Summation of the debate on the feasibility of a phenomenological theory of justice

Odysseus Makridis
{"title":"Summation of the debate on the feasibility of a phenomenological theory of justice","authors":"Odysseus Makridis","doi":"10.1080/15456870309367448","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Murray (2003a, in this issue) addresses some of the points raised by Makridis (2003) in response to Murray's earlier article entitled \"The dialogical prioritization of calls: Toward a communicative model of justice\" (Murray, 2003b). If anyone is eminently qualified to argue the case for a Levinasianphenomenological theory of justice, it must be he. Murray has deep knowledge of Levinas' phenomenology and is conversant both with the primary sources and with the growing bibliography on Levinas' work. My continuing reservations about the prospects of developing a Levinasian theory of justice should not, therefore, be taken to reflect on Murray's acumen or competence. If anything, it is fair to say that if Murray is stymied in his efforts, this is already a telling sign that a phenomenological theory of justice may be unobtainable. The deeper theoretical significance of this would be that, as many a prophet of post-modernism has gloated or lamented, one does indeed reach the dead end for normativity with the development of certain characteristically modern trends. One cannot have it both ways. Ivan Karazamov's grim aside (either there is a God, or everything is permitted) may sound at first like a false dichotomy but its inner core, which makes this utterance so effective, fulfils a curiously stringent methodological requirement: Unless preference-transcendent criteria are available to the moral agent (either on natural foundations or as rational decision making procedures) ethical demands cannot be defended. Phenomenology rejects objectivist claims; it also rejects theory-laden rationalisms of all kinds. What is left, then, to furnish phenomenology with normative grounds? How can phenomenology produce a normative theory of any kind? It is to Murray's credit that he has undertaken so difficult, as it is high-stakes, a task as to convince us that a phenomenological theory of justice (*1) is feasible. Levinasian phenomenology is radically opposed to theory. In fact, this stern opposition to theory, which it dismisses as a totalizing and intrinsically hegemonic expropriation of human spontaneity, has a moral pathos to it. Far from serving as a possible foundation for a normative theory, however, this pathos is consistently anti-foundationalist: it equally resists, or ought to resist, its own","PeriodicalId":113832,"journal":{"name":"New Jersey Journal of Communication","volume":"12 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2003-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"New Jersey Journal of Communication","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/15456870309367448","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Murray (2003a, in this issue) addresses some of the points raised by Makridis (2003) in response to Murray's earlier article entitled "The dialogical prioritization of calls: Toward a communicative model of justice" (Murray, 2003b). If anyone is eminently qualified to argue the case for a Levinasianphenomenological theory of justice, it must be he. Murray has deep knowledge of Levinas' phenomenology and is conversant both with the primary sources and with the growing bibliography on Levinas' work. My continuing reservations about the prospects of developing a Levinasian theory of justice should not, therefore, be taken to reflect on Murray's acumen or competence. If anything, it is fair to say that if Murray is stymied in his efforts, this is already a telling sign that a phenomenological theory of justice may be unobtainable. The deeper theoretical significance of this would be that, as many a prophet of post-modernism has gloated or lamented, one does indeed reach the dead end for normativity with the development of certain characteristically modern trends. One cannot have it both ways. Ivan Karazamov's grim aside (either there is a God, or everything is permitted) may sound at first like a false dichotomy but its inner core, which makes this utterance so effective, fulfils a curiously stringent methodological requirement: Unless preference-transcendent criteria are available to the moral agent (either on natural foundations or as rational decision making procedures) ethical demands cannot be defended. Phenomenology rejects objectivist claims; it also rejects theory-laden rationalisms of all kinds. What is left, then, to furnish phenomenology with normative grounds? How can phenomenology produce a normative theory of any kind? It is to Murray's credit that he has undertaken so difficult, as it is high-stakes, a task as to convince us that a phenomenological theory of justice (*1) is feasible. Levinasian phenomenology is radically opposed to theory. In fact, this stern opposition to theory, which it dismisses as a totalizing and intrinsically hegemonic expropriation of human spontaneity, has a moral pathos to it. Far from serving as a possible foundation for a normative theory, however, this pathos is consistently anti-foundationalist: it equally resists, or ought to resist, its own
关于现象学正义理论可行性的辩论总结
Murray (2003a,在本期中)回应了Makridis(2003)在Murray之前的文章“呼叫的对话优先顺序:走向正义的沟通模式”(Murray, 2003b)中提出的一些观点。如果有人特别有资格为列文式的现象学正义理论辩护,那一定是他。穆雷对列维纳斯的现象学有很深的了解,熟悉原始资料来源和列维纳斯作品的日益增多的参考书目。因此,我对发展列文西亚正义理论的前景一直持保留态度,不应被视为对默里的智慧或能力的反映。如果有什么的话,公平地说,如果穆雷的努力受到阻碍,这已经是一个明显的迹象,表明正义的现象学理论可能是无法获得的。正如许多后现代主义的先见之明所幸幸于乐或哀叹的那样,这种情况的更深层次的理论意义在于,随着某些具有特色的现代趋势的发展,人们确实进入了规范性的死胡同。鱼与熊掌不可兼得。Ivan Karazamov的冷酷的旁白(要么有一个上帝,要么一切都是允许的)乍听起来像是一个错误的二分法,但它的核心,使这句话如此有效,满足了一个奇怪的严格的方法论要求:除非道德主体可以获得超越偏好的标准(要么在自然基础上,要么作为理性决策程序),否则道德要求无法辩护。现象学拒绝客观主义的主张;它也拒绝各种充满理论的理性主义。那么,还剩下什么来为现象学提供规范依据呢?现象学如何产生一种规范理论?值得赞扬的是,穆雷承担了如此困难的任务,因为这是一项高风险的任务,以说服我们,正义的现象学理论(*1)是可行的。列文的现象学与理论完全对立。事实上,这种对理论的严厉反对,它认为这是对人类自发性的总体化和内在霸权的剥夺,对它有一种道德上的悲情。然而,这种悲情远不能作为规范理论的可能基础,它始终是反基础主义的:它同样抵制,或者应该抵制,它自己的
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信