Xenotransplantation clinical trials: Should patients with diminished capacity be permitted to enroll?

IF 3.3 4区 医学 Q2 MEDICINE, RESEARCH & EXPERIMENTAL
Daniel Rodger, James Mack, Christopher Bobier, Luz Padilla, Daniel J. Hurst
{"title":"Xenotransplantation clinical trials: Should patients with diminished capacity be permitted to enroll?","authors":"Daniel Rodger, James Mack, Christopher Bobier, Luz Padilla, Daniel J. Hurst","doi":"10.1111/xen.12857","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<h2>1 INTRODUCTION</h2>\n<p>Before xenotransplantation clinical trials begin, it is essential to establish clear and equitable participant selection criteria. Selection criteria have been suggested in the literature, as well as in a proposed kidney xenotransplantation phase 1 clinical trial.<span><sup>1-4</sup></span> In each, inclusion criteria is predicated on patients possessing clinical decision-making capacity. Ensuring informed consent for xenotransplantation clinical trials with patients who have decision-making capacity is recognized as complex for the following reasons: the possibility of therapeutic misconception, potential for xenozoonosis, and the potentially burdensome requirement for lifelong biosurveillance.<span><sup>5, 6</sup></span> Informed consent for enrollment in a xenotransplantation trial with adult persons who have diminished capacity would involve additional complexities. By diminished capacity, we mean to describe someone who—for various medical reasons—does not have the ability to provide informed consent. To our knowledge, no xenotransplantation investigator, nor the proposed kidney xenotransplantation phase I clinical trial in the United States, currently proposes including persons with diminished capacity. Nonetheless, the topic has been broached, and we believe it requires additional independent scrutiny.</p>\n<h3>1.1 Current recommendations for including persons with diminished capacity</h3>\n<p>Xenotransplantation clinical trials with persons who lack decision-making capacity have not been considered at length and would likely be controversial. The Nuffield Council on Bioethics recommended that “the first xenotransplantation trials should not involve adults incapable of consenting to participation on their own behalf” (7.25).<span><sup>7</sup></span> It made an exception, however: “The Medical Research Council has recommended that the participation of incapacitated adults in therapeutic research may be justified if, in addition to evidence that the procedure will benefit the individual, it relates to their incapacitating condition and the relevant knowledge could not be gained by research in adults able to consent” (7.26).<span><sup>7</sup></span> Similarly, the United States Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS) stated: “enrollment of mentally impaired individuals into xenotransplantation protocols should be limited to those in whom mental capacity is likely to be restored by the procedure.”<span><sup>8</sup></span> Additionally, in the DHHS guidelines, a surrogate must confirm that the clinical trial aligns with the person's preferences or would promote their best interests and that they are “likely to adhere to lifelong follow-up requirements.”<span><sup>8</sup></span></p>\n<p>In 2012, the American Medical Association (AMA) Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs posited that it “would be ethical to include children and incompetent adults in xenotransplantation research protocols only when the patients are terminally ill and alternative treatments are not available” (Opinion 2.169.4).<span><sup>9</sup></span> The AMA <i>Code of Medical Ethics</i> states:</p>\n<p>Physicians who choose to participate in clinical research that involves transplantation of organs or tissues from nonhuman sources should:</p>\n<p>(e) Ensure that if participation by individuals who lack decision-making capacity is contemplated, appropriate measures are taken to safeguard their interests.<span><sup>10</sup></span></p>\n<h3>1.2 Critique of current recommendations</h3>\n<p>The current recommendations for enrolling participants with diminished capacity into a xenotransplantation clinical trial are vague and insufficiently ethically justified to be practicable. The AMA states that “appropriate measures” should be taken to safeguard the interests of those enrolled, yet what constitutes such measures, aside from trying to ensure the surrogate has any assistance they need to assess quality of life pre- and post-intervention, is largely undefined for xenotransplantation. In the DHHS guidelines, three requirements are envisioned to enroll persons with diminished capacity: (i) the procedure must be “likely” to restore the mental impairment; (ii) the surrogate decision-maker must have evidence that xenotransplantation is what the person wanted or, if such evidence is lacking, determine that xenotransplantation is in the person's best interest; (iii) confirm that the patient is a responsible person who is “likely to adhere to lifelong follow-up requirements.” DHHS guidelines are unlikely to be satisfied—at least in the earlier phases of clinical trials. Condition (i) may prove difficult to initially meet. Given the lack of xenotransplantation outcomes in humans, “likely” benefit is tenuous. Additionally, some clinical and biological causes for diminished capacity may be irreversible. Condition (ii) is difficult to establish, as very few people are likely to discuss xenotransplantation and all the implications of receiving a xenograft (e.g., biosurveillance) in advance. There is also no clear definition as to what evidence would be acceptable to meet such criteria. Condition (iii) will always be difficult to determine with any certainty because it will be dependent on several variables, for example, their degree of physical dependency and need following their restored capacity. Even individuals with capacity and a social support system can be non-compliant with medical requirements. It is also worth drawing attention to the importance of ensuring that any lifelong biosurveillance requirements carefully balance what is clinically necessary against how burdensome they are for a patient and how logistically feasible enforcement is. After all, the more burdensome the requirements are, the less likely that a patient may be to comply—in either the short or long-term—especially in cases where informed consent was given by a surrogate.</p>\n<p>A phase I clinical trial is unlikely to meet the threshold for the DHHS requirements that the xenograft is “likely” to restore the patient's impaired capacity. A phase I trial's purpose is to assess safety and evaluate certain limitations and advantages. While xenotransplantation could theoretically restore capacity in very limited instances, there are existing therapeutic options that are less risky and more clinically appropriate for end-stage renal disease and end-stage heart failure (e.g., hemodialysis, allotransplantation). Due to the experimental nature of the therapy, the requisite likelihood of success would be too low to be deemed acceptable in the context of a phase I trial. The case for a favorable risk-benefit evaluation is lowest at the phase I stage and becomes more favorable at each subsequent clinical trial phase. However, if we suppose that dialysis is not a viable clinical option and the likelihood of receiving an allograft is low, it may be appropriate to consider such patients for inclusion in later phase clinical trials given that a degree of safety and efficacy would have been demonstrated; in such cases, if a xenograft may offer a sufficiently reasonable likelihood of restoring capacity, then the balance shifts. However, as most guidelines recommend post-xenotransplantation monitoring for xenozoonotic disease, further complications exist with the DHHS recommendations regarding how a person can be reasonably expected to comply with monitoring when they never agreed to comply with such, potentially burdensome, conditions.</p>\n<h3>1.3 Comment</h3>\n<p>It would be a high benchmark to meet, as well as require significant justification, to determine that an unproven and risky clinical trial is likely to restore capacity or has the highest probable net benefit among available treatment options (including continued dialysis; allograft waitlisting; palliative care) and is therefore in the patient's best interest. If xenotransplantation proves to be a safe and effective clinical option, it may also be unethical to withhold participation in a later phase clinical trial (e.g., phase III) to individuals with diminished capacity and who need a transplant. Striking a balance between advancing clinical research and protecting the rights and well-being of vulnerable individuals requires careful ethical reflection and the development of robust safeguards. At this point, the current recommendations to allow persons with diminished capacity to participate in early xenotransplantation clinical trials are under-developed and should not be considered ethically permissible. Nevertheless, in later phase clinical trials where the clinical risk may be sufficiently reduced it might be ethically acceptable for certain patients with a diminished capacity to be considered for inclusion. The case would be strongest for those patients that are not eligible for allotransplantation, but where there is a realistic likelihood that a xenotransplantation could reverse the cause of their diminished capacity or possibly improve their quality of life.</p>","PeriodicalId":23866,"journal":{"name":"Xenotransplantation","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.3000,"publicationDate":"2024-04-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Xenotransplantation","FirstCategoryId":"3","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/xen.12857","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"医学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"MEDICINE, RESEARCH & EXPERIMENTAL","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

1 INTRODUCTION

Before xenotransplantation clinical trials begin, it is essential to establish clear and equitable participant selection criteria. Selection criteria have been suggested in the literature, as well as in a proposed kidney xenotransplantation phase 1 clinical trial.1-4 In each, inclusion criteria is predicated on patients possessing clinical decision-making capacity. Ensuring informed consent for xenotransplantation clinical trials with patients who have decision-making capacity is recognized as complex for the following reasons: the possibility of therapeutic misconception, potential for xenozoonosis, and the potentially burdensome requirement for lifelong biosurveillance.5, 6 Informed consent for enrollment in a xenotransplantation trial with adult persons who have diminished capacity would involve additional complexities. By diminished capacity, we mean to describe someone who—for various medical reasons—does not have the ability to provide informed consent. To our knowledge, no xenotransplantation investigator, nor the proposed kidney xenotransplantation phase I clinical trial in the United States, currently proposes including persons with diminished capacity. Nonetheless, the topic has been broached, and we believe it requires additional independent scrutiny.

1.1 Current recommendations for including persons with diminished capacity

Xenotransplantation clinical trials with persons who lack decision-making capacity have not been considered at length and would likely be controversial. The Nuffield Council on Bioethics recommended that “the first xenotransplantation trials should not involve adults incapable of consenting to participation on their own behalf” (7.25).7 It made an exception, however: “The Medical Research Council has recommended that the participation of incapacitated adults in therapeutic research may be justified if, in addition to evidence that the procedure will benefit the individual, it relates to their incapacitating condition and the relevant knowledge could not be gained by research in adults able to consent” (7.26).7 Similarly, the United States Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS) stated: “enrollment of mentally impaired individuals into xenotransplantation protocols should be limited to those in whom mental capacity is likely to be restored by the procedure.”8 Additionally, in the DHHS guidelines, a surrogate must confirm that the clinical trial aligns with the person's preferences or would promote their best interests and that they are “likely to adhere to lifelong follow-up requirements.”8

In 2012, the American Medical Association (AMA) Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs posited that it “would be ethical to include children and incompetent adults in xenotransplantation research protocols only when the patients are terminally ill and alternative treatments are not available” (Opinion 2.169.4).9 The AMA Code of Medical Ethics states:

Physicians who choose to participate in clinical research that involves transplantation of organs or tissues from nonhuman sources should:

(e) Ensure that if participation by individuals who lack decision-making capacity is contemplated, appropriate measures are taken to safeguard their interests.10

1.2 Critique of current recommendations

The current recommendations for enrolling participants with diminished capacity into a xenotransplantation clinical trial are vague and insufficiently ethically justified to be practicable. The AMA states that “appropriate measures” should be taken to safeguard the interests of those enrolled, yet what constitutes such measures, aside from trying to ensure the surrogate has any assistance they need to assess quality of life pre- and post-intervention, is largely undefined for xenotransplantation. In the DHHS guidelines, three requirements are envisioned to enroll persons with diminished capacity: (i) the procedure must be “likely” to restore the mental impairment; (ii) the surrogate decision-maker must have evidence that xenotransplantation is what the person wanted or, if such evidence is lacking, determine that xenotransplantation is in the person's best interest; (iii) confirm that the patient is a responsible person who is “likely to adhere to lifelong follow-up requirements.” DHHS guidelines are unlikely to be satisfied—at least in the earlier phases of clinical trials. Condition (i) may prove difficult to initially meet. Given the lack of xenotransplantation outcomes in humans, “likely” benefit is tenuous. Additionally, some clinical and biological causes for diminished capacity may be irreversible. Condition (ii) is difficult to establish, as very few people are likely to discuss xenotransplantation and all the implications of receiving a xenograft (e.g., biosurveillance) in advance. There is also no clear definition as to what evidence would be acceptable to meet such criteria. Condition (iii) will always be difficult to determine with any certainty because it will be dependent on several variables, for example, their degree of physical dependency and need following their restored capacity. Even individuals with capacity and a social support system can be non-compliant with medical requirements. It is also worth drawing attention to the importance of ensuring that any lifelong biosurveillance requirements carefully balance what is clinically necessary against how burdensome they are for a patient and how logistically feasible enforcement is. After all, the more burdensome the requirements are, the less likely that a patient may be to comply—in either the short or long-term—especially in cases where informed consent was given by a surrogate.

A phase I clinical trial is unlikely to meet the threshold for the DHHS requirements that the xenograft is “likely” to restore the patient's impaired capacity. A phase I trial's purpose is to assess safety and evaluate certain limitations and advantages. While xenotransplantation could theoretically restore capacity in very limited instances, there are existing therapeutic options that are less risky and more clinically appropriate for end-stage renal disease and end-stage heart failure (e.g., hemodialysis, allotransplantation). Due to the experimental nature of the therapy, the requisite likelihood of success would be too low to be deemed acceptable in the context of a phase I trial. The case for a favorable risk-benefit evaluation is lowest at the phase I stage and becomes more favorable at each subsequent clinical trial phase. However, if we suppose that dialysis is not a viable clinical option and the likelihood of receiving an allograft is low, it may be appropriate to consider such patients for inclusion in later phase clinical trials given that a degree of safety and efficacy would have been demonstrated; in such cases, if a xenograft may offer a sufficiently reasonable likelihood of restoring capacity, then the balance shifts. However, as most guidelines recommend post-xenotransplantation monitoring for xenozoonotic disease, further complications exist with the DHHS recommendations regarding how a person can be reasonably expected to comply with monitoring when they never agreed to comply with such, potentially burdensome, conditions.

1.3 Comment

It would be a high benchmark to meet, as well as require significant justification, to determine that an unproven and risky clinical trial is likely to restore capacity or has the highest probable net benefit among available treatment options (including continued dialysis; allograft waitlisting; palliative care) and is therefore in the patient's best interest. If xenotransplantation proves to be a safe and effective clinical option, it may also be unethical to withhold participation in a later phase clinical trial (e.g., phase III) to individuals with diminished capacity and who need a transplant. Striking a balance between advancing clinical research and protecting the rights and well-being of vulnerable individuals requires careful ethical reflection and the development of robust safeguards. At this point, the current recommendations to allow persons with diminished capacity to participate in early xenotransplantation clinical trials are under-developed and should not be considered ethically permissible. Nevertheless, in later phase clinical trials where the clinical risk may be sufficiently reduced it might be ethically acceptable for certain patients with a diminished capacity to be considered for inclusion. The case would be strongest for those patients that are not eligible for allotransplantation, but where there is a realistic likelihood that a xenotransplantation could reverse the cause of their diminished capacity or possibly improve their quality of life.

异种器官移植临床试验:是否应允许能力减弱的患者参加?
1 引言 在异种器官移植临床试验开始之前,必须制定明确、公平的参与者选择标准。文献以及一项拟议的肾脏异种移植第一阶段临床试验都提出了选择标准。由于以下原因,确保具有决策能力的患者在异种移植临床试验中获得知情同意被认为是非常复杂的:可能出现治疗误解、可能发生异种动物疫病以及可能需要进行繁琐的终身生物监测5, 6。我们所说的能力减退,是指由于各种医学原因,没有能力做出知情同意的人。据我们所知,目前还没有异种移植研究者或美国拟进行的肾脏异种移植 I 期临床试验提议将能力减退者纳入其中。1.1 关于将行为能力减退者纳入异种器官移植临床试验的现有建议 对缺乏决策能力者进行异种器官移植临床试验的问题尚未进行详细讨论,因此很可能会引起争议。纳菲尔德生物伦理学委员会建议,"首批异种器官移植试验不应涉及无能力代表自己同意参 与试验的成年人"(7.25)。7 不过,该委员会也提出了一个例外:"医学研究委员会建议,如果除了有证据表明有关 程序将使当事人受益外,还与当事人丧失能力的状况有关,而且无法通过对能够表示同意的成 年人进行研究来获得相关知识,那么让丧失能力的成年人参与治疗性研究是合理的"(7.26):7 同样,美国卫生与人类服务部(DHHS)指出:"应将精神受损者纳入异种移植方案,但仅限于那些有可能通过手术恢复精神能力的人。"8 此外,在 DHHS 的指导方针中,代理者必须确认临床试验符合当事人的偏好或将促进其最大利益,而且他们 "有可能遵守终身随访要求"。"8 2012 年,美国医学会(AMA)伦理与司法事务委员会认为,"只有在患者病入膏肓且无法获得替代治疗的情况下,将儿童和无行为能力的成年人纳入异种移植研究方案才是合乎伦理的"(第 2.169.4 号意见)。9 美国医学会《医学伦理守则》规定:选择参与涉及移植非人类器官或组织的临床研究的医生应:(e) 确保在考虑让缺乏决策能力的个人参与时,采取适当措施保障他们的利益。.2 对目前建议的批评 目前关于让能力减弱的参与者参加异种器官移植临床试验的建议含糊不清,在伦理上也不 够合理可行。美国医学会指出,应采取 "适当的措施 "来保障参试者的利益,然而,对于异种移植而言,除了努力确保代治者在评估干预前后的生活质量时获得所需的任何帮助之外,这些措施的构成要素在很大程度上并不明确。在卫生与健康部的指导方针中,对能力减退者的入选提出了三项要求:(i) 手术必须 "有可能 "恢复其智力障碍;(ii) 代理决策者必须有证据证明异种移植是该患者所希望的,如果缺乏此类证据,则必须确定异种移植符合该患者的最佳利益;(iii) 确认患者是一个有责任心的人,"有可能遵守终身随访要求"。至少在临床试验的早期阶段,不太可能满足卫生与健康部的指导方针。条件(i)最初可能难以满足。鉴于缺乏人体异种移植的结果,"可能 "获益并不可靠。此外,导致能力减弱的某些临床和生物学原因可能是不可逆的。条件(ii)很难确定,因为很少有人会事先讨论异种移植以及接受异种移植物的所有影响(如生物监测)。此外,也没有明确定义何种证据可被接受以满足此类标准。 条件(iii)总是很难确定的,因为这取决于几个变量,例如,他们的身体依赖程 度和恢复能力后的需要。即使是有行为能力和社会支持系统的人也可能不遵守医疗要求。同样值得注意的是,必须确保任何终身生物监测要求都能谨慎地平衡临床需要与对患者造成的负担以及强制执行在后勤上的可行性。毕竟,要求越繁琐,患者在短期或长期内遵守要求的可能性就越小,尤其是在知情同意是由代理人做出的情况下。I 期临床试验不太可能达到卫生与健康部要求的门槛,即异种移植 "很可能 "恢复患者受损的能力。I 期临床试验的目的是评估安全性以及某些局限性和优势。虽然异种移植理论上可以在非常有限的情况下恢复能力,但对于终末期肾病和终末期心力衰竭而言,现有的治疗方案(如血液透析、异体移植)风险更低,更适合临床。由于该疗法属于试验性质,其成功的可能性太低,在 I 期试验中无法被接受。在 I 期临床试验阶段,风险-效益评估的有利程度最低,而在随后的临床试验阶段,风险-效益评估的有利程度会越来越高。然而,如果我们假设透析不是一种可行的临床选择,而且接受异体移植的可能性很低,那么考虑将此类患者纳入后期临床试验可能是合适的,因为一定程度的安全性和有效性已经得到证明;在这种情况下,如果异体移植有足够合理的可能性恢复容量,那么平衡就会发生变化。然而,由于大多数指南都建议在异种移植后对异种动物疾病进行监测,因此,卫生与健康部的建议存在着进一步的复杂性,即在患者从未同意遵守这些可能是沉重负担的条件的情况下,如何合理地期望患者遵守监测。.3 评论要确定一项未经证实的高风险临床试验有可能恢复患者的能力,或在现有治疗方案(包括继续透析、等待异体移植、姑息治疗)中具有最高的净效益,并因此符合患者的最佳利益,需要达到很高的基准,并需要提供充分的理由。如果异种移植被证明是一种安全有效的临床选择,那么拒绝需要移植的能力减退患者参与后期临床试验(如 III 期)可能也是不道德的。要在推进临床研究与保护弱势个体的权利和福祉之间取得平衡,需要进行认真的伦理思考,并制定强有力的保障措施。目前,允许能力减退者参与早期异种移植临床试验的建议尚不成熟,在伦理上不应被视为是允许的。不过,在后期临床试验中,临床风险可能会充分降低,从伦理角度来说,考虑让某些行为能力减弱的病人参加试验可能是可以接受的。对于那些不符合异种移植条件,但异种移植有可能逆转能力减退的原因或有可能改善其生活质量的病人来说,这样做的理由最为充分。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
Xenotransplantation
Xenotransplantation 医学-医学:研究与实验
CiteScore
6.80
自引率
15.40%
发文量
58
审稿时长
>12 weeks
期刊介绍: Xenotransplantation provides its readership with rapid communication of new findings in the field of organ and tissue transplantation across species barriers.The journal is not only of interest to those whose primary area is xenotransplantation, but also to veterinarians, microbiologists and geneticists. It also investigates and reports on the controversial theological, ethical, legal and psychological implications of xenotransplantation.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信