Rethinking Critique and Theory

IF 1.2 Q3 POLITICAL SCIENCE
Martin Saar
{"title":"Rethinking Critique and Theory","authors":"Martin Saar","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12731","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>A distance of exactly 100 years separates our present from the intellectual and institutional context in which talking of “critical” theory, as distinct from “traditional” theory, began to play the identity-forming role to which today's discussion owes its topic. Reflecting not only on the possible continuity but also on this factual distance can be helpful for gaining a clearer perspective of what it can mean to connect to this program today. For, first, it is only in a long history of the impact of certain texts, themes, and a certain style of theory that the impression of unity or coherence of this tradition has emerged, of which there was hardly a trace in the first decades. Neither the objectives of the Institute for Social Research in its founding phase nor the personal composition of the circle of (exclusively male) scholars around Max Horkheimer had made such a unity likely beyond a shared commitment to a heterodox, non-party Marxism.</p><p>The internal discussions in the Institute, in the pages of the <i>Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung</i> and its successor organs, and in scholarly communication with international colleagues were rather diverse and pluralistic. The disputes about the right relation to Marx and Marxism, to “bourgeois” philosophy, to psychoanalysis, to culture, to the Soviet Union, or to the question of revolution from the 1930s to the 1960s were so fierce because the one consensual line was not given and the protagonists of the debates did not agree on much. It would be rather anachronistic to assume coherence retrospectively, where a dynamic, ever-changing context of discussions had formed.</p><p>Second, in these 100 years, during which almost no stone has been left unturned in the social, cultural, and technological world, the contexts and conditions of both theory formation in general and of political–critical intervention in particular have changed profoundly. Already between the prewar and the postwar Institute, while the postal address remained the same, there were such profound differences in material endowment, symbolic significance, public efficacy, and embeddedness in academic context that the theoretical and political practice possible in each case was of a fundamentally different form. That this also affects the internal development of academic research should be evident, for it meant something different around 1930, around 1950, and around 1965 to refer to the general state of the social sciences, to react to international developments, or to work in an interdisciplinary or transdisciplinary way. That this applies <i>a fortiori</i> to the contrast with the position around 2024 is to be expected. It might therefore be unproductive to create the suggestion of a seamless continuity and availability of an earlier academic-political practice, which was, after all, subject to its own situational contextual restrictions and potentials.</p><p>These skeptical remarks are intended to ward off all too great expectations that essential points could be identified for this theoretical–political context, which would then clearly determine who belongs and who does not and who is today more authentically taking on this heritage than others. Those who (like myself) today emphasize the internal plurality of the original institutional and personal context and the historical discontinuity of the surrounding conditions will certainly lose a sense of the solid identity or uniformity of a clear-cut paradigm (or an intellectual brand). Nevertheless, they might gain freedom in the possibility of taking up and carrying on certain elements from the main and the side paths of this tradition.</p><p>For it will make a difference whether in the quest for a Critical Theory today, one is guided by Horkheimer's plea for interdisciplinary materialism, by Adorno's early idea of an “interpretive” social philosophy, by Kirchheimer's and Pollock's materialist working through of law and economics, by Fromm's social psychology, by Kracauer's philosophy of culture, or by Benjamin's philosophy of history. This openness reflects itself in the problem of whether one should place the importance of Marx alongside or above that of Hegel, Weber, and Nietzsche as the vectors of influence for the first generation. Taking sides in these issues does not even address the question of whether it is not the shock stemming from the experience of the “rupture of civilization” (or <i>Zivilisationsbruch</i>, to use Dan Diner's term) that has inscribed itself as a central epistemic and political motif into this tradition of thought from the 1940s on that should be taken as the one unifying concern of this tradition to which the individual members reacted differently.</p><p>The freedom offered by this perception of a historical distance and of an openness of the paradigmatic profile lies in the possibility to consciously identify and appropriate individual motifs of Critical Theory without fearing to betray the supposedly binding shape of a uniform theoretical approach. Already hidden in the text corpus of the historical protagonists of this tradition lie threads of several different critical theories that can be drawn out in multiple ways into the present. These possibilities are by no means unlimited or arbitrary, for they are determined by a real and well-documented history of texts and authors. Into this history sometimes new positions hitherto marked as peripheral can be integrated (for example, the contributions of Bloch, Sohn-Rethel, Scholem, Negt, Sonnemann, and many others), thus highlighting other webs of the network, which can (but do not necessarily) make for particularly original new readings.</p><p>However, such reflections on the inner multiplicity of Critical Theory will remain tied to what occurs in all relevant texts as the main object: domination. One might say that any Critical Theory of the Frankfurt type begins with the premise or presupposition of the existence of social domination. The fact of social domination, to which in the eyes of his 1920s/1930s readers Marx had devoted the exemplary analysis in his theory of bourgeois society and its economic structures, thus indeed, forms a kind of “axiom”. However, how exactly this domination is constituted, on what it depends and who carries it, and in which media and procedures it functions lead again exactly into the midst of the inner-theoretical differences and divergences which make up the history of the theoretical Left in general.</p><p>Those who emphasize the above arguments for the internal plurality of the project of a critical social theory inscribed in its Frankfurt line of development and for the temporal distance from its body of theory and political possibilities can look with relative equanimity at some of the seemingly profound differences in the contemporary field of theory formation. If the heritage itself is already so diverse, there will also be more than one way to accept and continue it. Since the emphases have been divergent and contested from the beginning, the differences will tend to intensify as the theory continues to evolve, as more and more additional programmatic and conceptual options, including external ones, are added.</p><p>The fact that particularly fruitful developments in the history of Critical Theory's <i>Wirkungsgeschichte</i> for a certain time occurred in pedagogy and social psychology, others in the theory of the state and law, was no accident, but neither were they the only options. The high hopes directed at a synthesis of more functionalist social theories with the elements of earlier Critical Theory have presumably been exhausted, as has the euphoria with which a communication-theoretical grounding of earlier motifs was initially greeted. That reception, in general, had, from a certain point on, focused almost exclusively on the work of Jürgen Habermas, and that almost all debates about Critical Theory demanded partisanship for or against this particular contribution, has certainly tended to obscure the plural character of the overall enterprise, but this time, too, seems to have passed, for better or for worse.</p><p>Today's prominent proposals on how to actualize the basic mode of a Critical Theory, such as (to just refer to authors defining the German context) the more Hegelian-oriented theory of recognition of Axel Honneth, a more neo-Kantian grounded theory of justification of Rainer Forst, or a more comprehensive theory of forms of life and their internal normative dynamics of Rahel Jaeggi, can with quite some right claim to take up again specific central motifs of the tradition. The fact that authors as Robin Celikates have emphasized the connection to social movements and practices of resistance and disobedience represents an important counterpoint to some of the overly high-theoretical tendencies of the debate about the forms of critique, which was often conducted in a metatheoretical or methodological manner. The newly flared discussion of a fundamental critique of law, including the contributions by Christoph Menke and Daniel Loick can invoke motifs of the 1920s and 1930s, and yet, at the same time, has an urgency that can hardly be dismissed in an age of crumbling sovereignties and neo-authoritarian state practices. The trend to re-establish the critique of political economy as the central, perhaps even main, field of critical social theory, whether Marxist or not, can rightfully be seen as a necessary correction of a somewhat culturalist one-sidedness of recent decades. Moreover, it should not be forgotten that some of the most powerful positions of recent Critical Theory have emerged at the interface between feminist theory and political theory and have exerted enormous influence, thus already bending the centering on a narrow understanding of the Marxist legacy to a multidimensional or intersectional analysis that also encompasses different subject and identity lines.</p><p>The fact that more anthropologically based conceptions like the sociology of resonance of Hartmut Rosa, to refer to another prominent social theory in the German Debate, place themselves in this line might seem astonishing against the background of some of its premises, but because of its practical and diagnostic orientation, it cannot be completely rejected. The fact that in recent years more and more contributions referring back to the Frankfurt tradition have occurred in the field of radical democratic theory and theories of the political shows once again that the political and theoretical impact of a tradition is even more unpredictable and open than some expectations suggest.</p><p>Does this mean that all paradigmatic boundaries are blurred? In all these areas, the basic systematic operation remains crucial: Critical Theory in a very general sense takes place wherever philosophical and social-scientific analyses start from the intention of criticizing domination, and here, for many, the reference to the texts, authors, and models of thought of this tradition (in its narrower sense) offers itself as a resource, an inspiration, and a model. This promise of these resources can be illustrated with reference to two current discussions, in both of which voices from the context under discussion here are not absent but not particularly loud either, and for both, it can be argued that this tradition, in particular, could make promising contributions but will also benefit from complementary theoretical tools from other contexts.</p><p>It has taken several decades for the full force of the question of the afterlife of colonial and imperialist structures of Western-dominated modernity to be felt in scholarly and political debates, and not all potentially affected fields of scholarship have yet responded appropriately. Developments in recent years in particular have shown how this complex poses enormously difficult problems for which the classical disciplines of the humanities and social sciences are not always well equipped. How does one conceptualize the historical responsibility of entire cultural groups across centuries? What are the epistemic consequences of colonization? What might seem like a particular field of historical phenomena at first, which only came to consciousness in the era of decolonization in the postwar period, on closer inspection concerns the heart of the cultural and moral self-understanding of Western modernity.</p><p>Now it has become undeniable that precisely that process which has hitherto been understood primarily as a history of progress and liberation, namely, as intellectual enlightenment and political emancipation, is interwoven with exploitative expansion and dehumanizing subjugation. If, in other words, in historical reality, enlightenment and freedom, on the one hand, were essentially related to slavery and racism, on the other, it is no longer possible to tell the history of modernization in a unidirectional and triumphant way, and this equally affects political, economic, scientific, and intellectual history alike.</p><p>Such a readjustment cannot pass Critical Theory without leaving a trace, for this affects its own basic categories. Emancipation and defense against domination are its own urgent interests, and often enough Critical Theory has framed this task as an internal problem of European societies. Despite the internationalist and anti-imperialist elements in the history of Left theory, its theorists have also often remained representatives of a merely <i>Western</i> Marxism in a problematic sense, and the few references to non-European conditions do not provide a particularly favorable testimony here. The suspicion that Critical Theory itself embodies the methodological and political Eurocentrism that a <i>truly</i> cosmopolitan perspective on liberation would actually have to overcome is justified.</p><p>Yet, it is precisely in this tradition of thought that resources lie with which to respond to these problems, whether or not their authors might have intended it. Benjamin's partisanship for the perspective of the defeated in historiography, Adorno's and Horkheimer's insistence on the deep ambivalence of enlightenment ideals, and Marcuse's clear-sighted perception of the central role of the excluded and marginalized, whom the capitalist system cannot even properly exploit, are starting points for a radical self-critique of the Western liberation movements, which have yet to admit their own entanglement in domination elsewhere and thus should actually make way for an even more radical, decentered enlightenment and liberation. Critical Theory, perhaps <i>malgré soi</i>, was already partially thinking in this direction. In the urgently needed alliances today, even across geopolitical borders, Critical Theory can (and should) therefore, according to its own understanding, be an ally of the dominated wherever they are—and not a party offended by the accusation of Eurocentric complicity.</p><p>A comparable constellation can also be stated for a second topic. By now it should be generally evident that the problem of man-made climate change, threatening ecological catastrophes together with their political consequences, the irreversible extinction of species, and the accelerated destruction of future natural resources represent the most urgent challenge for political action and social awareness in the coming decades. Again, it has taken a long while for the human sciences to address this issue in its full breadth. In the meantime, debates about the Anthropocene and climate justice, sustainability and post-growth, human/animal/plant relations, and the critique of anthropocentrism, fossil capitalism, and geo-capitalism are receiving exactly the attention they deserve, and they even transcend long-established disciplinary boundaries, as basic theoretical and applied, technical, political, and cultural questions are being raised here at the same time.</p><p>Critical Theory has so far succeeded only sporadically in setting a particular agenda here, and often enough it looks as if it, too, would become the target of the accusation that it always thinks of politics and power only from the point of view of humans. Beyond the idea of a democracy of free and equal subjects, its conception of the goal of a liberated society remains, at least according to the first impression, astonishingly anthropocentric and unimaginative. This tradition also seems to have little to contribute to the question in which form contemporary communities could face the endangerment of their own survival. To admit that the exploitation of nature and environmental destruction were inscribed in the very functioning of capitalist modernity is just the first step.</p><p>Also here, as with the previous topic, it is true that Critical Theory already has produced concepts and models of thought whose relevance is perhaps only fully revealed today. The somewhat esoteric, speculative reflections of Adorno and Benjamin on mimesis and on the relationship of humans to inanimate nature, the persistent focus of the <i>Dialectic of Enlightenment</i> on the domination of inner and outer nature as the flip side of social domination, and the topos of “creative matter” from the history of German Idealism and materialism, which is enormously powerful in Bloch and in the very early Habermas, are just two first, absolutely relevant starting points here. From them, connections to the present conjuncture of the “New Materialism” and new holistic ontologies arise almost by themselves.</p><p>The fact that subject–object relations and their distortion and instrumentalization lie at the core of almost all problems concerning the human being, that being human is itself a question of mediations with the other, the non-human, forms a theoretical precondition on which one can build. The conviction that “domination” and “subjugation” are the names for relations on this fundamental, ontological level, and that the theme of power and politics itself is inscribed in the level of being, paves the way for the thematization of deep political relations, a politics of nature as well as an ecology of politics. From here it is only a small step to the expectation that on the basis of such, admittedly rather speculative motifs, helpful perspectives could be gained that might respond to the misery of the present, but also prefigure the possible splendor of a different, alternative relation to nature.</p><p>Critical Theory, as I imagine it, can take on these urgent problems of the present and respond to them, not in the mode of problem-solving, but in the mode of self-critical, persistent problematization of the structures of domination that come to bear in them. To this end, it uses all available theoretical insights that serve to see the world in all its divisions and contradictions more clearly in the face of a confusing and often enough paralyzing situation. This would be a possible realization of a problem-oriented, open-ended, cross-disciplinary program in which theory and practice do not merge, but challenge each other, passionately invested in forms of living, feeling, and acting that seek to escape the grip of powers and dominations without indulging in illusions of absolute freedom. This kind of theory, then as now, is all about finding the loopholes and spaces from which to see and experience that things could be different than they are under the spell of current regimes of domination.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"30 4","pages":"426-430"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-12-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12731","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12731","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

A distance of exactly 100 years separates our present from the intellectual and institutional context in which talking of “critical” theory, as distinct from “traditional” theory, began to play the identity-forming role to which today's discussion owes its topic. Reflecting not only on the possible continuity but also on this factual distance can be helpful for gaining a clearer perspective of what it can mean to connect to this program today. For, first, it is only in a long history of the impact of certain texts, themes, and a certain style of theory that the impression of unity or coherence of this tradition has emerged, of which there was hardly a trace in the first decades. Neither the objectives of the Institute for Social Research in its founding phase nor the personal composition of the circle of (exclusively male) scholars around Max Horkheimer had made such a unity likely beyond a shared commitment to a heterodox, non-party Marxism.

The internal discussions in the Institute, in the pages of the Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung and its successor organs, and in scholarly communication with international colleagues were rather diverse and pluralistic. The disputes about the right relation to Marx and Marxism, to “bourgeois” philosophy, to psychoanalysis, to culture, to the Soviet Union, or to the question of revolution from the 1930s to the 1960s were so fierce because the one consensual line was not given and the protagonists of the debates did not agree on much. It would be rather anachronistic to assume coherence retrospectively, where a dynamic, ever-changing context of discussions had formed.

Second, in these 100 years, during which almost no stone has been left unturned in the social, cultural, and technological world, the contexts and conditions of both theory formation in general and of political–critical intervention in particular have changed profoundly. Already between the prewar and the postwar Institute, while the postal address remained the same, there were such profound differences in material endowment, symbolic significance, public efficacy, and embeddedness in academic context that the theoretical and political practice possible in each case was of a fundamentally different form. That this also affects the internal development of academic research should be evident, for it meant something different around 1930, around 1950, and around 1965 to refer to the general state of the social sciences, to react to international developments, or to work in an interdisciplinary or transdisciplinary way. That this applies a fortiori to the contrast with the position around 2024 is to be expected. It might therefore be unproductive to create the suggestion of a seamless continuity and availability of an earlier academic-political practice, which was, after all, subject to its own situational contextual restrictions and potentials.

These skeptical remarks are intended to ward off all too great expectations that essential points could be identified for this theoretical–political context, which would then clearly determine who belongs and who does not and who is today more authentically taking on this heritage than others. Those who (like myself) today emphasize the internal plurality of the original institutional and personal context and the historical discontinuity of the surrounding conditions will certainly lose a sense of the solid identity or uniformity of a clear-cut paradigm (or an intellectual brand). Nevertheless, they might gain freedom in the possibility of taking up and carrying on certain elements from the main and the side paths of this tradition.

For it will make a difference whether in the quest for a Critical Theory today, one is guided by Horkheimer's plea for interdisciplinary materialism, by Adorno's early idea of an “interpretive” social philosophy, by Kirchheimer's and Pollock's materialist working through of law and economics, by Fromm's social psychology, by Kracauer's philosophy of culture, or by Benjamin's philosophy of history. This openness reflects itself in the problem of whether one should place the importance of Marx alongside or above that of Hegel, Weber, and Nietzsche as the vectors of influence for the first generation. Taking sides in these issues does not even address the question of whether it is not the shock stemming from the experience of the “rupture of civilization” (or Zivilisationsbruch, to use Dan Diner's term) that has inscribed itself as a central epistemic and political motif into this tradition of thought from the 1940s on that should be taken as the one unifying concern of this tradition to which the individual members reacted differently.

The freedom offered by this perception of a historical distance and of an openness of the paradigmatic profile lies in the possibility to consciously identify and appropriate individual motifs of Critical Theory without fearing to betray the supposedly binding shape of a uniform theoretical approach. Already hidden in the text corpus of the historical protagonists of this tradition lie threads of several different critical theories that can be drawn out in multiple ways into the present. These possibilities are by no means unlimited or arbitrary, for they are determined by a real and well-documented history of texts and authors. Into this history sometimes new positions hitherto marked as peripheral can be integrated (for example, the contributions of Bloch, Sohn-Rethel, Scholem, Negt, Sonnemann, and many others), thus highlighting other webs of the network, which can (but do not necessarily) make for particularly original new readings.

However, such reflections on the inner multiplicity of Critical Theory will remain tied to what occurs in all relevant texts as the main object: domination. One might say that any Critical Theory of the Frankfurt type begins with the premise or presupposition of the existence of social domination. The fact of social domination, to which in the eyes of his 1920s/1930s readers Marx had devoted the exemplary analysis in his theory of bourgeois society and its economic structures, thus indeed, forms a kind of “axiom”. However, how exactly this domination is constituted, on what it depends and who carries it, and in which media and procedures it functions lead again exactly into the midst of the inner-theoretical differences and divergences which make up the history of the theoretical Left in general.

Those who emphasize the above arguments for the internal plurality of the project of a critical social theory inscribed in its Frankfurt line of development and for the temporal distance from its body of theory and political possibilities can look with relative equanimity at some of the seemingly profound differences in the contemporary field of theory formation. If the heritage itself is already so diverse, there will also be more than one way to accept and continue it. Since the emphases have been divergent and contested from the beginning, the differences will tend to intensify as the theory continues to evolve, as more and more additional programmatic and conceptual options, including external ones, are added.

The fact that particularly fruitful developments in the history of Critical Theory's Wirkungsgeschichte for a certain time occurred in pedagogy and social psychology, others in the theory of the state and law, was no accident, but neither were they the only options. The high hopes directed at a synthesis of more functionalist social theories with the elements of earlier Critical Theory have presumably been exhausted, as has the euphoria with which a communication-theoretical grounding of earlier motifs was initially greeted. That reception, in general, had, from a certain point on, focused almost exclusively on the work of Jürgen Habermas, and that almost all debates about Critical Theory demanded partisanship for or against this particular contribution, has certainly tended to obscure the plural character of the overall enterprise, but this time, too, seems to have passed, for better or for worse.

Today's prominent proposals on how to actualize the basic mode of a Critical Theory, such as (to just refer to authors defining the German context) the more Hegelian-oriented theory of recognition of Axel Honneth, a more neo-Kantian grounded theory of justification of Rainer Forst, or a more comprehensive theory of forms of life and their internal normative dynamics of Rahel Jaeggi, can with quite some right claim to take up again specific central motifs of the tradition. The fact that authors as Robin Celikates have emphasized the connection to social movements and practices of resistance and disobedience represents an important counterpoint to some of the overly high-theoretical tendencies of the debate about the forms of critique, which was often conducted in a metatheoretical or methodological manner. The newly flared discussion of a fundamental critique of law, including the contributions by Christoph Menke and Daniel Loick can invoke motifs of the 1920s and 1930s, and yet, at the same time, has an urgency that can hardly be dismissed in an age of crumbling sovereignties and neo-authoritarian state practices. The trend to re-establish the critique of political economy as the central, perhaps even main, field of critical social theory, whether Marxist or not, can rightfully be seen as a necessary correction of a somewhat culturalist one-sidedness of recent decades. Moreover, it should not be forgotten that some of the most powerful positions of recent Critical Theory have emerged at the interface between feminist theory and political theory and have exerted enormous influence, thus already bending the centering on a narrow understanding of the Marxist legacy to a multidimensional or intersectional analysis that also encompasses different subject and identity lines.

The fact that more anthropologically based conceptions like the sociology of resonance of Hartmut Rosa, to refer to another prominent social theory in the German Debate, place themselves in this line might seem astonishing against the background of some of its premises, but because of its practical and diagnostic orientation, it cannot be completely rejected. The fact that in recent years more and more contributions referring back to the Frankfurt tradition have occurred in the field of radical democratic theory and theories of the political shows once again that the political and theoretical impact of a tradition is even more unpredictable and open than some expectations suggest.

Does this mean that all paradigmatic boundaries are blurred? In all these areas, the basic systematic operation remains crucial: Critical Theory in a very general sense takes place wherever philosophical and social-scientific analyses start from the intention of criticizing domination, and here, for many, the reference to the texts, authors, and models of thought of this tradition (in its narrower sense) offers itself as a resource, an inspiration, and a model. This promise of these resources can be illustrated with reference to two current discussions, in both of which voices from the context under discussion here are not absent but not particularly loud either, and for both, it can be argued that this tradition, in particular, could make promising contributions but will also benefit from complementary theoretical tools from other contexts.

It has taken several decades for the full force of the question of the afterlife of colonial and imperialist structures of Western-dominated modernity to be felt in scholarly and political debates, and not all potentially affected fields of scholarship have yet responded appropriately. Developments in recent years in particular have shown how this complex poses enormously difficult problems for which the classical disciplines of the humanities and social sciences are not always well equipped. How does one conceptualize the historical responsibility of entire cultural groups across centuries? What are the epistemic consequences of colonization? What might seem like a particular field of historical phenomena at first, which only came to consciousness in the era of decolonization in the postwar period, on closer inspection concerns the heart of the cultural and moral self-understanding of Western modernity.

Now it has become undeniable that precisely that process which has hitherto been understood primarily as a history of progress and liberation, namely, as intellectual enlightenment and political emancipation, is interwoven with exploitative expansion and dehumanizing subjugation. If, in other words, in historical reality, enlightenment and freedom, on the one hand, were essentially related to slavery and racism, on the other, it is no longer possible to tell the history of modernization in a unidirectional and triumphant way, and this equally affects political, economic, scientific, and intellectual history alike.

Such a readjustment cannot pass Critical Theory without leaving a trace, for this affects its own basic categories. Emancipation and defense against domination are its own urgent interests, and often enough Critical Theory has framed this task as an internal problem of European societies. Despite the internationalist and anti-imperialist elements in the history of Left theory, its theorists have also often remained representatives of a merely Western Marxism in a problematic sense, and the few references to non-European conditions do not provide a particularly favorable testimony here. The suspicion that Critical Theory itself embodies the methodological and political Eurocentrism that a truly cosmopolitan perspective on liberation would actually have to overcome is justified.

Yet, it is precisely in this tradition of thought that resources lie with which to respond to these problems, whether or not their authors might have intended it. Benjamin's partisanship for the perspective of the defeated in historiography, Adorno's and Horkheimer's insistence on the deep ambivalence of enlightenment ideals, and Marcuse's clear-sighted perception of the central role of the excluded and marginalized, whom the capitalist system cannot even properly exploit, are starting points for a radical self-critique of the Western liberation movements, which have yet to admit their own entanglement in domination elsewhere and thus should actually make way for an even more radical, decentered enlightenment and liberation. Critical Theory, perhaps malgré soi, was already partially thinking in this direction. In the urgently needed alliances today, even across geopolitical borders, Critical Theory can (and should) therefore, according to its own understanding, be an ally of the dominated wherever they are—and not a party offended by the accusation of Eurocentric complicity.

A comparable constellation can also be stated for a second topic. By now it should be generally evident that the problem of man-made climate change, threatening ecological catastrophes together with their political consequences, the irreversible extinction of species, and the accelerated destruction of future natural resources represent the most urgent challenge for political action and social awareness in the coming decades. Again, it has taken a long while for the human sciences to address this issue in its full breadth. In the meantime, debates about the Anthropocene and climate justice, sustainability and post-growth, human/animal/plant relations, and the critique of anthropocentrism, fossil capitalism, and geo-capitalism are receiving exactly the attention they deserve, and they even transcend long-established disciplinary boundaries, as basic theoretical and applied, technical, political, and cultural questions are being raised here at the same time.

Critical Theory has so far succeeded only sporadically in setting a particular agenda here, and often enough it looks as if it, too, would become the target of the accusation that it always thinks of politics and power only from the point of view of humans. Beyond the idea of a democracy of free and equal subjects, its conception of the goal of a liberated society remains, at least according to the first impression, astonishingly anthropocentric and unimaginative. This tradition also seems to have little to contribute to the question in which form contemporary communities could face the endangerment of their own survival. To admit that the exploitation of nature and environmental destruction were inscribed in the very functioning of capitalist modernity is just the first step.

Also here, as with the previous topic, it is true that Critical Theory already has produced concepts and models of thought whose relevance is perhaps only fully revealed today. The somewhat esoteric, speculative reflections of Adorno and Benjamin on mimesis and on the relationship of humans to inanimate nature, the persistent focus of the Dialectic of Enlightenment on the domination of inner and outer nature as the flip side of social domination, and the topos of “creative matter” from the history of German Idealism and materialism, which is enormously powerful in Bloch and in the very early Habermas, are just two first, absolutely relevant starting points here. From them, connections to the present conjuncture of the “New Materialism” and new holistic ontologies arise almost by themselves.

The fact that subject–object relations and their distortion and instrumentalization lie at the core of almost all problems concerning the human being, that being human is itself a question of mediations with the other, the non-human, forms a theoretical precondition on which one can build. The conviction that “domination” and “subjugation” are the names for relations on this fundamental, ontological level, and that the theme of power and politics itself is inscribed in the level of being, paves the way for the thematization of deep political relations, a politics of nature as well as an ecology of politics. From here it is only a small step to the expectation that on the basis of such, admittedly rather speculative motifs, helpful perspectives could be gained that might respond to the misery of the present, but also prefigure the possible splendor of a different, alternative relation to nature.

Critical Theory, as I imagine it, can take on these urgent problems of the present and respond to them, not in the mode of problem-solving, but in the mode of self-critical, persistent problematization of the structures of domination that come to bear in them. To this end, it uses all available theoretical insights that serve to see the world in all its divisions and contradictions more clearly in the face of a confusing and often enough paralyzing situation. This would be a possible realization of a problem-oriented, open-ended, cross-disciplinary program in which theory and practice do not merge, but challenge each other, passionately invested in forms of living, feeling, and acting that seek to escape the grip of powers and dominations without indulging in illusions of absolute freedom. This kind of theory, then as now, is all about finding the loopholes and spaces from which to see and experience that things could be different than they are under the spell of current regimes of domination.

重新思考批评与理论
在整整100年的时间里,我们的现在与知识分子和制度背景分开了,在这种背景下,“批判”理论作为与“传统”理论不同的理论,开始扮演形成身份的角色,而今天的讨论正是基于这种角色。不仅要反思可能的连续性,而且要反思这种实际距离,这有助于我们更清晰地了解今天与这个项目联系在一起意味着什么。因为,首先,只有在某些文本、主题和某种理论风格的影响的漫长历史中,这种传统的统一或连贯的印象才会出现,而在最初的几十年里几乎没有任何痕迹。无论是社会研究所在其成立阶段的目标,还是马克斯·霍克海默(Max Horkheimer)周围的学者圈子(完全是男性)的个人构成,都不可能使这种团结超越对非正统、无党派马克思主义的共同承诺。研究所的内部讨论、在《社会研究时代》及其后续机构的版面上以及在与国际同事的学术交流中都是相当多样化和多元化的。关于与马克思和马克思主义、与“资产阶级”哲学、与精神分析学、与文化、与苏联或与20世纪30年代至60年代的革命问题的正确关系的争论是如此激烈,因为没有给出一条共识路线,辩论的主角也没有达成太多共识。在形成了动态的、不断变化的讨论背景的情况下,追溯地假设连贯性是相当不合时宜的。其次,在这100年里,在社会、文化和技术世界中几乎没有留下任何石头,理论形成的背景和条件,特别是政治批评干预,都发生了深刻的变化。在战前和战后的研究所之间,虽然邮政地址保持不变,但在物质禀赋、象征意义、公共效力和学术背景的嵌入性方面存在着如此深刻的差异,以至于每种情况下可能的理论和政治实践都具有根本不同的形式。这也影响了学术研究的内部发展,这应该是显而易见的,因为在1930年左右,1950年左右和1965年左右,它指的是社会科学的总体状况,对国际发展作出反应,或者以跨学科或跨学科的方式工作,这意味着一些不同的东西。这与2024年前后的情况形成了对比,这是可以预料的。因此,创造一种早期学术-政治实践的无缝连续性和可用性的建议可能是徒劳的,毕竟,这种实践受制于其自身的情境上下文限制和潜力。这些持怀疑态度的言论是为了避免所有过高的期望,即可以为这种理论-政治背景确定要点,然后清楚地确定谁属于谁不属于谁以及今天谁比其他人更真正地继承了这一遗产。今天那些(像我一样)强调原始制度和个人背景的内部多元性以及周围条件的历史不连续性的人,肯定会失去一种明确范式(或知识品牌)的坚实同一性或统一性的感觉。然而,他们可能会获得自由,从这个传统的主要和次要路径中接受和继承某些元素。因为它会对今天的批判理论的探索产生影响,一个人是否被霍克海默对跨学科唯物主义的请求,阿多诺早期的“解释性”社会哲学,基希海默和波洛克的唯物主义法律和经济学,弗洛姆的社会心理学,克拉考尔的文化哲学,或本雅明的历史哲学所指导。这种开放性反映在一个问题上,即人们是否应该将马克思的重要性置于黑格尔、韦伯和尼采的重要性之上,作为第一代影响的载体。在这些问题上采取立场,甚至没有解决这样一个问题,即从20世纪40年代开始,“文明的破裂”(或用丹·迪纳的术语“文明的破裂”)的经历所产生的冲击,是否已经成为这一思想传统的核心认知和政治主题,应该被视为这一传统的统一关注点,而个体成员对此的反应不同。这种对历史距离和范式轮廓的开放性的感知所提供的自由,在于有可能有意识地识别和适当地使用批判理论的个人母旨,而不必担心违背统一理论方法的假定约束形式。 在这一传统的历史主角的文本语料库中,已经隐藏着几种不同的批判理论的线索,这些理论可以以多种方式延伸到现在。这些可能性绝不是无限的或武断的,因为它们是由文本和作者的真实和有据可查的历史决定的。在这段历史中,迄今为止被标记为外围的新立场有时可以被整合(例如,布洛赫、索恩-雷塞尔、肖勒姆、内格特、索内曼和许多其他人的贡献),从而突出了网络的其他网络,这些网络可以(但不一定)产生特别原创的新读物。然而,这种对批判理论内在多样性的反思将仍然与作为主要对象的所有相关文本中发生的事情联系在一起:统治。有人可能会说,任何法兰克福式的批判理论都是以社会统治存在的前提或前提开始的。在他20世纪20年代和30年代的读者看来,马克思在他的资产阶级社会及其经济结构理论中对社会统治的事实进行了典型的分析,因此,这一事实确实形成了一种“公理”。然而,这种统治究竟是如何构成的,取决于它依靠什么和谁来实现它,以及它在何种媒介和程序中发挥作用,又恰好导致了构成理论左派一般历史的内部理论分歧和分歧。那些强调上述论点的人认为,在法兰克福发展路线中,批判性社会理论项目的内部多元性,以及与理论主体和政治可能性的时间距离,可以相对平静地看待当代理论形成领域中一些看似深刻的差异。如果遗产本身已经如此多样化,那么接受和延续它的方式也将不止一种。由于重点从一开始就存在分歧和争议,随着理论的不断发展,随着越来越多的方案和概念选择,包括外部选择的加入,这些差异将趋于加剧。在批判理论的历史上,有一段时间在教育学和社会心理学领域取得了特别富有成效的发展,在国家理论和法律领域也取得了特别富有成效的发展,这并非偶然,但它们也不是唯一的选择。对功能主义社会理论与早期批判理论元素的综合寄予厚望,想必已经耗尽,正如早期主题的交流理论基础最初受到欢迎时所带来的欣快感一样。一般来说,从某一点开始,这种接受几乎完全集中在j<s:1>根·哈贝马斯的工作上,几乎所有关于批判理论的辩论都要求支持或反对这一特殊贡献的党派之争,当然倾向于模糊整体事业的多元特征,但这一次,无论是好是坏,似乎也已经过去了。今天关于如何实现批判理论的基本模式的突出建议,例如(仅参考定义德国语境的作者)阿克塞尔·霍尼特的更以黑格尔为导向的认识理论,雷纳·福斯特的更以新康德为基础的证明理论,或者拉赫尔·贾基的更全面的生命形式及其内部规范动力学理论,可以有相当多的权利要求再次接受传统的具体中心主题。像Robin Celikates这样的作者强调了与社会运动和抵抗和不服从实践的联系,这一事实代表了对批判形式辩论中一些过于高度理论化的倾向的重要对比,这些倾向通常以元理论或方法论的方式进行。新近爆发的关于法律基本批判的讨论,包括克里斯托夫·门克和丹尼尔·洛克的贡献,可以唤起20世纪20年代和30年代的主题,但与此同时,在一个主权崩溃和新威权主义国家实践的时代,这种紧迫性很难被忽视。将政治经济学批判重新确立为批判社会理论的中心,甚至是主要领域的趋势,无论是否马克思主义,都可以理所当然地被视为对近几十年来某种文化主义的片面性的必要纠正。此外,不应忘记,最近批判理论中一些最有力的立场出现在女权主义理论和政治理论之间的界面上,并产生了巨大的影响,从而已经将对马克思主义遗产的狭隘理解的中心弯曲为多维或交叉分析,也包括不同的主体和身份线。 事实上,更多基于人类学的概念,比如哈特穆特·罗莎的共振社会学,引用德国辩论中另一个著名的社会理论,将自己置于这条线中,在其某些前提的背景下,似乎令人惊讶,但由于其实践性和诊断性取向,它不能被完全拒绝。近年来,在激进民主理论和政治理论领域中出现了越来越多的关于法兰克福传统的贡献,这一事实再次表明,传统的政治和理论影响比一些预期所暗示的更加不可预测和开放。这是否意味着所有范式的界限都是模糊的?在所有这些领域,基本的系统操作仍然是至关重要的:在非常普遍的意义上,批判理论发生在哲学和社会科学分析从批评统治的意图开始的地方,在这里,对许多人来说,对这一传统(在其狭义上)的文本、作者和思想模式的参考提供了自己作为一种资源、一种灵感和一种模式。这些资源的承诺可以通过两个当前的讨论来说明,在这两个讨论中,来自这里讨论的背景的声音都不是缺席,但也不是特别响亮,对于两者来说,可以认为这一传统,特别是可以做出有希望的贡献,但也将受益于来自其他背景的互补理论工具。在学术和政治辩论中,西方主导的现代性的殖民和帝国主义结构的来世问题的全部力量被感受到,并不是所有可能受到影响的学术领域都做出了适当的回应。特别是近年来的发展表明,这种复杂性如何带来了极其困难的问题,而人文和社会科学的经典学科并不总是能够很好地解决这些问题。一个人如何将几个世纪以来整个文化群体的历史责任概念化?殖民化的认知后果是什么?乍一看,这似乎是一个特殊的历史现象领域,直到战后的非殖民化时代才被人们意识到,但仔细观察,它涉及到西方现代性文化和道德自我理解的核心。现在,不可否认的是,正是这个迄今为止主要被理解为进步和解放的历史,即智力启蒙和政治解放的过程,与剥削性的扩张和非人化的征服交织在一起。换句话说,如果在历史现实中,启蒙运动和自由一方面本质上与奴隶制和种族主义有关,另一方面,就不可能以一种单向的、胜利的方式来讲述现代化的历史,而这同样影响着政治、经济、科学和思想史。这种调整不可能不留下痕迹而通过批判理论,因为这影响到它自己的基本范畴。解放和抵抗统治是批判理论自身的迫切利益,批判理论常常将这一任务视为欧洲社会的内部问题。尽管在左翼理论的历史中有国际主义和反帝国主义的因素,但它的理论家也经常在一个有问题的意义上仅仅是西方马克思主义的代表,而且很少提到非欧洲的情况,在这里并没有提供特别有利的证据。怀疑批判理论本身体现了方法论和政治上的欧洲中心主义,而真正的世界主义解放观实际上必须克服这种怀疑是有道理的。然而,正是在这一思想传统中,存在着应对这些问题的资源,无论这些问题的作者是否有意为之。本雅明在史学中对失败者观点的党派之争,阿多诺和霍克海默对启蒙理想深层矛盾的坚持,以及马尔库塞对被排斥和边缘化的核心角色的清晰认识,资本主义制度甚至不能适当地利用这些人,是对西方解放运动进行激进自我批判的起点。他们还没有承认自己与其他地方的统治纠缠在一起,因此实际上应该为更激进、去中心化的启蒙和解放让路。批判理论,也许是错误的,已经部分地朝这个方向思考了。在当今迫切需要的联盟中,甚至跨越地缘政治边界,因此,根据批判理论自己的理解,它可以(也应该)成为被支配者的盟友,无论他们在哪里——而不是被欧洲中心主义共谋的指控所冒犯的一方。 对于第二个主题,也可以陈述一个类似的星座。到目前为止,应该普遍清楚的是,人为造成的气候变化问题、具有威胁性的生态灾难及其政治后果、物种不可逆转的灭绝以及对未来自然资源的加速破坏,是未来几十年政治行动和社会意识面临的最紧迫挑战。同样,人文科学花了很长时间才全面地解决了这个问题。与此同时,关于人类世和气候正义、可持续性和后增长、人类/动物/植物关系、对人类中心主义、化石资本主义和地缘资本主义的批评等问题的争论也得到了应有的关注,甚至超越了长期建立的学科界限,同时提出了基础理论和应用、技术、政治和文化问题。到目前为止,批判理论只是偶尔成功地在这里设定了一个特定的议程,而且看起来它似乎也会成为指责的目标,因为它总是只从人类的角度来考虑政治和权力。除了自由平等主体的民主理念之外,它关于一个解放社会的目标的概念,至少从第一印象来看,仍然令人惊讶地以人类为中心,缺乏想象力。这一传统似乎对当代社区以何种形式面临自身生存危险的问题也没有什么贡献。承认对自然的剥削和对环境的破坏是资本主义现代性运作的本质,这只是第一步。同样在这里,正如前面的主题一样,批判理论确实已经产生了一些概念和思维模式,它们的相关性可能只是在今天才被充分揭示出来。阿多诺和本雅明对模仿和人类与无生命自然的关系的一些深奥的思辨思考,启蒙辩证法对内在和外在自然的统治作为社会统治的另一面的持续关注,以及德国唯心主义和唯物主义历史中的“创造性物质”主题,这在布洛赫和哈贝马斯的早期非常强大,这只是两个第一,绝对相关的起点。由此,“新唯物主义”与新的整体本体论之间的联系几乎是自发产生的。主客体关系及其扭曲和工具化是几乎所有关于人类问题的核心,人类本身就是一个与他者(非人类)进行调解的问题,这一事实形成了一个理论前提,人们可以在此基础上进行建构。“统治”和“征服”是这种基本的、本体论层面上的关系的名称,权力和政治本身的主题是刻在存在层面上的,这种信念为深层政治关系的主题化铺平了道路,这是一种自然的政治,也是一种政治生态。从这里开始,这只是一小步的期望,在这样的基础上,诚然,相当投机的主题,可以获得有益的观点,可能回应目前的痛苦,但也预示着可能的辉煌,与自然的另一种关系。批判理论,正如我想象的那样,可以接受这些紧迫的问题,并对它们做出回应,不是以解决问题的方式,而是以自我批判的方式,对支配结构进行持续的问题化。为此目的,它利用一切现有的理论见解,在面对令人困惑和往往足够瘫痪的局势时,更清楚地看到世界的所有分裂和矛盾。这将是一个以问题为导向的、开放式的、跨学科的项目的可能实现,在这个项目中,理论和实践并不融合,而是相互挑战,热情地投入到生活、感觉和行动的形式中,寻求摆脱权力和统治的控制,而不沉溺于绝对自由的幻想。这种理论,无论是当时还是现在,都是为了寻找漏洞和空间,从中看到和体验到,在当前统治制度的魔咒下,事情可能会有所不同。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信