Interdisciplinary materialism and the task of critical institutionalism

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Hubertus Buchstein
{"title":"Interdisciplinary materialism and the task of critical institutionalism","authors":"Hubertus Buchstein","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12721","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>My first encounter with Horkheimer's seminal <span>1931</span> speech “The Present Situation of Social Philosophy and the Tasks of an Institute for Social Research” dates back to 1981 when I was struggling as a young student to read the final chapters of Jürgen Habermas's just published <i>Theory of Communicative Action</i>. Habermas made a strong case for Horkheimer's program of interdisciplinary materialism in his book. He reconstructed Horkheimer's original program and presented an ambitious update (see Habermas, <span>1987</span>, pp. 374–403). This encouraged me to read Horkheimer's famous speech of January 1931 and became the inspirational starting point for my ongoing interest in the history of the Frankfurt School.</p><p>The primary reason for the appeal of the classical Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School until today is that while it remains within a Marxist framework, it contrasted the economism of Marxist orthodoxy. It restored an autonomous logic to the domains that orthodox Marxism qualified as “superstructure.” This perspective yields inspiring findings in cultural theory and social psychology to this day. Yet in the early period of the Frankfurt School, the inner circle around Horkheimer did not achieve comparable results; at no point did this circle elaborate a theory of the political or of political institutions. This shortcoming dates back to the very beginnings of the Frankfurt School, to Horkheimer's programmatic inaugural speech as the new director of <i>Institut für Sozialforschung</i> (IfS) of <span>1931</span> in particular.</p><p>When Horkheimer enumerated the subdisciplines of interdisciplinary materialism in his speech, the absence of political science was striking. He defined social philosophy as the philosophical interpretation of human beings as members of a community; social philosophy must therefore primarily concern itself with the social existence of human beings. Horkheimer named “the state” and the “law” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 25) first in the list of social phenomena, even above economy and religion. He dug deeper in his discussion of social philosophy with an examination of Hegel's theory of objective spirit by criticizing Hegel's idea that the state could serve as a solution to integrate the conflicts of capitalist society (see Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, pp. 26–28). He included “the state” and “political association” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 31) as part of the investigation of the ways in which people live together.</p><p>In his following deliberations about the “ongoing dialectical permeation and evolution of philosophical theory and empirical-scientific praxis” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 29), however, Horkheimer quickly lost sight of political associations and the state. In his list of the scientific disciplines that are supposed to participate in socio-philosophical research, <i>Staatswissenschaft</i> and <i>Wissenschaft von der Politik</i>—as the discipline newly emerging at some universities in the German <i>Reich</i> was called at the time—are simply absent. Next to philosophers, sociologists, historians, and psychologists only “political economists” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 32) are briefly mentioned. Neither the state apparatus, nor political associations like parties or interest groups, parliaments, elections, or political debates are mentioned even once. The “law” as a research topic gets minimized among “specific areas of culture” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 33) in the final paragraphs of his speech, echoing the traditional Marxist view of law and politics as elements of the “superstructure.” This kind of absence of studies about the state and political associations also stands out in Horkheimer's lists of the research topics he considered most pressing in the preface of the first issue of <i>Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung</i> (see Horkheimer, <span>1932</span>) and in the preface of <i>Studien über Autorität und Familie</i> (Studies on Authority and Family, see Horkheimer, <span>1936</span>, pp. 329–330). This absence is also echoed in Walter Benjamin's favorable portrait of the IfS, written for an audience of German-speaking exiles (see Benjamin, <span>1938</span>, p. 519).</p><p>In my view, there is a systematic reason for this thematic gap, besides motives stemming from the personal disgust with current politics characteristic of the inner circle of the Institute. With the dominant focus of social philosophy on capitalist “society” as the fundamental analytic category, it seemed only natural for him to transform potential topics of political science into questions of sociology and social psychology. According to the assumption behind this approach, society is held together less by political institutions and more by the glue of culture and psychological dispositions.</p><p>This perspective continued in Horkheimer's two famous programmatic essays published in 1937. In “Traditionelle und kritische Theorie” (Traditional and Critical Theory) and in “Philosophie und kritische Theorie” (Philosophy and Critical Theory), he outlined the Institute's interdisciplinary work on a comprehensive theory of the “historical course of society as a whole” (Horkheimer, <span>1937b</span>, p. 247). Dismissing works by “students of political science” (Horkheimer, <span>1937a</span>, p. 222)—characterized as an academic discipline with a limited intellectual horizon—he went as far as to postulate a direct “dependence of politics on the economy” (Horkheimer, <span>1937b</span>, p. 271).</p><p>At the time when Horkheimer gave his speech, it was Hermann Heller who became a colleague at the University of Frankfurt in the following year, who acknowledged the “relative autonomy” of political institutions. He propagated political science as an academic discipline that is focused on the “description, explanation and criticism of political phenomena” (Heller, <span>1934</span>, p. 227). Since the late 1930s, three members of the “periphery” (Honneth, <span>1987</span>, p. 350) of the Frankfurt School in exile—Franz L. Neumann, Otto Kirchheimer, and Arkadij Gurland—followed Heller's impulse, alas with no success at the IfS.</p><p>But there is more to Horkheimer's inaugural speech than its deficits about politics. His diagnosis that the vision of an “individualistic society” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 28) has replaced the old Hegelian metaphysics of the objective spirit provides the starting point for an alternative way to renovate Critical Theory. Horkheimer's statement that the disappointment of the belief in the pre-stabilized harmony of individual interests will take “revenge” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 28) has particular relevance for politics in our times.</p><p>The most radical version of Horkheimer's statement today is presented by Rational Choice. Rational choice, of all things! From the perspective of classical Critical Theory, Rational Choice is the incarnation of fetishized reification and instrumental rationality. In my view, such clear-cut opposition between Critical Theory and Rational Choice is outdated and deserves to be revised.<sup>1</sup> Mancur Olson's insight about the collective irrationality of individual rational behavior (Olson, <span>1965</span>), Amartya Sen's description of the “rational fool” (Sen, <span>1977</span>), and Jon Elster's reflections on the rational boundaries of rational decision-making (Elster, <span>2002</span>)—to mention just a few landmark contributions in this tradition of immanent critique—make it possible to turn Rational Choice into a valuable instrument of Critical Theory.</p><p>Like Critical Theory, Rational Choice has a materialistic approach, because it assumes egoistic, mostly materialistic actor preferences. In addition, the methodological individualism of Rational Choice permits to reconstruct the collective irrationalities and social disasters to which the unrestricted aggregation of individual rational calculations leads. The selective use of Rational Choice for Critical Theory provides a way to transfer the insight of Horkheimer's criticism of the naïve optimism in Hegel's creation of the state out of “the medley of arbitrariness” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 27) in capitalist society into the framework of his <i>Dialectic of Enlightenment</i> and his <i>Critique of Instrumental Reason</i> about the pathologies of instrumental rationality.</p><p>The best-known constellation in Rational Choice theory for the production of collective irrationalities is the Prisoners’ Dilemma (PD) game. PD constellations have been diagnosed in many areas in the field of political science (from trade unions’ organizing problems to international disarmament and global climate policy). The PD game represents a constellation in which all actors involved are forced to depart from their ideally preferred preference. Thus, the PD constellation refers to dividing the concept of subjective interests into a dualism of preferences.<sup>2</sup> The PD payoff matrix forces rational individual actors to orient themselves toward what I call “real preferences,” which rank below their “ideal preferences”—both her or his own and those of all other players in the game.</p><p>The question arises: Under which conditions may ideal preferences trump real preferences? In the case of the PD game, individual actors orient toward their ideal preferences if they have reasons to expect that all (or at least most) other actors will also act cooperatively. Already in 1984, Robert Axelrod explained in his seminal computer tournaments how a series of repeated, iterative games produces a new starting point to overcome the PD. If we follow Axelrod's tested theory of iterative games,<sup>3</sup> then an actor can attain this guarantee—or at least justifiable grounds for it—within the instrumentally rational mode of action only if it is not a one-time game, but repeated games with an indeterminate or infinite time horizon.</p><p>The best strategy for solving the PD in iterative games is tit-for-tat. Tit-for-tat means that an actor selects a strategy of strict reciprocity for solving the game, responding to other players’ cooperation with cooperation and to their non-cooperation with non-cooperation. The tit-for-tat strategy intentionally takes the risk of making the first cooperative step. Its proponents initially behave according to their ideal preferences, yet not out of a virtuous motivation, human kindness, or other moral considerations, but out of the egoistic calculation of sending a clear signal to the other party to nudge it toward choosing its own ideal preferences. Only when the other player refuses to cooperate in response (real preference) does the first player react by switching to her or his real preference, thus employing a tit-for-tat strategy. The appeal of the strategy described lies in the fact that tests comparing it with all the other possible game strategies show it to be not only the morally sympathetic one but also the best in terms of positive payoffs. Following the work of Axelrod, tit-for-tat is one of the rare cases in which justness and self-interests coincide. In the context of my line of argument, tit-for-tat in iterative games describes a kind of “ideal game situation.” It corresponds to the case in which, in a world of egoists without a central supervisory body, ideal and real preferences become identical. The ideal game situation offers a normative point of reference without placing high ethical or moral standards on the actors’ orientations in an “individualistic society” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 28).</p><p>A critical reading of Rational Choice teaches an important lesson for Critical Theory: The political institutions of modern mass democracy are not organized in a way that motivates people to cooperate and to form and follow preferences that can be considered responsible (and thus morally defensible)—in other words, preferences that do not provide grounds for regrets in retrospect. Instead, political institutions should encourage individual censorship over those preferences that are less rational in terms of their political or social consequences—i.e., preference formation in a kind of mode of anticipated retrospect.</p><p>Whereas Horkheimer's approach later led him to the vision of an encompassing “theory of society” (Horkheimer, <span>1937a</span>), the research program of Critical Institutionalism follows a different line in his speech, which is his prompt in the final sections to “keep in touch with reality” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 35) and to use “the experience of practitioners” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 35). Critical Institutionalism takes on the practical task to identify alternative institutional arrangements for modern democracies which encourage the formation and articulation of ideal preferences. The rich literature on aleatory democracy and citizen juries provides some examples of political institutions that encourage auto-paternalistic preference formation and articulation (see Buchstein, <span>2019</span>).</p><p>At the very beginning of his speech, Horkheimer stated that due to the present situation in the sciences, “the traditional boundaries between disciplines are in question” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 25) and that one does not yet know where they might be drawn in the future. He also suggested “to find new methods” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 32) for critical social research and explicitly mentioned the work of “political economists” (Horkheimer, <span>1931</span>, p. 32) in this context. I consider my proposal to make selective use of Rational Choice as an unorthodox way to follow his suggestion.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"30 4","pages":"414-418"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-12-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12721","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12721","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

My first encounter with Horkheimer's seminal 1931 speech “The Present Situation of Social Philosophy and the Tasks of an Institute for Social Research” dates back to 1981 when I was struggling as a young student to read the final chapters of Jürgen Habermas's just published Theory of Communicative Action. Habermas made a strong case for Horkheimer's program of interdisciplinary materialism in his book. He reconstructed Horkheimer's original program and presented an ambitious update (see Habermas, 1987, pp. 374–403). This encouraged me to read Horkheimer's famous speech of January 1931 and became the inspirational starting point for my ongoing interest in the history of the Frankfurt School.

The primary reason for the appeal of the classical Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School until today is that while it remains within a Marxist framework, it contrasted the economism of Marxist orthodoxy. It restored an autonomous logic to the domains that orthodox Marxism qualified as “superstructure.” This perspective yields inspiring findings in cultural theory and social psychology to this day. Yet in the early period of the Frankfurt School, the inner circle around Horkheimer did not achieve comparable results; at no point did this circle elaborate a theory of the political or of political institutions. This shortcoming dates back to the very beginnings of the Frankfurt School, to Horkheimer's programmatic inaugural speech as the new director of Institut für Sozialforschung (IfS) of 1931 in particular.

When Horkheimer enumerated the subdisciplines of interdisciplinary materialism in his speech, the absence of political science was striking. He defined social philosophy as the philosophical interpretation of human beings as members of a community; social philosophy must therefore primarily concern itself with the social existence of human beings. Horkheimer named “the state” and the “law” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 25) first in the list of social phenomena, even above economy and religion. He dug deeper in his discussion of social philosophy with an examination of Hegel's theory of objective spirit by criticizing Hegel's idea that the state could serve as a solution to integrate the conflicts of capitalist society (see Horkheimer, 1931, pp. 26–28). He included “the state” and “political association” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 31) as part of the investigation of the ways in which people live together.

In his following deliberations about the “ongoing dialectical permeation and evolution of philosophical theory and empirical-scientific praxis” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 29), however, Horkheimer quickly lost sight of political associations and the state. In his list of the scientific disciplines that are supposed to participate in socio-philosophical research, Staatswissenschaft and Wissenschaft von der Politik—as the discipline newly emerging at some universities in the German Reich was called at the time—are simply absent. Next to philosophers, sociologists, historians, and psychologists only “political economists” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 32) are briefly mentioned. Neither the state apparatus, nor political associations like parties or interest groups, parliaments, elections, or political debates are mentioned even once. The “law” as a research topic gets minimized among “specific areas of culture” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 33) in the final paragraphs of his speech, echoing the traditional Marxist view of law and politics as elements of the “superstructure.” This kind of absence of studies about the state and political associations also stands out in Horkheimer's lists of the research topics he considered most pressing in the preface of the first issue of Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung (see Horkheimer, 1932) and in the preface of Studien über Autorität und Familie (Studies on Authority and Family, see Horkheimer, 1936, pp. 329–330). This absence is also echoed in Walter Benjamin's favorable portrait of the IfS, written for an audience of German-speaking exiles (see Benjamin, 1938, p. 519).

In my view, there is a systematic reason for this thematic gap, besides motives stemming from the personal disgust with current politics characteristic of the inner circle of the Institute. With the dominant focus of social philosophy on capitalist “society” as the fundamental analytic category, it seemed only natural for him to transform potential topics of political science into questions of sociology and social psychology. According to the assumption behind this approach, society is held together less by political institutions and more by the glue of culture and psychological dispositions.

This perspective continued in Horkheimer's two famous programmatic essays published in 1937. In “Traditionelle und kritische Theorie” (Traditional and Critical Theory) and in “Philosophie und kritische Theorie” (Philosophy and Critical Theory), he outlined the Institute's interdisciplinary work on a comprehensive theory of the “historical course of society as a whole” (Horkheimer, 1937b, p. 247). Dismissing works by “students of political science” (Horkheimer, 1937a, p. 222)—characterized as an academic discipline with a limited intellectual horizon—he went as far as to postulate a direct “dependence of politics on the economy” (Horkheimer, 1937b, p. 271).

At the time when Horkheimer gave his speech, it was Hermann Heller who became a colleague at the University of Frankfurt in the following year, who acknowledged the “relative autonomy” of political institutions. He propagated political science as an academic discipline that is focused on the “description, explanation and criticism of political phenomena” (Heller, 1934, p. 227). Since the late 1930s, three members of the “periphery” (Honneth, 1987, p. 350) of the Frankfurt School in exile—Franz L. Neumann, Otto Kirchheimer, and Arkadij Gurland—followed Heller's impulse, alas with no success at the IfS.

But there is more to Horkheimer's inaugural speech than its deficits about politics. His diagnosis that the vision of an “individualistic society” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 28) has replaced the old Hegelian metaphysics of the objective spirit provides the starting point for an alternative way to renovate Critical Theory. Horkheimer's statement that the disappointment of the belief in the pre-stabilized harmony of individual interests will take “revenge” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 28) has particular relevance for politics in our times.

The most radical version of Horkheimer's statement today is presented by Rational Choice. Rational choice, of all things! From the perspective of classical Critical Theory, Rational Choice is the incarnation of fetishized reification and instrumental rationality. In my view, such clear-cut opposition between Critical Theory and Rational Choice is outdated and deserves to be revised.1 Mancur Olson's insight about the collective irrationality of individual rational behavior (Olson, 1965), Amartya Sen's description of the “rational fool” (Sen, 1977), and Jon Elster's reflections on the rational boundaries of rational decision-making (Elster, 2002)—to mention just a few landmark contributions in this tradition of immanent critique—make it possible to turn Rational Choice into a valuable instrument of Critical Theory.

Like Critical Theory, Rational Choice has a materialistic approach, because it assumes egoistic, mostly materialistic actor preferences. In addition, the methodological individualism of Rational Choice permits to reconstruct the collective irrationalities and social disasters to which the unrestricted aggregation of individual rational calculations leads. The selective use of Rational Choice for Critical Theory provides a way to transfer the insight of Horkheimer's criticism of the naïve optimism in Hegel's creation of the state out of “the medley of arbitrariness” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 27) in capitalist society into the framework of his Dialectic of Enlightenment and his Critique of Instrumental Reason about the pathologies of instrumental rationality.

The best-known constellation in Rational Choice theory for the production of collective irrationalities is the Prisoners’ Dilemma (PD) game. PD constellations have been diagnosed in many areas in the field of political science (from trade unions’ organizing problems to international disarmament and global climate policy). The PD game represents a constellation in which all actors involved are forced to depart from their ideally preferred preference. Thus, the PD constellation refers to dividing the concept of subjective interests into a dualism of preferences.2 The PD payoff matrix forces rational individual actors to orient themselves toward what I call “real preferences,” which rank below their “ideal preferences”—both her or his own and those of all other players in the game.

The question arises: Under which conditions may ideal preferences trump real preferences? In the case of the PD game, individual actors orient toward their ideal preferences if they have reasons to expect that all (or at least most) other actors will also act cooperatively. Already in 1984, Robert Axelrod explained in his seminal computer tournaments how a series of repeated, iterative games produces a new starting point to overcome the PD. If we follow Axelrod's tested theory of iterative games,3 then an actor can attain this guarantee—or at least justifiable grounds for it—within the instrumentally rational mode of action only if it is not a one-time game, but repeated games with an indeterminate or infinite time horizon.

The best strategy for solving the PD in iterative games is tit-for-tat. Tit-for-tat means that an actor selects a strategy of strict reciprocity for solving the game, responding to other players’ cooperation with cooperation and to their non-cooperation with non-cooperation. The tit-for-tat strategy intentionally takes the risk of making the first cooperative step. Its proponents initially behave according to their ideal preferences, yet not out of a virtuous motivation, human kindness, or other moral considerations, but out of the egoistic calculation of sending a clear signal to the other party to nudge it toward choosing its own ideal preferences. Only when the other player refuses to cooperate in response (real preference) does the first player react by switching to her or his real preference, thus employing a tit-for-tat strategy. The appeal of the strategy described lies in the fact that tests comparing it with all the other possible game strategies show it to be not only the morally sympathetic one but also the best in terms of positive payoffs. Following the work of Axelrod, tit-for-tat is one of the rare cases in which justness and self-interests coincide. In the context of my line of argument, tit-for-tat in iterative games describes a kind of “ideal game situation.” It corresponds to the case in which, in a world of egoists without a central supervisory body, ideal and real preferences become identical. The ideal game situation offers a normative point of reference without placing high ethical or moral standards on the actors’ orientations in an “individualistic society” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 28).

A critical reading of Rational Choice teaches an important lesson for Critical Theory: The political institutions of modern mass democracy are not organized in a way that motivates people to cooperate and to form and follow preferences that can be considered responsible (and thus morally defensible)—in other words, preferences that do not provide grounds for regrets in retrospect. Instead, political institutions should encourage individual censorship over those preferences that are less rational in terms of their political or social consequences—i.e., preference formation in a kind of mode of anticipated retrospect.

Whereas Horkheimer's approach later led him to the vision of an encompassing “theory of society” (Horkheimer, 1937a), the research program of Critical Institutionalism follows a different line in his speech, which is his prompt in the final sections to “keep in touch with reality” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 35) and to use “the experience of practitioners” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 35). Critical Institutionalism takes on the practical task to identify alternative institutional arrangements for modern democracies which encourage the formation and articulation of ideal preferences. The rich literature on aleatory democracy and citizen juries provides some examples of political institutions that encourage auto-paternalistic preference formation and articulation (see Buchstein, 2019).

At the very beginning of his speech, Horkheimer stated that due to the present situation in the sciences, “the traditional boundaries between disciplines are in question” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 25) and that one does not yet know where they might be drawn in the future. He also suggested “to find new methods” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 32) for critical social research and explicitly mentioned the work of “political economists” (Horkheimer, 1931, p. 32) in this context. I consider my proposal to make selective use of Rational Choice as an unorthodox way to follow his suggestion.

跨学科唯物主义与批判制度主义的任务
我第一次接触霍克海默1931年的开创性演讲“社会哲学的现状和社会研究所的任务”要追溯到1981年,当时我还是一个年轻的学生,正在努力阅读j<s:1>根·哈贝马斯刚刚出版的《交往行为理论》的最后几章。哈贝马斯在他的书中有力地论证了霍克海默的跨学科唯物主义。他重建了霍克海默的原始计划,并提出了一个雄心勃勃的更新(见哈贝马斯,1987,第374-403页)。这鼓励我阅读霍克海默1931年1月的著名演讲,并成为我对法兰克福学派历史感兴趣的鼓舞人心的起点。法兰克福学派的经典批判理论直到今天仍然具有吸引力的主要原因是,尽管它仍然在马克思主义框架内,但它与马克思主义正统的经济主义形成了对比。它为正统马克思主义称之为“上层建筑”的领域恢复了一种自主逻辑。这一观点至今仍在文化理论和社会心理学中产生了鼓舞人心的发现。然而,在法兰克福学派的早期,霍克海默周围的小圈子并没有取得类似的成果;这个圈子从来没有详细阐述过政治或政治制度的理论。这一缺陷可以追溯到法兰克福学派之初,尤其是在1931年,霍克海默作为<s:1>社会科学研究所(IfS)新任所长发表的纲领性就职演说。当霍克海默在他的演讲中列举跨学科唯物主义的分支学科时,政治科学的缺失令人震惊。他将社会哲学定义为对作为共同体成员的人类的哲学解释;因此,社会哲学必须首先关注人类的社会存在。霍克海默将“国家”和“法律”(霍克海默,1931,第25页)列为社会现象之首,甚至高于经济和宗教。他对黑格尔的客观精神理论进行了更深入的探讨,批评了黑格尔认为国家可以作为整合资本主义社会冲突的解决方案的观点(见霍克海默,1931,第26-28页)。他把“国家”和“政治协会”(霍克海默,1931年,第31页)作为研究人们共同生活方式的一部分。然而,在他接下来关于“哲学理论和经验科学实践的持续辩证渗透和演变”的思考中(霍克海默,1931,第29页),霍克海默很快就忽视了政治协会和国家。在他列出的应该参与社会哲学研究的科学学科清单中,当时在德意志帝国的一些大学中新兴的学科Staatswissenschaft和Wissenschaft von der politit根本没有出现。在哲学家、社会学家、历史学家和心理学家之后,只有“政治经济学家”(霍克海默,1931年,第32页)被简单地提到。国家机器、政党或利益集团等政治团体、议会、选举或政治辩论都没有被提及。在他演讲的最后几段,“法律”作为一个研究课题在“特定的文化领域”中被最小化(霍克海默,1931,第33页),呼应了传统的马克思主义观点,即法律和政治是“上层建筑”的要素。这种对国家和政治协会研究的缺失,在霍克海默在《社会研究》(Zeitschrift fr Sozialforschung)第一期的序言(见霍克海默,1932年)和《studen ber Autorität und Familie》(《权威与家庭研究》,见霍克海默,1936年,第329-330页)的序言中列出的他认为最紧迫的研究课题中也很突出。沃尔特·本雅明(Walter Benjamin)为讲德语的流亡者撰写的对IfS的正面描述也反映了这种缺失(见本杰明,1938,第519页)。在我看来,除了研究所内部圈子对当前政治的个人厌恶的动机外,这种主题差距还有系统的原因。由于社会哲学的主要焦点是资本主义“社会”,这是基本的分析范畴,对他来说,将潜在的政治学主题转化为社会学和社会心理学问题似乎是很自然的。根据这种方法背后的假设,社会不是由政治制度维系的,而是由文化和心理倾向的粘合剂维系的。霍克海默1937年发表的两篇著名的纲领性论文延续了这一观点。 在《传统与批判理论》(Traditionelle und kritische Theorie)和《哲学与批判理论》(Philosophie und kritische Theorie)中,他概述了该研究所在“整个社会的历史进程”综合理论方面的跨学科工作(霍克海默,1937年b期,第247页)。他对“政治学学生”(霍克海默,1937年a版,第222页)的著作不屑一顾,认为这是一门知识视野有限的学术学科,他甚至假设“政治依赖于经济”(霍克海默,1937年b版,第271页)。在霍克海默发表演讲时,次年成为法兰克福大学同事的赫尔曼·海勒(Hermann Heller)承认了政治机构的“相对自主性”。他将政治学宣传为一门专注于“对政治现象的描述、解释和批评”的学术学科(Heller, 1934,第227页)。自20世纪30年代末以来,流亡的法兰克福学派“外围”(Honneth, 1987, p. 350)的三位成员——franz L. Neumann、Otto Kirchheimer和Arkadij gurland——追随了海勒的冲动,可惜在IfS没有取得成功。但在霍克海默的就职演说中,除了政治赤字之外,还有更多内容。他对“个人主义社会”的看法(霍克海默,1931,第28页)的诊断已经取代了旧的客观精神的黑格尔形而上学,为更新批判理论的另一种方式提供了起点。霍克海默关于对个人利益预先稳定的和谐的信念的失望将采取“报复”的声明(霍克海默,1931,第28页)与我们这个时代的政治特别相关。今天,《理性选择》提出了霍克海默言论最激进的版本。一切都是理性的选择!从古典批判理论的角度看,《理性选择》是拜物化理性和工具理性的化身。在我看来,这种批判理论与理性选择的鲜明对立已经过时,值得修改Mancur Olson对个人理性行为的集体非理性的洞见(Olson, 1965), Amartya Sen对“理性傻瓜”的描述(Sen, 1977),以及Jon Elster对理性决策的理性边界的反思(Elster, 2002)——这些都是内在批判传统中具有里程碑意义的贡献——使理性选择成为批判理论的宝贵工具成为可能。像批判理论一样,理性选择也有唯物主义的方法,因为它假设了自私的,主要是唯物主义的行为者偏好。此外,理性选择的方法论个人主义允许重建集体非理性和社会灾难,这些非理性和社会灾难是由不受限制的个人理性计算的聚集导致的。在批判理论中选择性地使用《理性选择》提供了一种方法,可以将霍克海默对资本主义社会中黑格尔从“随意性的混合”中创造国家的naïve乐观主义(霍克海默,1931,第27页)的批评见解,转移到他的《启蒙辩证法》和《工具理性批判》关于工具理性病态的框架中。在理性选择理论中,最著名的关于集体非理性产生的组合是囚徒困境(PD)博弈。PD星座已经在政治学领域的许多领域被诊断出来(从工会的组织问题到国际裁军和全球气候政策)。PD博弈代表了一个星座,在这个星座中,所有参与者都被迫偏离他们的理想偏好。因此,PD星座指的是将主观兴趣的概念划分为偏好的二元论PD收益矩阵迫使理性个体行为者将自己定位于我所说的“真实偏好”,它的排名低于他们的“理想偏好”——无论是她或他自己的偏好还是游戏中所有其他参与者的偏好。问题来了:在什么条件下,理想偏好会胜过真实偏好?在PD博弈中,如果个体行为者有理由期望所有(或至少大多数)其他行为者也会合作行事,他们就会倾向于自己的理想偏好。早在1984年,Robert Axelrod就在他的开创性计算机锦标赛中解释了一系列重复的、迭代的游戏是如何创造出克服PD的新起点的。如果我们遵循阿克塞尔罗德的迭代博弈理论,那么参与者就可以在工具理性的行动模式中获得这种保证,或者至少是合理的理由,除非它不是一次性的游戏,而是具有不确定或无限时间范围的重复游戏。在迭代游戏中解决PD的最佳策略便是以牙还牙。 “以牙还牙”是指参与者选择严格互惠的策略来解决博弈,以合作回应其他参与者的合作,以不合作回应其他参与者的不合作。以牙还牙的策略有意冒着迈出合作第一步的风险。它的支持者最初根据他们的理想偏好行事,但不是出于善良的动机,人类的善良,或其他道德考虑,而是出于自私的计算,向另一方发出明确的信号,推动其选择自己的理想偏好。只有当另一个玩家拒绝合作(真实偏好)时,第一个玩家才会转向自己的真实偏好,从而采用针锋相对的策略。所描述的策略的吸引力在于,将其与所有其他可能的博弈策略进行比较的测试表明,它不仅在道德上令人同情,而且在正收益方面也是最好的。在阿克塞尔罗德的研究之后,以牙还牙是正义和自身利益相一致的罕见案例之一。在我的论述中,迭代游戏中的针锋相对描述了一种“理想的游戏情境”。它对应的情况是,在一个没有中央监督机构的利己主义者的世界里,理想偏好和现实偏好变得相同。理想的游戏情境提供了一个规范性的参考点,而不会在“个人主义社会”中对参与者的行为取向设置很高的伦理或道德标准。对《理性选择》的批判性解读给批判理论上了重要的一课:现代大众民主的政治制度并没有以一种激励人们合作、形成和遵循可被认为是负责任的(因此在道德上是可辩护的)偏好的方式组织起来——换句话说,这种偏好不会让人事后后悔。相反,政治机构应该鼓励个人审查,而不是那些在政治或社会后果方面不太理性的偏好。,偏好形成一种预期的回顾模式。尽管霍克海默的方法后来使他产生了一个包含“社会理论”的愿景(霍克海默,1937),但批判制度主义的研究计划在他的演讲中遵循了一条不同的路线,这是他在最后几节中提示“与现实保持联系”(霍克海默,1931,第35页)并使用“实践者的经验”(霍克海默,1931,第35页)。批判制度主义承担的实际任务是确定现代民主国家的其他制度安排,这些安排鼓励理想偏好的形成和表达。关于选择性民主和公民陪审团的丰富文献提供了一些鼓励自动家长式偏好形成和表达的政治制度的例子(见Buchstein, 2019)。在演讲的一开始,霍克海默就表示,由于科学的现状,“学科之间的传统界限受到质疑”(霍克海默,1931,第25页),而且人们还不知道未来会在哪里划定这些界限。他还建议为批判性社会研究“寻找新的方法”(霍克海默,1931年,第32页),并在此背景下明确提到“政治经济学家”(霍克海默,1931年,第32页)的工作。我认为我有选择地使用《理性选择》的建议是遵循他的建议的一种非正统的方式。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信