Effective Actions

L. Schulz, Catherine Hooppell, Adrianna C. Jenkins
{"title":"Effective Actions","authors":"L. Schulz, Catherine Hooppell, Adrianna C. Jenkins","doi":"10.1017/9781139048040.005","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Three studies look at whether the assumption of causal determinism (the assumption that all else being equal, causes generate effects deterministically) affects children’s imitation of modeled actions. We show that, even when the frequency of an effect is matched, both preschoolers (N = 60; mean: 56 months) and toddlers (N = 48; mean: 18 months) imitate actions more faithfully when modeled actions are deterministically rather than probabilistically effective. A third study suggests that preschoolers’ (N = 32; mean: 58 months) imitation is affected, not just by whether the agent’s goal is satisfied but also by whether the action is a reliable means to the goal. Children’s tendency to generate variable responses to probabilistically effective modeled actions could support causal learning. DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 3 Imagine that every time your Uncle Robbie makes a soufflé it rises perfectly, but when your Uncle Sam makes a soufflé, sometimes it rises and sometimes it falls. Although you might learn to cook both by observing Uncle Sam’s failures and by observing Uncle Robbie’s successes, if you were learning from Uncle Robbie, you would probably imitate his technique faithfully, while if you were learning from Uncle Sam, you might be inclined to vary the recipe. That is, the precision with which you imitate an observed action might be affected by your beliefs about the efficacy of the action; optimal learning might depend on knowing when to imitate and when to explore. In this study, we look at whether a similar proposition is true for young children: do children differentially imitate deterministically and probabilistically effective actions? Previous research on children’s imitation raises a puzzle. On the one hand, children are very good at reproducing modeled actions. Indeed, in some contexts, children will faithfully copy even arbitrary, unnecessary actions. For instance, children will imitate elaborate, causally irrelevant routines to open a box even when the mechanisms that could be used to open the box directly are obvious (Horner & Whiten, 2005; Lyons, Young, & Keil, 2006; Whiten, Custance, Gomez, Teixidor, & Bard, 1996). Similarly, children will copy an actor who, for no apparent reason, activates a toy with her head, even though the children can (and often do) also activate the toy with their hands (Geregely, Bekkering, Kiraly, 2002; Meltzoff 1992). On the other hand, children will sometimes override modeled actions in order to generate their own means to inferred ends. Thus for instance, toddlers do not copy actions that fail to achieve the agent’s intended outcome (Meltzoff, 1995). If an adult pulls on a barbell toy but does not pull it apart, 18-month-olds do not imitate the ‘failed’ DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 4 action. Instead they act to achieve the inferred goal of the action: they pull apart the toy. Critically children do not ‘read through the goals’ of the action if the action is performed by a machine rather than a person; the physical action by itself is not sufficient to lead children to compete the causal sequence. However, it is equally striking, and to our knowledge, less often noted, that children’s only cue that the action failed to fulfill the adult’s intention was the failure of the expected causal relationships (e.g., between pulling and separating). That is, the children were not given any linguistic or affective cues suggesting that the action failed to achieve the agent’s goals (the actor did not say ‘whoops’ or frown); the children simply saw that the actor pulled on the toy and the toy remained intact. Thus the only cue that the action “failed” to achieve the agent’s goals was the absence of a causal relationship that the child expected (e.g. between pulling and separating). In the context of intentional action, children seem to be able to use their knowledge of the causal structure of an event to infer the intentional structure of the event. The puzzle then concerns the role of causal knowledge in children’s imitative learning. Why do children sometimes seem to suspend their own causal knowledge in order to copy modeled actions faithfully (even when there are simpler means to the end) but at other times use their causal knowledge to override modeled actions in favor of novel means to inferred ends? What predicts the fidelity with which young children reproduce modeled actions? Gergely and colleagues have proposed that some differences in children’s imitation can be explained by assuming that children respect a principle of rational action (Csibra & Gergely, 1998; Gergely & Csibra, 1997; Gergely & Csibra, 2003; DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 5 Gergely, Nadasdy, Csibra, & Biro, 1995). That is, children may assume that intentional actions performed by rational agents are optimal within the constraints of the situation. If children observe actions that appear to be sub-optimal (e.g., an adult using her head to activate a toy or using arbitrary routines to open a box), they may nonetheless assume that “there must be a good reason” (Gergeley et al., 2002) for the agent’s choice of action. In the absence of an obvious ‘good reason’ for the action, children might assume the action has an unobserved causal relationship to the effect or they might revise their understanding of the agent’s goals (e.g., they might assume the goal was to demonstrate a convention or ritual). In either case, children should imitate the modeled action faithfully. However, situational constraints can provide an obvious ‘good reason’ for the modeled action. As elegantly demonstrated by an extension of Meltzoff’s (1988) lightactivation paradigm, if the situational constraints on the actor and the child are different, the child may not imitate the modeled action. In the new paradigm, the actor again used her head to activate a toy, however, this time the actor’s hands were occupied holding a blanket. In this case, children did not imitate the head action; instead they activated the toy with their hands (Gergely et al., 2002). The situational constraint (holding the blanket) provided an explanation for the actor’s unusual action, thus we suggest, screening-off (Reichenbach, 1956) a causal role for the particular means used to achieve the dominant goal (activating the light). Since the child was not also imitating the ancillary goal of holding a blanket, this analysis freed the child to (a) infer the causal structure of the main event (depressing the button makes the light go on), and then (b) achieve the actor’s dominant goal by novel but simpler means (using their hands). DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 6 We are sympathetic to the idea that children adopt a principle of rational action, but we note that this proposal does not resolve our original puzzle. The claim that children assume that rational agents act optimally with respect to situational constraints is prima facie incompatible with the fact that children recognize that adults’ actions are sometime ineffective. As researchers have noted, “judgments about the ‘rationality’ of means always translate into judgments of ‘efficacy’” (Gergely & Csibra, 2003, p. 290). If children assume that agents perform the most rational action available given the constraints of the situation, it is difficult to understand how children might construe modeled intentional actions as ‘failed’ actions. Why would a child assume that an adult who activates a toy with her head (instead of her free hands) is acting optimally, but that an adult who pulls on a toy but fails to separate it is not? It is tempting to conclude that children assume that modeled actions are optimal when the actions achieve the agent’s goal and not when they fail. Note however, that this presumes that children can simply ‘read off’ the success or failure of the agents’ goal from the sequence of events. This may indeed be the case when the agent provides explicit linguistic and affective cues about whether or not her goal has been achieved (e.g., “There!” or “Whoops!”; Carpenter, Akhtar, & Tomasello, 1998). However if the agent pulls on a toy, it is possible to infer that the agent failed in her goal to separate the toy, but it is also possible to infer that the agent succeeded in her goal to pull on the toy. Critically, if children always assume that agents act optimally, the inference that the adult succeeded should be the preferred inference. That is, under the assumption that adults always take the most rational action given the situational constraints, children should not infer that they could improve upon the observed action. DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 7 Here we suggest that although children do assume that agents act rationally with respect to their goals, they do not make this assumption uncritically. We suggest that children analyze goal-directed actions in the context of their broader causal knowledge. As discussed, there is considerable evidence that, given common situational constraints, children faithfully imitate arbitrary, causally irrelevant actions (activating a toy with their heads, engaging in elaborate rituals to open a box). We suggest that this is because arbitrary actions are, by definition, actions about which children have few prior expectations. If children do not have sufficient prior causal knowledge to evaluate the efficacy of the modeled actions, we expect that children will adopt a principle of rational action and assume the adult actions are optimal. Provided the modeled actions are not screened-off by a known relationship to an ancillary goal, children should imitate such actions faithfully. Because children’s tendency to imitate arbitrary actions has been well established by previous research, we will not replicate that aspect of our analysis here. However, if children do have sufficient prior knowledge to evaluate the relationship of the modeled action to the goal, we predict that children will imitate the modeled action faithfully only if they construe the action as an optimal means to the inferred en","PeriodicalId":368804,"journal":{"name":"Introduction to Effective Field Theory","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2020-11-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"3","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Introduction to Effective Field Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781139048040.005","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

Abstract

Three studies look at whether the assumption of causal determinism (the assumption that all else being equal, causes generate effects deterministically) affects children’s imitation of modeled actions. We show that, even when the frequency of an effect is matched, both preschoolers (N = 60; mean: 56 months) and toddlers (N = 48; mean: 18 months) imitate actions more faithfully when modeled actions are deterministically rather than probabilistically effective. A third study suggests that preschoolers’ (N = 32; mean: 58 months) imitation is affected, not just by whether the agent’s goal is satisfied but also by whether the action is a reliable means to the goal. Children’s tendency to generate variable responses to probabilistically effective modeled actions could support causal learning. DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 3 Imagine that every time your Uncle Robbie makes a soufflé it rises perfectly, but when your Uncle Sam makes a soufflé, sometimes it rises and sometimes it falls. Although you might learn to cook both by observing Uncle Sam’s failures and by observing Uncle Robbie’s successes, if you were learning from Uncle Robbie, you would probably imitate his technique faithfully, while if you were learning from Uncle Sam, you might be inclined to vary the recipe. That is, the precision with which you imitate an observed action might be affected by your beliefs about the efficacy of the action; optimal learning might depend on knowing when to imitate and when to explore. In this study, we look at whether a similar proposition is true for young children: do children differentially imitate deterministically and probabilistically effective actions? Previous research on children’s imitation raises a puzzle. On the one hand, children are very good at reproducing modeled actions. Indeed, in some contexts, children will faithfully copy even arbitrary, unnecessary actions. For instance, children will imitate elaborate, causally irrelevant routines to open a box even when the mechanisms that could be used to open the box directly are obvious (Horner & Whiten, 2005; Lyons, Young, & Keil, 2006; Whiten, Custance, Gomez, Teixidor, & Bard, 1996). Similarly, children will copy an actor who, for no apparent reason, activates a toy with her head, even though the children can (and often do) also activate the toy with their hands (Geregely, Bekkering, Kiraly, 2002; Meltzoff 1992). On the other hand, children will sometimes override modeled actions in order to generate their own means to inferred ends. Thus for instance, toddlers do not copy actions that fail to achieve the agent’s intended outcome (Meltzoff, 1995). If an adult pulls on a barbell toy but does not pull it apart, 18-month-olds do not imitate the ‘failed’ DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 4 action. Instead they act to achieve the inferred goal of the action: they pull apart the toy. Critically children do not ‘read through the goals’ of the action if the action is performed by a machine rather than a person; the physical action by itself is not sufficient to lead children to compete the causal sequence. However, it is equally striking, and to our knowledge, less often noted, that children’s only cue that the action failed to fulfill the adult’s intention was the failure of the expected causal relationships (e.g., between pulling and separating). That is, the children were not given any linguistic or affective cues suggesting that the action failed to achieve the agent’s goals (the actor did not say ‘whoops’ or frown); the children simply saw that the actor pulled on the toy and the toy remained intact. Thus the only cue that the action “failed” to achieve the agent’s goals was the absence of a causal relationship that the child expected (e.g. between pulling and separating). In the context of intentional action, children seem to be able to use their knowledge of the causal structure of an event to infer the intentional structure of the event. The puzzle then concerns the role of causal knowledge in children’s imitative learning. Why do children sometimes seem to suspend their own causal knowledge in order to copy modeled actions faithfully (even when there are simpler means to the end) but at other times use their causal knowledge to override modeled actions in favor of novel means to inferred ends? What predicts the fidelity with which young children reproduce modeled actions? Gergely and colleagues have proposed that some differences in children’s imitation can be explained by assuming that children respect a principle of rational action (Csibra & Gergely, 1998; Gergely & Csibra, 1997; Gergely & Csibra, 2003; DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 5 Gergely, Nadasdy, Csibra, & Biro, 1995). That is, children may assume that intentional actions performed by rational agents are optimal within the constraints of the situation. If children observe actions that appear to be sub-optimal (e.g., an adult using her head to activate a toy or using arbitrary routines to open a box), they may nonetheless assume that “there must be a good reason” (Gergeley et al., 2002) for the agent’s choice of action. In the absence of an obvious ‘good reason’ for the action, children might assume the action has an unobserved causal relationship to the effect or they might revise their understanding of the agent’s goals (e.g., they might assume the goal was to demonstrate a convention or ritual). In either case, children should imitate the modeled action faithfully. However, situational constraints can provide an obvious ‘good reason’ for the modeled action. As elegantly demonstrated by an extension of Meltzoff’s (1988) lightactivation paradigm, if the situational constraints on the actor and the child are different, the child may not imitate the modeled action. In the new paradigm, the actor again used her head to activate a toy, however, this time the actor’s hands were occupied holding a blanket. In this case, children did not imitate the head action; instead they activated the toy with their hands (Gergely et al., 2002). The situational constraint (holding the blanket) provided an explanation for the actor’s unusual action, thus we suggest, screening-off (Reichenbach, 1956) a causal role for the particular means used to achieve the dominant goal (activating the light). Since the child was not also imitating the ancillary goal of holding a blanket, this analysis freed the child to (a) infer the causal structure of the main event (depressing the button makes the light go on), and then (b) achieve the actor’s dominant goal by novel but simpler means (using their hands). DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 6 We are sympathetic to the idea that children adopt a principle of rational action, but we note that this proposal does not resolve our original puzzle. The claim that children assume that rational agents act optimally with respect to situational constraints is prima facie incompatible with the fact that children recognize that adults’ actions are sometime ineffective. As researchers have noted, “judgments about the ‘rationality’ of means always translate into judgments of ‘efficacy’” (Gergely & Csibra, 2003, p. 290). If children assume that agents perform the most rational action available given the constraints of the situation, it is difficult to understand how children might construe modeled intentional actions as ‘failed’ actions. Why would a child assume that an adult who activates a toy with her head (instead of her free hands) is acting optimally, but that an adult who pulls on a toy but fails to separate it is not? It is tempting to conclude that children assume that modeled actions are optimal when the actions achieve the agent’s goal and not when they fail. Note however, that this presumes that children can simply ‘read off’ the success or failure of the agents’ goal from the sequence of events. This may indeed be the case when the agent provides explicit linguistic and affective cues about whether or not her goal has been achieved (e.g., “There!” or “Whoops!”; Carpenter, Akhtar, & Tomasello, 1998). However if the agent pulls on a toy, it is possible to infer that the agent failed in her goal to separate the toy, but it is also possible to infer that the agent succeeded in her goal to pull on the toy. Critically, if children always assume that agents act optimally, the inference that the adult succeeded should be the preferred inference. That is, under the assumption that adults always take the most rational action given the situational constraints, children should not infer that they could improve upon the observed action. DIFFERENTIAL IMITATION 7 Here we suggest that although children do assume that agents act rationally with respect to their goals, they do not make this assumption uncritically. We suggest that children analyze goal-directed actions in the context of their broader causal knowledge. As discussed, there is considerable evidence that, given common situational constraints, children faithfully imitate arbitrary, causally irrelevant actions (activating a toy with their heads, engaging in elaborate rituals to open a box). We suggest that this is because arbitrary actions are, by definition, actions about which children have few prior expectations. If children do not have sufficient prior causal knowledge to evaluate the efficacy of the modeled actions, we expect that children will adopt a principle of rational action and assume the adult actions are optimal. Provided the modeled actions are not screened-off by a known relationship to an ancillary goal, children should imitate such actions faithfully. Because children’s tendency to imitate arbitrary actions has been well established by previous research, we will not replicate that aspect of our analysis here. However, if children do have sufficient prior knowledge to evaluate the relationship of the modeled action to the goal, we predict that children will imitate the modeled action faithfully only if they construe the action as an optimal means to the inferred en
有效的行动
三项研究着眼于因果决定论的假设(假设所有其他条件相同,因果决定论地产生结果)是否会影响儿童模仿模仿的行为。我们发现,即使影响的频率是匹配的,学龄前儿童(N = 60;平均:56个月)和幼儿(N = 48;平均:18个月)当模拟的行动是确定性的而不是概率的有效时,他们会更忠实地模仿行动。第三项研究表明,学龄前儿童(N = 32;平均值:58个月)模仿受到影响,不仅受代理人的目标是否得到满足的影响,还受行动是否是实现目标的可靠手段的影响。儿童倾向于对概率有效的模式化行为产生不同的反应,这可以支持因果学习。想象一下,每次你的罗比叔叔做蛋奶酥时,它都会完美地浮起来,但当你的山姆大叔做蛋奶酥时,它有时会浮起来,有时会掉下来。虽然你可以通过观察山姆大叔的失败和罗比叔叔的成功来学习烹饪,但如果你向罗比叔叔学习,你可能会忠实地模仿他的技术,而如果你向山姆大叔学习,你可能会倾向于改变食谱。也就是说,你模仿观察到的行为的精确度可能会受到你对该行为有效性的信念的影响;最佳的学习可能取决于知道什么时候模仿,什么时候探索。在这项研究中,我们研究了一个类似的命题是否适用于幼儿:儿童是否会不同地模仿确定性和概率有效的行为?先前关于儿童模仿的研究提出了一个难题。一方面,孩子们非常擅长模仿模仿行为。事实上,在某些情况下,孩子们会忠实地模仿甚至是武断的、不必要的行为。例如,即使可以直接打开盒子的机制是显而易见的,孩子们也会模仿精心设计的、因果无关的惯例来打开盒子(Horner & Whiten, 2005;Lyons, Young, & Keil, 2006;white, Custance, Gomez, Teixidor, & Bard, 1996)。同样,孩子们会模仿一个演员,没有明显的原因,用她的头激活玩具,即使孩子们可以(而且经常)用他们的手激活玩具(Geregely, Bekkering, Kiraly, 2002;迈尔左夫1992)。另一方面,孩子们有时会无视模仿的行为,以产生他们自己的手段来推断目的。例如,蹒跚学步的幼儿不会模仿那些未能达到行为主体预期结果的行为(Meltzoff, 1995)。如果一个成年人拉上一个杠铃玩具,但没有把它拆开,18个月大的婴儿就不会模仿这个“失败的”差异模仿动作。相反,他们的行动是为了实现行动的推断目标:他们拉开玩具。关键的是,如果动作是由机器而不是人执行的,孩子们就不会“理解动作的目标”;身体动作本身并不足以引导孩子去竞争因果顺序。然而,同样引人注目的是,据我们所知,很少有人注意到,儿童认为该行为未能实现成人意图的唯一线索是预期因果关系的失败(例如,在拉和分离之间)。也就是说,孩子们没有得到任何语言或情感上的暗示,表明行为没有达到行为主体的目标(行为主体没有说“哎呀”或皱眉);孩子们只是看到演员拉动玩具,玩具仍然完好无损。因此,行为“失败”实现行为者目标的唯一线索是缺乏孩子所期望的因果关系(例如,在拉和分离之间)。在有意行为的背景下,儿童似乎能够利用他们对事件因果结构的知识来推断事件的有意结构。这个难题涉及到因果知识在儿童模仿学习中的作用。为什么孩子们有时似乎为了忠实地模仿模仿行为而搁置自己的因果知识(即使有更简单的达到目的的方法),但在其他时候却用他们的因果知识来推翻模仿行为,以支持实现推断目的的新方法?什么能预测幼儿模仿模仿行为的准确性?Gergely及其同事提出,儿童模仿的一些差异可以通过假设儿童尊重理性行为原则来解释(Csibra & Gergely, 1998;Gergely & Csibra, 1997;Gergely & Csibra, 2003;差异模仿(Gergely, Nadasdy, Csibra, & Biro, 1995)。也就是说,孩子们可能会假设,在这种情况的约束下,理性行为者所做的有意行为是最优的。如果孩子观察到的行为似乎是次优的(例如: 例如,一个成年人用她的头来激活一个玩具,或者用任意的程序来打开一个盒子),尽管如此,他们可能会认为“一定有一个很好的理由”(Gergeley et al., 2002)对于代理人的行动选择。在缺乏一个明显的“好理由”的情况下,孩子们可能会认为这个行为与效果有一个未观察到的因果关系,或者他们可能会修改他们对行为者目标的理解(例如,他们可能会假设目标是展示一个惯例或仪式)。在任何一种情况下,孩子都应该忠实地模仿模仿的动作。然而,情境约束可以为模拟行动提供一个明显的“好理由”。正如Meltzoff(1988)的光激活范式的扩展所优雅地证明的那样,如果行为人和孩子的情境约束不同,孩子可能不会模仿模仿的动作。在新的范例中,演员再次用她的头来激活一个玩具,然而,这一次演员的手被毯子占据了。在这种情况下,孩子们没有模仿头部的动作;相反,他们用手激活玩具(Gergely et al, 2002)。情境约束(拿着毯子)为行为人的不寻常行为提供了解释,因此我们认为,屏蔽(Reichenbach, 1956)是用于实现主导目标(激活光线)的特定手段的因果作用。由于孩子并没有模仿拿毯子的辅助目标,这种分析使孩子能够(a)推断出主要事件的因果结构(按下按钮使灯亮起),然后(b)通过新颖但更简单的手段(使用他们的手)实现行动者的主要目标。差别模仿我们赞同儿童养成理性行为原则的观点,但我们注意到这一建议并不能解决我们最初的困惑。儿童认为理性行为者在情境约束下的行为是最优的这一说法,与儿童认识到成人的行为有时是无效的这一事实表面上是不相容的。正如研究人员所指出的,“对手段的‘合理性’的判断总是转化为对‘有效性’的判断”(Gergely & Csibra, 2003年,第290页)。如果孩子们假设代理在给定的情况下执行最理性的行为,就很难理解孩子们如何将模拟的故意行为解释为“失败”的行为。为什么一个孩子会认为一个成年人用她的头(而不是她空闲的手)激活玩具是最佳行为,而一个成年人拉着玩具却没有把它分开,这就不是最佳行为?我们很容易得出这样的结论:孩子们认为,当行为达到行为主体的目标时,而不是当行为失败时,模型行为是最优的。然而,请注意,这是假设儿童可以简单地从事件序列中“读出”代理目标的成功或失败。当智能体提供了明确的语言和情感线索来说明她的目标是否已经实现时(例如,“那里!或“哎呀!”Carpenter, Akhtar, & Tomasello, 1998)。然而,如果智能体拉玩具,则可以推断出智能体未能实现分离玩具的目标,但也可以推断出智能体成功实现了拉玩具的目标。关键的是,如果孩子们总是假设代理人的行为是最佳的,那么成人成功的推论应该是首选的推论。也就是说,在假设成年人总是在情境约束下采取最理性的行动的情况下,儿童不应该推断他们可以改进观察到的行动。这里我们认为,尽管儿童确实认为行为主体就其目标而言是理性的,但他们并不是不加批判地做出这种假设的。我们建议孩子们在他们更广泛的因果知识的背景下分析目标导向的行为。如前所述,有相当多的证据表明,在常见的情境限制下,儿童忠实地模仿任意的、因果无关的行为(用他们的头激活玩具,参与复杂的仪式来打开一个盒子)。我们认为,这是因为武断的行为,从定义上讲,是孩子们事先没有多少期望的行为。如果儿童没有足够的先验因果知识来评估模拟行为的有效性,我们预计儿童将采用理性行为原则,并假设成人的行为是最优的。如果模拟的行为没有被已知的与辅助目标的关系所屏蔽,孩子们应该忠实地模仿这些行为。因为以前的研究已经很好地证实了儿童模仿任意行为的倾向,所以我们不会在这里重复这方面的分析。 然而,如果儿童确实有足够的先验知识来评估模拟动作与目标的关系,我们预测儿童只有在将动作解释为推断目标的最佳手段时才会忠实地模仿模拟动作
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信