The Higher Learning in a Democracy

C. Clark
{"title":"The Higher Learning in a Democracy","authors":"C. Clark","doi":"10.1086/intejethi.47.3.2989388","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"IT IS now some centuries since Aristotle announced the philosophic principle of induction as the process by which the universal is extracted from a number of varying cases, to be followed by definition, fixing the principle thus extracted for use in all subsequent thinking. In so doing he not only developed a logical theory which furnished the intellectual method of Europe for almost two thousand years but laid the seeds of an intellectual controversy still rife today. As the lines came eventually to be drawn, the battle is between rationalism, on the one hand, and empiricism, on the other; the former devoted to principles, the latter to facts. The protagonist of the former is typically Descartes; of the latter, Francis Bacon. We have long been assured by our leading philosophers that the battle is largely sham, that all thinking worth while must make use of the rationalistic process of deduction, and of the empirical process of induction, of speculation and experimentation, of theorizing and of observing facts, each as complements of the other. If, therefore, an individual emphasizes one process more than the other, it is because of his tastes and inclination and not for reasons of eternal verity. In the natural sciences there seems a fair agreement on this, and it is accepted that the essence of scientific method is the verification of intelligent theory or even of shrewd guess. But in the social sciences such reconciliation is far from being obtained. John Dewey refers to the split as tragic, pointing to our oscillation \"between a normative and rationalistic logic in morals and an empirical, purely descriptive method in concrete matters of fact,\" so that \"our supposed ultimate ideals and aims","PeriodicalId":346392,"journal":{"name":"The International Journal of Ethics","volume":"68 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1937-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"3","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The International Journal of Ethics","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1086/intejethi.47.3.2989388","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

Abstract

IT IS now some centuries since Aristotle announced the philosophic principle of induction as the process by which the universal is extracted from a number of varying cases, to be followed by definition, fixing the principle thus extracted for use in all subsequent thinking. In so doing he not only developed a logical theory which furnished the intellectual method of Europe for almost two thousand years but laid the seeds of an intellectual controversy still rife today. As the lines came eventually to be drawn, the battle is between rationalism, on the one hand, and empiricism, on the other; the former devoted to principles, the latter to facts. The protagonist of the former is typically Descartes; of the latter, Francis Bacon. We have long been assured by our leading philosophers that the battle is largely sham, that all thinking worth while must make use of the rationalistic process of deduction, and of the empirical process of induction, of speculation and experimentation, of theorizing and of observing facts, each as complements of the other. If, therefore, an individual emphasizes one process more than the other, it is because of his tastes and inclination and not for reasons of eternal verity. In the natural sciences there seems a fair agreement on this, and it is accepted that the essence of scientific method is the verification of intelligent theory or even of shrewd guess. But in the social sciences such reconciliation is far from being obtained. John Dewey refers to the split as tragic, pointing to our oscillation "between a normative and rationalistic logic in morals and an empirical, purely descriptive method in concrete matters of fact," so that "our supposed ultimate ideals and aims
民主国家的高等教育
亚里士多德曾宣布归纳的哲学原理是一个过程,通过这个过程,可以从许多不同的情况中提取出普遍的东西,然后给它下定义,并把这样提取出来的原理固定在以后的一切思维中,这已经有几个世纪了。在这样做的过程中,他不仅发展了一种逻辑理论,为欧洲提供了近两千年的知识方法,而且为今天仍然盛行的知识争论埋下了种子。随着界限的最终划定,这场战争在理性主义和经验主义之间展开;前者致力于原则,后者致力于事实。前者的主角是典型的笛卡尔;后者是弗朗西斯·培根。长期以来,我们的主要哲学家向我们保证,这场斗争在很大程度上是虚假的,所有有价值的思考都必须利用推理的理性过程,归纳的经验过程,思辨和实验的过程,理论化和观察事实的过程,每一个都是相互补充的。因此,如果一个人强调一个过程多于另一个过程,那是因为他的品味和倾向,而不是出于永恒真理的原因。在自然科学中,人们似乎对这一点达成了相当一致的看法,人们普遍认为,科学方法的本质是对智慧理论甚至是精明猜测的验证。但在社会科学领域,这种调和还远远没有实现。约翰·杜威(John Dewey)将这种分裂称为悲剧性的,指出我们“在道德上的规范和理性主义逻辑和在具体事实问题上的经验的、纯粹描述性的方法之间”摇摆,因此“我们假定的最终理想和目标”
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信