerity. In everyday language, this means, in part, to practice what one preaches. Embodied sincerity refers to speaking the views and experiences one embodies: to do what you say and say what you do. Whether, for example, a person acts in antiracist ways is critical for assessing antiracist views and whether a self-professed feminist actually takes feminist action is critical for how we understand the practical importance of their claims. Without this connection between discourse and practice, or speech and action, deliberation easily turns into a game of words—it is enough to know what views and terms others see as acceptable or progressive. But if deliberation is to serve emancipatory political action, and if deliberative theory is to stay true to its roots in critical theory, it needs to be oriented not just toward advancing rhetoric but also toward transformative social change.

Personal accountability, we argue, ought to be an essential part of any process of deliberation because it performs three critical functions: it helps assess a person's commitment to what they say, it helps understand and assess the experiences that inform a person's views, and it helps generate critical self-reflection by bringing discourse to bear on concrete practices.

Next, we discuss previous critiques of the conventional idea of rational argumentation in deliberations. These suggest that we need to embrace narrative, emotions, and identities as constitutive of deliberative processes. Our view is that these arguments seek to broaden the modes of political communication, rather than emphasizing the relationship between words and action. We then outline what we mean by personal accountability and explain what difference the shift to the ethics of personal accountability makes for how we act toward one another in conversations and how we evaluate knowledge—both our own and that of others. In the fourth section, we address several possible objections. The most important of these, we suggest, is that the consequences of acting on our beliefs and of sharing what personal experiences inform our views are not equal but vary depending on our positions in power structures. For this reason, we respond, the ethics of walking the walk needs to be seen as a situated ethics, not as an unqualified imperative. What our argument implies is not that all people should act the same or be held accountable the same way, but that all people ought to be challenged to reflect on whether they do act on their beliefs, and whether the way that they have come to believe something to be true reflects ethical and epistemological commitments to inclusion and equality, to an extent they can justify to themselves and others. Thus, we do not defend moral perfectionism or purity. Rather, as we stress in our concluding discussion, practicing the norm of embodied sincerity involves understanding whether, under the conditions we act, we might have, and ought to have, acted differently, and if and how we could act differently in the future. As a form of critical reflection, it allows people to move beyond sophisticated discussions to actions that challenge social injustices.

According to deliberative democratic theory, political decisions should be the product of fair discussions and be guided by a reciprocal give-and-take of reasons and a willingness to change one's opinion (Dahlberg, 2004). When public deliberation succeeds, it is thought to neutralize power imbalances that give some people better chances than others to influence decisions and discussions. In a good deliberative conversation, people consider arguments on their own merits. They yield only to “the forceless force of the better argument” (Habermas, 1975, p. 108). In theory, such deliberation would help expose structural injustices and support individuals’ emancipation (Hammond, 2019; Rostbøll, 2008).

During the last decades, deliberative democratic theory has moved, through several “generations” of theorists from idealistic propositions to practical exploration and empirical research (Elstub, 2010; Elstub et al., 2016). As part of this development, newer generations of theorists have tried to accommodate a worrisome criticism: that the original ideal of deliberative reason-giving obscures exclusions and inequalities. Critics have, for example, argued that deliberative theory maintains structural injustices by privileging universality over particularity and impartiality over partiality (Williams, 2000; Young, 1996, 2000). Further, some have argued that people's practical understanding and expectations of what it means to give reasons and be convincing often privilege styles of speaking that are articulate, ordered, and dispassionate over ways of speaking that are emotional, passionate, and personal (Sanders, 1997; Young, 2000, pp. 36–51). This, critics suggest, reproduces and legitimizes practices of discrimination and exclusion of marginalized social groups that are often viewed as being emotional rather than rational and as expressing subjective feelings instead of objectively valid arguments (see also Hayward, 2004; Olson, 2011).

To make deliberation more inclusive and equal, various theorists have sought to push the boundaries of what counts as reason-giving. Most notably, Iris Marion Young (2000, chapter 2) has introduced greeting, rhetoric, and narrative as enriching accounts of public discussion and deliberation. More recent contributions to this discussion have sought to demonstrate a need to broaden the concept of public deliberation to include forms of communication that may be seen as nonpublic or as not fitting the label “deliberation.” For example, several theorists have reasoned that deliberative democrats should accept and even embrace protest and other confrontational tactics as part of public deliberation in an unequal society (Curato, 2021; Fung, 2005; Holdo, 2020a; Young, 2001). More recently, scholars have emphasized nonverbal forms of expression as a way to express reasons. For example, Toby Rollo (2017) has highlighted enactive protest, exit, and silence as contributions to public debate, and Mendonça et al. (2020) have argued that visuals and sounds play important roles in public argumentative exchanges.

In addition to suggesting practices that widen the concept of reason-giving in deliberation, scholars have also taken an interest in strategies that can reveal how people's social location shape their claims and renegotiate the influence of marginalized participants and perspectives. According to Azmanova (2012, pp. 218–219), the relation between a social position and a normative position needs to be thematized in public deliberation to disclose the structural sources of injustice that are encoded within all claims that participants advance. She asserts that this can be done by giving “reasons for having reasons,” that is, by explaining how one has come to an opinion and for what reason one formed it.1

We endorse the previous critiques suggesting that we need to recognize alternative modes of reasoning and take into account participants’ social locations and situated motives. However, these contributions have not connected what participants in deliberation say—their claims, objections, and proclamations—to how they live their lives, that is, whether what they say corresponds to what they do. In this paper, we explore whether such a link can help guide collective critical reflection and hold participants accountable for what they say. Compared with previous research, we take a radical step toward making deliberation more personal. Thus, we also challenge in a more fundamental way the norm of disembodied objectivity—a norm that frames deliberation as being about “public” rather than “private” issues, “rational” arguments rather than “emotional” ones, and “objectively valid” points of view that are disconnected from personal experiences. These moves turn conversations away from the ways that personal struggles, shortcomings, and blind spots affect our concrete actions in everyday life as well as in our more specific engagements, and inhibit deliberation that can emancipate through accountability, recognition, and actions that confront injustices.

The question of disembodied objectivity has long been discussed by feminist epistemologists, especially in relation to scientific research. These scholars emphasize that dominant conceptions and practices of knowledge attribution, acquisition, and justification have disadvantaged women and other subordinated groups by excluding them from inquiry, denying them epistemic authority, and producing knowledge that reinforces gender and other social hierarchies. These failures are traced to flawed conceptions of knowledge, knowers, and objectivity, which, for example, insist that objective knowledge is ascertained through a “view from nowhere” (Haraway, 1988; Harding, 1995). Contrary to such beliefs, but without abandoning the concept of objectivity, feminist epistemologists emphasize that what is known reflects the situation and perspective of the knower. Reflecting on that situation and perspective, they suggest, ought to be part of the process of learning (Haraway, 1988; Harding, 1992).

Feminist epistemologists argue that situated knowers are responsible knowers: they take responsibility for what they know and how they claim to know what they know (Haraway, 1988). Patricia Hill Collins (2000) calls this an “ethic of personal accountability” (p. 284). According to her, Black feminist epistemology expects people to be personally accountable for their knowledge claims. This means that they are accountable not only for the validity of what they say but also for the personal convictions and actions that underlie or influence their positions. In line with this idea, assessments of knowledge claims must include an evaluation of an individual's character, values, and ethics. Knowledge claims from individuals who are ethically committed to their ideas carry more weight than claims from those who maintain a distance between what they say and how they live.

To demonstrate her point, Collins shares an experience from an undergraduate class session where Black female students refused to accept a prominent Black male scholar's analysis of Black feminism without some indication of his personal ethics. The students were especially interested in details of the scholar's life, such as his relationship with Black women and his social class background. According to Collins (2000), “they used this information to assess whether he really cared about his topic, and invoked this ethic of caring in advancing their knowledge claims about his work” (p. 285).

We suggest that theorists of deliberation should consider the implications that the ethic of personal accountability has for practices of deliberation, especially regarding the norms of sincerity and objectivity. Sincerity is usually understood by theorists of deliberation as a demand to mean what we say and say what we mean (Habermas, 2001, p. 34). By contrast, an ethic of personal accountability appears to require embodied sincerity—that we do what we say and say what we do. It thus connects the spoken word to the body and action. In other words, it helps expose not just the reasonableness of people's arguments but also people's integrity in acting on them (Nili, 2018). Rather than evaluating arguments based on their rational, universal justification, as suggested by the conventional (disembodied) norm of objectivity, embodied sincerity suggests that we assess what people say against the background of relevant aspects of their actions and ways of life: you may talk the talk, but do you walk the walk?

What difference does this shift mean for how we should act toward one another in conversations? We suggest that it affects both the kind of support a normative claim requires, as Collins herself argues, and, by implication, the importance we give to including different relevant experiences in the process of forming our views. Thus, as Collins suggests, the one who makes a normative claim needs to support it by explaining what this claim means for the speaker's way of living their lives. In addition, we suggest that it also means that speakers must pay attention to, learn from, and be held accountable to, how their claims relate to the lived experiences of others. We will explain these implications one at a time.

Collins illustrates the limits of the norm of disembodied objectivity by using the case with the students who confront the male scholar on his credibility in light of his biography and how he currently lives his life. The value of this move is that it changes what kind of merits one needs to obtain to be taken seriously. It is no longer sufficient to acquire rhetorical skills, socially appropriate language, or abstract “objective” knowledge. The important thing is not merely what he claims to believe but also whether and how he acts on that conviction. This idea contradicts the reasoning of many theorists, who think a good understanding of a problem and the ethical standing of different solutions are something valuable on their own, but it squares well with more practical thinking about social change, including antiracist thinking (Kendi, 2019) and ideas of critical reflection in practice (Holdo, 2023). To know something only in theory, in this view, is not to know enough. By contrast, to know something in practice is to be able to reflect critically. What personal experiences have shaped the knowledge of this male scholar? If he claims to advance feminism, how do his feminist assumptions and intentions affect his personal life? What do they require from his way of life, and does he live up to it? What consequences may discrepancies between talk and action have? How, for example, do they affect the struggle for Black women's emancipation?

There is an additional implication of this view of particular importance for public deliberation. Making things personal means questioning not only what experiences you had that informed your views but also if and how you considered the experiences of relevant others. Whose views are being silenced in this conversation and should be included? To take Collins’ example again, if you claim to support the rights of Black women, how did the experiences and views of Black women affect your understanding of how to do so? The idea of holding each other accountable for having considered experiences other than our own, and especially the experiences of people who are subject to epistemic injustices, is not exactly Collins’ point. But exploring this path is, we think, consistent with Collins’ argument for decentering political thought and critiquing Eurocentric and male-dominated discourse. It is also consistent with Collins’ emphasis on dialogue as essential for knowledge production. Collins contrasts Black feminist practices of learning through the sharing of experiences, through dialogue, to the idea of knowledge production as a process in which people separate “objective” knowledge from personal experience, or “subtract the personality of an individual from his or her ideas because they see personality as biasing those ideas” (Collins, 2000, p. 283). Thus, knowledge requires connection with others, based on the recognition of the validity and relevance of others’ experiences. Extending this idea slightly, we suggest that knowledge that is not based on dialogue with other people whose experiences should be relevant—because they are affected by the issues under discussion or because they have engaged with them—should not have equal weight as knowledge that is. This implication is important for how we extend Collins’ ethic of accountability to theorizing public deliberation.

Our argument has similarities with how feminist critics have shown that deliberative theorists have helped mask injustices by defending a norm of impartiality. Feminist critics of the impartiality principle have suggested that urging oppressed groups to put their partial interests aside risks trapping them in the very structures they seek to dismantle (Phillips, 1995; Williams, 2000; Young, 2000). While this debate concerns whether arguments need to speak to everyone's immediate experiences and interests, our concern is of a different kind: We are not concerned with the question of social difference and group representation in deliberation, but how arguments relate to deliberators' ways of life. We claim that arguing and judging must become more personal if deliberation is to serve social justice—as opposed to merely helping improve people's abilities to converse about things that they may care very little about in practice. Thus, while being concerned with a different issue than impartiality, our view shares with feminist critics of impartiality the questioning of norms that undermine objections to the domination of privileged groups.

By pointing toward an alternative standard for evaluating knowledge claims and normative claims, the ethic of personal accountability helps us articulate an ideal of embodied sincerity that disrupts the reproduction of biased and oppressive practices of knowledge production and illuminates the status quo–promoting disconnections between speech and action that such practices allow. For subordinate or dissenting groups, embodied sincerity helps hold privileged people accountable and detect ways of talking that may obstruct their emancipation. For the privileged, too, however, it offers a different kind of conversation, in which they are encouraged to reflect more deeply on how they participate in practices of domination. The latter is as important as the former since it is not always obvious what would be required of us to feel confident that we, and others, act in ways that correspond to the ethical convictions we claim to hold. Making our way of life part of exchanges of knowledge and views provides us with better possibilities to figure this out. It helps us to collectively reflect on and identify experiences and actions that matter for practicing what we preach.

While an ethic of personal accountability encourages reflection on discrepancies between views and actions, it is not sufficient to merely acknowledge that they exist. Consider an organizer of a debate or a roundtable discussion who, full of regret, states that the panel unfortunately only consists of men. Such action, we would suggest, remains an empty gesture—or a “nonperformative,” to use Ahmed's term, a speech act that “works” by allowing someone to not do what they claim to intend (Ahmed, 2006). In contrast to such nonperformatives, the norm of embodied sincerity tracks if and how normative positions are transformed into social actions. Thus, to comply with the norm, it is not enough to merely declare an intention or observe a failure to do so. Instead, the norm requires that participants take responsibility—and hold each other accountable—for actually walking the walk. In the case of the all-male roundtable discussion, embodied deliberation with the organizer and roundtable participants would raise questions such as: why did the organizer not make sure to recruit women? Why did they not reflect more on what it means to create roundtables that are relevant and inclusive to people of different gender identities? What would it mean to practice what they preach in this situation? And if the male participants in the roundtable agree with the norm of gender parity, should they not have made their participation conditional on a mixed panel?

In sum, the ethic of personal accountability means a shift toward holding each participant in a conversation accountable by demanding to know how a person's views resonate with their way of life. It also means a shift toward the aim of personal change through self-reflection on how we can get better at practicing what we preach. In these different ways, the ethic of personal accountability pushes deliberation in an emancipatory direction.

The norm of disembodied objectivity has been so established in public discourse and the literature on public deliberation that it may seem rash to suggest replacing it with a different norm. Are we, perhaps, throwing out the baby with the bathwater by giving up disembodied objectivity for embodied sincerity? Let us consider four specific problems on which the ethic of personal accountability forces us to take a stand.

Our embodied histories always play a crucial part in public deliberation, whether participants recognize this or not. Our aim in this paper has been to argue that rather than seeking ways to reduce their role, we should make the personal a more explicit part of our conversations. But what does deliberation look like when it gives appropriate room not just to our arguments but also to our personal lives?

In this different mode of deliberation, we apply the ethic of personal accountability. This means holding each other accountable to a norm of embodied sincerity: that we not only talk the talk but also walk the walk. This addresses a common problem of public deliberation: No matter how the terms of discourse change, injustices continue to be reproduced through concrete social practices.

The norm of embodied sincerity serves the emancipatory project with which deliberative theory was, at the outset, inseparable (Dryzek, 2000; Hammond, 2019; Khoban, 2019; Rostbøll, 2008). It provides all participants with the possibility to judge the sincerity of other speakers. Do they act according to their stated views? On what experiences and other sources of knowledge do they base their views? The ethic of personal accountability invites us to reflect on our own experiences and how they inform our views, and how we need to change to practice what we say we believe.

We gave four examples of problems that bring the conflict between the two ideals, embodied sincerity and disembodied objectivity, to the fore. Further scholarship might explore the conditions under which these problems can be handled with care or avoided, and in which contexts they may make it harmful to act on an ethics of personal accountability. We have responded to each of these potential objections by showing why they do not in themselves undermine the argument for making things personal. However, the consequences of this alternative norm will depend on the specific conditions under which it is acted upon. Thus, while we argue in support of making things personal as a desirable part of public deliberation, we recognize that the values associated with it will be realized only if practiced responsibly and under conditions of trust that will not be realized overnight or in an institutional vacuum. For us, this means much more work is needed to carefully consider how deliberation can be practiced in the service of social justice.

The idea of embodied sincerity can create discomfort. It means questioning other participants’ sincerity and confronting them about the ways they fail to practice what they preach. It also means questioning biases in how we listen to others and challenging ourselves to engage collectively with our different experiences and the lessons we can learn from them. Thus, even if it seems uncomfortable, it is precisely by bringing views and knowledge claims to bear on concrete actions that deliberation can spark social change. Too often, we allow each other to talk the talk while failing to walk the walk. That is how we reproduce social injustices, how we let each other do violence to others, while we congratulate ourselves and others for knowing all the right words, marching all the right marches, and tweeting all the right tweets.

以身作则:为什么我们需要在公共讨论中把事情个人化?
批判性反思和提高意识是当今许多人日常生活的一部分:在工作场所和组织中,在人际关系中,在媒体和畅销书中,人们越来越多地讨论平等对待彼此意味着什么,如何不成为种族主义者,以及我们仍然以性别、种族、能力、年龄、阶级、性取向或宗教观点为基础排斥或边缘化人们的许多方式。进行这样的对话并不容易。他们通常在一个非常普通的层面上进行,不指名道姓,不生气,也没有对抗。我们习惯于这样讨论:重要的不是个人的故事,而是一般的模式;不是我们的经历和感受,而是客观事实和论据;不是我们未能实现理想和信念,而是一些抽象的“我们”仍然需要努力。不涉及个人隐私是为了确保每个人都能畅所欲言,被倾听,而不管他们的个人经历和生活方式如何。在民主理论中,将集体反思理解为一种“理性讨论”一直是学者们研究公共审议领域的核心部分。在哈贝马斯的名言中,审议的参与者应该只对更好的论点的力量作出反应,而不是重视说话人的地位和权力(哈贝马斯,1975,1984)。虽然这是早期审议工作的关键组成部分,但这一观点现在受到了无数学者的批评(见Curato等人,2019;Holdo, 2020 b)。女权主义和批判理论家认为,这种观点模糊了在深思熟虑发生的真实情况下,人们的观点和表达自己的方式是如何体现的——也就是说,总是由他们特定的位置和经验塑造的(Hayward, 2004;Holdo, 2015;奥尔森,2011;Young, 1996, 2000)。今天,许多商议理论家承认,我们的交流方式——包括说和听,表达和思考——在一定程度上反映了文化和社会等级。这通常被视为一种论证,主张对应在审议中被接受的表达类型采取更具包容性的方法。因此,深思熟虑的学者们开始接受情感、证词、问候、修辞和讲故事,作为早期理性讨论理想的补充(见Bächtiger等人,2018;Elstub, 2010)。对审议理论早期理想的批评,在某种程度上,可以被看作是对无实体客观性规范的批评:我们应该倾听和回应所说的话,而不管谁在说。情感、证词和讲故事都是表达的方式,见证了我们是谁,我们经历了什么。在本文中,我们试图通过探索这种对审议理论的批评的含义来进一步挑战无实体客观性的规范——我们认为,我们需要以一种比审议理论家目前承认的更激进的方式使审议个人化。我们认为,人们应该通过让彼此对体现真诚的规范负责来让事情个人化。在日常语言中,这在一定程度上意味着实践自己所宣扬的东西。体现的真诚指的是说出一个人所体现的观点和经历:说到做到,说到做到。例如,一个人是否以反种族主义的方式行事对于评估反种族主义观点至关重要,而一个自称女权主义者的人是否真的采取了女权主义行动,对于我们如何理解她们的主张的实际重要性至关重要。如果没有这种话语与实践、言论与行动之间的联系,深思熟虑很容易变成一场文字游戏——知道别人认为什么观点和术语是可以接受的或进步的就足够了。但是,如果审议要为解放的政治行动服务,如果审议理论要忠实于它在批判理论中的根源,那么它不仅需要以推进修辞为导向,还需要以变革的社会变革为导向。我们认为,个人责任应该是任何审议过程的重要组成部分,因为它具有三个关键功能:它有助于评估一个人对其言论的承诺,它有助于理解和评估告知一个人观点的经验,它有助于通过将话语带到具体实践中来产生批判性的自我反思。接下来,我们讨论先前对审议中理性论证的传统观念的批评。这些表明,我们需要将叙事、情感和身份作为审议过程的组成部分。我们的观点是,这些争论试图拓宽政治沟通的模式,而不是强调言语与行动之间的关系。 然后,我们概述了个人责任的含义,并解释了个人责任伦理的转变对我们在对话中如何对待彼此以及我们如何评估知识(包括我们自己和他人的知识)有什么不同。在第四部分中,我们将讨论几个可能的反对意见。我们认为,其中最重要的是,根据我们的信念行事和分享个人经历对我们观点的影响的后果是不平等的,而是根据我们在权力结构中的位置而有所不同。出于这个原因,我们回应说,行行的伦理需要被视为一种情境伦理,而不是一种无条件的命令。我们的论证暗示的并不是所有人都应该采取同样的行动或以同样的方式承担责任,而是所有人都应该受到挑战,反思他们是否确实按照自己的信仰行事,以及他们相信某事为真的方式是否反映了对包容和平等的伦理和认识论承诺,在某种程度上,他们可以为自己和他人辩护。因此,我们不捍卫道德的完美主义或纯洁。相反,正如我们在结论讨论中强调的那样,实践具身真诚的规范包括理解,在我们行动的条件下,我们是否可能或应该采取不同的行动,以及我们是否以及如何在未来采取不同的行动。作为一种批判性反思的形式,它允许人们从复杂的讨论转向挑战社会不公正的行动。根据协商民主理论,政治决策应该是公平讨论的产物,并以互惠的理由和改变意见的意愿为指导(Dahlberg, 2004)。当公众审议成功时,它被认为可以消除权力不平衡,使一些人比其他人有更好的机会影响决策和讨论。在一个好的深思熟虑的谈话中,人们根据自己的优点来考虑论点。他们只屈服于“更好的论证的无力量”(哈贝马斯,1975,第108页)。理论上,这种深思熟虑将有助于揭露结构性不公正,支持个人解放(Hammond, 2019;Rostbø我,2008)。在过去的几十年里,协商民主理论经历了几代理论家从理想主义命题到实践探索和实证研究(Elstub, 2010;Elstub et al., 2016)。作为这一发展的一部分,新一代的理论家试图适应一种令人担忧的批评:即最初的审慎推理理想模糊了排除和不平等。例如,批评者认为,审议理论通过将普遍性置于特殊性之上,将公正性置于偏袒之上,从而维持了结构性的不公正(Williams, 2000;Young, 1996, 2000)。此外,一些人认为,人们对给出理由和令人信服意味着什么的实际理解和期望,往往优先于表达清晰、有序和冷静的说话方式,而不是情绪化、充满激情和个人化的说话方式(Sanders, 1997;Young, 2000,第36-51页)。批评者认为,这再现了歧视和排斥边缘社会群体的做法,并使其合法化,这些群体往往被视为情绪化而非理性,表达主观感受而不是客观有效的论点(另见Hayward, 2004;奥尔森,2011)。为了使审议更具包容性和平等性,各种理论家试图突破给出理由的界限。最值得注意的是,Iris Marion Young(2000,第2章)引入了问候语、修辞和叙事作为公共讨论和审议的丰富叙述。最近对这一讨论的贡献试图证明有必要扩大公共审议的概念,以包括可能被视为非公共或不适合“审议”标签的交流形式。例如,一些理论家认为,在一个不平等的社会中,协商民主派应该接受甚至拥抱抗议和其他对抗策略,作为公共协商的一部分(Curato, 2021;Fung, 2005;Holdo, 2020;年轻,2001)。最近,学者们强调非语言的表达方式是表达理由的一种方式。例如,Toby Rollo(2017)强调了主动抗议、退出和沉默对公共辩论的贡献,mendonpada等人(2020)认为视觉和声音在公共辩论交流中发挥着重要作用。除了建议拓宽审议中给出理由概念的实践之外,学者们还对揭示人们的社会位置如何塑造他们的主张以及重新协商边缘化参与者和观点的影响的策略感兴趣。根据Azmanova (2012, pp。 218-219),社会地位和规范地位之间的关系需要在公共审议中成为主题,以揭示参与者提出的所有主张中编码的不公正的结构性来源。她断言,这可以通过给出“有理由的理由”来实现,也就是说,通过解释一个人是如何形成一种观点的,以及出于什么原因形成这种观点。我们赞同先前的批评,认为我们需要认识到其他的推理模式,并考虑到参与者的社会位置和情境动机。然而,这些贡献并没有将参与审议的人所说的——他们的主张、反对和宣言——与他们的生活方式联系起来,也就是说,他们所说的是否与他们所做的相一致。在本文中,我们探讨了这种联系是否有助于指导集体批判性反思,并使参与者对他们所说的话负责。与之前的研究相比,我们在让思考更加个人化方面迈出了激进的一步。因此,我们也以一种更根本的方式挑战无实体客观的规范——一种将审议框架为“公共”而不是“私人”问题,“理性”而不是“情绪化”的论点,以及与个人经验脱节的“客观有效”观点的规范。这些举动使对话远离了个人斗争、缺点和盲点对我们日常生活中的具体行为以及更具体的交往的影响,并抑制了可以通过问责、承认和面对不公正的行动来解放的深思熟虑。女性主义认识论家长期以来一直在讨论无实体的客观性问题,特别是在科学研究方面。这些学者强调,知识归因、获取和证明的主导观念和实践将女性和其他从属群体排除在调查之外,否认她们的认知权威,并产生强化性别和其他社会等级的知识,从而使她们处于不利地位。这些失败可以追溯到对知识、知识者和客观性有缺陷的概念,例如,坚持认为客观知识是通过“无处可见的观点”来确定的(Haraway, 1988;哈丁,1995)。与这种信念相反,但不放弃客观性的概念,女性主义认识论强调已知的反映了知识者的情况和观点。他们认为,反思这种情况和观点应该是学习过程的一部分(Haraway, 1988;哈丁,1992)。女权主义认识论认为,情境知识者是负责任的知识者:他们对自己所知道的和他们如何声称知道他们所知道的负责(Haraway, 1988)。帕特里夏·希尔·柯林斯(Patricia Hill Collins, 2000)称其为“个人责任伦理”(第284页)。根据她的说法,黑人女权主义认识论希望人们对自己的知识主张负责。这意味着他们不仅要对自己言论的正确性负责,还要对作为其立场基础或影响其立场的个人信念和行为负责。根据这一观点,对知识要求的评估必须包括对个人性格、价值观和道德的评估。与那些在言行之间保持距离的人相比,那些从道德上坚持自己观点的人所提出的知识主张更有分量。为了证明她的观点,柯林斯分享了她在一次本科课堂上的经历,当时黑人女学生拒绝接受一位杰出的黑人男学者对黑人女权主义的分析,而不考虑他的个人道德。学生们对这位学者的生活细节特别感兴趣,比如他与黑人妇女的关系以及他的社会阶层背景。根据Collins(2000)的说法,“他们使用这些信息来评估他是否真的关心他的主题,并在推进他们对他的工作的知识主张时援引这种关心的伦理”(第285页)。我们建议,审议理论家应该考虑个人责任伦理对审议实践的影响,特别是关于真诚和客观性的规范。真诚通常被商议理论家理解为一种要求,要求我们言出必行,言出必行(哈贝马斯,2001,第34页)。相比之下,个人责任伦理似乎要求体现出真诚——我们说什么做什么,说什么做什么。因此,它将口头语言与身体和行动联系起来。换句话说,它不仅有助于揭示人们的论点的合理性,还有助于揭示人们在采取行动时的诚信(Nili, 2018)。 而不是根据理性的、普遍的理由来评估论点,正如传统的(无实体的)客观性规范所建议的那样,具体化的诚意建议我们在人们行为和生活方式的相关方面的背景下评估他们说的话:你可能会说到做到吗?这种转变对我们在谈话中应该如何对待对方意味着什么?我们认为,它既影响规范性主张所需要的那种支持,正如柯林斯自己所论证的那样,也影响我们在形成观点的过程中给予包括不同相关经验的重要性。因此,正如柯林斯所建议的那样,提出规范性主张的人需要通过解释这一主张对说话人的生活方式意味着什么来支持它。此外,我们认为这也意味着演讲者必须注意、学习并对他们的主张如何与他人的生活经历联系起来负责。我们将逐一解释这些含义。柯林斯举例说明了无实体客观规范的局限性,他的学生们根据这位男性学者的传记和他目前的生活方式,就他的可信度与他进行了对质。这一举动的价值在于,它改变了一个人需要获得什么样的优点才能得到重视。仅仅获得修辞技巧、适合社交的语言或抽象的“客观”知识已经不够了。重要的不仅仅是他声称相信什么,还包括他是否以及如何根据这种信念行事。这一观点与许多理论家的推理相矛盾,他们认为对问题的良好理解和不同解决方案的道德地位本身就是有价值的,但它与对社会变革的更实际的思考相吻合,包括反种族主义思维(Kendi, 2019)和实践中的批判性反思思想(Holdo, 2023)。在这种观点看来,仅仅在理论上了解一些事情是不够的。相反,在实践中了解事物就是能够批判性地反思。哪些个人经历塑造了这位男性学者的知识?如果他声称要推进女权主义,那么他的女权主义假设和意图如何影响他的个人生活?他们对他的生活方式有什么要求,他达到了吗?说话和行动之间的差异可能会产生什么后果?例如,他们是如何影响黑人妇女解放运动的?这一观点还有一个对公众审议特别重要的附加含义。把事情个人化意味着不仅要问你有哪些经历影响了你的观点,还要问你是否以及如何考虑相关的其他人的经历。谁的观点在这场对话中被压制了,应该被包括进来?再举柯林斯的例子,如果你声称支持黑人妇女的权利,黑人妇女的经历和观点是如何影响你对如何做到这一点的理解的?让每个人都对自己以外的经历负责,尤其是那些在认知上受到不公正对待的人的经历,这并不是柯林斯的观点。但我们认为,探索这条道路与柯林斯关于政治思想去中心化和批判欧洲中心主义和男性主导话语的论点是一致的。这也与柯林斯强调对话对于知识生产至关重要的观点相一致。柯林斯将黑人女权主义者通过分享经验、通过对话来学习的做法与知识生产的观点进行了对比,认为知识生产是一个过程,在这个过程中,人们将“客观”知识与个人经验分开,或者“从他或她的想法中减去个人的个性,因为他们认为个性会使这些想法产生偏见”(柯林斯,2000年,第283页)。因此,知识需要与他人建立联系,建立在承认他人经验的有效性和相关性的基础上。稍微扩展一下这个观点,我们认为,那些不是基于与其他人对话的知识,因为他们受到正在讨论的问题的影响,或者因为他们参与了这些问题,所以他们的经验应该是相关的,而这些知识不应该与那些相关的知识同等重要。这一含义对于我们如何将柯林斯的责任伦理扩展到公共审议的理论化是很重要的。我们的观点与女权主义批评家的观点有相似之处,他们认为,协商理论家通过捍卫公正的准则,帮助掩盖了不公正。批评不偏不倚原则的女权主义者认为,敦促受压迫群体把他们的部分利益放在一边,可能会使他们陷入他们试图拆除的结构中(Phillips, 1995;威廉姆斯,2000;年轻,2000)。 虽然这场辩论关注的是辩论是否需要涉及每个人的直接经验和利益,但我们关注的是另一种问题:我们不关心社会差异和审议中的群体代表问题,而是辩论如何与审议者的生活方式联系起来。我们认为,如果深思熟虑要服务于社会正义,辩论和判断就必须变得更加个人化——而不是仅仅帮助提高人们谈论他们在实践中可能很少关心的事情的能力。因此,虽然我们关注的是与公正不同的问题,但我们的观点与批评公正的女权主义者一样,质疑那些削弱对特权群体统治的反对的规范。通过指出评估知识主张和规范主张的另一种标准,个人责任伦理帮助我们阐明了一种体现真诚的理想,这种真诚破坏了知识生产中有偏见和压迫性实践的再生产,并阐明了这种实践允许的言论和行动之间的现状——促进了脱节。对于下属或持不同意见的群体,体现的真诚有助于让享有特权的人承担责任,并发现可能阻碍他们解放的谈话方式。然而,对于享有特权的人来说,它也提供了一种不同的对话,鼓励他们更深入地反思他们是如何参与统治实践的。后者与前者同样重要,因为我们需要什么才能对自己和他人的行为方式与我们声称持有的道德信念相一致感到自信,这并不总是显而易见的。让我们的生活方式成为知识和观点交流的一部分,为我们解决这个问题提供了更好的可能性。它帮助我们集体反思和识别经验和行动,对实践我们所宣扬的东西很重要。虽然个人负责的伦理鼓励对观点和行动之间的差异进行反思,但仅仅承认它们的存在是不够的。想想一位辩论或圆桌讨论的组织者,他满怀遗憾地说,很遗憾,小组成员都是男性。我们认为,这样的行为仍然是一种空洞的姿态——或者用艾哈迈德的话来说,是一种“非行为”,一种通过允许某人不做他们声称想做的事情而“起作用”的言语行为(艾哈迈德,2006)。与这些非执行行为相反,体现真诚的规范跟踪规范性立场是否以及如何转化为社会行动。因此,要遵守规范,仅仅宣布意图或观察未能这样做是不够的。相反,规范要求参与者承担责任——并让彼此承担责任——为实际行动负责。在全男性圆桌讨论的情况下,与组织者和圆桌参与者的具体讨论将提出这样的问题:为什么组织者不确保招募女性?为什么他们没有更多地思考创建与不同性别认同的人相关和包容的圆桌会议意味着什么?在这种情况下,实践他们所宣扬的意味着什么?如果圆桌会议的男性参与者同意性别平等的准则,他们不应该把自己的参与作为一个男女混合小组的条件吗?总而言之,个人问责的伦理意味着一种转变,通过要求知道一个人的观点如何与他们的生活方式产生共鸣,使对话中的每个参与者都负起责任。这也意味着通过自我反思,我们如何才能更好地实践我们所宣扬的,向个人改变的目标转变。通过这些不同的方式,个人责任伦理将审议推向解放的方向。在公共话语和关于公共审议的文献中,无实体客观性的规范已经如此确立,以至于建议用一种不同的规范来取代它似乎是轻率的。也许,我们为了体现的真诚而放弃无实体的客观性,是在把婴儿和洗澡水一起倒掉吗?让我们考虑个人责任伦理迫使我们采取立场的四个具体问题。无论参与者是否认识到这一点,我们所体现的历史总是在公共审议中发挥着至关重要的作用。我们在这篇论文中的目的是,我们应该让个人成为我们对话中更明确的一部分,而不是寻求减少他们的作用的方法。但是,当深思熟虑不仅给我们的争论,而且给我们的个人生活提供适当的空间时,它会是什么样子呢?在这种不同的审议模式中,我们运用个人责任的伦理。这意味着让彼此对体现真诚的规范负责:我们不仅要说到做到。 这解决了公共审议的一个共同问题:无论话语的条件如何变化,不公正都会通过具体的社会实践继续复制。体现真诚的规范服务于解放计划,审议理论从一开始就与解放计划密不可分(Dryzek, 2000;哈蒙德,2019;Khoban, 2019;Rostbø我,2008)。它为所有与会者提供了判断其他发言者的诚意的可能性。他们是否按照自己陈述的观点行事?他们的观点基于哪些经验和其他知识来源?个人责任的伦理要求我们反思自己的经历,思考它们如何影响我们的观点,以及我们需要如何改变以实践我们所说的信念。我们举了四个问题的例子,这些问题突出了体现的真诚和不体现的客观这两种理想之间的冲突。进一步的学术研究可能会探索在哪些条件下可以谨慎处理或避免这些问题,以及在哪些情况下,这些问题可能会对个人责任伦理造成伤害。我们已经对每一个潜在的反对意见做出了回应,说明了为什么这些反对意见本身并没有削弱把事情个人化的论点。然而,这种替代规范的后果将取决于采取行动的具体条件。因此,虽然我们支持将个人事务作为公共审议的理想组成部分,但我们认识到,与之相关的价值只有在负责任地实践并在信任的条件下才能实现,而信任不会在一夜之间或在制度真空中实现。对我们来说,这意味着需要做更多的工作来认真考虑如何进行审议以服务于社会正义。体现真诚的想法会带来不适。这意味着质疑其他参与者的诚意,直面他们言行不一的问题。这也意味着质疑我们如何倾听他人的偏见,挑战自己,以集体的方式参与我们不同的经历,并从中吸取教训。因此,即使看起来不舒服,但正是通过将观点和知识主张付诸具体行动,审议才能引发社会变革。太多的时候,我们允许对方只说不做。这就是我们如何再现社会不公,我们如何让彼此对他人施暴,而我们却为自己和他人知道了所有正确的词语、进行了所有正确的游行、发了所有正确的推文而庆幸。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信