Workplace democracy: The argument from the worker–society relation

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS
Zsolt Kapelner
{"title":"Workplace democracy: The argument from the worker–society relation","authors":"Zsolt Kapelner","doi":"10.1111/josp.12559","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Numerous arguments have been offered for workplace democracy, that is, the idea that employees should have an equal say in governing the firm. Lately, relational arguments, particularly of a republican and relational egalitarian kind, have become prominent. These claim that workers should have a say in how their firm is governed in order to avoid objectionable, for example, dominating or subordinating, relationships within the workplace. While I find these views appealing, I also believe that they are incomplete. By focusing on the moral quality of workers' interpersonal relations within the firm, that is, to bosses and other workers, they ignore the moral quality of workers' relations outside the firm, that is, to the rest of society. Yet, this latter is of no less significance for the justification of workplace democracy. In this article, I argue that part of the reason why workplace democracy should be adopted is that it allows workers to exert appropriate control over the operations of the firm, thus maintaining a grip on the general character of the relation between themselves as workers of the firm and the rest of society. This argument from the <i>worker–society relation</i> is not intended to refute or replace republican and relational egalitarian arguments, but rather to draw attention to a hitherto neglected aspect of the relational value of workplace democracy which the aforementioned approaches usually do not incorporate. In this way, the present argument strengthens the overall relational case for workplace democracy.</p><p>The structure of the article is as follows. First, I introduce the concept of and arguments for workplace democracy, focusing on the most prominent relational arguments, that is, republican and relational egalitarian ones. Second, I introduce the concept of the worker–society relation and discuss its moral significance. Third, I present my argument for workplace democracy based on the worker–society relation. Fourth, I discuss the relationship between the argument from the worker–society relation and republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy to show how the former differs from and complements these approaches. The last section concludes.</p><p>Workplace democracy is an arrangement in which all employees of a firm have an equal say in how it is governed, much like in a democratic state where all citizens have an equal say in how the state is governed, except for certain specific groups, such as minors. This broad definition can be further specified in a number of ways. There are many models and institutional designs for workplace democracy but for the purposes of this discussion, I will remain neutral as to which of these is best to implement. I will not discuss whether under workplace democracy employees must exercise their democratic say directly or indirectly through representatives, whether the establishment of workers' councils is required, or whether employee's share in board representation would suffice as well, and so on. While these matters certainly have both practical and theoretical significance, they are not directly relevant to the following argument which is focused on the question of the justification of workplace democracy as such, in whatever way it is implemented.</p><p>Arguments for workplace democracy are numerous and varied (Frega et al., <span>2019</span>). Examples include the arguments from the state-firm analogy (Dahl, <span>1985</span>; Ferreras &amp; Landemore, <span>2016</span>; González-Ricoy, <span>2014a</span>; McMahon, <span>1994</span>), meaningful work (Yeoman, <span>2014</span>), recognition (Hirvonen &amp; Breen, <span>2020</span>), and self-realization (Gould, <span>2004</span>). In recent years, however, <i>relational arguments</i>, based primarily on the republican ideal of freedom as nondomination and theories of relational equality, have gained prominence (Anderson, <span>2017</span>; Breen, <span>2015</span>; González-Ricoy, <span>2014b</span>; Gourevitch, <span>2013</span>). These arguments begin with the observation that today's workplace is saturated by unequal power relations, particularly between workers and bosses. By “workers” I mean those who have no power to make managerial decisions, to order other employees to perform tasks, to hire and fire employees, and the like. By “bosses,” on the other hand, I mean those who do have such powers. Of course, it would be overly simplistic to say that everyone in all workplaces can be neatly sorted into these two categories. For example, middle management often has limited autonomy to make managerial decisions, and some workplaces may be organized in a less hierarchical manner. Still, relying on this simplification will greatly contribute to the clarity and conciseness of the following discussion and it is fairly straightforward how the argument may be modified to accommodate these complexities.</p><p>Considerations about power inequality in the workplace lead many republicans and relational egalitarians to the view that the relationship between workers and bosses today is usually characterized by relational inequality if not outright domination (Berkey, <span>2023</span>). For example, Elizabeth Anderson (<span>2017</span>) describes contemporary firms, particularly in the United States, as miniature dictatorships with an all-powerful cadre of bosses ruling over the worker body. Of course, it is rarely the case that bosses have unlimited arbitrary power over employees in a literal sense, that is, in the sense a master has unlimited arbitrary power over a slave or a dictator over the subjects. Still, there is a clear sense in which the labor contract establishes a command hierarchy between the worker and the boss, in which one party has the ability to deprive the other from what may be her only source of income. Such power relations easily engender relational inequality (Néron, <span>2015</span>). It is true that whether this inequality further develops into domination, greatly depends on context and background conditions (cf. O'Shea, <span>2019</span>). Still, one may very well argue that at least the <i>threat</i> of domination produced by workplace hierarchies, which pervades contemporary workplaces, should be a salient concern for advocates of nondomination and relational equality. Republican and relational egalitarian advocates of workplace democracy argue that the only way to rectify this inequality is to ensure that workers and bosses share equal power to govern the firm. This would subject workers and bosses under one another's mutual control, thereby precluding the emergence of domination or relational inequality in the workplace.<sup>1</sup></p><p>This argument, of course, can be challenged in various ways (Jacob &amp; Neuhäuser, <span>2018</span>; Kolodny, <span>2023</span>, 145 ff; Taylor, <span>2019</span>). One may argue that the threat of domination can be sufficiently mitigated without workplace democracy, for example, by workers' consent and adequate exit options (see Arenson, <span>1993</span>; cf. Taylor, <span>2017</span>), by strong state regulations, which, it is worth noting, workers do democratically control as voters (Jacob &amp; Neuhäuser, <span>2018</span>, p. 932), or by strong internal rules and contestatory channels, that is, <i>workplace constitutionalism</i> (Hsieh, <span>2005</span>). Although the debate on the republican and relational egalitarian case for workplace democracy is certainly still ongoing, in my view, republicans and relational egalitarians have been able to provide promising responses to these criticisms (e.g., González-Ricoy, <span>2019</span>). But even if republican and relational egalitarian views prove defensible, I would argue that they still remain incomplete.</p><p>Republican and relational egalitarian advocates of workplace democracy primarily focus on <i>intra-firm</i> relations, such as the worker–boss relation. They argue that it is the morally defective properties of these relations, for example, relational inequality and domination that make workplace democracy necessary. This is not to say that the unequal and dominating relationship between bosses and workers is confined to the workplace. Think about running into your boss in the coffee shop. Even though you are outside the workplace, the fact that this person has the power to fire you or assign you menial tasks during the workday is bound to affect your interactions. Still, the source of this effect is an intra-firm power inequality between a worker and a boss within a single workplace.</p><p>What this approach ignores are the <i>extra-firm</i> relations, such as the relation of workers to the rest of society. As I will show, this relation is centrally important in understanding the value and justification of workplace democracy; workplace democracy is necessary to ensure that not only intra-firm, but also extra-firm relations are in good moral order. This means that even if republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy are sound, they do not give us the full picture of what justifies workplace democracy, given their focus on intra-firm relations. Once we consider extra-firm relations, we can identify new and distinct reasons for endorsing workplace democracy. This, of course, does not refute republican or relational egalitarian arguments. Rather, it contributes new relational considerations favoring workplace democracy which are compatible with republican and relational egalitarian ones but have hitherto received little to no attention in the literature. Thus, the following argument ultimately strengthens the overall relational case for workplace democracy.</p><p>Firms embed workers into large-scale economic systems of production, consumption, and the circulation of goods and services, and through such systems, they connect workers with other individuals outside the firm. Consumers use products and services produced and provided by workers. Workers cooperate and compete with employees of other firms, sometimes directly, sometimes indirectly. Direct cooperation or competition may occur, for example, when workers work together with employees of suppliers or subcontractors, or when salespersons compete for the same client. Examples of indirect cases may be workers using materials in production prepared at a far-removed element of the supply chain, or firms, although not particular workers directly, competing with one another for a market segment. Workers are also connected to regulators whose prescriptions they must comply with. Generally, by participating in the operations of the firm, workers enter into a particular kind of relation with the rest of society; I will call this the worker–society relation. Of course, in the case of many firms the relevant “society” extends far beyond the borders of a single state and encompasses the whole of the regional or even global economic system in which the firm operates, as well as all individuals who are affected by the firm's operations. This should be kept in mind throughout the following discussion, even though, for the sake of simplicity, I will continue to use the term “worker–society relation.” That the term “society” should be understood broadly, potentially encompassing global economic systems, will be clear in many of my examples.</p><p>The worker–society relation is a morally significant one for all participants, that is, both to workers and members of society. Consider, first, the moral import of this relation from the point of view of members of society. Take consumers, one group within society, and their relation to workers in sweatshops whose products they buy. Although the debate on the ethics of sweatshop labor and consumer responses to it is ongoing,<sup>2</sup> for the sake of argument, I will take it for granted that sweatshop labor is exploitative, and consuming sweatshop products is wrong. One of the reasons why it is wrong may be that continuing to purchase the products of sweatshop labor acknowledges the exploitative firm's standing as a legitimate economic actor, and thereby affronts sweatshop workers' dignity and exhibits a certain form of disrespect toward them. In other words, the continued consumption of sweatshop products counts as a failure to take proper account of the moral significance of consumers' <i>social connection</i> to unjust global structures of exploitation (Young, <span>2006</span>).</p><p>The harm associated with consuming the products of exploitative sweatshop labor is not simply the agent-neutral harm of producing injustice; it also involves a <i>relational harm</i> (Malmqvist &amp; Szigeti, <span>2021</span>). Consumers do not simply act wrongly from an impersonal point of view in that they perpetuate injustice and exploitation. They also wrong sweatshop workers specifically; by acting in ways that betray insufficient regard for their dignity and wellbeing, they fail to relate to them in a respectful and caring way, indeed, they fail to relate to all other members of society as respectful and caring agents more generally. This relational harm seems to carry considerable moral import. It is part of the reason, for example, why consumers should not simply offset the impersonal harm they cause, for example, by donating to any charity to reduce the amount of injustice and exploitation in the world, but repair their relation to sweatshop workers specifically, for example, by refusing to legitimate their employer's standing as a respectable business and by striving to improve their conditions specifically, rather than only justice generally.<sup>3</sup></p><p>The worker–society relation has moral significance not only for consumers, and other members of society, but for workers as well. For example, just as consumers' social connection to the harms and wrongs of sweatshop labor damages their relation to sweatshop workers, so too if workers partake in their firm's operations when those operations result in harms and wrongs to members of society, their relation to society is in some significant sense morally damaged. One may find this idea most appealing in cases where workers are directly implicated in the firm's wrongdoing. Recently, Stephanie Collins (<span>2023</span>) provided an illuminating discussion on the various ways in which workers may be so implicated. A worker may be a principal or complicitous <i>enactor</i> of a specific wrongdoing that the firm commits; a worker may be an <i>endorser</i> of wrongdoing, that is, explicitly or implicitly endorse some goals of a firm which foreseeably involve harm and wrongdoing; or they may be <i>omitters</i>, that is, ones who fail to take action that could hinder firm's wrongdoing, thereby omitting to act in appropriate ways in response to their firm's wrongdoing (Collins, <span>2023</span>, p. 135). In these cases, Collins argues, workers are culpably implicated in the firm's wrongdoing.</p><p>There are many workers, however, who do not fall under any of these categories; many workers, for example, in large corporations, which engage in wrongdoing may be neither enactors, nor endorsers, nor omitters in this sense. These are workers who “did nothing to contribute to the wrong, or they didn't support the wrong, or they couldn't have done anything to distance themselves from it.” (Collins, <span>2023</span>, p. 134) Collins's example is a cashier in a bank with no clear connection to the bank's objectionable operations, if there are any. We can also think of Kutz's (<span>2000</span>) example of a shipping clerk who works for an arms manufacturer that produces and distributes weapons to be used in unjust conflicts. Such low-level employees, Collins argues, are not morally implicated in the firm's wrongdoing, and are not blameworthy.<sup>4</sup> However, this does not mean that the firm's wrongdoing is morally indifferent to them. For example, Collins claims, it would still be appropriate for such workers to experience what Bernard Williams (<span>1981</span>) calls <i>agent-regret</i>, that is, regret over their blameless involvement in the firm's wrongdoing.</p><p>Regardless of her attitudes and commitments, through the practices she engages in, the shipping clerk manifests an objectionable kind of agency; she is a kind of agent who in her day-to-day activities contributes to a collective endeavor that harms others, and this <i>way of being in the world with others</i> establishes a certain relation with others, that is, a relation premised on a form disrespect or callousness toward the victims of the firm's activity to which these victims, indeed, anyone else, rightly objects. I do not mean that her continued participation shows that she secretly has disrespectful attitudes toward these victims. She may genuinely detest the fact that she contributes to the firm's harmful operations. What establishes a morally defective relationship between her and the victims is the way in which she functions as an agent within the firm and within society at large, that is, her functionally characterizable conception of agency. For the same reason, I do not think that she necessarily counts as an <i>endorser</i> in Collins's sense, that is, someone who commits to some goals of the firm that foreseeably involve wrongdoing. As Collins notes, firms may have many independent goals, and individual workers may only express commitment to some of them. The shipping clerk may commit to nothing more than the efficient handling of paperwork (Collins, <span>2023</span>, p. 148). Still, similarly to how consumers do not necessarily commit to or endorse exploitative sweatshops' objectionable goals by buying their products, yet their actions may still express disrespect and disregard toward sweatshop workers, the shipping clerk's continued participation in the arms company's operations may still express a functionally characterizable conception of agency that is morally objectionable, and thereby damage her relation to the rest of society.</p><p>The moral quality of the worker–society relation is independent not only from workers' subjective attitudes toward their firm's operations, but also from society's attitudes. To say that the worker–society relation is morally defective is not to report on, say, the social standing and public perception of workers or consumers, let alone their subjective stance toward one another. Perhaps the firm's wrongful operations are entirely normalized in society, that is, seen by all, including workers and the victims of the firm's wrongdoing, simply as unpleasant, but unobjectionable or unchangeable “business as usual.” But, the weight people assign to the worker–society relation is not necessarily the weight they should assign to it. Just as consumers should care about their relation to sweatshop workers, even if, as a matter of empirical fact, they do not, the shipping clerk should also care about their relation to those harmed by the arms company's operations, even if, as a matter of empirical fact, she does not. Regardless of what she or others think, the fact that they continue to engage with the firm's harmful operations means that her practical engagement with society—<i>qua</i> worker—continues to be predicated upon and guided by indefensible principles of impermissible disrespect or callousness toward others' interests which damages her relation to said others and the rest of society.</p><p>Of course, the worker–society relation is often indirect and highly mediated. There are numerous intermediaries between the arms manufacturer and the harm of unjust war, including distributors, logistics companies, regulatory agencies, governments and international institutions, military leaders, and unjust combatants themselves. These mediating factors all affect the severity of the moral damage to the worker–society relation. The shipping clerk's relationship to the victims of unjust conflict is not as defective as it would be, had she herself joined the conflict as an unjust combatant. Yet, as I discussed, our connection to even distant and mediated harms, as, for example, in the case of sweatshop labor or climate change do nonetheless have moral significance for us (cf. Schwenkenbecher, <span>2014</span>; Zoller, <span>2015</span>).</p><p>In addition, the worker–society relation is often highly complex, making the implications of its moral significance far from clear. Consider, for example, coal miners whose work may inflict considerable environmental damage while making an important economic contribution to their local communities.<sup>6</sup> To be sure, the worker–society relation has moral significance here, but which relation exactly? Does workers' relation to their local communities, which are kept afloat economically by their work, count for more or less than their relation to distant others who are perhaps most immediately harmed by the environmental damage their work causes? This is a hard question which I cannot hope to resolve in this article. Yet, the fact that this <i>is</i> a hard question indicates the moral significance of the worker–society relation. The way in which workers relate through their work to the rest of society matters morally, even if the question of <i>how precisely</i> it matters is an extremely complex one.<sup>7</sup> These considerations, I believe, suffice to show what the worker–society relation is and why it is morally significant. In the next section, I turn to the argument for workplace democracy based on the worker–society relation.</p><p>The moral significance of the worker–society relation provides a strong basis for an argument for workplace democracy. Members of society, understood broadly as encompassing all individuals within the large-scale economic system in which the firm operates, depend on workers' work for the availability of various resources to satisfy their needs and pursue their own projects. Their work may affect what opportunities are open to members of society and what life prospects they have. It is of preeminent moral significance that these relations between workers and society are in good order, morally speaking. Workers have a weighty interest not simply in minimizing the impersonal wrong of injustice in the world, but also in ensuring that they relate to those affected by their work as particular kinds of agents, that is, agents who are not indifferent about the way in which members of society are affected, but rather whose practical engagement with society is premised on principles of respect and care. To use the terminology introduced in the previous section, workers have a weighty interest in their functionally characterizable conception of agency, <i>qua</i> workers, not being based on and not conveying morally defective attitudes in their relation to the rest of society.</p><p>This implies that the way in which their firm is governed is of great significance to workers. For it is the way in which the firm is governed that determines the nature and purpose of the collective activity that constitutes the firm's operations to which workers contribute and which ultimately determines workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency, at least <i>qua</i> workers. Take, again, Kutz's example of the shipping clerk working for a malicious arms company. The reason why her functionally characterizable conception of agency is morally defective is that the nature and purpose of the collective undertaking in which she participates, that is, the operations of the arms company, is the illicit acquisition of profits by supplying weapons to unjust combatants in bloody conflicts. It is for this reason why her mundane daily activities of going to work, handling paperwork, attending meetings, and so on, make her the kind of agent that, regardless of her subjective attitudes, through her actions expresses disrespect and callous disregard toward the interests of the victims of the firm's operations. Even though as a low-level employee she may not be blameworthy for the firm's wrongdoing, and even though she thinks of the firm's operations as morally reprehensible, by going to work every day and contributing to these operations, her agency conveys a functionally characterizable conception of agency which the rest of society, particularly victims of the arms company's unjust dealings, have reason to view as morally defective. This is what damages her relation to society.</p><p>There is little the shipping clerk can do to ameliorate her relationship to society. Since it is stipulated that she is not an omitter, she cannot meaningfully thwart the firm's wrongful operations. She may quit, if she has adequate exit options, but this may not always be the case. Of course, the lack of adequate exit options may mitigate the problem of the moral defect of the worker–society relation, but it hardly eliminates it. In the case of workers who bear responsibility for the firm's wrongdoing, for example, as enactors, endorsers, or omitters, the absence of adequate exit options may reduce their blameworthiness or absolve them from blame altogether, and this may impact their relation to society. However, as I argued, blameworthiness is not the central problem here. Even if the shipping clerk, for example, is not blameworthy for the firm's wrongdoing, her contribution to this wrongdoing through her work may still render her relation to society morally defective. In this case, the lack of adequate exit options condemns her to be the kind of agent who, in her daily practices, acts upon indefensible principles, unable to relate to society in morally appropriate ways.</p><p>The shipping clerk may protest the firm's activity <i>outside</i> work, for example, she may participate in demonstrations or campaigns for the stricter regulation of arms companies. This would certainly impact her <i>overall</i> functionally characterizable conception of agency, but it would still leave her functionally characterizable conception of agency <i>qua</i> worker morally defective which would still disturb her relation to society. To use a rather extreme example, assuming the wrongness of capital punishment, the hangman who, in his free time, campaigns against the death penalty certainly does better than one who moonlights as an assassin. Yet, the first one certainly does not offset the damage his occupation does to his relation to society; he is not on a par with his fellow campaigners who work as teachers or plumbers, for example.</p><p>Suppose now that the shipping clerk does nothing, but the company's management has a change of heart and adopts a new, more socially benevolent business model. Not only do they stop supplying arms to unjust combatants, but also make bona fide efforts to remedy the harm to which they contributed and hold responsible decision-makers to account. The firm may pivot even more radically and decide to give up arms manufacturing for the sake of something more peaceable. Such changes in how the firm is governed would transform workers' relation to society; now the collective venture in which they participate daily has a wholly new, much more benign character. On the level of the day-to-day work of the shipping clerk, there may be no discernible changes. Her average workday may look much the same as before. Yet her relation to society changes; now she can rest assured that her functionally characterizable conception of agency, <i>qua</i> worker, conveys no disrespect toward anyone. The way in which the firm is governed, therefore, is particularly important for workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency, and, consequently, for the worker–society relation.</p><p>This consideration about the relevance of the governance of the firm to the moral quality of the worker–society relation is a strong reason for thinking that workers have a claim to control how the firm is governed through institutions of workplace democracy. This claim requires further argument, for, on the face of it, it is susceptible to a number of challenges. First, it is unclear why workers' interests concerning how the firm is governed should ground any claim to control at all. Workers may have an interest in the morally appropriate governance of the firm, but this may be achieved without workers controlling the firm in any way. Adequate regulations and benevolent bosses may be as capable of preventing firms' moral failings as worker control. But even if the necessity of worker control is established, it is unclear why this control should take shape as workplace democracy, rather than, say, some form of <i>unionism</i>, whereby workers are able to put pressure on bosses through petitions and strikes, or <i>workplace constitutionalism</i>, where managerial decisions are constrained by strict internal rules and workers have opportunities to appeal to an impartial body that can fairly arbitrate their grievances and penalize bosses for bad decisions. Such arrangements may also grant workers some degree of control; why would this not suffice?</p><p>One may offer <i>instrumentalist</i> arguments for workplace democracy by claiming that it is generally better at preventing firms from behaving badly and keeping the worker–society relation in good moral order. For example, it may be argued that workplace democracy is able to harness the beneficial epistemic effects of deliberation within large and diverse groups, thus ensuring that firms are governed better both from the economic and the moral point of view (Gerlsbeck &amp; Herzog, <span>2020</span>; Landemore, <span>2012</span>). Workplace democracy could also contribute to the development of what Lisa Herzog calls “transformational agency” within the workplace; workers as transformational agents do not blindly execute their organizational role, but rather work toward transforming their role and their organization in ways that better align with the requirements of morality (Herzog, <span>2018</span>, p. 193). This has the beneficial effect that both inefficiencies and the moral failings of the firm are detected and addressed more easily (Herzog, <span>2018</span>, p. 253), improving the quality of the worker–society relation.</p><p>The success of this instrumental argument greatly depends on the particular empirical background conditions against which workplace democracy is implemented. Workers are as capable of making terrible decisions as bosses, and whether they do so depends on their preferences, values, incentives, culture, institutional surroundings, and so on, which vary greatly from context to context. Under the right background conditions, workplace democracy may be a more effective instrument of keeping firms from moral failures, but there is no a priori reason to think that such background conditions will always or even mostly obtain. Still, I would not deny that under the right empirical circumstances, workplace democracy could have important instrumental benefits. However, I believe that the instrumentalist argument fails to fully account for why workplace democracy matters from the point of view of the worker–society relation.</p><p>Workplace democracy does not only matter because, and insofar as, it makes firms behave less badly. It matters because of the way in which it transforms the character and moral quality of the relation between workers and members of society. Recall that the harm associated with the moral defect of the worker–society relation is not simply the agent-neutral harm of producing injustice, but also a relational harm. Workers have an interest not only in minimizing injustice in the world, but also in relating to members of society as particular kinds of agents, that is, as caring and respectful agents who do not go about pursuing their projects and personal advantage disregarding the way in which they contribute to harms that befall on others. But they cannot relate to others as such agents without having an equal say in collective decision-making on how the firm is governed, that is, without workplace democracy. For without such a say, they are at the mercy of other agents—or external circumstances—for the moral quality of their relation to society. Even if they can in some way contest managerial decisions, for example, through unionism or workplace constitutionalism, they lack decision-making powers themselves; it is up to benevolent managers or the impartial arbitration body to govern the firm in morally acceptable ways. The moral quality of workers' relation to society is in the hands of others.</p><p>Being so dependent for the moral character of our interpersonal relations on others is an extremely precarious position to be in from the moral point of view. The benevolent discretion of strangers should not be the sole determinant of the moral quality of our relation to others. Both because this makes one powerless to prevent the emergence of morally defective interpersonal relations, and also because it makes one incapable of conveying adequate care and respect toward others through one's functionally characterizable conception of agency. As I argued, one's functionally characterizable conception of agency, <i>qua</i> worker, depends on the nature of the collective venture she partakes in, qua worker, and this, in turn, depends, on how the firm is governed. Even if a firm governed by bosses bestows the right kind of functionally characterizable conception of agency on workers, thereby imposing a morally adequate relation to society, the relation itself remains, in a significant sense, <i>imposed</i>. Workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency remains objectionably divorced from their judgment and action and is therefore unable to convey adequate care and respect to society. For care and respect to be adequately conveyed through our functionally characterizable conception of agency, it must be, in a significant sense, <i>our own making</i>.<sup>8</sup></p><p>This is achieved only under workplace democracy, and not unionism or workplace constitutionalism. Union members on strike, or workers contesting managerial decisions through the channels of workplace constitutionalism still <i>appeal</i> to others to set their relation to society right. In their case, it is still bosses, who eventually surrender to protests and contestation that make it the case that the firm is governed less wrongly. At the end of the day, workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency remains dependent on bosses' discretion. This dependence is resolved only under workplace democracy. Workplace democracy ensures that the worker–society relation is under the direct collective control of workers; the individual worker no longer <i>appeals</i> to others to improve their relation to society, but is herself a codecision-maker, a co-governor of the firm, capable of shaping this relation directly through co-governing the firm. Her agency is no longer divorced from the decisions that determine the moral character of her relation to society in the same way as in the absence of workplace democracy. This is a significant moral difference that distinguishes workplace democracy from all other arrangements, for example, unionism or workplace constitutionalism, where workers are not granted genuine decision-making powers over the governance of the firm.<sup>9</sup></p><p>One may object that workers do have direct control over the firm as voters via the democratic state; indeed, perhaps it is the responsibility of the state, rather than workers, to prevent corporate wrongdoing and ensure a good worker–society relation. However, outside command economies, the state usually regulates firms' economic activity by setting legal constraints and shaping their incentive structures. This leaves firms considerably free to pursue their goals within the boundaries set by the state. <i>Qua</i> voters, workers' control over the worker–society relation is not sufficiently direct; they can shape the regulatory environment in which the firm operates, but without workplace democracy, they remain at the mercy of bosses when it comes to the exact shape of the worker–society relation. They can still, at best, appeal to others to establish a good worker–society relation, rather than doing it themselves.</p><p>This is not to say that the democratic state and the regulatory environment it creates are irrelevant for having a good worker–society relation. In an ill-regulated economic environment firms may face extreme competitive pressure to stay in business by engaging in wrongdoing which may be hard to resist whether workplaces are democratic or not. This may especially be the case with firms operating in the global market. This means that in their role as voting citizens, workers have strong reasons to try to ensure, through democratic participation, that their state strives to create an economic environment, both domestically and internationally, which enables and facilitates establishing good worker–society relations, for example, through domestic economic policy, trade agreements, participation in international regulatory bodies, and so on. Still, if firms have any kind of autonomy from the state, then only under workplace democracy, in their capacity as co-governors of the firm, can workers themselves establish a good worker–society relation. In other words, even in a well-regulated economic environment firms will face various pressures to shape the worker–society relation in one way rather than another, and it remains important that it is not bosses alone who decide whether the firm succumbs to those pressures or not, but that workers too have a say in how their relation to society is ultimately shaped. This means that workplace democracy and state-level democracy, as well as other institutions and practices, for example, responsible consumer behavior, share and divide the work of creating worker–society relations in good moral order; workplace democracy may not be sufficient for this, but it is necessary.</p><p>This also means that even under workplace democracy and advantageous economic conditions, it is not guaranteed that the worker–society relation ends up being in good moral order. Even if the shipping clerk cares about this relation and wishes to ameliorate it, and even if the political and economic environment enables this, that is, there are no excessive pressures on the firm to engage in wrongdoing, workplace democratic outcomes may not reflect her individual judgment or preference. In a democracy one can always be outvoted, and as mentioned, workers are as capable of making terrible decisions as bosses. Although an individual worker may care about avoiding harms and wrongs to others, if their fellow workers do not, or if they strongly fear that refraining from corporate wrongdoing will put their firm at a competitive disadvantage and seriously damage their livelihoods, then they may implement harmful and wrongful company policies through the democratic governance of the firm. One answer to this problem would be that this risk is simply the price to be paid for ensuring workers' control over the worker–society relation, and thereby the adequate expression of care and respect through their functionally characterizable conception of agency. But this raises the question of whether this price is indeed worth paying.</p><p>I argued that in a nondemocratic workplace, workers' agency is in some ways divorced from their relation to society. One upside of this, one may argue, is that it allows at least some workers, for example, the shipping clerk, to maintain at least some distance from firms' wrongdoing. It is true that firms' wrongdoing may affect workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency, and thereby damage their relation to the rest of society, but their lack of control may mitigate this damage. Under workplace democracy, their agency becomes much more closely tied to the firm's governance; if the firm engages in wrongful actions, workers now will share responsibility for this as co-governors of the firm. Perhaps there are good reasons to prefer not taking on this responsibility, and leaving their agency distanced from the firm's governance.</p><p>The key premise of this objection is that it is worse if a morally defective worker–society relation is workers' own <i>making</i>, as it is under workplace democracy, than if it is <i>imposed</i> on them, as in nondemocratic workplaces. I have my doubts about this claim. It is true that workplace democracy carries with it the disvalue of increased responsibility for the firm's wrongdoings. But, first, for any individual worker, this responsibility may be mitigated, and their functionally characterizable conception of agency improved, if the worker at least votes against and tries to persuade others to vote against the wrongful decision. Second, the nondemocratic workplace also carries with it a disvalue, that is, the disvalue of the powerlessness over the worker–society relation. It seems to me that the objection requires that the disvalue of powerlessness be lesser than the disvalue of increased responsibility due to workplace democracy. It is far from obvious that this is true. Generally, would we prefer powerlessness over our interpersonal relations for the sake of avoiding responsibility when these relations turn morally defective? This does not seem right. By doing so, we would renounce key aspects of our moral agency. As for the worker–society relation specifically, I argued in the previous section that this relation is of great moral significance to workers. Powerlessness over it may well be worse than the burden of responsibility for decisions resulting in the firm's wrongdoing, especially if a worker did all they could to avoid this in their capacity as a democratic co-governor of the firm.</p><p>To be sure, it is often extremely challenging to determine what exactly a worker should do to wield their democratic governing power responsibly. Think of the example of the coal miners again; once they gain democratic control over their firm, how should they govern it? Should they continue their extractive and environmentally damaging, activity to secure economic support for their local communities, or should they prioritize reducing the environmental harm their activity does to distant others? Here, again, I cannot settle this question. But, the very fact that the worker–society relation raises such hard and complex moral problems testifies to the importance of workers' control over this relation. We all have a weighty interest in our judgment bearing on how such complex questions about our relation to others are settled; that others should settle these hard moral questions about our interpersonal lives affronts our standing as full moral agents and damages our interpersonal relations themselves. The worker–society relation is indeed complex. All the more reason why workers and not only bosses should have a say in what shape it takes.</p><p>How does my argument and republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy relate to each other? As noted, the latter tend to focus on intra-firm power relations between bosses and workers, especially insofar as these threaten with domination or relational inequality. My argument, in contrast, focuses on the extra-firm relation between workers and the rest of society. However, while my argument does focus on the worker–society relation, there is a sense in which it also criticizes a particular kind of unequal intra-firm power relation, that is, bosses' unequal power to determine the moral character of workers' relation to society. What does this argument add, then, to existing republican and relational egalitarian discussions on workplace democracy, besides pointing out yet another way in which workers are dominated by or subordinated to bosses in the contemporary workplace? To answer, let us take a closer look at why exactly various arguments object to unequal power relations in the workplace.</p><p>Republicans object to intra-firm power inequalities because, and insofar as, they constitute <i>domination</i>, that is, a particularly objectionable interpersonal relation exemplified in its most extreme form by the relationship between the master and the slave (McCammon, <span>2015</span>). The argument from the worker–society relation, in contrast, is not about domination; indeed, in the first place, it is not even about the worker–boss relation. First and foremost, it objects to workers' powerlessness to keep their relation to society in good moral order, for this precludes their expressing adequate care and respect toward the rest of society. If this powerlessness is engendered by bosses' unequal power over workers, then the argument objects to this power inequality too. But this does not presuppose that this power inequality constitutes domination. This is not to say that it does not constitute domination. Perhaps it does. If so, then there are republican reasons for objecting to it. But the reasons identified by the argument from the worker–society relation are not reasons of this republican kind. The argument finds this power inequality objectionable <i>irrespective of</i> whether it counts as domination or not. Something similar is true in the case of relational egalitarian arguments. These claim that intra-firm inequalities of power are objectionable because they prevent workers and bosses from relating as equals. But according to my argument, workers' powerlessness over the worker–society relation is objectionable <i>whether or not</i> bosses and workers relate as equals. This, again, is not to say that this powerlessness may not contribute to relational inequality between workers and bosses. Perhaps it does. But my argument does not presuppose this. The argument claims that this powerlessness is wrong in and of itself, regardless of whether it is also wrong by virtue of creating relational inequality.</p><p>Suppose that some objection against republican and relational egalitarian analyses of workplace power inequality succeeds, for example, someone successfully argues that workplace hierarchies, while involving power inequality, are sufficiently “tempered” not to constitute objectionable relationships of genuine domination or relational inequality (Kolodny, <span>2023</span>, pp. 148–152). This would refute republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy. But it would not refute my argument. For even if it were true that workers are neither dominated by nor relationally unequal to bosses, they may still object to the fact that bosses have unilateral control over the moral quality of their relationship to the rest of society; not because this makes their relationship <i>to bosses</i> morally defective, for example, dominating or relationally unequal, but because it makes their relationship <i>to society</i> morally defective. This is what constitutes the moral precarity to which the argument from the worker–society relation objects.</p><p>To illustrate my point, consider the case of coal miners again. Republicans and relational egalitarians argue that they should have a democratic say in how their firm is governed because otherwise they are dominated by or relate unequally to their bosses. On this view, what matters in the first place is the intra-firm worker–boss relation. On the argument from the worker–society relation, it is the other way around. The reason why they should have a democratic say in the workplace is because it is of great moral importance that they themselves shape the worker–society relation; what matters in the first place is the extra-firm worker–society relation. Of course, in the absence of workplace democracy, it is bosses who shape this extra-firm relation; bosses decide if the firm continues its extractive activities, benefiting workers' local communities, but harming distant others through environmental damage, or if the firm transitions into less environmentally harmful activities which may not be as economically beneficial for local communities, or if they find some middle way. This shaping of the worker–society relation may or may not count as domination or relational inequality. If it does, then there may be republican or relational egalitarian reasons to oppose it. But <i>even if it does not</i>, my argument provides independent reasons for introducing workplace democracy, that is, the inherent wrong, independent of domination or relational inequality, of workers not shaping their relationship to society. The two arguments are not mutually exclusive, but they are independent; it is possible to accept both or one without the other. Thus, my argument does not merely add to the list of republican and relational egalitarian grievances about power inequality in the contemporary workplace. Rather, it identifies distinct and independent grounds for introducing workplace democracy.</p><p>Could republican or relational egalitarian arguments incorporate the argument from the worker–society relation? After all, extra-firm relations should matter to republicans and relational egalitarians as well. As Nicholas Vrousalis (<span>2019</span>) argues, for example, extra-firm domination pervades capitalist economies; firms and their bosses dominate other firms by exerting competitive pressure, and they dominate states through their power to disinvest and relocate. These extra-firm relations, he argues, should worry republicans too. Indeed, the coal company and its bosses may dominate not only their workers, but also their local communities and distant others on whom they arbitrarily bestow economic benefit and environmental harm. As Vrousalis argues, however, workplace democracy alone may do little to address these concerns; democratic firms can dominate society in the same way nondemocratic firms do. Democratizing the coal company would only mean allowing its workers to dominate their local community and distant others just as their bosses used to. Arguably, from a republican or relational egalitarian viewpoint, extra-firm domination and relational inequality need to be addressed by reforming the underlying economic conditions that make these objectionable relations possible;<sup>10</sup> workplace democracy, in itself, is not a solution.</p><p>However, even if in the extra-firm case workplace democracy does not eliminate domination or relational inequality in the same way it does in the intra-firm case, the argument from the worker–society relation can still show why it matters for the moral quality of extra-firm relations. I argued that workplace democracy is necessary for workers to convey adequate care and respect through their functionally characterizable conception of agency to members of society they affect through their work. This is a relational gain even if the worker–society relation remains tainted by domination or relational inequality. That is, even if workplace democracy does not improve workers' extra-firm relations in terms of nondomination or relational equality, it may improve it along other dimensions. Of course, workers still have reasons to eliminate extra-firm domination and relational inequality by using their democratic powers as citizens to reform the underlying economic conditions through the democratic state. Still, these considerations suggest that the argument from the worker–society relation is not easily incorporated into republican or relational egalitarian accounts; it picks out a relational value distinct from nondomination or relational equality, and thus identifies reasons for adopting workplace democracy that republican and relational egalitarian analyses do not.<sup>11</sup></p><p>Workplace democracy, I believe, is best justified by workers' interest to keep their interpersonal relations in good moral order. Republican and relational egalitarian arguments capture one element of this interest, that is, workers' interests in relating in egalitarian and nondominating ways to their bosses and each other. But, there is another, no less relevant relation that grounds workers' claims for workplace democracy: the worker–society relation. Work embeds individuals in large-scale systems of production, consumption, logistics, and services; systems, through which they maintain and reproduce the economic bases of their shared social life. This system may bring flourishing to the people who are caught up in them, or it may produce deprivation, vulnerability, and injustice. Workers have an interest in promoting the former through their work rather than the latter, not simply because of the general impersonal imperative of reducing disvalue in the world, but also because they have an interest in relating to all individuals within this system as agents who are not callous or disrespectful toward them, but rather exhibit care and respect. This weighty interest grounds a strong claim on the part of workers for workplace democracy. For only under workplace democracy do they not depend on others for the moral quality of their relation to society and are able to convey adequate care and respect within this relation.</p><p>This work was supported by the GOODINT Project, funded by the Research Council of Norway, project no. 313846.</p><p>The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"56 2","pages":"167-184"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2024-01-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12559","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12559","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Numerous arguments have been offered for workplace democracy, that is, the idea that employees should have an equal say in governing the firm. Lately, relational arguments, particularly of a republican and relational egalitarian kind, have become prominent. These claim that workers should have a say in how their firm is governed in order to avoid objectionable, for example, dominating or subordinating, relationships within the workplace. While I find these views appealing, I also believe that they are incomplete. By focusing on the moral quality of workers' interpersonal relations within the firm, that is, to bosses and other workers, they ignore the moral quality of workers' relations outside the firm, that is, to the rest of society. Yet, this latter is of no less significance for the justification of workplace democracy. In this article, I argue that part of the reason why workplace democracy should be adopted is that it allows workers to exert appropriate control over the operations of the firm, thus maintaining a grip on the general character of the relation between themselves as workers of the firm and the rest of society. This argument from the worker–society relation is not intended to refute or replace republican and relational egalitarian arguments, but rather to draw attention to a hitherto neglected aspect of the relational value of workplace democracy which the aforementioned approaches usually do not incorporate. In this way, the present argument strengthens the overall relational case for workplace democracy.

The structure of the article is as follows. First, I introduce the concept of and arguments for workplace democracy, focusing on the most prominent relational arguments, that is, republican and relational egalitarian ones. Second, I introduce the concept of the worker–society relation and discuss its moral significance. Third, I present my argument for workplace democracy based on the worker–society relation. Fourth, I discuss the relationship between the argument from the worker–society relation and republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy to show how the former differs from and complements these approaches. The last section concludes.

Workplace democracy is an arrangement in which all employees of a firm have an equal say in how it is governed, much like in a democratic state where all citizens have an equal say in how the state is governed, except for certain specific groups, such as minors. This broad definition can be further specified in a number of ways. There are many models and institutional designs for workplace democracy but for the purposes of this discussion, I will remain neutral as to which of these is best to implement. I will not discuss whether under workplace democracy employees must exercise their democratic say directly or indirectly through representatives, whether the establishment of workers' councils is required, or whether employee's share in board representation would suffice as well, and so on. While these matters certainly have both practical and theoretical significance, they are not directly relevant to the following argument which is focused on the question of the justification of workplace democracy as such, in whatever way it is implemented.

Arguments for workplace democracy are numerous and varied (Frega et al., 2019). Examples include the arguments from the state-firm analogy (Dahl, 1985; Ferreras & Landemore, 2016; González-Ricoy, 2014a; McMahon, 1994), meaningful work (Yeoman, 2014), recognition (Hirvonen & Breen, 2020), and self-realization (Gould, 2004). In recent years, however, relational arguments, based primarily on the republican ideal of freedom as nondomination and theories of relational equality, have gained prominence (Anderson, 2017; Breen, 2015; González-Ricoy, 2014b; Gourevitch, 2013). These arguments begin with the observation that today's workplace is saturated by unequal power relations, particularly between workers and bosses. By “workers” I mean those who have no power to make managerial decisions, to order other employees to perform tasks, to hire and fire employees, and the like. By “bosses,” on the other hand, I mean those who do have such powers. Of course, it would be overly simplistic to say that everyone in all workplaces can be neatly sorted into these two categories. For example, middle management often has limited autonomy to make managerial decisions, and some workplaces may be organized in a less hierarchical manner. Still, relying on this simplification will greatly contribute to the clarity and conciseness of the following discussion and it is fairly straightforward how the argument may be modified to accommodate these complexities.

Considerations about power inequality in the workplace lead many republicans and relational egalitarians to the view that the relationship between workers and bosses today is usually characterized by relational inequality if not outright domination (Berkey, 2023). For example, Elizabeth Anderson (2017) describes contemporary firms, particularly in the United States, as miniature dictatorships with an all-powerful cadre of bosses ruling over the worker body. Of course, it is rarely the case that bosses have unlimited arbitrary power over employees in a literal sense, that is, in the sense a master has unlimited arbitrary power over a slave or a dictator over the subjects. Still, there is a clear sense in which the labor contract establishes a command hierarchy between the worker and the boss, in which one party has the ability to deprive the other from what may be her only source of income. Such power relations easily engender relational inequality (Néron, 2015). It is true that whether this inequality further develops into domination, greatly depends on context and background conditions (cf. O'Shea, 2019). Still, one may very well argue that at least the threat of domination produced by workplace hierarchies, which pervades contemporary workplaces, should be a salient concern for advocates of nondomination and relational equality. Republican and relational egalitarian advocates of workplace democracy argue that the only way to rectify this inequality is to ensure that workers and bosses share equal power to govern the firm. This would subject workers and bosses under one another's mutual control, thereby precluding the emergence of domination or relational inequality in the workplace.1

This argument, of course, can be challenged in various ways (Jacob & Neuhäuser, 2018; Kolodny, 2023, 145 ff; Taylor, 2019). One may argue that the threat of domination can be sufficiently mitigated without workplace democracy, for example, by workers' consent and adequate exit options (see Arenson, 1993; cf. Taylor, 2017), by strong state regulations, which, it is worth noting, workers do democratically control as voters (Jacob & Neuhäuser, 2018, p. 932), or by strong internal rules and contestatory channels, that is, workplace constitutionalism (Hsieh, 2005). Although the debate on the republican and relational egalitarian case for workplace democracy is certainly still ongoing, in my view, republicans and relational egalitarians have been able to provide promising responses to these criticisms (e.g., González-Ricoy, 2019). But even if republican and relational egalitarian views prove defensible, I would argue that they still remain incomplete.

Republican and relational egalitarian advocates of workplace democracy primarily focus on intra-firm relations, such as the worker–boss relation. They argue that it is the morally defective properties of these relations, for example, relational inequality and domination that make workplace democracy necessary. This is not to say that the unequal and dominating relationship between bosses and workers is confined to the workplace. Think about running into your boss in the coffee shop. Even though you are outside the workplace, the fact that this person has the power to fire you or assign you menial tasks during the workday is bound to affect your interactions. Still, the source of this effect is an intra-firm power inequality between a worker and a boss within a single workplace.

What this approach ignores are the extra-firm relations, such as the relation of workers to the rest of society. As I will show, this relation is centrally important in understanding the value and justification of workplace democracy; workplace democracy is necessary to ensure that not only intra-firm, but also extra-firm relations are in good moral order. This means that even if republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy are sound, they do not give us the full picture of what justifies workplace democracy, given their focus on intra-firm relations. Once we consider extra-firm relations, we can identify new and distinct reasons for endorsing workplace democracy. This, of course, does not refute republican or relational egalitarian arguments. Rather, it contributes new relational considerations favoring workplace democracy which are compatible with republican and relational egalitarian ones but have hitherto received little to no attention in the literature. Thus, the following argument ultimately strengthens the overall relational case for workplace democracy.

Firms embed workers into large-scale economic systems of production, consumption, and the circulation of goods and services, and through such systems, they connect workers with other individuals outside the firm. Consumers use products and services produced and provided by workers. Workers cooperate and compete with employees of other firms, sometimes directly, sometimes indirectly. Direct cooperation or competition may occur, for example, when workers work together with employees of suppliers or subcontractors, or when salespersons compete for the same client. Examples of indirect cases may be workers using materials in production prepared at a far-removed element of the supply chain, or firms, although not particular workers directly, competing with one another for a market segment. Workers are also connected to regulators whose prescriptions they must comply with. Generally, by participating in the operations of the firm, workers enter into a particular kind of relation with the rest of society; I will call this the worker–society relation. Of course, in the case of many firms the relevant “society” extends far beyond the borders of a single state and encompasses the whole of the regional or even global economic system in which the firm operates, as well as all individuals who are affected by the firm's operations. This should be kept in mind throughout the following discussion, even though, for the sake of simplicity, I will continue to use the term “worker–society relation.” That the term “society” should be understood broadly, potentially encompassing global economic systems, will be clear in many of my examples.

The worker–society relation is a morally significant one for all participants, that is, both to workers and members of society. Consider, first, the moral import of this relation from the point of view of members of society. Take consumers, one group within society, and their relation to workers in sweatshops whose products they buy. Although the debate on the ethics of sweatshop labor and consumer responses to it is ongoing,2 for the sake of argument, I will take it for granted that sweatshop labor is exploitative, and consuming sweatshop products is wrong. One of the reasons why it is wrong may be that continuing to purchase the products of sweatshop labor acknowledges the exploitative firm's standing as a legitimate economic actor, and thereby affronts sweatshop workers' dignity and exhibits a certain form of disrespect toward them. In other words, the continued consumption of sweatshop products counts as a failure to take proper account of the moral significance of consumers' social connection to unjust global structures of exploitation (Young, 2006).

The harm associated with consuming the products of exploitative sweatshop labor is not simply the agent-neutral harm of producing injustice; it also involves a relational harm (Malmqvist & Szigeti, 2021). Consumers do not simply act wrongly from an impersonal point of view in that they perpetuate injustice and exploitation. They also wrong sweatshop workers specifically; by acting in ways that betray insufficient regard for their dignity and wellbeing, they fail to relate to them in a respectful and caring way, indeed, they fail to relate to all other members of society as respectful and caring agents more generally. This relational harm seems to carry considerable moral import. It is part of the reason, for example, why consumers should not simply offset the impersonal harm they cause, for example, by donating to any charity to reduce the amount of injustice and exploitation in the world, but repair their relation to sweatshop workers specifically, for example, by refusing to legitimate their employer's standing as a respectable business and by striving to improve their conditions specifically, rather than only justice generally.3

The worker–society relation has moral significance not only for consumers, and other members of society, but for workers as well. For example, just as consumers' social connection to the harms and wrongs of sweatshop labor damages their relation to sweatshop workers, so too if workers partake in their firm's operations when those operations result in harms and wrongs to members of society, their relation to society is in some significant sense morally damaged. One may find this idea most appealing in cases where workers are directly implicated in the firm's wrongdoing. Recently, Stephanie Collins (2023) provided an illuminating discussion on the various ways in which workers may be so implicated. A worker may be a principal or complicitous enactor of a specific wrongdoing that the firm commits; a worker may be an endorser of wrongdoing, that is, explicitly or implicitly endorse some goals of a firm which foreseeably involve harm and wrongdoing; or they may be omitters, that is, ones who fail to take action that could hinder firm's wrongdoing, thereby omitting to act in appropriate ways in response to their firm's wrongdoing (Collins, 2023, p. 135). In these cases, Collins argues, workers are culpably implicated in the firm's wrongdoing.

There are many workers, however, who do not fall under any of these categories; many workers, for example, in large corporations, which engage in wrongdoing may be neither enactors, nor endorsers, nor omitters in this sense. These are workers who “did nothing to contribute to the wrong, or they didn't support the wrong, or they couldn't have done anything to distance themselves from it.” (Collins, 2023, p. 134) Collins's example is a cashier in a bank with no clear connection to the bank's objectionable operations, if there are any. We can also think of Kutz's (2000) example of a shipping clerk who works for an arms manufacturer that produces and distributes weapons to be used in unjust conflicts. Such low-level employees, Collins argues, are not morally implicated in the firm's wrongdoing, and are not blameworthy.4 However, this does not mean that the firm's wrongdoing is morally indifferent to them. For example, Collins claims, it would still be appropriate for such workers to experience what Bernard Williams (1981) calls agent-regret, that is, regret over their blameless involvement in the firm's wrongdoing.

Regardless of her attitudes and commitments, through the practices she engages in, the shipping clerk manifests an objectionable kind of agency; she is a kind of agent who in her day-to-day activities contributes to a collective endeavor that harms others, and this way of being in the world with others establishes a certain relation with others, that is, a relation premised on a form disrespect or callousness toward the victims of the firm's activity to which these victims, indeed, anyone else, rightly objects. I do not mean that her continued participation shows that she secretly has disrespectful attitudes toward these victims. She may genuinely detest the fact that she contributes to the firm's harmful operations. What establishes a morally defective relationship between her and the victims is the way in which she functions as an agent within the firm and within society at large, that is, her functionally characterizable conception of agency. For the same reason, I do not think that she necessarily counts as an endorser in Collins's sense, that is, someone who commits to some goals of the firm that foreseeably involve wrongdoing. As Collins notes, firms may have many independent goals, and individual workers may only express commitment to some of them. The shipping clerk may commit to nothing more than the efficient handling of paperwork (Collins, 2023, p. 148). Still, similarly to how consumers do not necessarily commit to or endorse exploitative sweatshops' objectionable goals by buying their products, yet their actions may still express disrespect and disregard toward sweatshop workers, the shipping clerk's continued participation in the arms company's operations may still express a functionally characterizable conception of agency that is morally objectionable, and thereby damage her relation to the rest of society.

The moral quality of the worker–society relation is independent not only from workers' subjective attitudes toward their firm's operations, but also from society's attitudes. To say that the worker–society relation is morally defective is not to report on, say, the social standing and public perception of workers or consumers, let alone their subjective stance toward one another. Perhaps the firm's wrongful operations are entirely normalized in society, that is, seen by all, including workers and the victims of the firm's wrongdoing, simply as unpleasant, but unobjectionable or unchangeable “business as usual.” But, the weight people assign to the worker–society relation is not necessarily the weight they should assign to it. Just as consumers should care about their relation to sweatshop workers, even if, as a matter of empirical fact, they do not, the shipping clerk should also care about their relation to those harmed by the arms company's operations, even if, as a matter of empirical fact, she does not. Regardless of what she or others think, the fact that they continue to engage with the firm's harmful operations means that her practical engagement with society—qua worker—continues to be predicated upon and guided by indefensible principles of impermissible disrespect or callousness toward others' interests which damages her relation to said others and the rest of society.

Of course, the worker–society relation is often indirect and highly mediated. There are numerous intermediaries between the arms manufacturer and the harm of unjust war, including distributors, logistics companies, regulatory agencies, governments and international institutions, military leaders, and unjust combatants themselves. These mediating factors all affect the severity of the moral damage to the worker–society relation. The shipping clerk's relationship to the victims of unjust conflict is not as defective as it would be, had she herself joined the conflict as an unjust combatant. Yet, as I discussed, our connection to even distant and mediated harms, as, for example, in the case of sweatshop labor or climate change do nonetheless have moral significance for us (cf. Schwenkenbecher, 2014; Zoller, 2015).

In addition, the worker–society relation is often highly complex, making the implications of its moral significance far from clear. Consider, for example, coal miners whose work may inflict considerable environmental damage while making an important economic contribution to their local communities.6 To be sure, the worker–society relation has moral significance here, but which relation exactly? Does workers' relation to their local communities, which are kept afloat economically by their work, count for more or less than their relation to distant others who are perhaps most immediately harmed by the environmental damage their work causes? This is a hard question which I cannot hope to resolve in this article. Yet, the fact that this is a hard question indicates the moral significance of the worker–society relation. The way in which workers relate through their work to the rest of society matters morally, even if the question of how precisely it matters is an extremely complex one.7 These considerations, I believe, suffice to show what the worker–society relation is and why it is morally significant. In the next section, I turn to the argument for workplace democracy based on the worker–society relation.

The moral significance of the worker–society relation provides a strong basis for an argument for workplace democracy. Members of society, understood broadly as encompassing all individuals within the large-scale economic system in which the firm operates, depend on workers' work for the availability of various resources to satisfy their needs and pursue their own projects. Their work may affect what opportunities are open to members of society and what life prospects they have. It is of preeminent moral significance that these relations between workers and society are in good order, morally speaking. Workers have a weighty interest not simply in minimizing the impersonal wrong of injustice in the world, but also in ensuring that they relate to those affected by their work as particular kinds of agents, that is, agents who are not indifferent about the way in which members of society are affected, but rather whose practical engagement with society is premised on principles of respect and care. To use the terminology introduced in the previous section, workers have a weighty interest in their functionally characterizable conception of agency, qua workers, not being based on and not conveying morally defective attitudes in their relation to the rest of society.

This implies that the way in which their firm is governed is of great significance to workers. For it is the way in which the firm is governed that determines the nature and purpose of the collective activity that constitutes the firm's operations to which workers contribute and which ultimately determines workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency, at least qua workers. Take, again, Kutz's example of the shipping clerk working for a malicious arms company. The reason why her functionally characterizable conception of agency is morally defective is that the nature and purpose of the collective undertaking in which she participates, that is, the operations of the arms company, is the illicit acquisition of profits by supplying weapons to unjust combatants in bloody conflicts. It is for this reason why her mundane daily activities of going to work, handling paperwork, attending meetings, and so on, make her the kind of agent that, regardless of her subjective attitudes, through her actions expresses disrespect and callous disregard toward the interests of the victims of the firm's operations. Even though as a low-level employee she may not be blameworthy for the firm's wrongdoing, and even though she thinks of the firm's operations as morally reprehensible, by going to work every day and contributing to these operations, her agency conveys a functionally characterizable conception of agency which the rest of society, particularly victims of the arms company's unjust dealings, have reason to view as morally defective. This is what damages her relation to society.

There is little the shipping clerk can do to ameliorate her relationship to society. Since it is stipulated that she is not an omitter, she cannot meaningfully thwart the firm's wrongful operations. She may quit, if she has adequate exit options, but this may not always be the case. Of course, the lack of adequate exit options may mitigate the problem of the moral defect of the worker–society relation, but it hardly eliminates it. In the case of workers who bear responsibility for the firm's wrongdoing, for example, as enactors, endorsers, or omitters, the absence of adequate exit options may reduce their blameworthiness or absolve them from blame altogether, and this may impact their relation to society. However, as I argued, blameworthiness is not the central problem here. Even if the shipping clerk, for example, is not blameworthy for the firm's wrongdoing, her contribution to this wrongdoing through her work may still render her relation to society morally defective. In this case, the lack of adequate exit options condemns her to be the kind of agent who, in her daily practices, acts upon indefensible principles, unable to relate to society in morally appropriate ways.

The shipping clerk may protest the firm's activity outside work, for example, she may participate in demonstrations or campaigns for the stricter regulation of arms companies. This would certainly impact her overall functionally characterizable conception of agency, but it would still leave her functionally characterizable conception of agency qua worker morally defective which would still disturb her relation to society. To use a rather extreme example, assuming the wrongness of capital punishment, the hangman who, in his free time, campaigns against the death penalty certainly does better than one who moonlights as an assassin. Yet, the first one certainly does not offset the damage his occupation does to his relation to society; he is not on a par with his fellow campaigners who work as teachers or plumbers, for example.

Suppose now that the shipping clerk does nothing, but the company's management has a change of heart and adopts a new, more socially benevolent business model. Not only do they stop supplying arms to unjust combatants, but also make bona fide efforts to remedy the harm to which they contributed and hold responsible decision-makers to account. The firm may pivot even more radically and decide to give up arms manufacturing for the sake of something more peaceable. Such changes in how the firm is governed would transform workers' relation to society; now the collective venture in which they participate daily has a wholly new, much more benign character. On the level of the day-to-day work of the shipping clerk, there may be no discernible changes. Her average workday may look much the same as before. Yet her relation to society changes; now she can rest assured that her functionally characterizable conception of agency, qua worker, conveys no disrespect toward anyone. The way in which the firm is governed, therefore, is particularly important for workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency, and, consequently, for the worker–society relation.

This consideration about the relevance of the governance of the firm to the moral quality of the worker–society relation is a strong reason for thinking that workers have a claim to control how the firm is governed through institutions of workplace democracy. This claim requires further argument, for, on the face of it, it is susceptible to a number of challenges. First, it is unclear why workers' interests concerning how the firm is governed should ground any claim to control at all. Workers may have an interest in the morally appropriate governance of the firm, but this may be achieved without workers controlling the firm in any way. Adequate regulations and benevolent bosses may be as capable of preventing firms' moral failings as worker control. But even if the necessity of worker control is established, it is unclear why this control should take shape as workplace democracy, rather than, say, some form of unionism, whereby workers are able to put pressure on bosses through petitions and strikes, or workplace constitutionalism, where managerial decisions are constrained by strict internal rules and workers have opportunities to appeal to an impartial body that can fairly arbitrate their grievances and penalize bosses for bad decisions. Such arrangements may also grant workers some degree of control; why would this not suffice?

One may offer instrumentalist arguments for workplace democracy by claiming that it is generally better at preventing firms from behaving badly and keeping the worker–society relation in good moral order. For example, it may be argued that workplace democracy is able to harness the beneficial epistemic effects of deliberation within large and diverse groups, thus ensuring that firms are governed better both from the economic and the moral point of view (Gerlsbeck & Herzog, 2020; Landemore, 2012). Workplace democracy could also contribute to the development of what Lisa Herzog calls “transformational agency” within the workplace; workers as transformational agents do not blindly execute their organizational role, but rather work toward transforming their role and their organization in ways that better align with the requirements of morality (Herzog, 2018, p. 193). This has the beneficial effect that both inefficiencies and the moral failings of the firm are detected and addressed more easily (Herzog, 2018, p. 253), improving the quality of the worker–society relation.

The success of this instrumental argument greatly depends on the particular empirical background conditions against which workplace democracy is implemented. Workers are as capable of making terrible decisions as bosses, and whether they do so depends on their preferences, values, incentives, culture, institutional surroundings, and so on, which vary greatly from context to context. Under the right background conditions, workplace democracy may be a more effective instrument of keeping firms from moral failures, but there is no a priori reason to think that such background conditions will always or even mostly obtain. Still, I would not deny that under the right empirical circumstances, workplace democracy could have important instrumental benefits. However, I believe that the instrumentalist argument fails to fully account for why workplace democracy matters from the point of view of the worker–society relation.

Workplace democracy does not only matter because, and insofar as, it makes firms behave less badly. It matters because of the way in which it transforms the character and moral quality of the relation between workers and members of society. Recall that the harm associated with the moral defect of the worker–society relation is not simply the agent-neutral harm of producing injustice, but also a relational harm. Workers have an interest not only in minimizing injustice in the world, but also in relating to members of society as particular kinds of agents, that is, as caring and respectful agents who do not go about pursuing their projects and personal advantage disregarding the way in which they contribute to harms that befall on others. But they cannot relate to others as such agents without having an equal say in collective decision-making on how the firm is governed, that is, without workplace democracy. For without such a say, they are at the mercy of other agents—or external circumstances—for the moral quality of their relation to society. Even if they can in some way contest managerial decisions, for example, through unionism or workplace constitutionalism, they lack decision-making powers themselves; it is up to benevolent managers or the impartial arbitration body to govern the firm in morally acceptable ways. The moral quality of workers' relation to society is in the hands of others.

Being so dependent for the moral character of our interpersonal relations on others is an extremely precarious position to be in from the moral point of view. The benevolent discretion of strangers should not be the sole determinant of the moral quality of our relation to others. Both because this makes one powerless to prevent the emergence of morally defective interpersonal relations, and also because it makes one incapable of conveying adequate care and respect toward others through one's functionally characterizable conception of agency. As I argued, one's functionally characterizable conception of agency, qua worker, depends on the nature of the collective venture she partakes in, qua worker, and this, in turn, depends, on how the firm is governed. Even if a firm governed by bosses bestows the right kind of functionally characterizable conception of agency on workers, thereby imposing a morally adequate relation to society, the relation itself remains, in a significant sense, imposed. Workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency remains objectionably divorced from their judgment and action and is therefore unable to convey adequate care and respect to society. For care and respect to be adequately conveyed through our functionally characterizable conception of agency, it must be, in a significant sense, our own making.8

This is achieved only under workplace democracy, and not unionism or workplace constitutionalism. Union members on strike, or workers contesting managerial decisions through the channels of workplace constitutionalism still appeal to others to set their relation to society right. In their case, it is still bosses, who eventually surrender to protests and contestation that make it the case that the firm is governed less wrongly. At the end of the day, workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency remains dependent on bosses' discretion. This dependence is resolved only under workplace democracy. Workplace democracy ensures that the worker–society relation is under the direct collective control of workers; the individual worker no longer appeals to others to improve their relation to society, but is herself a codecision-maker, a co-governor of the firm, capable of shaping this relation directly through co-governing the firm. Her agency is no longer divorced from the decisions that determine the moral character of her relation to society in the same way as in the absence of workplace democracy. This is a significant moral difference that distinguishes workplace democracy from all other arrangements, for example, unionism or workplace constitutionalism, where workers are not granted genuine decision-making powers over the governance of the firm.9

One may object that workers do have direct control over the firm as voters via the democratic state; indeed, perhaps it is the responsibility of the state, rather than workers, to prevent corporate wrongdoing and ensure a good worker–society relation. However, outside command economies, the state usually regulates firms' economic activity by setting legal constraints and shaping their incentive structures. This leaves firms considerably free to pursue their goals within the boundaries set by the state. Qua voters, workers' control over the worker–society relation is not sufficiently direct; they can shape the regulatory environment in which the firm operates, but without workplace democracy, they remain at the mercy of bosses when it comes to the exact shape of the worker–society relation. They can still, at best, appeal to others to establish a good worker–society relation, rather than doing it themselves.

This is not to say that the democratic state and the regulatory environment it creates are irrelevant for having a good worker–society relation. In an ill-regulated economic environment firms may face extreme competitive pressure to stay in business by engaging in wrongdoing which may be hard to resist whether workplaces are democratic or not. This may especially be the case with firms operating in the global market. This means that in their role as voting citizens, workers have strong reasons to try to ensure, through democratic participation, that their state strives to create an economic environment, both domestically and internationally, which enables and facilitates establishing good worker–society relations, for example, through domestic economic policy, trade agreements, participation in international regulatory bodies, and so on. Still, if firms have any kind of autonomy from the state, then only under workplace democracy, in their capacity as co-governors of the firm, can workers themselves establish a good worker–society relation. In other words, even in a well-regulated economic environment firms will face various pressures to shape the worker–society relation in one way rather than another, and it remains important that it is not bosses alone who decide whether the firm succumbs to those pressures or not, but that workers too have a say in how their relation to society is ultimately shaped. This means that workplace democracy and state-level democracy, as well as other institutions and practices, for example, responsible consumer behavior, share and divide the work of creating worker–society relations in good moral order; workplace democracy may not be sufficient for this, but it is necessary.

This also means that even under workplace democracy and advantageous economic conditions, it is not guaranteed that the worker–society relation ends up being in good moral order. Even if the shipping clerk cares about this relation and wishes to ameliorate it, and even if the political and economic environment enables this, that is, there are no excessive pressures on the firm to engage in wrongdoing, workplace democratic outcomes may not reflect her individual judgment or preference. In a democracy one can always be outvoted, and as mentioned, workers are as capable of making terrible decisions as bosses. Although an individual worker may care about avoiding harms and wrongs to others, if their fellow workers do not, or if they strongly fear that refraining from corporate wrongdoing will put their firm at a competitive disadvantage and seriously damage their livelihoods, then they may implement harmful and wrongful company policies through the democratic governance of the firm. One answer to this problem would be that this risk is simply the price to be paid for ensuring workers' control over the worker–society relation, and thereby the adequate expression of care and respect through their functionally characterizable conception of agency. But this raises the question of whether this price is indeed worth paying.

I argued that in a nondemocratic workplace, workers' agency is in some ways divorced from their relation to society. One upside of this, one may argue, is that it allows at least some workers, for example, the shipping clerk, to maintain at least some distance from firms' wrongdoing. It is true that firms' wrongdoing may affect workers' functionally characterizable conception of agency, and thereby damage their relation to the rest of society, but their lack of control may mitigate this damage. Under workplace democracy, their agency becomes much more closely tied to the firm's governance; if the firm engages in wrongful actions, workers now will share responsibility for this as co-governors of the firm. Perhaps there are good reasons to prefer not taking on this responsibility, and leaving their agency distanced from the firm's governance.

The key premise of this objection is that it is worse if a morally defective worker–society relation is workers' own making, as it is under workplace democracy, than if it is imposed on them, as in nondemocratic workplaces. I have my doubts about this claim. It is true that workplace democracy carries with it the disvalue of increased responsibility for the firm's wrongdoings. But, first, for any individual worker, this responsibility may be mitigated, and their functionally characterizable conception of agency improved, if the worker at least votes against and tries to persuade others to vote against the wrongful decision. Second, the nondemocratic workplace also carries with it a disvalue, that is, the disvalue of the powerlessness over the worker–society relation. It seems to me that the objection requires that the disvalue of powerlessness be lesser than the disvalue of increased responsibility due to workplace democracy. It is far from obvious that this is true. Generally, would we prefer powerlessness over our interpersonal relations for the sake of avoiding responsibility when these relations turn morally defective? This does not seem right. By doing so, we would renounce key aspects of our moral agency. As for the worker–society relation specifically, I argued in the previous section that this relation is of great moral significance to workers. Powerlessness over it may well be worse than the burden of responsibility for decisions resulting in the firm's wrongdoing, especially if a worker did all they could to avoid this in their capacity as a democratic co-governor of the firm.

To be sure, it is often extremely challenging to determine what exactly a worker should do to wield their democratic governing power responsibly. Think of the example of the coal miners again; once they gain democratic control over their firm, how should they govern it? Should they continue their extractive and environmentally damaging, activity to secure economic support for their local communities, or should they prioritize reducing the environmental harm their activity does to distant others? Here, again, I cannot settle this question. But, the very fact that the worker–society relation raises such hard and complex moral problems testifies to the importance of workers' control over this relation. We all have a weighty interest in our judgment bearing on how such complex questions about our relation to others are settled; that others should settle these hard moral questions about our interpersonal lives affronts our standing as full moral agents and damages our interpersonal relations themselves. The worker–society relation is indeed complex. All the more reason why workers and not only bosses should have a say in what shape it takes.

How does my argument and republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy relate to each other? As noted, the latter tend to focus on intra-firm power relations between bosses and workers, especially insofar as these threaten with domination or relational inequality. My argument, in contrast, focuses on the extra-firm relation between workers and the rest of society. However, while my argument does focus on the worker–society relation, there is a sense in which it also criticizes a particular kind of unequal intra-firm power relation, that is, bosses' unequal power to determine the moral character of workers' relation to society. What does this argument add, then, to existing republican and relational egalitarian discussions on workplace democracy, besides pointing out yet another way in which workers are dominated by or subordinated to bosses in the contemporary workplace? To answer, let us take a closer look at why exactly various arguments object to unequal power relations in the workplace.

Republicans object to intra-firm power inequalities because, and insofar as, they constitute domination, that is, a particularly objectionable interpersonal relation exemplified in its most extreme form by the relationship between the master and the slave (McCammon, 2015). The argument from the worker–society relation, in contrast, is not about domination; indeed, in the first place, it is not even about the worker–boss relation. First and foremost, it objects to workers' powerlessness to keep their relation to society in good moral order, for this precludes their expressing adequate care and respect toward the rest of society. If this powerlessness is engendered by bosses' unequal power over workers, then the argument objects to this power inequality too. But this does not presuppose that this power inequality constitutes domination. This is not to say that it does not constitute domination. Perhaps it does. If so, then there are republican reasons for objecting to it. But the reasons identified by the argument from the worker–society relation are not reasons of this republican kind. The argument finds this power inequality objectionable irrespective of whether it counts as domination or not. Something similar is true in the case of relational egalitarian arguments. These claim that intra-firm inequalities of power are objectionable because they prevent workers and bosses from relating as equals. But according to my argument, workers' powerlessness over the worker–society relation is objectionable whether or not bosses and workers relate as equals. This, again, is not to say that this powerlessness may not contribute to relational inequality between workers and bosses. Perhaps it does. But my argument does not presuppose this. The argument claims that this powerlessness is wrong in and of itself, regardless of whether it is also wrong by virtue of creating relational inequality.

Suppose that some objection against republican and relational egalitarian analyses of workplace power inequality succeeds, for example, someone successfully argues that workplace hierarchies, while involving power inequality, are sufficiently “tempered” not to constitute objectionable relationships of genuine domination or relational inequality (Kolodny, 2023, pp. 148–152). This would refute republican and relational egalitarian arguments for workplace democracy. But it would not refute my argument. For even if it were true that workers are neither dominated by nor relationally unequal to bosses, they may still object to the fact that bosses have unilateral control over the moral quality of their relationship to the rest of society; not because this makes their relationship to bosses morally defective, for example, dominating or relationally unequal, but because it makes their relationship to society morally defective. This is what constitutes the moral precarity to which the argument from the worker–society relation objects.

To illustrate my point, consider the case of coal miners again. Republicans and relational egalitarians argue that they should have a democratic say in how their firm is governed because otherwise they are dominated by or relate unequally to their bosses. On this view, what matters in the first place is the intra-firm worker–boss relation. On the argument from the worker–society relation, it is the other way around. The reason why they should have a democratic say in the workplace is because it is of great moral importance that they themselves shape the worker–society relation; what matters in the first place is the extra-firm worker–society relation. Of course, in the absence of workplace democracy, it is bosses who shape this extra-firm relation; bosses decide if the firm continues its extractive activities, benefiting workers' local communities, but harming distant others through environmental damage, or if the firm transitions into less environmentally harmful activities which may not be as economically beneficial for local communities, or if they find some middle way. This shaping of the worker–society relation may or may not count as domination or relational inequality. If it does, then there may be republican or relational egalitarian reasons to oppose it. But even if it does not, my argument provides independent reasons for introducing workplace democracy, that is, the inherent wrong, independent of domination or relational inequality, of workers not shaping their relationship to society. The two arguments are not mutually exclusive, but they are independent; it is possible to accept both or one without the other. Thus, my argument does not merely add to the list of republican and relational egalitarian grievances about power inequality in the contemporary workplace. Rather, it identifies distinct and independent grounds for introducing workplace democracy.

Could republican or relational egalitarian arguments incorporate the argument from the worker–society relation? After all, extra-firm relations should matter to republicans and relational egalitarians as well. As Nicholas Vrousalis (2019) argues, for example, extra-firm domination pervades capitalist economies; firms and their bosses dominate other firms by exerting competitive pressure, and they dominate states through their power to disinvest and relocate. These extra-firm relations, he argues, should worry republicans too. Indeed, the coal company and its bosses may dominate not only their workers, but also their local communities and distant others on whom they arbitrarily bestow economic benefit and environmental harm. As Vrousalis argues, however, workplace democracy alone may do little to address these concerns; democratic firms can dominate society in the same way nondemocratic firms do. Democratizing the coal company would only mean allowing its workers to dominate their local community and distant others just as their bosses used to. Arguably, from a republican or relational egalitarian viewpoint, extra-firm domination and relational inequality need to be addressed by reforming the underlying economic conditions that make these objectionable relations possible;10 workplace democracy, in itself, is not a solution.

However, even if in the extra-firm case workplace democracy does not eliminate domination or relational inequality in the same way it does in the intra-firm case, the argument from the worker–society relation can still show why it matters for the moral quality of extra-firm relations. I argued that workplace democracy is necessary for workers to convey adequate care and respect through their functionally characterizable conception of agency to members of society they affect through their work. This is a relational gain even if the worker–society relation remains tainted by domination or relational inequality. That is, even if workplace democracy does not improve workers' extra-firm relations in terms of nondomination or relational equality, it may improve it along other dimensions. Of course, workers still have reasons to eliminate extra-firm domination and relational inequality by using their democratic powers as citizens to reform the underlying economic conditions through the democratic state. Still, these considerations suggest that the argument from the worker–society relation is not easily incorporated into republican or relational egalitarian accounts; it picks out a relational value distinct from nondomination or relational equality, and thus identifies reasons for adopting workplace democracy that republican and relational egalitarian analyses do not.11

Workplace democracy, I believe, is best justified by workers' interest to keep their interpersonal relations in good moral order. Republican and relational egalitarian arguments capture one element of this interest, that is, workers' interests in relating in egalitarian and nondominating ways to their bosses and each other. But, there is another, no less relevant relation that grounds workers' claims for workplace democracy: the worker–society relation. Work embeds individuals in large-scale systems of production, consumption, logistics, and services; systems, through which they maintain and reproduce the economic bases of their shared social life. This system may bring flourishing to the people who are caught up in them, or it may produce deprivation, vulnerability, and injustice. Workers have an interest in promoting the former through their work rather than the latter, not simply because of the general impersonal imperative of reducing disvalue in the world, but also because they have an interest in relating to all individuals within this system as agents who are not callous or disrespectful toward them, but rather exhibit care and respect. This weighty interest grounds a strong claim on the part of workers for workplace democracy. For only under workplace democracy do they not depend on others for the moral quality of their relation to society and are able to convey adequate care and respect within this relation.

This work was supported by the GOODINT Project, funded by the Research Council of Norway, project no. 313846.

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

工作场所民主:工人与社会关系的论证
人们提出了许多关于职场民主的论点,也就是说,员工在管理公司方面应该有平等的发言权。最近,关于关系的争论,特别是关于共和主义和关系平等主义的争论,变得非常突出。他们声称,员工应该对公司的管理方式有发言权,以避免令人反感的工作场所关系,例如,支配或从属关系。虽然我觉得这些观点很吸引人,但我也认为它们是不完整的。通过关注工人在企业内部,即对老板和其他工人的人际关系的道德质量,他们忽略了工人在企业外部,即对社会其他部分的关系的道德质量。然而,后者对于证明职场民主的正当性同样重要。在这篇文章中,我认为应该采用工作场所民主的部分原因是,它允许工人对公司的运作施加适当的控制,从而保持对他们作为公司工人与社会其他部分之间关系的一般特征的控制。工人-社会关系的论点并不是为了反驳或取代共和主义和关系平等主义的论点,而是为了引起人们对工作场所民主的关系价值的一个迄今为止被忽视的方面的注意,而上述方法通常没有包括这个方面。通过这种方式,目前的论点加强了工作场所民主的整体关系案例。文章的结构如下。首先,我介绍了工作场所民主的概念和论点,重点是最突出的关系论点,即共和主义和关系平等主义。其次,介绍了工人与社会关系的概念,并讨论了其道德意义。第三,我提出了基于工人与社会关系的工作场所民主的论点。第四,我讨论了工人-社会关系的论点与共和主义和关系平等主义关于工作场所民主的论点之间的关系,以显示前者如何与这些方法不同并补充这些方法。最后一部分是总结。工作场所民主是一种安排,在这种安排中,公司的所有员工在如何管理公司方面都有平等的发言权,就像在一个民主国家,所有公民在如何管理国家方面都有平等的发言权,除了某些特定群体,比如未成年人。这个广泛的定义可以通过多种方式进一步说明。职场民主有许多模式和制度设计,但为了讨论的目的,我将保持中立,不知道哪一种最好实施。在工作场所民主制度下,雇员是否必须通过代表直接或间接地行使他们的民主发言权,是否需要建立工人委员会,或者雇员在董事会中的代表份额是否也足够,等等,我不会讨论。虽然这些问题当然具有实践和理论意义,但它们与以下论点没有直接关系,该论点的重点是工作场所民主的正当性问题,无论以何种方式实施。支持工作场所民主的论据多种多样(弗雷加等人,2019)。例子包括来自国有企业类比的论点(Dahl, 1985;费雷拉和Landemore 2016;Gonzalez-Ricoy, 2014;McMahon, 1994), meaningful work (Yeoman, 2014), recognition (Hirvonen &amp;Breen, 2020)和自我实现(Gould, 2004)。然而,近年来,主要基于作为非统治的自由的共和理想和关系平等理论的关系论点得到了突出(Anderson, 2017;布林,2015;Gonzalez-Ricoy, 2014 b;Gourevitch, 2013)。这些争论始于这样一种观察:当今的工作场所充斥着不平等的权力关系,尤其是在员工和老板之间。我所说的“工人”是指那些没有权力做出管理决策、命令其他员工执行任务、雇佣和解雇员工等的人。另一方面,我所说的“老板”是指那些确实拥有这种权力的人。当然,如果说所有工作场所的每个人都可以被整齐地分为这两类,那就过于简单化了。例如,中层管理人员通常有有限的自主权来做出管理决策,一些工作场所可能以不那么分层的方式组织。尽管如此,依赖于这种简化将极大地有助于以下讨论的清晰和简洁,并且如何修改论点以适应这些复杂性是相当直接的。 可以说,从共和主义或关系平等主义的观点来看,需要通过改革使这些令人反感的关系成为可能的潜在经济条件来解决超企业支配和关系不平等问题;工作场所民主本身并不是一个解决方案。然而,即使在企业外案例中,工作场所民主并没有像在企业内案例中那样消除支配或关系不平等,来自工人-社会关系的论点仍然可以说明为什么它对企业外关系的道德质量很重要。我认为,工作场所的民主是必要的,工人可以通过他们的功能特征的代理概念,向他们通过工作影响的社会成员传达足够的关心和尊重。这是一种关系上的收获,即使工人与社会的关系仍然受到统治或关系不平等的污染。也就是说,即使工作场所民主不能在非支配性或关系平等方面改善工人的超公司关系,它也可能在其他方面改善这种关系。当然,工人仍然有理由通过民主国家利用他们作为公民的民主权力来改革潜在的经济状况,从而消除额外的公司统治和关系不平等。尽管如此,这些考虑表明,工人-社会关系的论点不容易被纳入共和主义或关系平等主义的说法;它选择了一种不同于非支配性或关系平等的关系价值,从而确定了采用共和主义和关系平等主义分析所没有的工作场所民主的原因。工作场所的民主,我认为,最合理的理由是工人的利益,保持良好的人际关系的道德秩序。共和党和关系平等主义的论点抓住了这种兴趣的一个要素,即工人以平等和非支配的方式与老板和彼此建立关系的兴趣。但是,还有另一种同样相关的关系是工人要求工作场所民主的基础:工人与社会的关系。工作将个人嵌入到生产、消费、物流和服务的大规模系统中;他们赖以维持和再生产共同社会生活的经济基础的制度。这种制度可能会给陷入其中的人带来繁荣,也可能会产生剥夺、脆弱和不公正。工人有兴趣通过他们的工作来促进前者,而不是后者,不仅仅是因为减少世界上的不价值的一般非个人的必要性,还因为他们有兴趣将这个系统中的所有个人作为代理人,对他们不是冷酷无情或不尊重,而是表现出关心和尊重。这一重大利益使工人们有理由强烈要求职场民主。因为只有在工作场所民主的情况下,他们才不依赖于他人来维持他们与社会关系的道德品质,并且能够在这种关系中传达足够的关心和尊重。这项工作得到了GOODINT项目的支持,该项目由挪威研究委员会资助,项目号:313846.作者声明不存在利益冲突。 考虑到工作场所的权力不平等,许多共和党人和关系平等主义者认为,今天的工人和老板之间的关系通常以关系不平等为特征,如果不是完全的统治(Berkey, 2023)。例如,伊丽莎白·安德森(Elizabeth Anderson, 2017)将当代公司,尤其是美国的公司,描述为微型独裁政权,由一群无所不能的老板统治着工人群体。当然,在字面意义上,老板对员工有无限的专断权力,也就是说,主人对奴隶或对臣民有无限的专断权力,这种情况很少发生。然而,很明显,劳动合同在工人和老板之间建立了一种命令等级制度,其中一方有能力剥夺另一方可能是她唯一的收入来源。这种权力关系容易产生关系不平等(nsamron, 2015)。诚然,这种不平等是否会进一步发展为统治,在很大程度上取决于背景和背景条件(参见O’shea, 2019)。尽管如此,人们可能会很好地辩称,至少由工作场所等级制度产生的统治威胁(这种威胁在当代工作场所普遍存在)应该成为非统治和关系平等倡导者的一个突出问题。提倡工作场所民主的共和党和关系平等主义者认为,纠正这种不平等的唯一途径是确保工人和老板分享管理公司的平等权力。这将使工人和老板处于彼此的相互控制之下,从而防止在工作场所出现统治或关系不平等。当然,这一论点可以通过各种方式受到质疑(Jacob &;纽豪斯,2018;科洛德尼,2023,145页;泰勒,2019)。有人可能会争辩说,没有工作场所的民主,例如,通过工人的同意和适当的退出选择,可以充分减轻统治的威胁(见Arenson, 1993;cf. Taylor, 2017),通过强有力的国家法规,值得注意的是,工人确实作为选民进行民主控制(Jacob &amp;Neuhäuser, 2018, p. 932),或通过强有力的内部规则和争议渠道,即工作场所宪政(Hsieh, 2005)。尽管关于工作场所民主的共和党和关系平等主义案例的辩论当然仍在进行中,但在我看来,共和党人和关系平等主义者已经能够对这些批评提供有希望的回应(例如,González-Ricoy, 2019)。但是,即使共和党和关系平等主义的观点被证明是站得住脚的,我认为它们仍然是不完整的。共和党和关系平等主义的工作场所民主倡导者主要关注公司内部关系,如工人与老板的关系。他们认为,正是这些关系的道德缺陷,例如关系不平等和支配,使得工作场所的民主成为必要。这并不是说老板和员工之间的不平等和支配关系仅限于工作场所。想象一下在咖啡店遇到你的老板。即使你不在工作场所,这个人有权力在工作日解雇你或给你分配卑微的任务,这一事实必然会影响你的互动。尽管如此,这种影响的根源是同一工作场所内员工和老板之间的公司内部权力不平等。这种方法忽略的是额外的牢固关系,例如工人与社会其他人的关系。正如我将展示的,这种关系对于理解工作场所民主的价值和正当性至关重要;职场民主对于确保不仅是企业内部关系,而且是企业外部关系处于良好的道德秩序是必要的。这意味着,即使共和主义和关系平等主义关于工作场所民主的论点是合理的,它们也不能给我们提供证明工作场所民主的完整图景,因为它们关注的是企业内部关系。一旦我们考虑到公司外的关系,我们就能找到支持职场民主的新的、独特的理由。当然,这并不能反驳共和主义或关系平等主义的论点。相反,它提供了有利于工作场所民主的新的关系考虑,这些考虑与共和主义和关系平等主义的民主相容,但迄今为止在文献中几乎没有受到关注。因此,下面的论点最终加强了工作场所民主的整体关系案例。企业将工人嵌入到生产、消费、商品和服务流通的大规模经济系统中,并通过这样的系统将工人与企业外的其他个人联系起来。消费者使用工人生产和提供的产品和服务。工人与其他公司的雇员合作和竞争,有时直接,有时间接。 这些员工“没有做任何助长错误的事情,或者他们不支持错误的事情,或者他们无法做任何事情来与之保持距离。”(Collins, 2023, p. 134) Collins的例子是一个银行的出纳,他与银行的不良业务没有明确的联系,如果有的话。我们也可以想到库茨(2000)的例子,一个为一家武器制造商工作的船务员,生产和分销用于不公正冲突的武器。柯林斯认为,这些低级雇员在道德上与公司的不法行为无关,也不应受到谴责然而,这并不意味着公司的不法行为在道德上与他们无关。例如,柯林斯声称,对于这些员工来说,体验伯纳德·威廉姆斯(Bernard Williams, 1981)所说的“代理人后悔”(agent-regret)仍然是合适的,即对自己无可指责地参与了公司的不法行为感到后悔。不管船务员的态度和承诺如何,通过其所从事的行为,船务员表现出一种令人反感的代理行为;她是一种代理人,在她的日常活动中为伤害他人的集体努力做出贡献,这种与他人共处的方式建立了与他人的某种关系,也就是说,这种关系的前提是对公司活动的受害者不尊重或麻木不仁,而这些受害者,实际上,任何其他人,都理所当然地反对这种关系。我并不是说她的持续参与表明她私下里对这些受害者有不尊重的态度。她可能真的很讨厌自己对公司有害的运作有所贡献。在她和受害者之间建立道德缺陷关系的是她在公司和整个社会中作为代理人的方式,也就是说,她对代理的功能特征化概念。出于同样的原因,我认为她不一定能算作柯林斯意义上的拥护者,也就是说,她承诺公司的一些目标,而这些目标可以预见会涉及不法行为。正如柯林斯所指出的,公司可能有许多独立的目标,而个别员工可能只对其中的一些目标表示承诺。船务人员可能只承诺有效地处理文书工作(Collins, 2023,第148页)。然而,就像消费者不一定通过购买血汗工厂的产品来承诺或支持他们令人反感的剥削目标一样,他们的行为可能仍然表达了对血汗工厂工人的不尊重和漠视,船工继续参与武器公司的运营可能仍然表达了一种功能上可表征的代理概念,这在道德上是令人反感的,从而损害了她与社会其他部分的关系。工人与社会关系的道德品质既独立于工人对企业经营的主观态度,也独立于社会的态度。说工人-社会关系在道德上有缺陷,并不是要报道工人或消费者的社会地位和公众看法,更不用说他们对彼此的主观立场了。也许公司的不法行为在社会上是完全正常化的,也就是说,包括工人和公司不法行为的受害者在内的所有人都认为,公司的不法行为只是令人不快,但无可非议或不可改变的“照常营业”。但是,人们赋予工人社会关系的权重并不一定是他们应该赋予它的权重。就像消费者应该关心他们与血汗工厂工人的关系一样,即使从经验事实来看,他们并不关心,货运职员也应该关心他们与那些受到军火公司业务伤害的人的关系,即使从经验事实来看,她并不关心。不管她或其他人怎么想,他们继续参与公司有害业务的事实意味着,她作为工人与社会的实际接触继续以不可容忍的不尊重或对他人利益的无情原则为基础和指导,这些原则损害了她与上述他人和社会其他部分的关系。当然,工人与社会的关系往往是间接的、高度中介的。在武器制造商和非正义战争的危害之间有许多中间人,包括分销商、物流公司、管理机构、政府和国际机构、军事领导人和非正义战斗人员本身。这些中介因素都影响着劳资关系道德损害的严重程度。船务员与不公正冲突的受害者的关系并不像她自己作为不公正的战斗员加入冲突那样有缺陷。然而,正如我所讨论的,我们与遥远的、间接的伤害之间的联系,例如血汗工厂的劳工或气候变化,对我们来说确实具有道德意义(参见Schwenkenbecher, 2014;Zoller, 2015)。 此外,工人与社会的关系往往是高度复杂的,使其道德意义的含义远不清楚。例如,考虑一下煤矿工人,他们的工作可能造成相当大的环境破坏,同时对当地社区作出重要的经济贡献诚然,工人与社会的关系在这里具有道德意义,但究竟是哪种关系呢?工人们与当地社区的关系(这些社区靠他们的工作维持经济上的运转)是否比他们与远方的其他人的关系更重要呢?这些人可能最直接地受到他们工作造成的环境破坏的伤害。这是一个很难回答的问题,我不希望在本文中解决。然而,这是一个很难回答的问题,这一事实表明了工人与社会关系的道德意义。工人通过他们的工作与社会其他部分联系起来的方式在道德上是重要的,即使它到底有多重要的问题是一个极其复杂的问题我相信,这些考虑足以说明工人与社会的关系是什么,以及为什么它具有道德意义。在下一节中,我将转向基于工人-社会关系的工作场所民主的论点。工人-社会关系的道德意义为工作场所民主的论点提供了强有力的基础。社会成员,广义地理解为包括企业运作的大规模经济系统中的所有个人,依靠工人的工作来获得各种资源,以满足他们的需求并追求他们自己的项目。他们的工作可能影响向社会成员开放的机会和他们的生活前景。从道德上讲,工人和社会之间的这些关系处于良好的秩序中,这具有卓越的道德意义。工人的重大利益不仅在于最大限度地减少世界上不公正的非个人错误,而且在于确保他们与受其工作影响的人作为特定类型的代理人联系起来,也就是说,这些代理人对社会成员受到影响的方式并不漠不关心,而是以尊重和关心的原则为前提的实际参与社会。使用前一节介绍的术语,工人对他们的功能特征的代理概念有重大的兴趣,作为工人,在他们与社会其他部分的关系中,不基于也不传达道德上有缺陷的态度。这意味着他们公司的管理方式对工人来说意义重大。因为企业的治理方式决定了集体活动的性质和目的,集体活动构成了企业的运作,工人们为此做出了贡献,并最终决定了工人们对代理(至少是作为工人)的功能特征概念。再次以库茨的例子为例,一个为恶意武器公司工作的货运职员。她的职能特征的代理概念在道德上有缺陷的原因是,她参与的集体事业的性质和目的,即武器公司的业务,是通过在血腥冲突中向不公正的战斗人员提供武器来非法获取利润。正是由于这个原因,她的日常工作,处理文书工作,参加会议等平凡的日常活动,使她成为那种代理人,不管她的主观态度如何,通过她的行为表达了对公司运营受害者利益的不尊重和无情的漠视。即使作为一名低级员工,她可能不应该为公司的不法行为负责,即使她认为公司的行为在道德上应该受到谴责,但通过每天上班并为这些行为做出贡献,她的代理传达了一种功能上可表征的代理概念,而社会上的其他人,尤其是武器公司不公正交易的受害者,有理由认为这是道德上的缺陷。这就破坏了她与社会的关系。船务人员几乎无法改善她与社会的关系。既然规定她不是遗漏者,她就不能有效地阻止公司的不法运作。如果她有足够的退出选择,她可能会辞职,但情况可能并非总是如此。当然,缺乏适当的退出选择可能会缓解劳资关系的道德缺陷问题,但很难消除这一问题。对于那些为公司的不法行为承担责任的工人,例如,作为执行者、支持者或省略者,缺乏适当的退出选择可能会减少他们的可责备性或完全免除他们的责任,这可能会影响他们与社会的关系。然而,正如我所说,应该受到指责并不是这里的核心问题。 例如,即使船务员不应因公司的不法行为而受到谴责,她通过工作对不法行为的贡献仍可能使她与社会的关系在道德上存在缺陷。在这种情况下,缺乏足够的退出选择使她成为那种在日常实践中根据站不住脚的原则行事的人,无法以道德上适当的方式与社会联系。船务员可能会抗议公司在工作之外的活动,例如,她可能会参加示威或要求对军火公司进行更严格监管的运动。这肯定会影响她对代理的整体功能特征概念,但这仍然会让她对代理的功能特征概念,作为一个道德缺陷的工作者,这仍然会扰乱她与社会的关系。举一个比较极端的例子,假设死刑是错误的,一个刽子手在业余时间反对死刑肯定比一个兼职刺客做得更好。然而,第一种收入肯定不能抵消他的职业对他与社会关系造成的损害;例如,他与其他从事教师或水管工工作的竞选者不一样。假设现在货运职员什么都不做,但公司的管理层改变了主意,采用了一种新的、更有利于社会的商业模式。它们不仅停止向不公正的战斗人员提供武器,而且还作出真诚的努力,纠正它们造成的伤害,并追究负责任的决策者的责任。该公司可能会更加激进地转向,为了更和平的事业而决定放弃武器制造。企业管理方式的这种变化将改变工人与社会的关系;现在,他们每天参与的集体冒险有了一种全新的、良性得多的特征。在运输职员的日常工作层面上,可能没有明显的变化。她的日常工作看起来可能和以前没什么两样。然而,她与社会的关系发生了变化;现在她可以放心了,她对代理的功能特征概念,即作为工人,没有对任何人不敬。因此,企业的治理方式对于工人的代理概念的功能特征,以及因此对工人-社会关系尤为重要。考虑到公司治理与工人-社会关系的道德质量的相关性,这是一个强有力的理由,让我们认为工人有权通过工作场所民主制度控制公司的治理方式。这种说法需要进一步论证,因为从表面上看,它容易受到许多挑战。首先,不清楚为什么工人关心公司如何管理的利益应该成为任何控制要求的基础。工人可能对道德上适当的公司治理感兴趣,但这可能在没有工人以任何方式控制公司的情况下实现。适当的规章制度和仁慈的老板也许能像工人控制一样防止公司的道德沦丧。但是,即使建立工人控制的必要性,也不清楚为什么这种控制应该形成工作场所民主,而不是某种形式的工会主义,工人可以通过请愿和罢工向老板施加压力,或者工作场所宪政主义,管理决策受到严格的内部规则的约束,工人有机会向一个公正的机构上诉,这个机构可以公平地仲裁他们的不满,并惩罚老板的错误决定。这样的安排也可能给予工人一定程度的控制权;为什么这还不够呢?有人可能会为工作场所民主提供工具主义的论据,声称它通常更能防止公司的不良行为,并使工人与社会的关系保持良好的道德秩序。例如,有人可能会认为,工作场所民主能够利用在大型和多样化群体中审议的有益认知效应,从而确保公司从经济和道德的角度得到更好的管理(Gerlsbeck &amp;赫尔佐格,2020;Landemore, 2012)。工作场所的民主也有助于丽莎·赫尔佐格(Lisa Herzog)所说的工作场所“转型机构”(transformational agency)的发展;作为转型代理人的员工不会盲目地执行他们的组织角色,而是努力以更符合道德要求的方式转变他们的角色和组织(Herzog, 2018,第193页)。这有一个有益的效果,即更容易发现和解决公司的低效率和道德失败(Herzog, 2018,第253页),从而提高工人-社会关系的质量。 这种工具性论点的成功在很大程度上取决于实施工作场所民主的特定经验背景条件。员工和老板一样有可能做出糟糕的决定,而他们是否会做出糟糕的决定取决于他们的偏好、价值观、激励机制、文化、制度环境等等,而这些都因环境而异。在适当的背景条件下,工作场所民主可能是防止企业道德失败的更有效工具,但没有先验的理由认为这样的背景条件总是或甚至大部分会得到。不过,我不否认,在适当的经验环境下,职场民主可能会带来重要的工具性好处。然而,我认为,工具主义的论点未能充分解释为什么从工人与社会关系的角度来看,工作场所民主很重要。职场民主之所以重要,不仅因为它能让公司的行为不那么糟糕。它之所以重要,是因为它改变了工人和社会成员之间关系的性质和道德品质。回想一下,与工人-社会关系的道德缺陷相关的伤害不仅仅是产生不公正的代理人中性伤害,而且是一种关系伤害。工人的利益不仅在于减少世界上的不公正,而且在于把社会成员作为一种特殊的代理人,也就是说,作为一种关心和尊重的代理人,他们不去追求自己的项目和个人利益,而不顾自己对他人造成伤害的方式。但是,如果在企业如何管理的集体决策中没有平等的发言权,也就是说,没有工作场所民主,他们就不能作为这样的代理人与他人联系起来。因为如果没有这样的发言权,他们与社会关系的道德品质就会受到其他行为者或外部环境的摆布。即使他们可以以某种方式对管理决策提出异议,例如通过工会主义或工作场所宪政主义,他们自己也缺乏决策权;这取决于仁慈的管理者或公正的仲裁机构以道德上可接受的方式管理公司。工人与社会关系的道德品质掌握在他人手中。从道德的角度来看,我们人际关系的道德品质如此依赖于他人是一种极其危险的处境。陌生人善意的谨慎不应成为我们与他人关系的道德品质的唯一决定因素。因为这使一个人无力阻止道德缺陷的人际关系的出现,也因为它使一个人无法通过一个功能特征化的代理概念向他人传达足够的关心和尊重。正如我所论证的,一个人的代理的功能特征概念,作为工人,取决于她所参与的集体冒险的性质,作为工人,而这反过来又取决于公司是如何管理的。即使一家由老板管理的公司赋予工人正确的功能特征化代理概念,从而将道德上适当的关系强加给社会,但在很大意义上,这种关系本身仍然是强加的。令人反感的是,工人对代理的功能特征概念仍然与他们的判断和行动脱节,因此无法向社会传达足够的关心和尊重。要想通过我们的功能特征化的代理概念充分传达关怀和尊重,在很大程度上,它必须是我们自己创造的。这只有在工作场所民主的情况下才能实现,而不是工会主义或工作场所宪政。罢工的工会成员,或者通过工作场所宪政主义渠道对管理决策提出异议的工人,仍然会呼吁其他人纠正他们与社会的关系。在他们的案例中,仍然是老板们,他们最终屈服于抗议和争论,这使得公司的管理不那么错误。在一天结束的时候,员工对代理的功能特征概念仍然取决于老板的判断力。这种依赖只有在工作场所民主下才能解决。工作场所民主确保工人与社会的关系处于工人的直接集体控制之下;个体工人不再呼吁他人改善他们与社会的关系,而是自己成为企业的共同决策者、共同管理者,能够通过共同管理企业直接塑造这种关系。她的代理不再与决定她与社会关系的道德品质的决定相分离,就像在没有工作场所民主的情况下一样。 这是一个重要的道德差异,将工作场所民主与所有其他安排区分开来,例如,工会主义或工作场所宪政主义,在这些安排中,工人没有被授予对公司治理的真正决策权。有人可能会反对说,工人确实可以通过民主国家作为选民直接控制公司;事实上,也许是国家的责任,而不是工人的责任,来防止企业的不法行为,并确保良好的工人-社会关系。然而,在计划经济之外,国家通常通过设置法律约束和塑造激励结构来调节企业的经济活动。这使得企业可以在国家设定的范围内自由地追求目标。作为选民,工人对工人-社会关系的控制不够直接;他们可以塑造公司运作的监管环境,但如果没有工作场所的民主,当涉及到工人-社会关系的确切形态时,他们仍然受老板的摆布。他们最多也只能呼吁他人建立良好的工人与社会关系,而不是自己动手。这并不是说民主国家及其创造的监管环境与良好的工人社会关系无关。在一个管理不善的经济环境中,公司可能会面临极端的竞争压力,通过从事不法行为来维持业务,无论工作场所是否民主,这种行为都很难抗拒。在全球市场运营的公司尤其如此。这意味着,作为有投票权的公民,工人有充分的理由通过民主参与,努力确保他们的国家在国内和国际上努力创造一个经济环境,例如,通过国内经济政策、贸易协定、参与国际监管机构等,使并促进建立良好的工人与社会关系。尽管如此,如果企业有任何形式的独立于国家的自主权,那么只有在工作场所民主下,作为企业的共同管理者,工人自己才能建立良好的工人-社会关系。换句话说,即使在一个监管良好的经济环境中,公司也会面临各种压力,以一种而不是另一种方式塑造工人与社会的关系,重要的是,不仅仅是老板决定公司是否屈服于这些压力,工人也有发言权,他们与社会的关系最终是如何形成的。这意味着工作场所民主和国家级民主,以及其他制度和做法,例如负责任的消费者行为,共同分担和分工创造良好道德秩序的工人-社会关系的工作;工作场所的民主可能不足以实现这一点,但它是必要的。这也意味着,即使在工作场所民主和有利的经济条件下,也不能保证工人-社会关系最终处于良好的道德秩序。即使船务人员关心这种关系并希望改善它,即使政治和经济环境允许这样做,也就是说,公司没有过度的压力从事不法行为,工作场所的民主结果可能不会反映她的个人判断或偏好。在一个民主国家,一个人总是会被投票否决,正如前面提到的,工人和老板一样有能力做出糟糕的决定。尽管个别员工可能关心避免对他人造成伤害和错误,但如果他们的同事不这样做,或者如果他们强烈担心避免公司不法行为将使他们的公司处于竞争劣势并严重损害他们的生计,那么他们可能会通过公司的民主治理来实施有害和错误的公司政策。这个问题的一个答案是,这种风险只是为了确保工人对工人-社会关系的控制,从而通过他们的功能特征的代理概念充分表达关心和尊重而付出的代价。但这就提出了这样一个问题:付出这样的代价是否真的值得?我认为,在一个非民主的工作场所,工人的代理在某种程度上脱离了他们与社会的关系。有人可能会说,这样做的一个好处是,它至少允许一些工人,比如船务人员,与公司的不法行为保持一定的距离。的确,企业的不当行为可能会影响工人对代理的功能特征概念,从而损害他们与社会其他部分的关系,但他们缺乏控制可能会减轻这种损害。在工作场所民主的情况下,他们的代理机构与公司的治理联系得更加紧密;如果公司从事不法行为,工人现在将作为公司的共同管理者分担责任。 也许有很好的理由不愿意承担这一责任,让他们的代理机构与公司的治理保持距离。这一反对意见的关键前提是,如果道德上有缺陷的工人与社会关系是工人自己造成的,就像在工作场所民主的情况下一样,而不是像在非民主的工作场所那样被强加给他们,情况会更糟。我对这种说法表示怀疑。的确,工作场所的民主带来了对公司错误行为承担更多责任的贬值。但是,首先,对于任何工人个人来说,如果工人至少投票反对并试图说服其他人投票反对错误的决定,这种责任可能会减轻,他们的功能特征代理概念也会得到改善。其次,非民主的工作场所也带有一种不价值,即对工人-社会关系的无能为力的不价值。在我看来,这种反对意见要求,由于工作场所民主而增加的责任的不价值小于无能为力的不价值。这是不是真的还远不明显。一般来说,当人际关系出现道德缺陷时,我们会为了逃避责任而选择无能为力而不是人际关系吗?这似乎不对。这样做,我们就放弃了我们道德能动性的关键方面。具体到工人与社会的关系,我在前一节中指出,这种关系对工人具有重大的道德意义。在这方面的无能为力可能比为导致公司不法行为的决策承担责任的负担更糟糕,特别是如果一个工人以公司民主的共同管理者的身份尽其所能避免这种情况。可以肯定的是,要确定一个工人究竟应该做些什么来负责任地行使他们的民主权力,往往是极具挑战性的。再想想煤矿工人的例子;一旦他们获得了对公司的民主控制,他们该如何管理公司呢?他们应该继续他们的采掘和破坏环境的活动,以确保对当地社区的经济支持,还是应该优先减少他们的活动对遥远的其他人造成的环境危害?在这里,我再一次无法解决这个问题。但是,工人与社会的关系引发了如此艰难而复杂的道德问题,这一事实本身就证明了工人对这种关系的控制的重要性。关于我们与他人的关系这类复杂问题如何解决,我们都对自己的判断非常感兴趣;让别人来解决这些关于我们人际生活的棘手道德问题,不仅冒犯了我们作为完全道德主体的地位,而且损害了我们的人际关系本身。工人与社会的关系确实很复杂。正因为如此,工人(而不仅仅是老板)应该对未来的发展有发言权。我的论点和共和主义的,关系平等主义的关于工作场所民主的论点是如何相互联系的?如前所述,后者倾向于关注老板和工人之间的公司内部权力关系,特别是在这些关系威胁到统治或关系不平等的情况下。相反,我的论点集中在工人和社会其他部分之间的异常牢固的关系上。然而,虽然我的论点确实关注工人-社会关系,但在某种意义上,它也批评了一种特殊的不平等的企业内部权力关系,即老板在决定工人与社会关系的道德特征方面的不平等权力。那么,除了指出当代职场中工人被老板支配或从属于老板的另一种方式之外,这一论点对现有的关于工作场所民主的共和主义和相关平等主义讨论又有什么补充呢?为了回答这个问题,让我们仔细看看为什么各种各样的观点反对工作场所不平等的权力关系。共和党人反对公司内部的权力不平等,因为它们构成了统治,也就是说,这是一种特别令人反感的人际关系,其最极端的形式是主人和奴隶之间的关系(McCammon, 2015)。相比之下,工人与社会关系的论点与统治无关;事实上,首先,它甚至与员工与老板的关系无关。首先,它反对工人无力维持他们与社会的良好道德秩序,因为这妨碍了他们对社会其他人表达足够的关心和尊重。如果这种无力感是由老板对员工的权力不平等造成的,那么该论点也反对这种权力不平等。但这并不预设这种权力不平等构成统治。这并不是说它不构成统治。也许是这样。如果是这样,那么共和党人就有理由反对它。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信